Dilemmas, Dichotomies and Definitions:: Acousmatic Music and Its Precarious Situation in The Arts
Dilemmas, Dichotomies and Definitions:: Acousmatic Music and Its Precarious Situation in The Arts
Dilemmas, Dichotomies and Definitions:: Acousmatic Music and Its Precarious Situation in The Arts
Jonty Harrison
Professor of Composition and Electroacoustic Music; Director, Electroacoustic Music Studios & BEAST
University of Birmingham
Edgbaston
Birmingham B15 2TT
0121-414 5787
[email protected]
http://www.bham.ac.uk/music/ea-studios/ (http://www.beastmusic.co.uk)
http://www.compassmusic.co.uk
http://www.bham.ac.uk/music
Abstract
For just about everybody but its practitioners, acousmatic music seems to have an identity crisis. Is it, for example,
‘music’ at all? In their heart of hearts, many professional musicians do not really think so. Yet could we not argue
that, as music is an art form based on sound, then acousmatic music – which exists only as sound, with no score to
be interpreted by performers – must be music in its purest form?
Perhaps the problem is simply one of language. In its normal English usage, the adjective ‘acousmatic’ requires a
noun. As that noun is normally ‘music’, we run the risk of offending both those with a more traditional view of what
constitutes music, and practitioners who may use similar tools and techniques, but whose work is more readily
situated in the ‘art world’. Most ‘sound art’ (to use the increasingly popular term) does not have a musical intent and
it is certainly not all acousmatic, any more than most music is.
But this is merely the first of many problems surrounding acousmatics (to use the more neutral term found in
anglophone Quebec, presumably taken from the French use of l’acousmatique as a noun) – problems which make
the field a quagmire of confusing terminology and consequent misunderstanding. One might be tempted to argue
that such things are unimportant as they are only labels – but (as we all know to our cost from searching for a
particular album in the wrong section of the Virgin Megastore, or trying to work out what the local council has
decided to call the refuse collection service this week so that we can look them up in the phone book), labels are
important because they grant or deny access to information and understanding.
This paper begins by re-examining some of the terminology of acousmatic music, with the aim of clarifying some of
the underlying thinking and principles associated with it, and so revealing and reiterating its significance. Of
fundamental importance in this discussion is the whole question of sound material, its nature and how it can be
manipulated and transformed directly into a sounding artwork, without the mediation of notation or performers.
Inevitably, techniques and tools need to be discussed, along with the delicate question of the relationship between
art/music and technology (unfortunately, they are often confused, especially within education). Traditional
approaches to music will not escape scrutiny, nor will matters pertaining to performance (and performers!),
perception and the distinctions between hearing and listening. Without venturing too far into metaphysics, the
discussion also engages with matters of time (one of music’s dominant structuring strategies) and space (one of
art’s), for it is here that boundaries really are being blurred. Finally, the current and potential relationships between
acousmatic music and other art forms are explored, with particular emphasis on collaboration, hybridisation and the
issue of whether digital representation of material (visual, aural or of any other persuasion) renders all material
essentially ‘the same’. In the course of addressing these issues, I hope to shed light on a question which has puzzled
me for many years: why is acousmatic music so frequently dismissed (particularly, though probably not exclusively,
by the ‘music world’) as being ‘irrelevant’, ‘old hat’ and, most perplexing of all, ‘academic’?
Is anybody listening?
During 30 years’ involvement with acousmatic music, one of the most significant things I have
learned about it is that, for most people, it seems to have an identity crisis. Although
practitioners and aficionados have no difficulty in grasping what it is, understand its concerns,
techniques and rationales, and can situate it within practice in ‘the arts’, it seems to have a ‘bad
press’ (well, in fact, virtually no press!) when it comes to attracting the public to an acousmatic
event in any given location (except, perhaps, Paris or Montreal). If a promoter is offered a
concert of acousmatic music, or if an arts funding body is asked to finance such an event, it
seems to be a case of quizzical looks all round: ‘acousmatic music – what’s that?’ In one sense,
one might suppose it doesn’t really matter. There are enough people worldwide who do want to
listen to acousmatic music to make it worthwhile for composers to continue to create it. My
involvement with people who are exposed (often by accident!) to this medium, however,
suggests to me that potential local audiences are much bigger than we (and promoters and
funders) might suppose. So, if there is a problem ‘out there’, then it is probably in our interests
to identify what it is.
There is another issue which is less ‘out there’ than the question of public profile, however,
which is linked to the perception of acousmatic music, and this is even more confusing. For
reasons I have never really been able to fathom, there is a popular myth that acousmatic music is
‘academic’ (even this conference, in listing the subject areas of papers, included the phrase
‘academic acousmatic music’). This implies to me that one can assume that there is,
automatically, an audience in ‘the academy’. I have not found this to be so and would take issue
with attempts to make ‘academic’ and ‘acousmatic’ synonymous. The linking of the two words
seems to play on the pejorative implications of ‘academic’ – hidebound by tradition,
conservative, stagnant, ossified, governed by rules, formulaic, elitist, etc. I do not want to
become embroiled in a wholesale defence of academia, but for reasons which I hope will
become clear, I have to say that I do not recognise acousmatic music as having any of these
characteristics. If the linking of the words is merely because, at one stage in its history, it
required resources beyond the financial means of individual composers, then I can at least
understand the point historically. This situation led to the nurturing of acousmatic music within
British universities and by radio stations in mainland Europe. However, those days are long gone
– and we don’t talk about ‘radio station acousmatic music’!
It is evident that any attempt to find the reasons for acousmatic music’s relative lack of profile is
fraught with difficulties. Acousmatic music is sometimes barely recognised as ‘music’ at all,
even among trained musicians, including several whose attitude is distinctly hostile. I might go
further and point out that this latter group includes many academics in the discipline of music.
The situation is further complicated by the fact that, although ‘acousmatic music’ may well be
shunned by ‘musicians’, it may, ironically, have many characteristics which would be
recognised by practitioners and aficionados from other fields – let’s say, for the sake of
argument, the ‘art world’. The problem (well, a problem for me at least) is that they probably
would not call it music either.
As you have probably guessed by now, I am a musician; worse, I am a composer; worse still, I
am a composer of acousmatic music. I am going to be bold and presume that the reason I am
standing here today is precisely because I am a composer of acousmatic music and not because I
also happen to be an academic. So this accidental academic is going to play the role of a keynote
speaker wearing his true colours as an unashamed composer of acousmatic music, and assume
the right to be forthright and outspoken (or blunt and bigoted, if you prefer) about my theme. I
shall be unapologetically critical of some approaches and practices whilst being fiercely
protective and partisan about others, paying little heed to what might be thought of as ‘normal
academic balance’. I shall state the obvious, on the assumption that some of the underlying
thinking concerning acousmatic music may not be familiar to everyone (or may even have been
forgotten by some!). I shall present acousmatic music (which, at under 60 years old, I believe
still qualifies as a ‘young’ art), as a striking new trend (and the lack of awareness of it in many
quarters suggests that it is still ‘news’ and that its impact is certainly not yet exhausted). I shall
also challenge some accepted positions and I fully expect that some of what I say may be
construed as provocative – and it may even rustle a few feathers.
The time has come to return to our initial starting point – the idea that acousmatic music seems
to have an identity crisis. Why should this be so and what are the root causes? As I have said,
among those who have active experience of this field, there is no such crisis. So is the problem
simply that insufficient numbers of people know about acousmatic music (and, if so, what is the
reason)? Or is there something fundamentally ‘wrong’ with acousmatic music which would
explain its low public profile (and, if so, what is this fatal flaw)? And beyond these questions
lurks another: what (if anything) should be done to rectify the situation?
Of course, it is entirely possible that the problem is simply one of language: people are not
familiar with ‘acousmatic music’ because they are not familiar with the label. This explanation
has some merit, though its corollary suggests that they may still have some knowledge of the
actual music – an optimistic view, I think! People may well have heard music from or related to
this field, but it is likely that this will have been in other contexts – in a film, perhaps, or with
contemporary dance. However, it remains the case that many of the dilemmas and dichotomies
surrounding our primary question may be caused by confusion over terminology, so it is to this
that we must now turn our attention.
Definitions
• Acousmatic
Any attempt at getting to the bottom of the perceived problem of acousmatic music must start
with a definition of ‘acousmatic’ itself. The word derives from the practice of disciples of
Pythagoras who listened to the master lecture from behind a curtain, so that they could focus
aurally on the content of his lecture without visual distractions. Thus, in its most basic form, the
adjective ‘acousmatic’ describes the reception of aural information where the source or cause of
the sound is not seen. It came into use in a musical context in relation to the musique concrète of
Pierre Schaeffer and has been emphasised by composers such as François Bayle and Francis
Dhomont. In practical terms, we can say that the term refers to music specifically composed and
designed to be heard over loudspeakers (though the loudspeakers are not the things which
caused the sounds in the first place). Typically, such music can incorporate sound material and
processes highly unlikely to be capable of being physically present at the time of reception. Of
course, a listening situation could also be ‘acousmatic’, even when what is actually heard was
not originally created for that kind of reception.
‘... the concrete (pure sound matter) and proceeds towards the abstract (musical structures) –
hence the name musique concrète – in reverse of what takes place in instrumental writing,
where one starts with concepts (abstract) and ends with a performance (concrete)’ [Dhomont,
1995; 1996].
• Musique concrète
Musique concrète, then, is so called because it starts from ‘concrete’ (i.e. observable) qualities in
sound material itself, from which structural implications are extrapolated and links to other
sound materials made. What finally emerges, as Dhomont has pointed out, is an ‘abstract’
musical discourse (in the sense that all musical discourse can be deemed to have an abstract
dimension, given that music is essentially ephemeral and truly exists only at the time of being
heard) which has been ‘abstracted’ from the concrete starting points. Simon Emmerson discusses
the distinction between abstract and abstracted materials [Emmerson, 1986] (though it is worth
noting that French makes a less clear distinction between the two English terms, the word
abstrait serving as both adjective and past participle). In the early days, the sound material in
question was recorded and this has led to a tendency (especially in English) to equate musique
concrète with ‘music made using recordings of real sounds’, which is only a partial truth. As
well as its starting point in concrete (i.e. existing) material, a further aspect of what is ‘concrete’
about musique concrète is the method of working: it is ‘hands-on’, with immediate aural
feedback. Its composition is a partnership between composer and material, with each
interrogating the other, posing problems and offering possible solutions. The success or failure
of sound material and its transformations in specific musical contexts is assessed by ear, by the
composer as first listener (but also representative of other listeners with similar ear/brain
mechanisms – i.e. other human beings). Through this process of interaction between equal
parties a final structure emerges.
• Elektronische Musik
I would argue that, in contrast to musique concrète, which is primarily concerned with qualities
of sound material, much music has been, and continues to be, more concerned with quantities.
This is to some extent inevitable when, as Dhomont says, ‘one starts with concepts’ – in order to
flesh out concepts in sound, one has to be able to ‘measure’ how much to put where and for how
long. Intervals between pitches and the durational structure of rhythm are quantitative devices,
capable of precise differentiation through musical notation; other parameters, like dynamics,
though less precise, are also amenable to structuring in similar ways. The Cologne school of
elektronische Musik was primarily driven by serialism (which was, in turn, a continuation of
what Trevor Wishart calls lattice-based thinking [Wishart, 1985; 1996]), and exploited the
ability of the electronic medium to deliver precise values of serialised dynamic and durational
structure (which by the late 50s were beginning to exceed the abilities of even the most
dedicated performers). The focus on the use of electronically generated signals such as sine
tones was a result of the theoretical possibility of also subjecting the parameter of timbre to
serial organisation (something impossible with acoustic instruments) and also afforded the
history books a handy contrast with musique concrète. Yet another parameter for serial control,
spatial location, emerged with the playback of discrete audio tracks on the recording machines
over separate loudspeakers.
• Electroacoustic music
This problematic term is an attempt to cover over the rift between the two schools of musique
concrète and elektronische Musik. According to the history books, the antagonism between the
two began to be eroded with the incorporation of sound recordings in several of Stockhausen’s
‘tape’ pieces, from Gesang der Jünglinge (1956) onwards, and the installation of synthesis
modules in the studios of the Groupe de Recherches Musicales in Paris (into which Schaeffer’s
original research group evolved), which feature strongly in major works of Bayle, Parmegiani
and others. Despite this convenient simplification, however, the vestiges of the differences in
thinking between the two schools still continue to trouble the field today, with much ‘computer
music’ (to use yet another label) continuing the structure-dominated thinking of elektronische
Musik and the work of Schaeffer and his followers struggling for recognition outside the French-
speaking world.
• L’objet sonore
Key to an understanding of the entire field and underpinning the whole existence of any of this
music is the rather important matter of sound recording – the single most significant
development in and for music during the twentieth century (far more important than abandoning
tonality, for instance). Sound recording and storage enabled immediate access to sound material,
for repeated aural scrutiny, and this in turn revealed that ‘the same’ notated events do not result
in identical sonic events, even though notation implies that they do. Let me expand on this for a
moment. Record a violinist playing a notated musical event twice and listen carefully. The two
recordings will have differing characteristics of attack, tone, intonation, nuance, dynamic,
length, etc. The two events are quite distinct, so we might conclude that their notated
equivalence, the very basis of instrumental music (and of its analysis!), is no longer tenable. This
led Schaeffer to his formulation of the notion of the objet sonore (frequently translated into
English as ‘sound object’, though possibly better rendered by the term ‘sonic object’) – a unique
gestalt stored on a fixed (recording/storage) medium, with observable qualities and
characteristics in terms of time-varying spectral/frequency, fluctuating amplitude, erratic density
and spatial behaviour content, but which is not to be (and, in fact cannot easily be) reduced to
repeatable static values in the parameters of pitch, duration, amplitude, etc) – the very basis of
serialism.
• Reduced listening
Another Schaefferian term and a further extension of his theories was the notion of écoute
réduite (reduced listening) – the importance of detaching the sound as heard (the sonic object)
from the sound-producing source, the physical object which generated the sound. In other words,
it is important to hear the violin events we just discussed in terms of their specific, individual
and unique sonic qualities (sound as sound) and not in terms of their ‘violin-ness’ (sound as
representation of source). Schaeffer was critical of his own early works, such as the Etude aux
chemins de fer (1948), precisely because the sound material was too recognisable, too
reminiscent of the physical objects which produced them, and he felt that this ‘referential’
quality interfered with a truly ‘musical’ appreciation of the material. Nevertheless, from Luc
Ferrari onward, there was a compositional exploitation of the fact that there can be signification
(i.e. meaning) resulting from our recognition of the source/cause of sound material. The fact is
(if I may be so bold as to say so) that Schaeffer missed a trick here – it seems to me and to many,
many composers of acousmatic music to this day, that the intermingling of abstract(ed) musical
structures and source sounds which can suddenly reveal themselves in their unashamed
naturalness is one of the most powerful expressive attributes of the medium.
I mentioned sound recording and storage as being crucial, as the technology has implications
well beyond the mere documentation and re-creation of existing performances (its original
‘design brief’). It offers entirely new possibilities which were simply not available before; and
this can only have the most profound impact on creativity itself.
It is worth reminding ourselves of what these new possibilities offered by sound storage were
and how they enhanced – and, indeed, changed – music in the second half of the last century.
Much of what I am about to say here refers to discoveries made by Schaeffer and his fellow-
researchers at what became the Groupe de Recherches Musicales in Paris. I make no apologies
for this, for my own experience echoed theirs (though with less rigour!). Moreover, the
importance of the early years in Paris has left a legacy of thinking with which I and many other
composers continue to engage, but which has, strangely, not travelled as widely as one might
have expected, despite its significance.
We have already discussed the often forgotten aspect of sound storage – that it gives us
immediate access to sound and to infinite repetitions These features enable us to interact with
sound material in an almost physical way, sculpting it and working directly with sound to create
music without having to go via the symbolic, silent, abstract medium of notation.
Perhaps even more obviously, sound storage meant that any sound that could be captured was
potentially available for inclusion in ‘music’; composers were no longer restricted to sound
material traditionally defined as ‘musical’. The expansion of sound material made available to
music through recording thus extends to what we might call ‘everyday’ sounds: environmental
and anecdotal sound materials, which are capable of evoking specific times and places in the
personal histories of individual listeners. This area is a strong characteristic of early musique
concrète and of acousmatic music, but it must be acknowledged that it is probably a source of
immense irritation for many musicians of a ‘traditional’ bent and might explain the antagonism
towards the medium from that quarter. For me, though, one of the exciting things about the
acousmatic domain is that the poetic of ‘music’ is enlarged by being able to include, for
example, the sound of a cuckoo, whilst Beethoven had to be content with imitating one with a
clarinet!
Sound Transformation
Another major impact of sound storage on the domain of music is that it facilitates the
manipulation, modification and transformation of sound. The basic principle is that changing the
playback conditions or altering the data prior to playback changes the sound. What was
particularly interesting for music, especially in the early days of the electroacoustic medium, was
that stored sound could be manipulated beyond the physical constraints which limited what was
possible in the ‘real world’ or in ‘real time’ and this is arguably still true today.
The early techniques of sound transformation were somewhat limited, being restricted to simple
operations like speed change (transposition), reverse direction, looping (by scratching across the
wall separating the grooves on a record in the days before analogue tape), and so on. More
sophisticated and elaborate processes developed after the shift to magnetic tape and through the
impact of electronic circuitry, and soon there were many means of modifying and transforming
sound, including filtering and equalisation in the frequency domain, reverberation, delay and
echo effects in the time domain, and compression, expansion and limiting in the amplitude
domain. With the advent of analogue synthesisers, other techniques became available, such as
ring modulation, envelope shaping and the whole range of voltage control options – all of which
could also be applied to recorded ‘real world’ sounds. A quantum leap forward followed the
application of digital technology to sound and it is now possible to perform operations on the
microscopic level of sound material’s internal structure – phase vocoding, time-stretching,
brassage, convolution, cross-filtering, freezing, frequency warping, frequency shifting,
granulation, etc, etc – which were all but unthinkable at the start of my career. In fact, I can now
perform all of these things on this laptop for a fraction of the price of even the most basic studio
two decades ago – and I can carry it around with me!
Of course, it is all too easy to get carried away with the potential of the tools themselves and lose
sight of the original goal – to make music. I deliberately omitted one of the most musically
profound sound transformations from my list, but I want to mention it now because it is at once
the most simple and the most drastic thing one can do to a sound. I am talking about cutting the
sound. The interruption of normal expectations regarding the flow of time is probably the most
extreme characteristic of music and it seems to be perfectly encapsulated in the possibility of
cutting a sound so that its onset or its continuation are removed. This brings me to a crucial area
of discussion: time itself. But before I launch into that I thought it might be a good idea to give
everyone a bit of a rest from the sound of my voice and play some music. Actually what I want
to do is to draw your attention to some of the things I have been discussing in theoretical terms
at work in practice by playing some examples from my piece Unsound Objects, which you will
have the opportunity to hear in its 13 minute entirety at the concert this lunchtime.
So now we come to something which brings this paper closer to the general theme of this
conference. All my remarks thus far have referred to ‘acousmatic music’. Here, then, is the next
problem for today: the m-word.
I do not actually want to get too embroiled in this question, because with such a range of people
and interests as we have here, I doubt we would ever reach agreement. Everyone I meet, in
whatever circumstances, has a stake in music. Everyone ‘owns’ music, and so has a view on
what it is and what it is not. However, we might consider a fundamental definition of music
along the lines once proposed by Edgard Varèse: the organisation of sound in time.
Much of what I have already said has revolved around the question of sound, and the difference
in attitudes or approaches to its organisation is what makes musique concrète and acousmatic
music distinct from most instrumental music, and also from elektronische Musik. We have yet to
consider the other component in Varèse’s definition: time; and I think that perhaps we might
broaden the discussion to embrace another aspect which has a kind of inverse relationship to it:
space. Time is one of music’s dominant characteristics and structuring strategies; space is one of
art’s. And it is here that boundaries really are being blurred.
Time is what makes music out of sound. In my view, it is possible to have sound without music
but you cannot have music without sound (and I don’t think I’m misreading Cage on this!).
‘Music’ happens when sounds establish (either by happenstance or through the intervention of a
performer, improviser, artist or ‘composer’) relationships in time between each other which
make some kind of sense – i.e. they ‘communicate’ (to use a dangerous word, for it raises the
question of whether music is a ‘language’ in any objective sense) ‘meaning’ (an even more
dangerous word!). This is not to say that music is only about structure – if this were true, integral
serialism might well be our musical lingua franca. Qualitative aspects of the sound material also
come into play. Human beings tend to like to establish that something is ‘beautiful’ in and of
itself as well as discerning beauty in the relationships between things. However, if a piece of
music is based only on the structural relationships between events which in themselves are of no
intrinsic interest, it tends dangerously towards the barren; conversely, if a piece is concerned
only with surface beauty, with little heed paid to structural aspects, then repeated playings will
soon render the listener tired and ultimately dissatisfied. And in case anyone is thinking that I am
still stuck in the nineteenth century, let alone the twentieth, let me clarify that in making these
comments I make no distinction between composed music, free improvisation (with instruments,
laptops or any other means) or simply the potentially musical experience of walking down the
street – all are equally amenable to the interpretation or testing processes I am describing.
My emphasis of the time axis in all this is, it seems to me, a crucial distinction between whether
we perceive sonic events as music or as something else, such as ‘sound art’. It seems fairly clear
and uncontentious to assert that time plays a major part in musical communication, in musical
structure (naturally occurring or imposed by human intervention) and in understanding an event
as ‘musical’. In much sound art, by contrast, we might cite space as the central reality of our
understanding. In many sound installation works, for example, the sound material might be
continuously present – possibly even on a loop – and the assumption is that listeners/viewers
will experience different aspects of the piece as a function of moving their location, and as a
function of when they entered the installation and how long they stay. Of course, ‘time’ thus also
comes into the equation, for one cannot be in more than one location at once, but my point is that
the time axis is incidental rather than fundamental – an inversion or reversal of their respective
priorities in music. This is not to say that the incidental parameter is not important (‘incidental’
is not the same as saying ‘of no significance’). In acousmatic music, spatial characteristics have
played an increased role in establishing the nature and definition of sonic objects and their
structuring, and the practice of sound diffusion is based, at least in part, on controlling the spatial
behaviour of sound material. But the fact that we can listen to an acousmatic work on CD as well
as in diffusion over n channels suggests that some crucial aspects of the music, including spatial
information, are still present.
To underline some of what I have been saying here about the differences between sound art and
music, I would like to mention a discussion I had with Bill Fontana a little over two years ago, at
the start of his residency in the Birmingham Music Department (yes, the Music Department,
where he is an Honorary Senior Research Fellow). While walking around Birmingham to find
interesting locations for a project, he attached an accelerometer (a sensor used in stress testing
which is, in effect, a high quality contact microphone) on the metal hinge of a canal lock gate.
The delicate sound of tricking water, filtered by the wood and metal of the physical structure of
the gate was enchanting. I commented that I could imagine all kinds of ways of using,
transforming and incorporating it in a piece (of music). Bill laughed and said something along
the lines of ‘Well, that’s the difference between you and me, Jonty. I just let them be and don’t
intervene or tinker with them!’ At that moment I understood why Bill says that he used to be a
composer! His work is frequently based on the idea of ‘discovering’ environmental sounds in
what we might call ‘dislocation’ – i.e. in a place you would not normally expect to find them.
For instance his recent work at the Tate Modern involved the internal sound world of
Millennium Bridge (captured via accelerometers, once again) ‘transported’ into the Turbine Hall
(and also into a nearby Underground station).
So now I have said it. Music and sound art are not synonymous. Music may be sound art but, by
my definitions, sound art is not music. Of course, it probably does not matter anyway but,
having been rejected from some quarters of ‘music’, acousmatic music is now in danger of being
subsumed by a ‘sound art’ agenda which is motivated by completely different concerns. I am not
objecting to the existence of this parallel world. I do, however, have some concerns about
agencies who say they want to help BEAST develop, when it transpires that what this means is
not that they want to help BEAST in its core activity of presenting acousmatic music to the
public at the highest possible standard, but for BEAST to work in ‘new’ fields – to take on, in
fact, a supporting role for other arts and inter-media work – a fundamental contradiction of
BEAST’s acousmatic raison d’être.
Acousmatic Music and Performance
Sound diffusion is the practice of distributing acousmatic works (predominantly stereo, but
increasingly in a bewildering array of multi-channel formats) over a large number of
loudspeakers. The rationale for this is that the historical storage media of tape or even CD cannot
adequately encode the dynamic range expected by the ear, nor can carefully composed spatial
detail necessarily be heard everywhere in a large public space. Diffusion addresses these
problems by means of a performer who exaggerates the dynamic range and the spatial gestures
on the storage medium by dynamically redistributing the original sound image, manually and in
real time, over multiple loudspeakers positioned around the space; the aim is to reinstate spatial
detail and reinvigorate the dramatic impact of the music.
I am sometimes criticised for setting out seats for BEAST events which all face in one direction.
The justification for this is that maximising what is heard by a large number of people is best
achieved if they all face the same way, as our ears are best at detecting spatial detail in front of
us and curving round to the sides. This physiological fact is disregarded by people who advocate
lying on the floor to listen, or allowing people to wander around or to come in and out at will. I
don’t have a problem with those modes of presentation, but they require different music or
sound material, which is not as dependent on that type of spatial articulation. Another criticism I
hear quite regularly is that there is nothing to look at (well, this is acousmatic music that’s being
played), though this could just as easily be code for the disorientation people sometimes
experience when they hear unfamiliar sounds to which they cannot ascribe a cause. There is also
the troubling fact that if a visual stimulus is also present, aural attentiveness tends to suffer.
The criticisms of diffusion events to which I just referred are usually based on the assumption
that acousmatic composers and diffusion performers are perpetuating an outmoded
presentational paradigm – the ‘concert’. This is often unfavourably compared to the trend
towards laptop performances in recent years. Many of my students are involved in this area of
work and I have even been known to try it for myself (if you buy me a pint later, I’ll even reveal
my dreadful stage name!). At its best, this is a perfectly valid practice with which I have no
quibbles. I do, however, object to this particular performance mode being exalted above all
others within the sonic arts scene, especially if it is on the spurious grounds that diffusion
concerts are, by contrast, inherently old-fashioned. I would argue that, on the contrary, it is the
laptop performance that is based on a truly traditional concert paradigm, with its focus on the
performer, often on a stage and in a spotlight. What is usually lacking, though, in laptop events
is the cause/effect relationship between human gesture and the resulting sound. Because the
computer is not immediately or intrinsically a physical tool or instrument (though I admit that it
can be programmed to be), there is no necessary causal relationship between what the
‘performer’ is seen to do and what is heard. For all the audience knows, the performer, hunched
over a laptop on stage, could be playing a CD while checking e-mails or downloading porn.
(Well, I did say I might ruffle a few feathers!)
Collaboration, diversification and hybridisation
Collaboration between practitioners from different art forms makes possible further expressive
and structural exploration – specifically the added underlining of important moments through
synchronisation of events (the time axis again!) and its ‘opposite’, the extension of contrapuntal
opportunities. Unfortunately, it is all too possible for works combining two or more art-forms to
rely too heavily on only one of these two extreme positions, resulting either in ‘Mickey-
Mousing’ in the first case or apparently random, unconnected cohabitation in the second. The
argument that, as human beings, we supply our own causality or connectivity in the latter case is
persuasive only up to a point, and is, for me at least, too unreliable and fragile a principle to use
as a basis for collaboration.
Though it is actually nothing new in itself, digital technology and ready access to programs
which enable the editing, mixing and sequencing of sound, images, video, graphics, etc has
increased the number of people now engaging in what I call diversification – the creation by a
single artist of ‘inter-’, ‘cross-’ or ‘multi-media’ works combining different identifiable art-
forms. There seem to me to be some potential dangers here, of which the main one is
dilettantism. Years of training, practice and knowledge- and experience-gathering go into the
formation (and I deliberately invoke the French sense of this word – i.e. education – as well as
the obvious English meaning) of a creative artist in whatever field. How is it possible that
someone can, effectively overnight, become an equally adept practitioner or expert in another
field, simply because some new software makes access easier? Even within a single cognate
discipline such as ‘music’, there is such a bewildering variety of skills that no one individual can
have them all to a high level. No-one here would, for example, thank me if I now tried to sing to
you or play the cello. I am even more confident in asserting that any attempts I might make at
visual art or poetry would be perceived by practitioners in those fields as precisely what they
would be: amateur dabbling. Yet we insist on deluding ourselves with the notion that, since the
invention of Final Cut Pro, we are all Fellini. If only it were so simple! Some composers have
tried this, of course – and some attempts are pretty good in my view (though I make this claim
purely on the basis that I like what I see and not from any real confidence in my own ability to
judge the other art-form) and some have won acclaim from the visual arts field to corroborate
my reaction; most are not good. As a musician, I cringe at what choreographers sometimes do to
music, stringing together, via bad edits, existing pieces of music without concern or even
awareness of the musical logic intrinsic to each one. I also find many instances of ‘sound art’
rather thin in musical terms, as the sonic and structural implications of the sound material itself
is not built into anything beyond its initial self. Of course, the counter-argument to this is that the
intention of the artist was not ‘musical’ in the first place, so my objections are invalid. As sound
is often the poor relation in the arts, however (remember the differing percentages of visual and
aural information which are processed by the brain when both are present), I feel that I must
fight for a corner of the arts patch for an art which is based purely on sound, in which listening is
the only activity and where there are no visual distractions to make our ears go walkabout for a
while – an art which is, in other words, acousmatic.
The third type of inter-art form creative activity might be called hybridisation. In this, what
emerges is actually a new art form. One might make a case here for some kinds of activities
combining elements of sound, musical performance and electronics (Cage’s Cartridge Music,
for instance) establishing something new, though I have already discussed the extent to which I
am convinced by such claims from some advocates of laptop performance.
The most dangerous tendency in this area, though, I consider to be the trendy perpetration of a
gross fiction. It has been claimed by many that, because we now live and work in a world where
all information is stored in digital form, this somehow standardises the information itself and
renders it all essentially ‘the same’). Try as I might, I cannot see the logic of this argument,
which is rather like saying that, because they are all stored in bottles, there is no essential
difference between a good Pauillac, sunflower oil or bleach.
Before finishing this presentation, I must return to my bête noire, the linking of ‘acousmatic’ and
‘academic’. Acousmatic music challenges the very basis of what most western academics
consider music to be. It does this, as Wishart has so eloquently pointed out, by bypassing
notation as the means of encoding, transmitting, storing and studying music. Yet if the study of
music in western academia is characterised by any single thing, it is surely the reliance on
notation as its primary tool and the thing by which music is analysed and ultimately judged –
what we might term the verification, ratification and authorisation of given pieces of music as
‘masterpieces’. How is it, then, that acousmatic music (which, as we have seen is properly a
term describing a listening condition and, by extension, an approach to organising sound
material in a way which takes account primarily of its characteristics as perceived on listening)
is so often characterised as ‘academic acousmatic music’? In what sense, precisely, is it
‘academic’?
Is it because some people involved in its creation happen to teach in universities and colleges? If
so, I believe the connection is spurious. Like me, many composers who teach in higher
education institutions in the UK and around the world are academics by accident rather than by
design. Is it because its creation was at one time only really feasible in an institutional setting,
when the resources necessary to produce it (multiple tape recorders, mixers, processing devices
and loudspeakers) were far beyond the financial means of individuals? Though this may have
been true at one time, the emergence of the personal computer has progressively undermined this
situation to the extent that, since 2003, I – and large numbers of other people – have been able to
do more extensive and more complex signal processing and mixing, and to a higher audio
quality, on laptop machines than was possible in any tape/analogue studio.
You may well be relieved to hear that I now propose to move towards summarising and
concluding this defence of acousmatics within an arts context in which its survival is by no
means guaranteed.
I have tried to establish that acousmatic music, descended from musique concrète is an art form
based on qualitative assessments of the observable attributes of sound material. The key to
structuring this material also lies in the characteristics of the material itself.
Sound material appropriate to acousmatic music can be drawn from any sounding source, though
any given source is no guarantee of good music – this is something to be established between
material and composer. The expanded sound world of acousmatic music can range widely
between ‘real-world’ and ‘abstract’ material, can incorporate referential, anecdotal and narrative
elements (without, however, any requirement to conform to verbal narrative conventions) and
can evoke, variously, ‘real’, ‘unreal’ and ‘surreal’ situations as well as more abstract musical
discourse (including within the same work and even concurrently).
Far from not being music, I would argue that, as music is an art form based on sound, then
acousmatic music – which exists only as sound, with no score to be interpreted by instrumental
or vocal performers – might be considered to be music in its purest form.
The performance paradigm of acousmatic music is specific to the needs of its public presentation
in consideration of the primary necessity to hear clearly what is being performed; any further
similarity with concert activity past or present is entirely coincidental.
Acousmatic music is insufficiently known for a number of reasons, including marketing (it is
difficult to find appropriate ‘images’ for advertising something with no visual content),
education (very few students arriving in university music departments have heard it or heard of
it) and cultural access within the English-speaking world (key texts, such as Schaeffer’s Traité
des objets musicaux have never been translated). In addition, the expanded poetic of the genre
and the problem of unfamiliar sounds without apparent causes may trouble those of a nervous
disposition.