The Basis of Stoic Ethics
The Basis of Stoic Ethics
The Basis of Stoic Ethics
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Harvard Studies in
Classical Philology
NICHOLAS P. WHITE
THE origins of Stoic ethics are not open to easy view. The historical
break conventionally marked by the deaths of Alexander the Great
in 323 and Aristotle in 322 has long discouraged the drawing of lines of
influence from the Classical to the Hellenistic period. In presentations
of the history of philosophy, the tendency to see discontinuity has been
strengthened by the idea that after Aristotle philosophy was decadent
and undistinguished, far beneath the level of past achievements. This
idea has been strengthened in turn by the paucity of evidence about
Hellenistic philosophy, which itself renders difficult the drawing of any
historical lines at all. Understanding of the origins of Stoic doctrine has
also been thwarted by the nature of the evidence that does remain. It is
predominantly doxographical: bits and pieces giving what our sources
and their sources believed to be the highlights of Stoic thought, rather
than sustained reports of the Stoics' positions and the arguments for
them. The result is that we often cannot tell which of their views the
Stoics thought central and which they thought peripheral. No philoso-
pher ever regards all his beliefs as on a par: some are basic while others
are part of the superstructure of corollaries and elaborations. But the
nature of our evidence about early Stoicism hinders us from drawing
this distinction. In consequence there is a blurring of the historical as
well as the philosophical picture. Not knowing in many instances which
beliefs the early Stoics took as basic to their doctrine, we are poorly
situated to tell which of their agreements and disagreements with
previous thinkers seemed to them vital and which were taken by them
to be less crucial. Thus, the clearer we can make the structure of their
philosophical doctrine, the better informed we can be about which
historical connections are most important.
Although the scholarly situation has improved in recent years, work
on the Stoics is still heavily under the spell of the doxographical tradi-
tion, in many ways continued by von Arnim's influential collection of
Stoic remains, the Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta. It is a pressing task
II
The scene shifts, then, to the first century B.C., where we find a dis-
cussion directly pertinent to these themes in Books III-V of Cicero's
De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum. In Book III we see a sketch of Stoic
ethics, with considerable attention to oikeiosis and moral development;
in Book IV the Stoic doctrine is attacked, with the same focus; and this
attack is followed in Book V by an exposition of another ethical doctrine,
157-161); Dirlmeier followed with an argument to much the same effect, with
particular emphasis on the notion of oikeiosis (" Die Oikeiosislehre Theophrasts,"
Philologus suppl. 30 [I937]). The idea was effectively rebutted by Pohlenz,
Grundfr. 1-81.
III
25 For this view and some of its attendant problems, see, e.g., Long, Hellenisti
Philosophy 189-I99.
26 We do not know, in fact, who originated this line of objection to the St
account. (I suspect that the question is in a way pointless, since I think that t
originator of the account, whether he was Zeno or Chrysippus or someone e
must from the start have been aware of the possibility of this sort of objecti
so obvious is it.) For the idea that Posidonius criticized Chrysippus for depict
the psychologies of children and adults as implausibly different from one an
other, see Pohlenz, Die Stoa I, 199-200.
27 Thus one finds Pohlenz, among others, citing Book V without any warni
as evidence for claims about Stoic doctrine (e.g., Grundfragen 95).
** Cc. 89 (bonum appello quidquid secundum naturam est, quod contra, malum),
66, 15-17.
40 Cc. 47, 6o.
41 Cc. 58-61, 47, 63-64, 55.
42 Hence the apparent repetitiousness of cc. 46-72 as against cc. 34-44 (and
esp. cc. 65-67 vs. 38, 43), noted by Madvig, ibid, and mistakenly taken by him
to be pointless.
48 Hence the emphasis on the naturalness of virtue in cc. 58-60, 65-66, long
after the new argumentandi genus has begun in c. 46, and in spite of the claim
there that it will not be based upon the prima commendatio naturae, which was
the impulse to self-preservation and self-perfection.
IV
To the wary eye it takes only a little care in the reading of Book III
to see that the structure of its argument is quite different from that of
Book V. In brief, the point is that Book III does not rest ultimately
upon a self-realizationist doctrine as does Book V, and that the account
of moral development in the former contains a crucial idea entirely
lacking in the doctrine of Antiochus in the latter.
The first step of the account of development in III indeed looks the
same as that of the account in V: all animals are said to strive for self-
preservation (c. 16, ad se conservandum) and to avoid what is inimical to
that end. As a part of this striving they are said to have "sense of self "
(sensus sui), without which they would not be able to strive for self-
preservation.45 What is distinctly lacking, however, is the insistence of
Book V that coordinate with, or arising immediately out of,46 the
impulse to self-preservation is a desire for perfection of one's parts and
of oneself as a whole. Indeed, the injunction to make oneself or one's
parts "perfect," while frequent in Book V, is conspicuously absent from
Book III.47 The same can be said of the idea, basic to Book V, that in
order to follow the injunctions of nature, the first thing that we must
do is to determine what the nature of man is (V. 34)- Man does indeed
have a special place in the scheme of Book III,48 to which we shall later
turn (section VIII), but that place is not accurately represented by
saying that on its doctrine, a person's good is simply the development
44 Cc. 71-72, 76 ff. I leave aside the question whether the view involved
ultimately is paradoxical or self-contradictory.
45 C. 16; cf. D.L. VII.85.
4" Cf. n.3o.
47 In Book V see cc. 26, 34, 35, 36, 37, 39-40, 43, 44, 59--60. (The occurrence
of perfectione at III.32 obviously has nothing to do with the present matter.)
48 See cc. 21 and, in a different connection, 63, 66, 67-68.
Commenting on this passage, Madvig was worried by the fact that although
the word officium occurs first in the clause primum est ... officium, the phrase cum
officio selectio a few lines later seems to suggest that only at a later stage does a
person actually perform officia (Madvig 372; cf. H. Rackham, trans., Cicero, De
Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass. 1931) 238n.). If one
does think that only what is done at the later stage can be an officium, then one
will take the first occurrence of the word to be misleading. In fact, however, the
Stoics saw no need for a creature to have reached any maturity or mental power
before it could perform officia or kathekonta. A kathekon, in their view, was some-
thing that, when done, had a plausible defense (ElEAoyov oaX4E d&roAoytaCpdv in D.L.
VII.Io7, and edAoyov &7roAoylav XE' in Stob. Ecl. II 85, 14-15, SVF I.230), but
this did not require that the creature who had done it be actually in a position
at the time to give that defense, as is shown by the fact that they allowed kathe-
konta to be performed by plants and lower animals as well as men (loc. cit.).
52 Intelligentia and notio are Cicero's suggested translations of Vwvota; cognitio
and ratio must respectively translate Ka-rac7~ArpL and AOyos. Cicero's frequent
need here to translate and even to explain terms from Stoic epistemology (cf.
also n.49) indicates that his immediate source at this point was a work pre-
supposing, or perhaps containing at an earlier point, some epistemological
material.
" The Stoic idea of honestum as the sole bonum is picked up later, as in cc. 26,
58, but it does not loom large in this book. When it does appear it is connected,
in a manner standard for Stoics but too involved to be discussed here, with the
notion of 6 oAoyl, as in c. 21. Associated with this notion is the phrase constans
consentaneaque naturae, in which Madvig (pp. 373, 375) rightly took constans to
express self-consistency, and consentanea naturae to have to do with consistency
with nature. (That these two ideas were linked by the Stoics is well known; see
Stob. Ecl. II 75, 11-76, 8, Madvig 374-375, and Pohlenz, Die Stoa I I16-118;
see section VII.)
"6 " It was not likely," says D.L. VII.85 (with von Arnim's additi
"that nature would estrange (&XAoTpcZcoa&) an animal from it
once it had made the animal, it [nature] would neither estrange it
dear tonot
would itself (olKEL7OaL)."
be oikeiosis, givenThe point
that must
nature be that
operates byit is not(see
design lik
assumption which D.L.'s source is taking as established already.
'6 Perhaps the point is strengthened by the phrase qua inventa selec
although difficulties plaguing the sentence in which it occurs make
weight on it inadvisable. (I assume that Madvig and subsequent
been right to read qua here for the more widely attested quae, but e
be questioned if the text were supposed to be more deeply cor
appears - not an impossibility.) If inventa alludes to a process
aware of, then it may be being claimed here already that one's ne
the principle of selection and rejection, which one formerly follo
impulse, helps lead to a later understanding of what is truly good
not be so if (as the anonymous reader points out and as Reid inter
instead means simply that the procedure has been arrived at or a
Fin. 1.23). Against this latter interpretation there is the following: w
c. I6 that the officia described in primum est officium ... contraria a
immediately from birth (cf. n.5i), so that it would be very odd t
principle of selection involved as arrived at or acquired. However
this word, severe problems remain. Some kind of selectio and reiec
But then something follows (sequitur), apparently described by t
officio selectio. But it would be very strange if this selectio were t
one just mentioned, which it seems to follow. But if it is differen
the difference? Its being in some sense cum officio whereas the o
But this hypothesis seems to conflict with the fact, just noted (and
the person has been performing at least certain officia all along.
unclear, and there seems to be confusion in the passage. Fortunat
the main point of the view of moral development is clear enough
poses without the evidence of this sentence.
" See the sentence of the De Nat. Deor. cited in n.78, along wit
and Plut. St. Rep. o154e-f (SVF II.550); Cic. De Nat. Deor. II
11.641).
TEXYKOv,
Deor. Oi flaGaov
11.57) through els y'EV
the words (D.L.
ignem esse VII.I56), rendered
artificiosum by Cicero
ad gignendum (De Nat.
progredientem
via; see also Cicero's remark just afterwards (11.58) that nature is artificiosa on
the ground that habet quasi viam quandam et sectam, and in particular Quintilian's
report that according to Cleanthes, ars est potestas viam, id est ordinem efficiens.
Also pertinent
concordia in Deare SVF
Fin. 1.72, 73
111.21); (cf. n.49),
11.413. 497 (d08K
See section VI. Ka Qov1dvws) - cf. ordo et
Nor can anyone judge truly of what is good and bad unless he knows
the whole plan of nature and also of the life of the gods, and whether or
not man's nature accords with nature in general.
virtutis est proprium, certe omnes virtutis compotes beati sunt. Et hoc quidem mihi
cum Bruto convenit, id est, cum Aristotele, Xenocrate, Speusippo, Polemone.
68 See in general the treatment of Pohlenz, Die Stoa I 191-207. On the debt
of the De Off. to him see II.6o, 111.7.
69 Cf. n.34.
70 On the matter of the duae naturae in Panaetius, see Rist, " The Innovations
of Panaetius," Stoic Philosophy (Cambridge 1969) 187-191.
T71 TO V KaTd& Ta& E oo.Lvas-g ~,ptV EK OaEWoS OOpptcs, Clem. Alex., Strom. II.xxi,
129, 4. On &aopLat here see Rist, 188-189.
72 ? -iqv &WPOiv-i-a -rciv rcicv Awv &OetLav Kati TLatV Kal aVYKa-raaKKEVa'?ovTa cu7IrV
KaTa To 8vva8rov, Clem. Alex. loc. cit.
7. See B. N. Tatakis, Panitius de Rhodes (Paris 1931) 163 ff with 164 n.2;
E. Br6hier, Chrysippe et l'ancien stoicisme (Paris 1910; 2nd ed. 1950) 225-226;
Rist 186-187.
74 Thus Rist, 200 and, in a rather different way, Pohlenz, e.g., Die Stoa I
204-205.
5 Ep. Mor. 121.3, 14 (though notice that the latter comes from the mout
of Seneca but of the interlocutor).
76 See, e.g., Diss. II.vi.14, I. xxviii.20-2I, III.i.24 i ff, though note tha
certain ways I.ix goes in a rather different direction, more like that of De Fi
7 Nor am I concerned with the, to my mind, quite different question wh
Stoics after Chrysippus began to adopt a more relaxed attitude toward th
called indifferents (see I. G. Kidd, "Stoic Intermediates and the End for M
Long, ed., Problems in Stoicism 150-172).
78 Neque enim dici potest in ulla rerum institutione non esse aliquid extr
atque perfectum, c. 35.
This passage registers the crucial turn taken by the Stoic account, but
only in the most cursory way. What it leaves unexplained and un-
answered is the Stoic contention that their theory of oikeiosis really does,
in the manner represented in III.20 ff, explain how a human being can
make the transition from the initial impulses implanted by nature to the
later attraction to virtue. As we saw in section IV, the Stoics think that
this transition is made via the appreciation of a certain pattern or order
in conduct, possibly consisting in the fact that following natural im-
pulses is conducive to survival. But the Stoic claim that the transition
is in some such way to be made intelligible is not confronted with any
directness by the anti-Stoic account of Book IV; and for the most part
the book simply expresses surprise at the Stoics for turning away from
the primary impulses (c. i9) and proceeds as though the Stoics had
never attempted to make clear even wherein they disagreed with
Polemo's story of moral development (c. 45)- So we must ask why it is
that Antiochus, or anyone else, could have given such meagre attention
to the ways in which the Stoic account differs from the one advanced
in Book V.
6s See cc. 32-39, esp. c. 37, and the opening sentence of the account in
c. I6.
87 See section IV.
VI
88 See esp.... Tale enim visum est ultimum Stoicorum . . ., which might simply
be Antiochus' interpretation, rather than a faithful report of Chrysippus' view.
89 IV.3, 14, 19.
9' Cic. De Nat. Deor. 11.58; AMt. Plac. 1.27.5 (= SVF I. 1.171, 176; see in general
on this idea in Zeno SVF 1.171-177); cf. n.59.
9' Adv. Math. IX.Io7 = SVF I.IIo. Likewise, the KdO'cLOs is 1 upbvXO0 and
voEpds (IX.Io4 = SVF I.iii, and in general SVF 1.109-I14).
96 Thus, e.g., SVF II.1oo9 (AMtius Plac. 1.6), 1027 (1.7, 33) with D.L. VII.i56
and De Nat. Deor. II passim, with n.59.
97 "Kleanthes' Zeushymnus," Hermes 75 (194o) 117-123, esp. 119-12o. See
also Cleanthes' hymn (SVF 1.537) esp. 11. 2, 7-8, 12, 24, and Clem. Strom. V.8,
48 (SVF 1.502), which says that the sun otov irA'4caawv rv KdOaLOV ELS EVapPLOVLOV
ropdaEv yet (cf. the concordia of De Fin. 111.21).
98 SVF 1.262, 263. Cf. also Stob. II, Io3, 24 ff, I50, 5-10o, on the unsociability
of the OaOAos, and above n.6I.
TO7LOVTV T77V POXrjv EXELV, El V LEAOPLEV OdpO L CO pEVrP tv 7rpl yaO?y V KCO KKaKWV,
It is impossible to find another source of justice or source of its develop-
ment than the one coming from Zeus and the common nature; for it is
thence that everything of this sort must have its source, if we are to speak
rightly about what is good and what is bad,
nor is there any more proper road by which to arrive at the account of
what is good and what is bad, nor at the virtues nor at happiness, than
the one which leads from the common nature and the arrangement of the
universe.
These remarks occur in a passage aiming to show how crucial for ethics
Chrysippus regarded the fact that "the universe is unified and finite
and is held together by a single power (rod avvEXeaeL dO c t8vvCdXLE 7rv
KOrLOV EMV TV7X Kal rTErTEpaUCLrVOv). That the bearing of this idea upon
ethics should not have been linked to the doctrine of oikeiosis is most
implausible.
Notice several things that I am not saying. I am not saying that
everything in De Finibus III is derived from Chrysippus. After all, the
book contains references to more recent authors. Nor am I attempting
to say who or what was the chief source of the book.99 Nor, further, am
99 Many attempts have been made to trace it, and candidates range from
Chrysippus down through Diogenes of Babylon and Antipater of Tarsus to
Hecato. See esp. Madvig 827-831 ; R. Hirzel, Untersuchungen zu Ciceros philo-
sophischen Schriften I-III (Leipzig 1877-83) esp. II, 2, I; M. Schiifer, Ein
friihmittelstoisches System der Ethik bei Cicero (Munich 1934); von Arnim, SVF,
I xxviii-xxix. On the view that the source is a doxographical one, see von
Arnim, ibid., and Philippson, review of Schilfer, Philologische Wochenschrift
(1936) 593-6o6. My thesis is fully compatible with saying that the overlay of
views and terminology later than those of Chrysippus is considerable. For
example (as Soreth points out to me) it is entirely possible - though not, I
think, certain - that the phrase ad extremum constans selectio has come from
the telos formulae of Diogenes of Babylonia and Antipater of Tarsus: see D.L.
especially so since terms like po'~vota, " v~owvca, auvortpa, Kdoos and
o og are repeated from one context to another, each being applied to
both cosmic and human matters. We have no explicit record that
Chrysippus included in his account of oikeiosis a stage like the one
described in De Fin. III.21, at which the developing human being
notices and is attracted by an order and harmony of conduct. But he
must have supposed that there was some point at which a person comes
to appreciate the cosmic perfection that he and Zeno believed in (on
Cleanthes see section VIII). It is not at all unlikely, therefore, that
there was a preliminary stage on the way to this appreciation of the
cosmic order such as De Fin. III.21 pictures. (Compare III.21 with
111.73: together they show that to notice the order and harmony of
conduct in the former is only to begin to understand the good, a com-
plete comprehension of which does not come without a knowledge of
the ratio naturae et vitae etiam deorum and of whether or not human
nature is in agreement with [conveniat; cf. convenientia for tpoAoylea in
c. 21] natura universa.) On the other hand perhaps the preliminary stage
was a post-Chrysippean invention designed to fill in the account of
development, which found its way into Cicero's hands. In either event,
the picture of development in De Fin. III is squarely in the tradition
of early Stoic views on the topic.
But before we accept this conclusion, we must reckon once again
VII.88; Stob. II 76, 9 (SVF III Diog. 45, 44); Clem. Alex. Strom. (Stiihlin)
II 183, 4-6 (SVF III Antip. 58); and Soreth, "Die zweite Telosformel des
Antipater von Tarsos," Archiv fiir Geschichte der Philosophie 50 (1968) 48-72.
VII
4&pErv (>-v
Chrysippus in reported
is also turn tohere
TO toKa7haveEprrTELpaV
expounded theT~WV d1JUEL
telos by the urvl~AwoVd ovrW v ,v).
(clearly fully equivalent) variant TO &KoAov'6o-w T 7- 0'etEL v, with the
added explanation (SVF 111.4):
O7TEP EaTL Ka-T ("E 77)V IV7TOV KM Kcz7-c 77)V TWV oAWV, OV..EV EVEpyOwVTaS CWv
cX7T(cyOp4vEELV4 ELO0EV Jvo/Lo0s KOLVOS,o O7"ITEP ETV 0P%9 A'yo9, St
Note in passing that this passage clearly corroborates our view of the
importance which Chrysippus attached to the idea of order and harmony
in his ethics.
Our other chief source on this matter, Stobaeus, presents a somewhat
different story, at least with regard to Zeno, and this is the story that
Pohlenz, along with probably most interpreters, accepts. At Ecl. II, 75,
11-76,1 (SVF 1.179), we have it that Zeno's telos was simply ir
d~oAoyovpE'vws (~7jv, explained as (the explanation fairly clearly purports
to be Zeno's or fully in his spirit) KicO' vcx hdyAov K(czt v'p)ovov ?v, Cas
7tV CVXOLWEVC S wvwOv KCKO8cZLtOVOrVTWv. We are then told that subse-
quent figures, rrpoc8&ap0poov-rEs, added the phrase -r7^ 0'EL, the first
such figure being Cleanthes, while Chrysippus then explained the en-
larged formula meaning (as in D.L.) (qv K(cz" EtLrELpuWV 7i-v VUrEL
vPflcwLVrVTWV.
Pohlenz, I have said, accepts this story. He accepts, that is, that
Zeno's explanation of the telos was simply dpoAoyovpE'vvws- v, without
i- r~ VEL (Die Stoa, II, I16-I 7), in the sense of "ein in sich einstim-
miges Leben." It is quickly apparent, however, that he believes not
only that this would for Zeno require a human being to live in accord
with his reason (logos),100 but also that although it does not appear in
his telos-formula, Zeno did stress the idea of the Kalzra OV pBloS, V mean-
ing by v';a here "die spezifische menschliche Natur."101
This belief rests upon a reading of the passage from Diogenes
Laertius that was advanced by Hirzel and continued by Pohlenz.102
For our purposes, the essential part of the argument rests on the pre-
ceding chapter, c. 96, where it is said that because in contrast to plants
and animals, logos is given to rois AOYLKO- Ka-r -EAeAELo-'pxV rpoU0aTrauv,
100 This is plausible enough, though one need not accept Pohlenz's claim here
that Zeno, because he was not a native speaker of Greek, would have had to
attend to the etymology of the word d'toAoyovCdvws and would have made some-
thing of the presence of the element -Aoy-.
101 Die Stoa II 117, 11. 24-26, 39-40, and "Zenon und Chrysipp," Nachr. von
der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu G6ttingen, Phil.-hist. KI., II, 9 (G6ttingen
1938) 173-2Io, esp. 199-202.
102 R. Hirzel, Untersuchungen, II. 10o5- 118; Pohlenz, "Zenon und Chrysipp"
(see n.Ioi).
VIII
it ought
tion to mean both that and human nature (181wo riv avOpworrvv, c. 89; cf. se
VIII).
Such are the difficulties which arise on the reading of Hirzel and Pohlen
In fact, matters are much more straightforward and comprehensible.
wellansuspect
by that heofbelieved
understanding that the
the structure andend ofof4t'oAoyovp'vo
order ,iv is aided
the whole universe,
and perhaps by an understanding of how that orderliness and harmony
can be introduced into the soul.e This understanding would no doubt
require an understanding of human nature, and particularly of human
psychology. Whether Zeno to this end employed a theory of oikeiosis
we cannot be sure (cf. section VI).
If Cleanthes really made the innovation in the telos-formula that
Stobaeus attributes to him, then he made a very important change
indeed. The ultimate end was no longer, as for Zeno, to live without
internal conflict, but rather to live in accordance with the organized
nature of the universe of which Zeno had already spoken. That is, an
understanding of that organization is no longer thought of as a means
to the end of some sort of harmony within one's own life. Rather, the
ultimate end is thought of as the fitting of oneself somehow into that
larger plan. It is not reported to us why Cleanthes adopted this view,
and I shall refrain from speculating on the reasons here. What is im-
portant for our present purposes is that the testimony concerning
Cleanthes furnishes no support for the idea that the beginnings of Stoic
thought were characterized by any sort of exclusive concern with human
nature, as opposed to the nature of the whole, organized universe.107
106 This is not to say that Zeno need himself have carried out any very exten-
sive investigations or even conjectures into what exactly the structure of the
universe is, and it can perfectly well be that thoroughgoing work on physics
had to await Cleanthes or subsequent figures.
107 We do not know whether Cleanthes meant actively to deny that the telos
is to live in accordance with some kind of specifically human nature. He may
have meant to do so; for one might take certain lines of his Hymn to Zeus
(SVF 1.537), such as 11. 17, 20-21, 26 ff, to be suggesting that there are bad
features of human nature that can come into conflict with the plan of nature as
a whole, and that when this happens the right course is to follow the latter.
108 He did not merely say, that is, that the two are compatible with each other.
This point is clear from the fact that rd Kar' aO'E7'V 7V is said to be Laov ... 74W
Ka7 CIrLTELpLav 7roV ~OEL uavflaLVOdPTv w l v (87), and that the desired ECipoLa flov
occurs when one's own 8al'pwv is in avI, wvla with q 70 o TOv JAOwv 8LOLKq)OIO floAV'aLg.
See also Galen, Plac. Hipp. et Plat. 450-451 (Muller; SVF III.12), which, as
Soreth points out to me, shows that Posidonius too believed that Chrysippus'
telos formula was equivalent to the formula d'Looyovgvw~s (v.
(Leipzig 1904) esp. 198 ff, 203 ff. In spite of the existence of this diverg
tradition, Pohlenz's account has raised, on the relevant counts, little objectio
It is followed by P. M. Valente, L'dthique stoicienne chez Ciciron (Paris 19
ioo, iio, and also, with respect to oikeiosis and De Fin. III.20-2i, by Lo
Hellenistic Philosophy 188 (though on pp. 179-184 Long seems to me mu
closer to the truth). One recent writer following the correct tradition is
Reiner, "Die ethische Weisheit der Stoiker heute," Gymnasium 76 (1969) 3
357, esp. 353-354.
112 Chrysippus' role, therefore, turns out to be virtually the diame
opposite of what Pohlenz portrays it as being (see esp. "Zenon und Chr
199 ff). Chrysippus' reputation (perhaps in part deserved) as somethin
logic chopper, along with his apparent identification of 7rdTc with Kpl~Ls
ever precisely he meant by it- see, e.g., D.L. VII. i i = SVF III111.456),
apparently had the effect of convincing many commentators that he was no
anti-" humanistic." If he was so, however, he was not so in a sense tha
upon the present discussion.
113 E.g., E. N. 1o97b24 ff, esp. 34, II177b27-28, Io78a2-8.
UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN