Speech act theory analyzes the ways in which utterances can be used to perform actions, beyond just presenting information. It considers locutionary acts (the act of saying something), illocutionary acts (the intention or point of an utterance, like requesting or ordering), and perlocutionary acts (effects or consequences of an utterance, like convincing or persuading someone). The theory was introduced by J.L. Austin and developed further by J.R. Searle, focusing on classifying the types of acts utterances can perform.
Speech act theory analyzes the ways in which utterances can be used to perform actions, beyond just presenting information. It considers locutionary acts (the act of saying something), illocutionary acts (the intention or point of an utterance, like requesting or ordering), and perlocutionary acts (effects or consequences of an utterance, like convincing or persuading someone). The theory was introduced by J.L. Austin and developed further by J.R. Searle, focusing on classifying the types of acts utterances can perform.
Speech act theory analyzes the ways in which utterances can be used to perform actions, beyond just presenting information. It considers locutionary acts (the act of saying something), illocutionary acts (the intention or point of an utterance, like requesting or ordering), and perlocutionary acts (effects or consequences of an utterance, like convincing or persuading someone). The theory was introduced by J.L. Austin and developed further by J.R. Searle, focusing on classifying the types of acts utterances can perform.
Speech act theory analyzes the ways in which utterances can be used to perform actions, beyond just presenting information. It considers locutionary acts (the act of saying something), illocutionary acts (the intention or point of an utterance, like requesting or ordering), and perlocutionary acts (effects or consequences of an utterance, like convincing or persuading someone). The theory was introduced by J.L. Austin and developed further by J.R. Searle, focusing on classifying the types of acts utterances can perform.
• It is a subfield of pragmatics concerned with the ways
in which words can be used not only to present information but also to carry out actions. See speech act. • Speech-act theory, as introduced by Oxford philosopher J.L. Austin (How to Do Things With Words, 1962) and further developed by American philosopher J.R. Searle, considers the types of acts that utterances can be said to perform: • Locutionary Acts • Illocutionary Acts • Perlocutionary Acts Illustrations • In the past three decades, speech act theory has become an important branch of the contemporary theory of language thanks mainly to the influence of [J.R.] Searle (1969, 1979) and [H.P.] Grice (1975) whose ideas on meaning and communication have stimulated research in philosophy and in human and cognitive sciences Illustrations • From Searle's view, there are only five illocutionary points that speakers can achieve on propositions in an utterance, namely: the assertive, commissive, directive, declaratory and expressive illocutionary points • Speakers achieve the assertive point when they represent how things are in the world, the commissive point when they commit themselves to doing something, the directive point when they make an attempt to get hearers to do something, the declaratory point when they do things in the world at the moment of the utterance solely by virtue of saying that they do and the expressive point when they express their attitudes about objects and facts of the world. Illustrations • This typology of possible illocutionary points enabled Searle to improve Austin's classification of performative verbs and to proceed to a reasoned classification of illocutionary forces of utterances which is not as language-dependent as that of Austin." (Daniel Vanderkeven and Susumu Kubo, "Introduction." Essays in Speech Act Theory. John Benjamins, 2002) Locutionary Acts
• The act of making a meaningful utterance. Also known
as locution. The term locutionary act was introduced by British philosopher John L. Austin in How to Do Things With Words (1962). • A locutionary act has to do with the simple act of a speaker saying something, i.e. the act of producing a meaningful linguistic expression. It consists of three sub-acts. they are (i) a phonic act of producing an utterance-inscription, (ii) a phatic act of composing a particular linguistic expression in a particular language, and (iii) a rhetic act of contextualizing the utterance- inscription Locutionary Acts • The first of these three sub-acts is concerned with the physical act of producing a certain sequence of vocal sounds (in the case of a spoken language), which is also called a phonetic act, or a set of written symbols (in the case of a written language). • The second refers to the act of constructing a well-formed string of sounds and/or symbols, be it a word, phrase, sentence, or discourse, in a particular language. Locutionary Acts • These two sub-acts are grouped by the American philosopher John Searle as performing an utterance act. The third sub-act is responsible for tasks such as assigning reference, resolving deixis, and disambiguating the utterance-inscription. This is referred to as a propositional act by Searle. Locutionary Acts • Thus, if John says to Mary, Pass me the glasses, please, meaning 'Hand the glasses over to me' with me referring to himself and glasses to spectacles, he performs the locutionary act of uttering the sentence Pass me the glasses, please." (Yan Huang, The Oxford Dictionary of Pragmatics. Oxford University Press, 2012) Illocutionary Acts
• It is a speaker's intention in delivering an
utterance. • The terms illocutionary act and illocutionary force were introduced by British linguistic philosopher John L. Austin in How to Do Things With Words (1962). Illocutionary Act and Illocutionary Force • An illocutionary act refers to the type of function a speaker intends to accomplish in the course of producing an utterance. It is an act accomplished in speaking and defined within a system of social conventions. • Thus, if John says to Mary Pass me the glasses, please, he performs the illocutionary act of requesting or ordering Mary to hand the glasses over to him. Illocutionary Act and Illocutionary Force • The functions or actions just mentioned are also referred to as the illocutionary force or illocutionary point of the speech act. • The illocutionary force of a speech act is the effect a speech act is intended to have by a speaker. Indeed, the term 'speech act' in its narrow sense is often taken to refer specifically to illocutionary act." (Yan Huang, The Oxford Dictionary of Pragmatics. Oxford University Press, 2012) Pragmatic Competence • Achieving pragmatic competence involves the ability to understand the illocutionary force of an utterance, that is, what a speaker intends by making it. This is particularly important in cross-cultural encounters since the same form (e.g. 'When are you leaving?') can vary in its illocutionary force depending on the context in which it is made (e.g. 'May I have a ride with you?' or 'Don't you think it is time for you to go?'). Pragmatic Competence • (Sandra Lee McKay, Teaching English as an International Language. Oxford Univ. Press, 2002) What I Really Mean . . . "When I say 'how are you' to a co-worker, I really mean hello. Although I know what I mean by 'how are you,' it is possible that the receiver does not know that I mean hello and actually proceeds to give me a fifteen minute discourse on his various maladies." (George Ritzer, Sociology: A Multiple Paradigm Science. Allyn & Bacon, 1980) Perlocutionary Acts
• It is an action or state of mind brought about by, or as a
consequence of, saying something. • Intuitively, a perlocutionary act is an act performed by saying something, and not in saying something. Persuading • angering, inciting, comforting and inspiring are often perlocutionary acts; but they would never begin an answer to the question 'What did he say?' Perlocutionary acts, in contrast with locutionary and illocutionary acts, which are governed by conventions, are not conventional but natural acts (Austin (1955), p. 121). Persuading, angering, inciting, etc. cause physiological changes in the audience, either in their states or behavior; conventional acts do not." (Aloysius Martinich, Communication and Reference. Walter de Gruyter, 1984) Perlocutionary Acts • In the perlocutionary instance, an act is perfomed by saying something. For example, if someone shouts 'fire' and by that act causes people to exit a building which they believe to be on fire, they have performed the perlocutionary act of convincing other people to exit the building. • In another example, if a jury foreperson declares 'guilty' in a courtroom in which an accused person sits, the illocutionary act of declaring a person guilty of a crime has been undertaken. Perlocutionary Acts • The perlocutionary act related to that illocution is that, in reasonable circumstances, the accused person would be convinced that they were to be led from the courtroom into a jail cell. • Perlocutionary acts are acts intrinsically related to the illocutionary act which precedes them, but discrete and able to be differentiated from the illocutionary act." (Katharine Gelber, Speaking Back: The Free Speech Versus Hate Speech Debate. John Benjamins, 2002)