Belonging Social Cohesion and Fundamental British Values
Belonging Social Cohesion and Fundamental British Values
Belonging Social Cohesion and Fundamental British Values
1. I NTRODUCTION
Much discussion in political and social philosophy over the past two decades has
centred on the widespread beliefs that modern, diverse societies are currently
failing to engender sufficient cohesion (both community and societal) to counter
the connected problems of social disorder, alienation, terrorism and fragmenta-
tion of belonging. These difficulties have their roots in many common political
issues across much of the western world: multiculturalism and integration of
minorities; the balance between the rights of individuals and communities;
worries about radicalisation or terrorism; the growth of independence movements
and the re-emergence of far-right political parties across the world.1 Faced by
such predicaments, governmental policy agendas struggle to reconceptualise
national identity, in the sense of what it is to ‘belong together’ at a time of
growing diversity and migration.
These problems have come to influence policy making across Europe, as well
as in the UK, where successive governments have attempted to promote cohesion
and integration (for example Bachtler and Mendez, 2016; Buonfino and
Thomson, 2007; Cantle, 2001; DCSF, 2007; Hooghe, 1996). In response to
terrorism and radicalisation anxieties within the UK (including concerns
ISSN 0007-1005 (print)/ISSN 1467-8527 (online)
© 2018 Society for Educational Studies
https://doi.org/10.1080/00071005.2018.1506091
http://www.tandfonline.com
424 BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES
emanating from the ‘Trojan horse’ schools in Birmingham), the former UK
Prime Minister, David Cameron, announced a new policy of the active promo-
tion of ‘fundamental British values’ (FBV) in schools.2 This came to be defined
as ‘the fundamental British values of democracy, the rule of law, individual
liberty and mutual respect and tolerance of those with different faiths and beliefs’
(DfE Nov 2014: 5). He justified the creation of this policy by claiming that some
form of value consensus was needed to unite us and build a ‘common home’.3 If
these values prove to be able to do this, they could potentially play a crucial role
in achieving important forms of social cohesion.
Whilst this paper focuses on a policy in the context of English liberal democ-
racy (education being one of the areas devolved to the regional parliaments), it has
a wider application by addressing issues relevant to the state education of citizens
elsewhere. Many of the debates emanating from this policy can be linked to
ongoing discussions in philosophical thinking: loyalty and loyalties; solidarity
and belonging; the structure and content of human values; the role of schools in
creating citizens. Nevertheless, the inherent theoretical problems arising from this
directive call into question the possibility of it achieving its stated goals, demon-
strating an urgent need for further significant philosophical work.
Starting from an outline of the policy in question and the need for social
cohesion, I then move into the main claims to be addressed in this paper: that there
are no good reasons to believe that this directive can create a deep sense of social
cohesion for three reasons. I then consider the first of these: that the directive has
an inadequate concept of belonging, a focus of one the major strands of research in
social cohesion. I suggest the addition of ‘perceived belonging’ needed for an
adequate understanding of social cohesion. After this, I turn to the second of the
three reasons: that the current lack of attention to the concept being used then leads
to a misunderstanding of the precise content (the values) needed to support social
cohesion. Next, I address the third reason: that the method of enactment (actively
promoting) lacks sufficient clarity about action with a corresponding ambiguity as
to how this might be translated into school practice. Finally, I argue that to reach
the desired end-goal of social cohesion requires more philosophical attention to be
paid to the way in which citizens might belong together.
based on the need to build a nation in which all groups are both included and to
which they feel attached, enabling them to act as one and/or to create a common
future together (Healy 2013). In other words, social cohesion creates a model for
how to think about belonging at a macro level (Dobbernack, 2010).
The need to belong is thought to have an evolutionary basis: when some are
in groups, it makes sense for survival purposes to belong to a group oneself –
particularly one comprising of familiar, cooperative people. An unspoken ‘inter-
nal mechanism’ orientates a sense of belonging and marks the commitment to
support those ‘like us’ in significant ways (Baumeister and Leary, 1995). Some
theorists attest that this can be achieved via some form of shared national
identity. In many such arguments, this is needed as a prerequisite to create the
background for stability, support for toleration or a shared sense of ‘the common
good’ needed to shape the social world (for example Barry, 1983; Miller, 1998).
Discourses in favour of ‘British Values’ could then be understood as a form of
political ‘rallying cry’: that those who share the same values will be loyal to the
source of these values and refrain from extremism, violence and disloyalty.
Needless to say, others claim that a purely civic identity, based on the relationship
between diverse citizens is more appropriate. Theorists in this camp worry that
deliberately fostering political loyalty (as in patriotism) may act to stifle judge-
ment over the worth of the loyalty-object (in this case, the patria), thus becoming
‘uncritical attachments’ (Hand, 2011; Keller, 2015; Nussbaum, 1996; Osler,
2009). Philosophers such as Michael Merry try to find a half-way point between
the two stances, indicating that one of the key responsibilities of citizens in a
democracy is that they should be able to hold their governments to account –
ruling out completely ‘uncritical attachments’, but accepting a legitimate form of
patriotic education: ‘critical patriotism’ (Merry, 2009).
Traditionally, state-provided schools have played a major role in creating
citizens in western societies, not least by transmitting basic norms through the
generations. This has historically been the case whether or not a society aligns
itself with some form of democracy. For the purposes of this paper, it may then
be initially tempting to interpret the policy in question, Fundamental British
Values (FBV), as just another articulation of such forms of citizenship education,
yet there are distinct differences.
The phrase itself, ‘Fundamental British Values’ (FBV), achieved public
prominence in a security approach from 2011, commonly known as the
Prevent strategy, aimed at prevention of extremism and radicalisation before
entering educational discourses (DfE 2014a; DfE, 2014b; DfE 2015b).4 In this
domain, radicalisation is usually understood as a process by which an individual
(or a group) adopts extreme stances that may entail rejecting the status quo,
whether it be political, religious or social (Wilner and Dubouloz, 2010).
Extremism pushes this further still, depicting stances far outside of majority
thinking that may prevent compromise or exclude other perspectives (Arthur,
2015; Kundnani 2012b). It is rarely a self-chosen label and often used in
reference to those who advocate some form of violence.
426 BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES
Nevertheless, it cannot automatically be assumed that adopting a radical
stance to currently accepted ideas is ‘dangerous’: many may adopt such a stance
without going on to engage in any form of terrorist activity at all (Sieckelinck
et al., 2015). Indeed, opposition to, or dissent from, any part of the Fundamental
British Values is now considered the very definition of extremism: ‘“Extremism”
is defined in the 2011 Prevent strategy as vocal or active opposition to funda-
mental British values…’ (HM Government, 2015: 20). But classifying some act
or thought as ‘extremist’ in these terms may be seen by some as suppressing
legitimate critique or as justifying arguments that the aim of the policy is indeed
to create the ‘uncritical attachments’ often associated with patriotic education.
This becomes particularly complex for educators required to patrol such issues in
that, as Sieckelinck et al., (2015) points out, the role of teachers is to educate
their students and not to see them as automatically suspect, dangerous or targets
for surveillance as might security forces.
The justification for this change in educational policy (from previous dis-
courses of ‘shared’ or ‘common values’ in citizenship education) was given as
being necessary to prepare pupils for life in modern Britain. The values in
question (originally named in the Prevent strategy) were formally listed in
educational documents as: ‘democracy, the rule of law, individual liberty and
mutual respect and tolerance of those with different faiths and beliefs and for
those without faith’ (Ofsted, 2015: 38). Besides the removal of the phrase ‘and
for those without faith’ in subsequent documents, there has been no further
official clarification, save recent reported comments from Ofsted that schools
should do more to prevent terrorism by ‘properly promoting British values’.5
Unlike many other ‘promoting’ policies, FBV was designed to be deeply
embedded into other educational policies and more general school policies. In
other words, it is not a ‘stand alone’ educational policy, but a reinforcement of
existing requirements found in other legislation. Schools were advised that this
new duty came with the expectation that FBV would permeate the ethos,
relationships and relevant activities beyond the classroom, as well as having a
place in the curriculum. Further directives were released on how this might be
done through social, moral, spiritual and cultural (SMSC) curricula (DfE, 2014a,
2015a) or linked to the prevent strategy (DfE, 2015b).
To date, much of the critique of this directive has focussed on the concept of
‘Britishness’, the securitisation for the state or exploring teachers’ practices (for
example Arthur, 2015; Lander, 2016; Panjwani, 2016; Richardson, 2015; Smith,
2016). Four areas attract attention in this expanding literature. First, teachers’
individual responsibility: the requirement is now that all teachers should ‘not
undermine’ fundamental British values (DfE, 2012) – but it is not spelled out
what exactly counts as undermining (Lander, 2016). As this is a requirement for
all teachers, and not just subject specialists in citizenship, PSHE, history, RE etc,
teachers need to know more fully what it is they are required to do in the
classroom – but equally what they should not be doing. Secondly, the content
(including the learning activities, particularly through SMSC (Spiritual Moral
BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES 427
Social and Cultural development.): there has been little to no reference made to
citizenship education as a distinct subject, which had previously covered many of
the activities cited as contributing to FBV: how democracy and the law works
etc. Thirdly, new legal responsibilities: making school leaders (head teachers and
governors) responsible for ensuring the school as a whole upholds FBV. They are
now required, as part of their professional duty, to actively promote fundamental
British values, to protect and safeguard children from radicalisation and extre-
mism, and the success of this will be reported on through Ofsted inspections
(Ofsted, 2015), yet with little clarity as to the precise boundaries of these terms.
Fourthly, through oversight arrangements (inspection frameworks overseen by
Ofsted): schools can now be given a fail grade for failure to promote funda-
mental British values (Ofsted, 2015). This would then give grounds for govern-
mental intervention on the grounds of ‘safe-guarding children’ and indeed
several schools have been failed in such a way.6
Much of the deliberation in policy comes from attempts to determine what
should be done and whether these principles provide a feasible standard for
practice. Admittedly, ideal models are not always easily articulated and realized
at the level of policy and pedagogy – but theory plays a crucial role by helping to
delineate those policies that accord with existing values, and to exclude those
contrary to them. Given the critical importance of this directive for practice,
further analysis of theory relevant to this area is urgently needed to make sense
of this directive, starting with what the bond between citizens ‘looks like’.
Perceived Belonging
This concept of ‘perceived belonging’ attempts to draw into the discourses of
belonging the voices beyond those provided by membership (in this case granted
by the state) or a sense of belonging (felt by individuals), emphasising that belonging
BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES 429
is at heart relational: it is about the self with others. As with many new concepts, it
draws on other similar concepts as interlocking systems of concepts that form a
framework for reasoning about shared commitments; in this case, it draws on
familiar concepts such as recognition and solidarity. In what follows, I highlight
the layers of relevant relational issues associated with this view of personhood.
In one form or another, recognition has emerged as a key concept in recent
decades, not only in philosophy but also in social theory, ‘identity politics’ and
the ‘politics of difference’ (Antonsich 2010; Jayaweera and Choudhary, 2008;
Probyn, 1996; Yuval-Davis et al., 2005). A number of social movements call for
a greater emphasis and acknowledgement of different ‘voices’ in discourses of
inclusion and exclusion including the willingness to grant social recognition.
Social recognition grants group members a status of holding and exercising
entitlements granted by the group, thus anchoring them in their self-identity.
In much of the existing literature on recognition, the focus is on the way in which
the self becomes recognised: those who are recognised as belonging, are then
accredited a social identity. The self, in this argument, is striving to become an ‘I’
or subject against a background from which her personhood arose, to evaluate and
seek esteem as an individual. Here the self attempts to delineate that which is ‘I’ from
others (they/them). This then suggests that when a person ‘asks’ for recognition, part
of what is being asked for is confirmation of what she believes herself to be.
Whilst I might come up with an account of who I believe myself to be, I also
need an account that describes how I might be seen (or perceived) by others.
Others may see me in very different ways: they may have a very different
opinion of me as a social being (which could add to the self-knowledge I may
already have about myself). I not only need to see myself, but I also need to be
seen by others, as a full member of the group, holding and exercising entitle-
ments granted by the group to its members. This gives perceived belonging a
dialogic role: I partially become conscious of who I am through the images
others have of me and that I have of them.
As Charles Taylor suggests, our core identity is not determined alone but in
company and in activity with others (Taylor, 1989). The concept of perceived
belonging serves to remind us that who I am is at least partly social, and as such,
is formed by how ‘I’ am defined by those around me. But it goes beyond this to
position membership in a group to be, at least in part, a matter of mutual
recognition: as something that is done with others. All parties bring together
their individual understandings and experiences, interacting and influencing each
other, constantly changing and adapting in response to the image significant
others may have. Such mutual recognition only works by seeing and treating
others as ‘one of us’: going from recogniser to recognised – ‘I recognise you’
and ‘you recognise me’ and it is only when this mutual recognition is achieved,
that discussion of the ‘we’ needed for cohesion becomes possible. This mutuality
evolves over time between members of the group as acknowledged and under-
stood parties, who may then be taken into account in policy formation or
revision.8 It is important to note that to achieve the ‘We-ness’ of cohesion does
430 BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES
not require adopting a deep shared identity: only that each party must willingly
accept the other as a fellow citizen concerned with the pursuit of at least some
common ends achieved through living together. Moving from the first person
singular (I) to a position of first person plural (we) places the self with others.
The individual then becomes a member of a group that can act as one – not by
the individual losing their own identity, nor subsuming it within that of another –
but by committing to treat others as belonging with us for particular purposes.
Looking at this problem from a different angle: without a commitment to
treat another as belonging with us, recognition becomes positioned purely as
something that is given to us, suggesting that individuals are mere spectators in
their own lives, as opposed to agents-who-can-act. In such circumstances,
individuals have not been included in the reflective appraisal involved but
have been presented with an account as defined by others which may, or may
not be accurate. Instead of being the active creator of a social identity, individuals
then become the passive receiver of another’s vision.
Similarly, when recognition is given, the range of available options for who-
I-might-be can result in some identities becoming contested or a source of conflict.
Take, for example, the wearing of overt religious symbols in France, which have
been banned in schools, universities or government buildings. Gereluk argues that
some forms of clothing are more than just an expression of one’s individuality and
can be a constitutive part of one’s identity (Gereluk, 2008). Refusing children the
right to wear particular clothing that is an outward sign of their faith commitments,
arguably compromises their identity; to be accepted, or to remain in school, then
requires them to fragment their identity in some way. In extreme circumstances,
such an imbalance between the ‘permitted’ given options and the self-chosen
identity might even demand one moves to the other’s position in public out of
fear, or even to resituate one’s own existing ontological landscape, to prevent
existing ‘recognition’ from being withdrawn.
Just as problematic as recognition being given is to have it withheld or
denied. To be denied recognition as a legitimate party can injure our pride, our
status and deny us a social identity; we can be humiliated, injured and disen-
franchised by being publicly positioned as ‘outsiders’. In such circumstances, the
‘we’ that is constructed reminds us from the start that we are perceived as neither
‘welcome’ nor ‘at home’.
Whilst the ideal is to be accepted and taken into account in our efforts to become
an active creator of our social identity, the reality is that power or control of the
discourses by particular players (usually the state or fellow citizens) inevitably
influences these metaphoric ‘conversations’. Because any discourse over shared
values and understandings of who ‘we’ are is often the result of struggles over
membership to begin with, debates can reflect or reinforce power structures in a
society and thus serve the interests of those who hold most power (Honneth and
Margalit, 2001; May, 2011). This means that not all may be ‘equal speakers’ in this
venture right from the start; some may be seen as outside of the community, ‘not one
of us’ and thus in need of ‘special attention’: some voices may be limited, or
BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES 431
distorted in practice; some are kept silent or ignored – thus the ability to negotiate or
‘become’ a speaker and to be heard and accepted may itself be restricted.
This affects some more that others and marginalised groups in particular
often lack power to negotiate on equal terms or lack adequate access to the
communal conditions affecting the capacity to exercise such agency. In such
situations, seeing one’s public persona to be found wanting (or to be trans-
formed) without being part of the process can be both upsetting and alienating.
In the context of this policy directive (FBV), this has left some to feel that the
default position indeed questions their status, belonging and loyalty (perceives
them as ‘other’ or ‘outsiders’), thus misrecognising them (Richardson, 2015).
This is particularly problematic in the context of schools, increasing the possi-
bility that conversations or discussions could be ‘shut down’ or avoided by
pupils for fear of being misunderstood or reported to authorities; staff themselves
might become reluctant to engage with controversial topics – and early reports
seem to suggest that this is precisely what has happened in some schools (Busher
et al., 2017; Press Association, 2015). If social cohesion is indeed an aim of this
policy, then is it appropriate that educational establishments should intimate that
some groups of pupils do not quite belong or are ‘suspect’ in some way?
But why does it matter how the bond between citizens is theorised? Is it just a
matter of semantics, or is there more at stake? I want to suggest two reasons
which I will address in the remainder of the paper. First, theory helps us to
identify the coherence of values between the desired goal and wider value
structures in society, making application more likely to be successful.
Secondly, having a clear view of the bond being aimed at is more likely to be
translated into successful school practice.
2001). Whilst there is obviously some overlap between both sets of values, it
does raise serious misgivings as to how the FBV could possibly support social
cohesion using the present restricted set of values.
6. CONCLUSION
Given that the self-declared end-goal of the FBV directive is to engender social
cohesion (and thus prevent terrorism), the claims that this is a possibility have to
be taken seriously. First, how the relationship needed for cohesion comes to be
understood is crucial, and it is here that the concept of ‘perceived belonging’
reminds us that who-I-am needs to be (at least) partially constructed with others.
A useful metaphor here is that of story-telling: we are all ‘story-tellers’. But self-
narratives are never purely singular: and the focal point of the most important
stories in a society tends to be relationship-based: our self with others. Each story
connects with the other, enabling development of shared stories. To place this
briefly in the language of relationships: the stories we tell ourselves about who
we are, are important in how we understand our connectivity; so too are the
stories that others tell about us. Without a clear picture of how we should ‘belong
together’, the values and dispositions needed to support this bond cannot be fully
identified, running the risk of seemingly random choices.
Secondly, citizens in a socially cohesive society need to have concern for the
public way of relating to each other and this in turn requires particular models of
civic relationships. Schools play a significant role in this by enabling wider
social interactions encouraging the reduction of the distance between citizens and
enabling an image of such lives as somehow ‘lived together’ to emerge.
BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES 435
7. D ISCLOSURE S TATEMENT
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.
8. N OTES
1
The threatened break-up of the UK union by the nationalist parties in Scotland and
Wales; the calls for independence in parts of Spain and in the Veneto region in Italy
etc.
2
Ofsted inspectors were called in to inspect a number of schools in Birmingham in
2014 after concerns were raised that some governors were having inappropriate
influence over the ethos and curriculum of their schools, leaving children ‘at risk’
of extremism.
3
See http://www.dailymail.co.uk/debate/article-2658171/DAVID-CAMERON-British-
values-arent-optional-theyre-vital-Thats-I-promote-EVERY-school-As-row-rages-
Trojan-Horse-takeover-classrooms-Prime-Minister-delivers-uncompromising-pledge.
html (last accessed 15.01.2018).
4
The origins of the policy itself can be traced further back to the increased securitisation
concerns of the state post ‘Cold War’ as well as more familiar responses to the Oldham
riots of 2001, terrorist attacks in London in 2005 and the so-called ‘Trojan horse affair’
of 2013–2014.
5
See The Daily Telegraph: http://www.telegraph.co.uk/education/2017/06/23/ofsted-
will-crackdown-extremism-promote-british-values-amanda/ 23.6.2017 reported by
Harry Yorke. The talk in question listed a number of other areas that could contribute:
SMSC; ‘a sense of patriotism’; a ‘real civic education’.
6
In late November 2014, it was reported that there had been 35 ‘no notice’ inspections
by Ofsted under the new rules, including 11 that were deemed to be not ‘preparing
pupils for life in modern Britain’: see http://www.telegraph.co.uk/education/education
news/11253436/Ofsted-rural-schools-failing-to-promote-British-values.html for details
(25th November: journalists – Graeme Paton and Melanie Hall). Also see: https://
www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/415115/
Advice_note_on_academies_and_maintained_schools_Birmingham_toSoS_
Education.pdf (accessed 10.11.2017).
436 BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES
7
This is particularly the case in some elements of the right wing press in the UK that
emphasise ‘desert’ rather than ‘need’ in relationship to the support given to migrants
and/or refugees, arguing that the former should not have access to welfare support
from the state for a period of time to re-establish the link between contributions and
shared welfare goods.
8
For example, the requirement to wear a helmet on a motorbike in the UK, which was
adapted to take account of the religious requirement for Sikhs to wear a turban.
9
There have been a multitude of previous attempts by politicians to identify or critique
what Britishness means and the subsequent deliberation of what the values binding us
together might be: John Major (1993), Tony Blair (2002), Gordon Brown (2004) to
name but a few.
9. R EFERENCES
Antonsich, M. (2009) On territory, the nation-state and the crisis of the hyphen, Progress
in Human Geography, 33 (6), 789–806. doi: 10.1177/0309132508104996
Antonsich, M. (2010) Searching for belonging – an analytical framework, Geography
Compass, 4 (6), 644–659. doi: 10.1111/geco.2010.4.issue-6
Arthur, J. (2015) Extremism and neo-liberal education policy: A contextual critique of
the trojan horse affair in birmingham schools, British Journal of Educational
Studies, 63 (3), 311–328. doi: 10.1080/00071005.2015.1069258
Bachtler, J. and Mendez, C. (2016) EU Cohesion Policy and European Integration: The
Dynamics of EU Budget and Regional Policy Reform (London, Routledge).
Barry, B. (1983) Self-Government Revisited. In D. Miller and L. Siedentop (Eds) The
Nature of Political Theory (Oxford, Oxford University Press).
Baumeister, R. F. and Leary, M. R. (1995) The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal
attachments as a fundamental human motivation, Psychological Bulletin, 117 (3),
497–529.
Buonfino, A. and Thomson, L. (2007) Belonging in Contemporary Britain (London,
Commission on Integration and Cohesion).
Busher, J., Choudhury, T., Thomas, P. and Harris, G. (2017) What the prevent duty means
for schools and colleges in England: an analysis of educationalists’ experiences.
Research Report. (Aziz Foundation., Durham University, University of Huddersfield
and Coventry University).
Cantle, T. (2001) Community cohesion: A Report Of The Independent Review Team,
(London, Home Office).
Christiansen, F. and Hedetoft, U. R. (Eds) (2004)The Politics of Multiple Belonging:
Nationalism and Ethnicity in Europe and East Asia (London, Ashgate).
Clark, J. (2009) Nation-state belonging among Asian Australians and the question of
transnationalism, Current Sociology, 57 (1), 27–46. doi: 10.1177/0011392108097451
DCSF. (2007) Guidance on the Duty to Promote Community Cohesion (Nottingham,
DfCSF Publications).
DfE. (2012) Teachers’ Standards (London, HMSO).
DfE. (2014a) Guidance on Promoting British Values in Schools (London, Crown
Publications).
DfE. (Nov 2014b) Promoting Fundamental British Values as Part of SMSC in Schools:
Departmental Advice for Maintained Schools (London, DfE).
DfE. (2015a) Personal, Social, Health and Economic (PSHE) Education: A Review of
Impact and Effective Practice (London, Crown Publications).
DfE. (2015b) Protecting Children from Radicalisation: The Prevent Duty (London, DfE).
Dobbernack, J. (2010) ‘Things fall apart’: social imaginaries and the politics of cohesion,
Critical Policy Studies, 4 (2), 146–163. doi: 10.1080/19460171.2010.490637
BELONGING, SOCIAL COHESION AND FUNDAMENTAL BRITISH VALUES 437
Correspondence
Mary Healy
Froebel College
University of Roehampton
London SW15 5PJ
Email: [email protected]