MunozLobo Miguel Angel 2007 5349319
MunozLobo Miguel Angel 2007 5349319
MunozLobo Miguel Angel 2007 5349319
BY
C2007
Miguel Ángel Muñoz Lobo
Committee members
Committee:
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Throughout the writing of this thesis, I have been blessed with the help,
support and guidance of many people and institutions. I would first like to thank
academically and personally. His mentoring has made me a better person and a
stronger scholar. After each of our meetings, I left with constructive criticism and
a feeling of being respected and esteemed. I owe to him much of the enjoyment I
had during the process of writing this thesis. Similarly, the other two members of
my committee, Prof. Beth Manolescu and Prof. Robert Rowland, were a source of
never-ending encouragement and insightful suggestions. Also, this list would not
be complete without Prof. Amy Rossomondo, who is one of the professors from
University of Kansas. They have all been wonderfully supportive and made my
experience at KU one of the best and most intense of my entire life. I would
especially like to thank Pinar Alakoc, Ryan Shepard and Susana Mariscal. I feel
for you as for my family and cannot think of these years without thinking of you.
of Education (MEC) and the Fulbright Program. The staff at all the institutions
Commission) worked very hard so that I would have a wonderful experience here
at KU. I feel especially fortunate for having been advised, guided and cared for by
Hodgie Bricke, Shelley Buckwalter and Victoria Ruiz. Thank you so very much
INDEX
7. Bibliography ........................................................................................... 76
1
CHAPTER I
are unanimous in lavishing on [… him] the highest praise” (Al-Farabi, Founder 6).
Scholars have indeed named him “the greatest political philosopher of the period”
(Mahdi 1) and “the second teacher” (after Aristotle). He lived in Damascus (where
he also died in 950), Central Asia, Egypt and Baghdad. Al-Farabi is also a
Muslim philosopher who chose to explore the tension between the individual and
the community, “and in the process brought to the fore philosophy’s philanthropic
spirit and the philosopher’s high minded devotion to the true welfare of his
studied.
The figure of al-Farabi has appealed to many scholars. In his 1962 annotated
were devoted to al-Farabi’s theory of rhetoric. In 1962 there was only one
presents al-Farabi’s theory of rhetoric and its relationship to the rest of his
1
All dates are A.D. unless specified otherwise.
2
Aouad studies the concept of point of view in al-Farabi. Butterworth focuses on al-Farabi’s
politics with an emphasis on the figure of the ruler. Parens focuses on the relationship between
Plato’s metaphysics and al-Farabi.
2
corpus. This fact is surprising if one heeds the plea for more research in
(Halldén 19; Netton 88; Peters vii; Rescher 127). My study aims at bridging
this gap and benefits from the 1968 French translation of al-Farabi’s treatise
significantly bigger. I will try to relate these broader aspects to the subject of study
Regarding the historical context, Netton defines the age of Farabism “as
running from the birth of al-Farabi in AD 870 to the death of Abu Hayyan al-
Tawhidi3 in about AD 1023” (1). This period is centered around the Abbasid
dynasty (750 – 945) and its fall. It is roughly equivalent to the Renaissance of
Islamic thought” (ibid.). It is also, however, a period “of deep instability and
change” (2). The relationship between both of these aspects was analyzed by
Kraemer in terms of its negative correlation (the less stable a period is, the richer it
claims that in the face of socioeconomic distress, humanistic culture and learning
3
“One of the most dynamic and informative members of the group which we have termed ‘the
school of al-Farabi’” (Netton 16).
3
learning during the Abbasid rule. To this extent, Gutas has stressed that under the
Abbasids “support for the translation movement cut across all lines of religious,
sectarian, ethnic, tribal and linguistic demarcation” (5). Al-Farabi would have been
a product of that very particular time whose spirit has been characterized by
for foreign wars of conquest and for control of the local populace. (27)
All these aspects can be said to have shaped al-Farabi’s thought. In this study,
I will heed the interplay between al-Farabi and his historical context analyzing the
Abbasids from a different perspective. I will also probe the relationship between
the Abbasids and the school of the Mutazilah. Peters categorizes the Mutazilah as
held to be one of the most authoritative scholars within the first generation of
opposition to the historical context, the degree to which Muslim scholars adopted
4
Another would be Abu Bishr Matta, a Christian philosopher.
4
aims to contribute. So far, only the relationship to Plato and Aristotle has been
Let us first focus on the dyad Plato - al-Farabi. On the one hand, we have
entered this new cultural ground via the translation route, and were to
earlier career … The Arabs received this tradition after five hundred
years of shaping in the later Greek schools and another two hundred
years at the hands of the Syrian Christians: between the corpus proper
and the falasifah stand the massive efforts incorporated into the Berlin
influence in al-Farabi. In the field of philosophy, this work has been undertaken by
Morewedge and Colmo; Mahdi has also explored al-Farabi’s Neoplatonism from
the point of view of politics. My purpose will be to add a study focused on rhetoric
to this literature.
But let us first examine the positions taken by the authors above. They are
related but not identical. According to Mahdi, al-Farabi presents “an un-Platonic
5
“Andronicus of Rhodes was nearly as much the father of Aristotelianism as was Aristotle
himself” Francis E. Peters, Aristotle and the Arabs: The Aristotelian Tradition in Islam (New York:
New York University Press, 1968) 4, Charles E. Butterworth, "Ethics in Medieval Islamic
Philosophy," Journal of Religious Ethics 11 (1983).
5
accidental and whose views of the relation between this-wordly affairs and other-
worldly affairs are more adequate than those of Aristotle” (ibid.).6 We have
his philosophical rhetoric but his philosophical system lies in square opposition to
both Plato and Aristotle’s thought. Focusing his study on al-Farabi’s trilogy The
Two Philosophies, he claims that the two philosophies to which al-Farabi alludes
are not the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle, but, on one hand the combined
same aim […] Philosophy is the original that religion imitates insofar as
philosophy seeks the truth of which religion is an imitation” (166) and, second, an
approach that “denies our access to the veritable or eternal and denies that these
Plato as a metaphysical dogmatist. Merging both Colmo and Mahdi, he argues that
(144). In his view, al-Farabi’s account of Plato would be more Platonic than
Western tradition and the Enlightenment (xi). It was the West, and not al-Farabi,
that had misunderstood a Plato as oriented toward man and its context.
6
For a similar view, cf. Majid Fakhry, Al-Farabi, Founder of Islamic Neoplatonism (Oxford:
Oneworld, 2002) 22.
6
obvious in the sense that complete translations and commentaries of his works are
extant. Still, just as it was the case with Plato, the Arab reception of the Organon
was not unmediated: it was received from both Alexandria and Constantinople. Al-
Farabi was related to the former in that he was a product of the Baghdad branch of
the school of Alexandria, which moved first to Antioch (ca. 720), then to Harran,
With regard to Aristotle, it was Druart who suggested that al-Farabi took
liberties with the Stagirite’s theory (135), modifying it so that it met his views. For
not include theology and posited proximity with the active intellect as the
It seems that, even if distorted, scholars have found and analyzed relationships
between the West and the East in the field of philosophy. This study will
include other systems such as that of Isocrates. To that extent, I should stress that
the relationship between East and West is not unidirectional: just as the effects of
introducing Aristotle and Plato into Islam “were manifold … upset[ting] the
scholarship was “not a mere clone of Greek thought” (Netton). Indeed, as Halldén
pointed out, “the influence of Greek rhetoric … does not, however, [… mean] that
Arab Islamic rhetoric is simply an amalgam of traditions that somehow are the
7
property of Western culture and civilization” (28). Rather, the Greek tradition was
this influence is “as patent as the Greek etymology of falsafah” (135). Yet, I would
take issue with his claim that “Hellenism created philosophy in Islam” (ibid.),
which he supports suggesting that falsafah is “the only word the Arabs had to
describe this utterly new phenomenon” (ibid.). Two remarks should be made about
that argument. First, I would stress the fact that he used “Hellenism” instead of
“Greece.” Indeed, as Cameron has suggested, the ancients may not have felt the
distinction between “Greek” and “Semitic” culture with the same force as we do.
has lost its former credibility, and this should be taken into
Second, we should also consider not only the tradition of kalam, but also
contexts prior to the advent of Greek scholarship. This study will not deal with
this body of pre-existing theories but will analyze the school of kalam (the
7
We see, again, the relevance of taking the historical context into account.
8
Mutazilah) and its interplay with Greek scholarship as well as certain features of
Islamic culture.
With regard to this point, one could well wonder what these characteristics of
Islamic culture are. I contend that the features that will prove relevant to this study
2. “The Muslim community is never satisfied with the present. It looks to the
future, but only insofar as it is called upon to bring about the revolution that will
suppress its own rebellion” (Mahdi 17). This point can be said to be shared with
3. “Man is the central concern of both philosophy and divine law: philosophy
is a human activity and the divine law is addressed to man … both call on man to
reach for something higher than himself, to become divine” (Mahdi 18).
demanded by the divine law, but a divine law that left man free to perfect these
arts according to his natural light” (Mahdi 27). According to Islamic philosophy,
those capable should pursue free inquiry according to the best available method
(Adamson in Bragg).
premise in its political philosophy. The sage, the religious leader and the ruler of
the community are all variations of the perfect man” (Morewedge 68). Both Aouad
7. Muslims are conscious of their inability to know the whole. Their frustration
from (and acceptance of) this fact derives into prayer “with a view to persuading
the power who rules the whole to order the whole in accordance with the vision we
study will be to analyze to what extent and how it was affected by these features.
With regard to al-Farabi’s rhetorical theory, this is the focus of very few
studies. I will expand my review to literature related to other fields such as the
other syllogistic arts (focusing on poetics, philosophy, and dialectics), plus two
areas that have proved significant in my review: politics and religion. I will
Fakhry (Al-Farabi, Founder 26) presents us with a clear schema of the aims of
each art. While poetry is concerned with imagination, science with demonstration
and dialectic with opinion, rhetoric is the art of persuasion. As it is usually the case
with clear schemata, the lines drawn are more defined than they are in reality. As
we will see, al-Farabi’s very special theory of opinion is subsumed under the
10
frame of his rhetoric and encompasses both certainty and supposition. Also, just as
opinion is not the exclusive realm of dialectics, persuasion takes place in other
fields such as politics, religion and philosophy. To this extent, rhetoric can be said
to play a part in those fields and this study also proposes to analyze the relations
already suggested the existence of interplay among all these areas in Medieval
Islam. Butterworth and Parens have done this from a political point of view;
Mahdi did the same with a focus on philosophy; whereas Kemal and Aouad and
Schoeler centered their investigation around the poetics. This study contributes to
that conversation with a focus on rhetoric and the figure of al-Farabi. My research
questions are derived from the gaps and unresolved controversies I have found in
the literature.
theory of rhetoric?
This question arises in part from my New Historicist bias as a scholar. To that
claim, together with Kraemer and the postulates of New Historicism, that, without
the Humanist structure of that time and place, al-Farabi could not have written his
works. Building upon the historical studies of Kraemer and Gutas, I will analyze
2. How are the eight characteristics of Islamic culture described above related to
Guillaume and Kouloughli; Smyth, qtd. in Hallén 20) that questions the Islamic
nature of al-Farabi’s thought and those who adopt his views. Previous literature
has already addressed this issue but it has not answered what is Islamic about the
essential point: there are alternatives to contemporary Islamic societies that do not
Farabi’s historical context to be similar to the one that allowed the sophists to
Farabi (Mahdi; Parens). Putting both aspects together, I expect to find an internal
(rather than external) relation between the sophists’ positions and al-Farabi’s
thought.
rhetoric on one side and philosophy, politics, dialectic, poetics and religion on the
other?
theory of rhetoric. To that extent, I will analyze the relationship between rhetoric
and the other syllogistic arts, with a focus on philosophy, dialectic and poetics.
This study will not probe the relationship between rhetoric and sophistry because
12
of a lack of a primary text on the latter. Instead, I will complement my study with
I think that the best way to answer these questions is to understand, together
should be. With this aim, a careful close analysis of the argument al-Farabi makes
in his texts will help us understand the context (RQ1), discover its structure (RQ4),
identify the arguments (RQ3) and signal the inherent values of the position (RQ2).
Accordingly, chapter two will explore the dynasty of the Abbasids and the
cultural revolution they espoused. Thanks to it, almost all non-literary and non-
historical secular Greek scholarship was translated into Arabic (Gutas 1). The
chapter will also expose darker aspects of the Abbasids; especially their strategies
to create a closed society where dissent is not allowed. At this point, the chapter
will also feature a presentation of the intellectual opposition force that the
Abbasids faced: the Mutazilah. Chapter three will examine the claim that al-
extent al-Farabi can be presented as a scholar who fits within the frame of that
culture and society. This chapter will also study al-Farabi’s approach to Sharia.
between al-Farabi’s theory of rhetoric and that of three classical Greek scholars
(Plato, Aristotle and Isocrates). Chapter five will situate rhetoric within the
structure of al-Farabi’s thought. This chapter will explore the relations between
rhetoric on the one hand and philosophy, dialectic, poetic, religion and politics on
the other. Finally, chapter six explores future research possibilities that can spring
13
out of this study and points at possible obstacles one could find to that extent. It
will also summarize the argument that this study tries to make about al-Farabi’s
theory of rhetoric.
14
CHAPTER II
One of the events [of this year] was the spread of the Qarmatian movement
was sent against them. He was ordered to search for them, seize all of them
that he might come upon, and bring them to the Caliph's court. He came
upon a leader of theirs known as Ibn Abi al-Qaws. He was sent with the
summoned him and interrogated him. He then ordered his teeth knocked
out. Thereafter, his (limbs) were dislocated by stretching one of his hands
with a pulley while a rock was attached to the other hand. He was left in
this state from midday to evening. The next day, his hands and feet were
cut off, and he was decapitated. His corpse was hung on the East Side.
together with the Qarmatians who had been hung there. (Al-Tabari 99)
This event took place only a couple of months after the arrival of al-Farabi
from Farab to Baghdad in 901; this move and the situation in Baghdad marked his
period of old age and full maturity. While it has traditionally been held that al-
himself aloof from political and social perturbations and turmoils” (Sharif 450), I
would like to show that his rhetorical theory reflects the socio-political
for us to better understand both their presence in al-Farabi’s work and the positions
he favored. To that extent, this second chapter will probe the dynasty during whose
15
caliphate al-Farabi lived: the Abbasids and their competing persuasive forces, the
The Abbasids overthrew the Umayyad dynasty in 750, when the Abbasid
(ancient Antipatris) and killed them in what is known as the Abbasid massacre
(Hitti 285). This feast of blood followed the fall of the leading city of al-Kufah, in
749. Gibbon’s analysis of the decline and fall of the Roman Empire, according to
which it was due to the loss of civic virtue among its citizens, has also been
applied to the fall of the Umayyads,8 against whom the Abbasids presented their
aspects other than religious reformism. The geopolitics of the Middle East
underwent a shift from the Arab and Byzantine-oriented Umayyads to the more
base of the new empire: Baghdad. Its etymology leads us to "the two ancient
Persian words Bagh, ‘God,’ and Dâdh, meaning ‘founded’ or foundation –whence
Baghdad would have signified the city 'Founded by God'" (Le Strange 11). The
italics are mine and they remind us of the Persian and theocratic foundations of the
Abbasid Empire.
8
Hitti records how “the characteristic vices of civilization, especially those involving wine, women
and song, had seized upon the youthful Arab society” (280)
16
This Persian influence cut through all aspects and layers of society9 and meant
a cultural revolution. For the Umayyads, Gutas tells us, "the prevailing high
the Umayyads were in direct contact, was the Greek Orthodox Christianity
irrelevant" (ibid.). Thus, the cultural orientation of the caliphate changed with the
the Abbasids allowed interest in the Hellenist heritage which would have never
taken place in the Umayyad Empire. Indeed, had al-Farabi not lived within the
The orientation of the Abbasids towards Persia and classical Greece was not
this point and suggest how it can be linked to both the opening quotation of this
chapter and al-Farabi’s rhetorical theory, I will analyze both of the following
fragments:
9
Hitti tells us how "Gradually Persian titles, Persian wines and wives, Persian mistresses, Persian
songs, as well as Persian ideas and thoughts, won the day. Al-Mansur, we are told, was the first to
adopt the characteristic Persian head-gear … in which he was naturally followed by his subjects."
(294)
10
This movement was espoused by the Abbasids and took place mainly in Baghdad between the
middle of the eighth century to the end of the tenth. It consisted in the translation of “almost all
non-literary and non-historical secular Greek books that were available throughout the Eastern
Byzantine Empire and the Near East” Dimitri Gutas, Greek Thought, Arabic Culture : The Graeco-
Arabic Translation Movement in Baghdad and Early Abbasid Society (2nd-4th/8th-10th Centuries)
(London ; New York: Routledge, 1998) 1.
17
Confusion now hath made his masterpiece! If the caliph is killed the whole
Most sacrilegious murder hath broke ope universe is disorganized, the sun
The Lord's anointed temple, and stole thence hides its face, rain ceases and
The fragment on the right is uttered by Macduff in Macbeth’s second act, third
scene, upon the discovery of the assassination of King Duncan. The one on the left
is taken from Ibn at-Tiqtaqa’s Kitab al-Fakhri (190), a source contemporary to the
fall of the Abbasid dynasty. Despite the temporal and geographical differences,
both texts share the same conception of the divinity of the body politic. Thus, just
as Claudius entrenched himself in the “divinity [that] doth hedge a king” (Hamlet,
IV.5), the Abbasids used Persian Zoroastrian texts to construe the conception that
their ascent to power was protected and commanded by God. Hence their usage of
such texts as Abu-Sahl’s Kitab an-Nahmutan, where subjects were reminded that
The people of every age and era acquire fresh experiences and have
knowledge renewed for them in accordance with the decree of the stars and
the signs of the zodiac, a decree which is in charge of governing time by the
Gutas suggests that the Abbasids interpreted from passages such as the one above
that God had commanded them to renew the sciences just as the Sasanians had
previously done. Invested with such a divine protection, they set to confront their
opponents through dialectic as a means to produce proofs against them and their
socio-cultural foundations.
Al-Mahdi was the first caliph to command the theologians who used
against the heretics and other infidels we have just mentioned. The
the truth in clear terms to the doubters (al-Mas’udi 3447, qtd. in Gutas 65)
The disputers of the Abbasids were the Umayyads, who were trying to regain
power, and return to their cultural foundations: Byzantium (the eastern part of
what once was the Roman Empire) and the Greek orthodox Christians. Both of
these foundations were the targets of Abbasid dialectic, which was used to
the following:
Both in their spoken and written language the Byzantines follow in the
footsteps of the Greek, though they never reached their level either in the
During the time of the ancient Greeks, and for a little while during the
Byzantine [i.e. in this case, Roman] empire, the philosophical sciences kept
Byzantines; they then effaced the signs of philosophy, eliminated its traces,
destroyed its paths, and they changed and corrupted what the ancient
19
Greeks had set forth in clear expositions. (Al-Mas’udi 741, qtd. in Gutas
89)
Both of these fragments prove for Gutas the rationalistic policy of the
there can never come together in a single state a concealed religious leader
and a declared political leader without the religious leader usurping the
power from the political leader, because religion is the foundation and royal
control of the entire edifice than he who controls the pillar. (Al-Abi 89, qtd
in Gutas 81)
In other words, "the king ought not to concede to worshippers, ascetics, and the
pious that they are worthier of the religion, more fond of it, and more angry on its
favored a rationalist intellectual elite over religious leaders. I would like to show,
however, that their rationalism is not as strong as Gutas suggests. Indeed, when
that endows those in power with a halo of infallibility and perfection. The same
20
uneasiness can be felt in the reassuring mantra that Ali repeated to himself the
It is reported that ‘Ali had kept watch that whole night before the murder
and that he kept repeating as he paced from the door to his bedroom, ‘God
knows I have never lied, nor been accused of lying. (Al-Mas'udi 423 qtd. in
Mernissi 28)
Again, Ali’s disquiet counters the divinity that hedges the body politic and
hints at the opposition to a fallible ruler. What is more, his assassination11 takes us
closer to the irrationality and violence of the opening quotation from al-Tabari
histories it is hard to defend Gutas' benign account. To this extent, I would favor
intellectual elite; but this elite was drawn from a specific tradition of thought: that
of the Sharia, which was understood as a banning reflection and as based on Taa
(obedience). This interpretation of the Sharia differs from the original meaning of
Sharia which, as the historical dictionary Lisan al-Arab records, denotes “going to
the source of water.” The mythological value of water in the Arabic culture has an
element of life and energy but I suggest that the Abbasids turned to blood rather
than water.
11
“On the night of Friday 13 Ramadan [January 20, 661] that woman withdrew for prayer under a
sort of mosquito net within the walls of the great mosque ... She brought a piece of silk which she
cut into strips and put around the men's foreheads, while the men took their swords and went to sit
facing the door through which ‘Ali would enter the mosque, as he did every morning at the first call
of the muezzin … [then] ‘Ali came out of his house and called out in a loud voice, 'Muslims, come
to prayer, come to prayer!’ Ibn Muljam and his accomplices threw themselves on him ... Ibn
Muljam struck him a sword blow on the top of his head” Al-Mas'udi, Muruj Al-Dhahab (Beirut:
Dar al-Ma'rifa, 1982) 423.
21
Similarly, Mernissi contends that “in order to serve the needs of the Abbasid
palace, the Sharia was stripped of its questioning, speculative dimension” and
“[t]he Imam became a bloodthirsty despot” (37). This is illustrated in the inaugural
discourse by Abu al-Abbas, the first Abbasid caliph, where he referred to himself
indicator of the degree of turmoil and political instability reached during this
rebellions: he was born the first year of the Zanj revolt, a 14-year slave rebellion in
which half a million people died (Hitti 468); he also experienced the uprising of
the 13 vizirs against al-Muqtadir (908-32), who had succeeded his second cousin,
Abdullah ibn al-Mutazz, upon being killed the day after he assumed the caliphate
What can be learned from all the facts and events above? Khomeini’s religious
orthodoxy and repressive tactics of any opposition was not unprecedented in the
history of the Islamic Middle East. Indeed, these can already be found in the
Abbasids. And yet, there are various differences between Khomeini and the
Abbasids. One of the most significant ones is that while the Abbasids could not
suppress the idea of there existing an opposition, Khomeini had enough media
provides us with an analogous situation. Claude François created it but it was Paul
Anka who made it world known. Also, while in François’ song the story is about a
couple and the narration is focused on the other partner, on “you”; in Paul Anka’s
12
Hitti points out that “the incoming dynasty [the Abbasids], much more than the outgoing [the
Umayyads], depended upon force in the execution of its policies. For the first time in the history of
Islam the leathern spread beside the caliph's seat, which served as a carpet for the use of the
executioner, became a necessary adjunct of the imperial's throne” (288).
22
version, the other vanishes under a monolithic I-speaker (which does not mean that
it does not exist: it is simply hidden). In any case, both Khomeini (less
He received a thousand blows and didn't utter a word (...) the executioner
cut off his hands and feet, cut off his head, which he kept aside, and then
burned the body. When it was nothing but ashes, he threw it into the Tigris
and planted the head on Baghdad's bridge. (140, qtd. in Mernissi 20)
His crime? He would insist that the human being was a creature of God,
of movements and ideas in line with what will be called much later in Europe the
Renaissance. For the time being, I will focus my analysis on an emerging pattern:
should be noted that such opposition did exist and manifested itself in two
different ways. One of the ways was intellectual. This was the trend followed by
the Mutazilites. The other way was violent and was adopted by the Kharijites.
While the former “proposed a profound reflection on the nature of humanity and
the nature of the divine, thus bringing up the question of the place of reason and
personal opinion, as did the western philosophers of the Enlightenment” (21), the
latter “never dreamed of changing the relationship between the leader and the
community; they simply thought that by rebelling against the imam and sometimes
Each tradition has a certain vocabulary. Thus, Sharia is the core word for the
Kharijites, who understand it is their duty to watch that the leader of the
community stays within the hudud (Allah’s limits). On the other hand, the
keywords for the Mutazilites are reason (aql) and personal opinion (ray). Their
goal is to apply both of these concepts to the political sphere. The relevance of the
Mutazilite approach is suggested by Mernissi: it allows all the people who are
capable of reasoning to enter the realm of the political and play an active role. Al-
The Mutazilah and other schools maintain that the title of imam is obtained
by the [free] vote of the nation. God and his prophet, they say, did not
designate a particular imam, and the Muslims were not obliged to give their
This fragment debunks the divinity halo that the Abbasids, as Claudius,
asserted to have. Similarly, one of the best definitions that I have found of
doctrines to what seems to be the requirements of reason. And yet, the philosophy
ideas, which Nader describes: First, the unity of God (al-tawhid). This is very
Islamic nature of any religious group. Indeed, this is the only characteristic that all
13
I would however note that this feature is not exclusive to Islam. Besides, the interpretations of
tawhid vary across Islamic groups. Thus, Nader alludes to the controversial Mutazilite
interpretation of the attributes of God (attributes are not extrinsic to the Divine essence).
24
movement.
heralds the liberum arbitrium of man basing its position both in what Isaiah Berlin
favoring verses such as "The truth is from your Lord: let him then who will,
believe; and let him who will, disbelieve" (The Quran 18: 28) over others such as
“and whom God shall please to guide, that man’s breast will He open to Islam; but
whom He shall please to go astray, strait and narrow will He make his heart” (6:
125). Nader focuses on these two characteristics but, in the context of this study, I
would stress the value of a different one: the intermediate position (al-manzilah
bayna al-manzilatayn).
Such a position is so relevant that the name of the movement is derived from
this root (Itizal). Itizal means separation and I will illustrate its meaning with an
example that unites both features: divine justice and the intermediate position. It
concerns the founder of the movement, Wasil ibn Ata. He separated himself from
the circles of thought existing during his time regarding the characterization of
others they were believers. Wasil ibn Ata was able to break out of the dichotomy
and propose a Guiddens-like third way: their essence was neither believing nor
unbelieving but a middle position between the two. The impact of this frame of
14
"A person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise" In
Harry G. Frankfurt, "Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility," The Importance of What
We Care About (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 1.
25
Neither are its consequences -and it should be noted that not all of them are
positive. Indeed, the Mutazilite ideas presented above unsettled the Abbasid
caliphs and religious imams alike. According to Mernissi, their reaction was to
shroud their ideas in the chador of foreigness. With her sociological background,
she analyses the metaphorical-mythological value the West, al-gharb, has in the
Gharb, the Arabic word for the West, is also the place of darkness and the
the place where the sun sets and where darkness awaits. It is in the West
that the night snaps up the sun and swallows it; then all terrors are possible.
(13)
explained as a consequence of natural law that relates to the sick person’s psyche
attributes rather than by physical symptoms. Indeed, one of the things that struck
me most during my conversations with Moroccans was that they saw Western
society not only as foreign, but also ill, poisoned from a fast-food moral system.
Attaching the Mutazilah and all its ideological system (moral responsibility,
rationalism, third-way strategies, etc.) to the foreign and ill West was one of the
most successful moves of the fearful (and feared) Abbasids. Mernissi argues that
the view that humanism and Islam are unrelated terms. In the chapters ahead, I
plan to show not only how the rhetorical theories of al-Farabi share a common
territory with the Mutazilah but also how close their tenets are to an Islamic
identity.
I have contributed towards that goal in this chapter by presenting the historical
context in which those theories developed. To that extent, I have introduced the
Abbasids as the dominant players in a game where, feeling vulnerable and afraid,
they resorted to violence and the stigmatization of their opponents. With regard to
CHAPTER III
861). In contrast to both his brother, al-Wathiq (842-847), and his father, al-
great mosque of Samarra -at its time, the largest and most fanciful in the world,
covered with mosaics of dark blue glass and having a spiral minaret of 180 feet.
The magnificence of this construction left very little space remaining in al-
something strange and foreign to the Islamic tradition. Thus, they ironically shared
the same condition the Greeks had suffered under the Umayyads.
The sad part of the story is that more than a thousand years later, the Mutazilah
and what it stands for, still carry a scarlet F, for foreign, which continues to burn.
This is relevant in as much as al-Farabi has also been condemned to wear that sign
that it is not an Arabic work. He then opposes the two terms in Arabic to talk about
rhetoric: khataba and balagha concluding that “the true Arabic rhetoric will only
be found in the Balagha” (Al-Farabi Rhetoric 27). Al-Farabi’s own translator and
editor will characterize him as foreign to the Arabic tradition! He does not
however make explicit which are the specific elements that make him a stranger to
15
Roman Jakobson introduced the theory of markedness according to which dichotomies have a
neutral, transparent side opposed to a marked one. The pair unmarked/marked has been likened to
the pair norm/deviation.
28
Arabic culture and Islam other than his supposed abstractness. In this chapter I will
truly Islamic scholar in whose conception of the ideal Islamic society rhetoric is
the word in Arabic for public speech is al-khataba rather than al-balagha, which is
backed by the fact that the words sermon (khutba), public discourse (khitab) and
preacher or orator (khatib) are derived not from balagha but from khataba. What is
more, “al-khataba was something for the rational mind to reflect on” (23). Indeed,
rationality (one of the pillars of the Mutazilah) is therefore linked to al-khataba and
Farabi’s Kitab al-Khataba (Book of Rhetoric) can indeed belong to the true
To probe the relationship between al-Farabi and the Islamic tradition, I will
describe the extent to which the eight major characteristics of Islam outlined in
chapter one can be found in al-Farabi’s work. The first characteristic alluded to
Sharia as the overall “definer of decorum in human behavior” (Halldén 23). Yet it
is necessary to point out that Sharia is a concept with different sides (Gallagher).
people. Thus, while for orthodox scholars it means the fixed doctrine of the Koran
and the Sunna; for Ramadan it means “the path of fidelity to the principles of
Islam” (Ramadan "The Way toward Radical Reform" 5), which implies that both
29
the Koran and the Sunna can be reinterpreted in accordance to each particular
context. Finally, Mernissi cites the entry in Manzur’s historical dictionary Lisan al-
Arab for Sharia according to which its etymology would stem from the concept of
“going toward the source of water … toward the element that assures life and
renews energy” (33). This last definition, again, allows for a reinterpretation of the
sacred texts contradicting orthodox doctrine. What is more, the guidelines for that
reinterpretation spring not from Islam directly (as in Ramadan) but from human
Does Sharia appear in the works of al-Farabi? If so, what is the position that he
takes in this regard? I contend first, that one can find a theory of Sharia in his
works. Second, I suggest that al-Farabi’s concept of Sharia is not a fixed corpus.
He will make this reinterpretability clear throughout his work. One of the most
the successor [of the first ruler] will be the one who determines what the
first did not determine. And not only this, but it is also up to him to alter
much of what the first had legislated and to determine it in another way,
when he knows that it is best for his time -not because the first erred, but
because the first made a determination according to what was best for his
subsequent to the time of the first, this being the kind of thing the first
16
Throughout this survey the terms Sharia and law will be used interchangeably in accordance with
the practice most extended among al-Farabi’s translators.
30
can be seen in his figure of the statesman, whom he describes as someone who
“should be able to lead people well along the right path to felicity and to the
text follows very closely the conceptualization of Sharia as a path toward the
source of life and energy. Something similar is affirmed at the beginning of his
Book of Religion:
If the first ruler is virtuous and his rulership truly virtuous, then in what he
prescribes he seeks only to obtain, for himself and for everyone under his
rulership, the ultimate happiness that is truly happiness; and that religion
prescribes he seeks only to obtain, for himself by means of them, one of the
important goods ... to win that good, be happy with it to the exclusion of
them, and make those he uses to arrive at his purpose and to retain in his
I will stress two themes from the citation above. First, that al-Farabi’s
conception of ruling restricts more the ruler than the ruled. Rulers are charged with
the responsibility of leading everyone to happiness and are warned against abusing
power for their own exclusive benefit. In this sense, al-Farabi classifies rulers in
two types: virtuous and non-virtuous -ignorant- ("Religion" 93), laying the
foundations for a critical attitude towards rules and rulers who are not infallible.
This attitude, in spite of what rulers would rather have people believe, is Islamic
insofar as the Prophet himself stated that “those who put in a position someone
31
who they know unworthy betrays God, the Prophet and the entirety of the
community” (Ramadan Islam & Société np). Indeed, as Ramadan points out “if
you are in front of God, develop a law that pleases God and God does not like
injustice” (ibid.). It is the responsibility of the Muslim to make sure that the most
honest and competent people rule the community. Therefore, there is a trend in
Islam to warn against bad rulers, and suggest that there can be such a thing. This
trend can be seen in al-Farabi’s work in his commentary about the ignorant rulers.
Second, al-Farabi's warning against exclusion is very much in line with Peters’
conception of Islam as “an inclusive culture with the ability to encompass within
itself sophisticated minorities and external influences” (Peters xix). Indeed, for al-
Farabi, there is a close relationship between the community and religion. Thus his
treatise on religion starts placing religion within the domain of actions and
provides us with a distinction between Islam and al-Farabi, and other more-
This role of rhetorical speech can be seen when al-Farabi describes the ideal
ruler, deeming it important for him to "be good at guiding the people by his speech
to fulfill the laws of the first sovereigns as well as those laws which he will have
deducted in conformity with their principles after their time" (Perfect State 252-
17
“Religion is opinions and actions, determined and restricted with stipulations and prescribed for a
community … The community may be a tribe, a city or district, a great nation, or many nations”
(93).
32
by means of statements that are excellent in persuading about each and every one
35). Rhetoric thus becomes a powerful and indispensable element in the society
rhetoricians are called to be the second pillar.18 Similarly, in his description of the
statesman he acknowledges that “it is difficult to find all these qualities united in
one man” (Perfect State 249)19 so he agrees to dropping some of the characteristics
of the best statesman but the quality of good public speech will never be discarded:
(1) He will be a philosopher, (2) He will know and remember the laws and
customs… (3) He will excel in deducing new law by analogy… (4) He will
situations for which the first sovereigns could not have laid down any law;
when doing this he will have in mind the good of the city. (5) He will be
significant and will be further explored in the next chapter. In this chapter, I would
18
“There are five parts of the virtuous city: the virtuous, the linguists, the assessors, the warriors
and the moneymakers. The virtuous are the wise, the prudent, those who have opinions about major
matters. Then are the transmitters of the creed and the linguists; they are the rhetoricians, the
eloquent, the poets, the musicians, the scribes, and those who act in the same way as they do and
are among their number” (“Aphorisms” 37).
19
This cite matches aphorism n. 97. Some scholars claim this is a spurious addition to the text.
While the present study does not aim at determining the status of this aphorism, it should be noted
that it seems to be in accordance to the spirit of the rest of the text as the citation above shows.
33
Islam (characteristic number five in chapter one) and its awareness of the
impossibility for man to know the whole (seventh characteristic of Islam in chapter
one), al-Farabi does show both the awareness of the inability of humans, and an
The virtuous regime is the one through which … the ruled gain virtues with
respect to their this-worldly life and the afterlife that they could not gain
except by means of it. With respect to their this-worldly life, it is [a] that
the body of each one have the best conditions possible for its nature to
receive, [b] that the soul of each one have the best conditions possible for
its individual nature and for its power to obtain the virtues that are the
reason for happiness in the afterlife, and [c] that their subsistence be better
and more pleasant than all the sorts of life and subsistence that others have
("Aphorisms" 58)
This practical, down-to-earth bias will show in all levels of al-Farabi’s work
and contradicts Langhade’s vague claim that his is an abstract approach. Thus, at
20
Discernment is the ability to light upon the correct judgment with respect to recondite opinions
that are disputed and the power to verify it. So it is excellently inferring what is sound in opinions
and is, therefore, one of the kinds of prudence (“Aphorisms” 31)
21
Defined as “the faculty by which a human being -through much experience in matters and long
observation of sense-perceptible things- attains premises by which he is able to seize upon what he
ought to prefer or avoid with respect to each one of the matters we are to do” (“Aphorisms” 31)
34
inevitably makes him imagine that what does not lead to that [particular]
goal does lead to it or makes him imagine that what leads to the contrary of
that goal leads to it. So his action and advice are in accordance with what
accordance with general knowledge and customs. He also posits again poetic
fulfilling an integrative function (“Aphorisms” 36). The emphasis is, again, on the
community rather than on the individual. As it has already been suggested, the
community is responsible for the critical observation of the ruler and the
the traditional political system in Islamic countries is, according to Sluglett, the
republic. Madzur’s Lisan al-Arab traces back the origins of the word republic
in this context "the majority of the people.” Mernissi quotes Manzur's example of
this use of the term: “jumhuriyya wine: ‘a wine that makes one very drunk’; it is
qtd. in Mernissi 72). Another example of the importance of collectivity can be seen
the first pillar of Islam, the Shahada,22 the Islamic profession of faith. It was what
the Prophet asked from the Quraysh council to pronounce so that they could rule
over both Arabs and non-Arabs. At that point, the council rejected Muhammad’s
request forcing him out of Mecca. When he came back from Medina, the Prophet
imposed the Shahada ending the adoration of multiple idols. Abdullah bin Masud
The Prophet entered Mecca and (at that time) there were three hundred-and-
sixty idols around the Ka'ba. He started stabbing the idols with a stick he
had in his hand and reciting: "Truth (Islam) has come and Falsehood
traditionally been assumed that this factor is of major relevance because it allowed
Islam to expand as quickly as fire. As Mernissi puts it, they substituted freedom
for rahma;23 and rahma “made Islam a peaceful, unobtrusive traveler circulating in
all simplicity, without armies or swords, using established trading routes” (110).
Rhetoric will play a key role in the establishment of social cohesion and as such it
is opposed to imagination:
22
“There is no God but Allah, and Muhammad is His Prophet.”
23
Rahma is a rich concept with multiple facets: sensitiveness (al-riqa), tenderness (al-ta’attuf), and
also forgiveness (al-maghfira). It is everything that is sweet and tender, nourishing and safe, like a
womb (Mernissi 88).
36
have an inclination or loathing for it, even if he has not assented to it.
(“Aphorisms” 36)
Farabi to persuasion as unifying force. He is, in this respect too a most Islamic
instrument which brings the sounds of other instruments together and it links them
in a pool of sound. It seems that rhetoric is for al-Farabi the bassoon of Islamic
society.
to the human arts whose practice is demanded by the divine law, but a divine law
that left man free to perfect these arts according to his natural light” (Mahdi 27).
Indeed, God commands in the Koran to read and to learn (The Quran 96.1).
Similarly, the first task that Ramadan proposes to Muslims is education together
with the development of a critical attitude which he finds lacking in today's Islam
but was a core element of the Prophet's life (“he argued with everyone”). Al-Farabi
philosophy:
virtuous ruler is not a vicious but an ignorant one. Similarly, he likens the ideal
complained that Muslim countries today “do not do put much effort in research
about and diffusion of past intellectual works” ("Entrevista" 4); they seem more
one, according to which Muslims are conscious of their inability to know the
whole. Indeed, it is contradictory to a certain extent to claim on the one hand that
humans must know, and state that humans cannot know on the other. Al-Farabi
(back again to the Mutazilah) drawn from his collectivist ideology: “Opinion can
be strengthened or weakened and it is to that extent that man does not perceive the
conversation with the others” (36). That is to say: the strength of any claim
depends not on a factual determination of its Truthfulness but on the fact that it
Therefore, it can be seen how all the pieces of the puzzle fit to create an
foreign to the Islamic tradition. Using a musical analogy, al-Farabi’s thought is not
philosophy, critical thought, and law are key, situate him within the frame of an
period. In the next chapter I move to analyze whether his melody is also in tune
with Greek classical thought and the type of relationship to three major classical
CHAPTER IV
While al-Farabi’s poetics, politics and philosophy have been studied and
written about extensively, his rhetoric is the least studied part of his corpus. In the
present chapter, I aim at exploring this territory. I will firstly probe al-Farabi’s
treatise on rhetoric to uncover his conception of rhetoric, and its major procedures,
with a focus on the enthymeme. Secondly, I will compare his theory to three main
Introducing the history of the text at this point may help understand the scarce
treatment that it has received. There are two manuscripts of the text. One was
found by Ahmed Ates in 1951 at the Hamidiye library of Istanbul while Dr. Karel
date the only extant text on rhetoric directly written by al-Farabi. It is not,
however, the only one he wrote. We know, for example, that he wrote two other
not have any manuscript of either so we only have references to them and partial
translations of them in the works of other authors. Thus, for example, Averroes
referred to al-Farabi’s long commentary as the only satisfying one (Averroes and
Aouad 26). The Book of Rhetoric was first (and only) translated into French in
1968 by Jacques Langhade. As such, both the fact that it was discovered less than
24
Aouad distinguishes between long and middle commentaries. While both types cite and explain
the source text, in the latter there is no distinction between explanation and citation. In opposition
to the comprehensive approach of both of those types, the short commentary is restricted to the
most important and necessary parts only. Averroes and Maroun Aouad, Commentaire Moyen À La
Rhétorique D'aristote (Paris: Vrin, 2002) 26.
40
60 years ago and that it has not been translated into more languages can be said to
have played a role in the limited modern repercussion of the text. As I try to show,
the fact that the text has not been properly explored before is not due to it being of
little relevance.
The treatise begins with an invocation to Allah, “the Most Gracious, Most
Merciful,” which is the standard prayer recited by Muslims at the beginning of any
endeavor. Then, al-Farabi first describes and situates the art of rhetoric as a
syllogistic art. As such, his treatise of rhetoric will be the seventh of his eight
books on logic. According to al-Farabi, logic is “the art which includes the things
which lead the rational faculty toward right thinking” (Al-Farabi and Dunlop 230).
On the other hand, syllogistic arts “are those which, when their parts are integrated
and perfected have as their action thereafter the employment of syllogism” (ibid.).
The syllogistic arts are five: “philosophy, the art of dialectic, the sophistic art, the
art of rhetoric, and the art of poetry” (ibid.). Following the steps of Black, who
analyze his theory of the rhetorical syllogism -the enthymeme- in al-Farabi but
speak to others by means of statements that are excellent in persuading about each
and every one of the possible matters that are such as to be preferred or avoided”
("Aphorisms" 35). Three elements are worth considering in that definition. First,
“persuasion is indeed, the ultimate goal of the acts of rhetoric” (Deux Ouvrages
25
“In all the ten genres” Al-Farabi, Deux Ouvrages Inédits Sur La Rhétorique, trans. Jacques
Langhade and Mario Grignaschi (Beyrouth: Dar el-Machreq, 1986) 30.
41
30). The question that arises is whether persuasion is the only goal. It seems that
al-Farabi’s answer is positive. To this extent, he affirms that “rhetoric has been
instituted only to convince” (58).26 And yet, related to persuasion there is a net of
other functions that al-Farabi will not deny. One example is the creation of
necessary and possible opinions, which the author characterizes as the proper task
of rhetoric. Also, rhetoric enlarges our thought and expands our viewpoints. In this
envisioned by the Abbasids) notes that “persuasion, even when it achieves the
strongest stage, necessarily lends space for the opposition, more or less [space],
between rhetoric and probability. In his Risalah on Logic, al-Farabi contends that
“rhetorical discourse seeks to satisfy the hearer by what will partially content his
soul, without reaching certainty” (231). In his treatise on rhetoric he will stress this
regarding that a thing is or it is not; and what one believes can be different from
the thing itself” (30). Opinion is opposed to certitude, which is “to believe in the
truthfulness of that which cannot be refuted” (ibid.) Contrary to what they might
seem, they are the two sides of the same coin: “they are both [opinion and
certitude] a point of view” (32); that is to say they both believe “that a thing is
such or is not such” (ibid.). The difference is that while certitude is expressed only
26
Al-Farabi does not make a distinction between “persuade” and “convince.” In Langhade’s
translation to French these terms are used interchangeably for the Arabic root “”ﻗﻨﻊ. I argue below
that the connotations of this term bring al-Farabi closer to the meaning of conviction than to
persuasion.
42
Necessity
Opinion
(persuasion)
Possibility
Point of
view
Certitude Necessity
The third aspect of the definition is the importance of “the other.” This element
certainty because “the firmest opinion is defined in relation to each particular man
and not in relation to itself” (Deux Ouvrages 40). Persuasion does not take place in
the realm of universal abstract Truth but on personal everyday encounters (36).
Furthermore, the relevance of the audience can be seen in the Arabic term for
this Arabic term seems to stress the role of the listener. Paraphrasing Perelman, it
seems the listener is content with the reasoning of the speaker rather than
follows:
view about it, then he examines it further as much as he can. If, in this way
the opposed to this point of view does not appear, nor does the truthfulness
27
Al-Farabi establishes a dichotomy between these two terms: “propositions in which discourse is
expressed and which form discourse are either necessary ( )ﺿﺮؤرﻳﺔor possible (( ”)ﻣﻤﻜﻨﺔRhetoric 32)
43
of its opposite, due to the fact that the opposed to his point of view is
hidden -hidden regarding him- then he has proven this point of view
Al-Farabi will present the same process again at other points of his treatise (36,
60, 62). The emphasis on this process of investigation suggests first that al-Farabi
“persuasion is not diminished by the fact that one perceives opposition to it” (ibid.
36). Instead, it is strengthened “when one has researched and has not found
opposition or opposition has been refuted” (ibid. 40). Therefore, the listener plays
a very important and active role in the rhetorical situation, exerting a search for
persuasion.
the treatise, which is about the aspects that lead to persuasion. There are twelve
which I will consider later; 2) “the moral excellence of the speaker and the defect
of his adversary” (70); 3) psychological influence over the listeners “to incline
their hearts to adhere to the speaker and to consider as false what the adversary
says” (72); 4) filling the listeners with enthusiasm and making them change their
smaller, more beautiful or uglier than it is; 6) the written habits which should be
either stressed if they are in tune with one’s claims or declared false if they work
trustworthy group” (76); 8) the desire of the speaker because he will expect a
benefit if he speaks the truth and fear a harm if his lie is discovered. Thus,
with great harm for making and keeping a position, if he keeps the position
he is sincere. (78)
The ninth point al-Farabi briefly mentions are challenges. To this extent, he
cites Galen who is said to have bet 10,000 dinars to whomever could show him
that the beginning of the nerve was in the heart. Related to this point, is aspect
number ten: “the oath of the speaker to back his affirmation” (78). The last two,
and most probably least,28 aspects are related to the canon of delivery: 11) “the
facial expression of the speaker, his physiognomy, the attitude of his members and
their aspect, or what he makes while he speaks” (ibid.); and 12) “the way of
speaking, the voice and intonation that accompany the declaration” (79).
There are several ideas that should be noted about al-Farabi’s catalogue of
persuasion devices. First, it merges together many of the aspects that Greek and
Roman classical scholars had rigidly tried to separate and analyze separately. In
this sense, his list combines not only technical and non-technical proofs, but also
elements of logos, pathos and ethos, and elements of invention, style and delivery.
Also, he emphasizes the importance of the listener again in his enumeration of the
aspects that cause persuasion. This importance can be seen in his theory of the
28
Al-Farabi implies there is a hierarchy of persuasion elements at the top of which is the
enthymeme and the comparison (Cf. below). He does not, however, make any further specifications
about the ranking of each element but the fact that he starts his enumeration with the enthymeme
may be taken as a sign of the fact that the enumeration may indeed be presented in order of
importance.
45
The enthymeme, together with the comparison, goes “by far, before all the
persuasive elements and these two elements are “the first among the things that
persuade.” Thus, their nature and dignity is superior by far and they are the
elements by which the art of rhetoric gains its coherence. Also, the other ten
features “are used as a help for the enthymemes and the comparisons” (ibid.).
Accordingly, he will focus the second part of his treatise on the enthymeme, which
follows:
which one uses omitting one of these two conjoint premisses. We call it
One can wonder whether this definition differs much from Aristotle’s notion of
the enthymeme and I would argue that the answer is no. The crux is, however, that
29
Damir. It is related to the root “conscience” in Arabic. It means “hidden.”
46
importance of the audience and the conception of the enthymeme as a full -rather
than truncated- syllogism, where one of the premisses is not cut off but hidden to
McBurney, al-Farabi will stress the possibility of reaching certainty through the
syllogism only in appearance” (84). This adds to the discussion of point of view
The fact that enthymemes can reach valid knowledge as the logical syllogism
been posited that al-Farabi is accounting for the validity of the Prophet
Muhammad’s rhetoric.31 I do not contest that. I do, however, think that al-Farabi’s
elements: the Quran (book of revelation) and the Sunna (the traditions instituted by
Muhammad). Both of these elements work to dictate how men should behave.
Thus, for example, the Quran says that one should engage in daily prayers and the
Sunna specifies how the prayer should be conducted. Nevetheless, the Quran and
30
Bitzer understands the production of enthymemes as follows: “The speaker draws the premises
for his proofs from propositions which members of his audience would supply if he were to
proceed by question and answer.” Thus, the successful construction of an enthymeme is a product
of “the joint efforts of speaker and audience” Lloyd F. Bitzer, "Aristotle's Enthymeme Revisited,"
Quarterly Journal of Speech 45 (1959): 408.
31
Al-Farabi tries then “to provide for Muhammad’s rhetoric. This inclusion (…) permits
him to contend that some rhetorical propositions, such as those offered by Muhammad,
might have the certitude attached to necessity” Charles E. Butterworth, "The Rhetorician
and His Relationship to the Community: Three Accounts of Aristotle's Rhetoric," Islamic
Theology and Philosophy, ed. Michael E. Marmura (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1984) 115.
47
the Sunna together do not account for the whole range of human acts and it is at
Fiqh interprets both the Quran and the Sunna and provides a guide whenever
there is no regulation in either of them. To do that it has to deduce new law from
previous one. This is a syllogistic process and consequently the major process of
Fiqh is qiyas, which is the term al-Farabi uses to refer to the syllogism. Then, as
Smirnov points out, there was a school in Islam that negated the ability of reason
to gain new knowledge (437). Al-Farabi himself alludes to the “negators of the
syllogism” (82). According to this school you cannot generate new valid
and integrity of the syllogism throughout his work. In his Book on Rhetoric he
specifically defended the rhetorical syllogism. Thus, he did not only back the
Fiqh. To this extent, it should be noted that qiyas is not the only source of Fiqh; the
frame of the controversy about Fiqh, it will be easier to grasp and contextualize not
only his defense of the enthymeme (the rhetorical syllogism) but also his emphasis
on the importance of the listener, community and common sense. Thus, his theory
approach to Sharia.
32
Aristotle establishes that the conclusion of a syllogism must be different from the premisses. The
invalid leap that negators of the syllogism denounce is thus inlaid in the definition of deduction: “A
deduction, then, is an argument in which certain things being supposed, something different from
the suppositions result of necessity through them” Aristotle, Robin Smith and Aristotle, Topics.
Books I and Viii, with Excerpts from Related Texts, Clarendon Aristotle Series (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1997).
48
Al-Farabi did not invent his theory of rhetoric out of the blue; he
acknowledged his debt to both Plato and Aristotle.33 I argue that analyzing the
extent to which each of them influences al-Farabi can help us better understand his
theory and context. Furthermore, it may contribute to counter the main trend in
scholarly work about al-Farabi, which is centered around al-Farabi’s politics and
Strauss. Cf. Chapter one). This study adds the perspective of al-Farabi’s rhetorical
been mentioned before, rhetoric for al-Farabi is one of the syllogistic arts and, as
Thus, the possibility of reaching certainty through the enthymeme moves al-
Farabi away from what is traditionally understood to be Plato’s stand (an idealist
and positivist for whom philosophy was superior to rhetoric and other arts). It
33
“These two sages are the fountainheads of philosophy, the originators of its beginnings and
fundamentals, the fulfillers of its ends and branches. We depend upon them for what is minor and
for what is major with respect to it” Al-Farabi, Alfarabi's Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans.
Muhsin Mahdi, Agora Editions (New York, N.Y.: Free Press of Glencoe, 1962) 126.
34
“That which was taught [in logic] at that time was up to the end of the assertoric figures [of the
syllogism]. But Abü Nasr al-Farabi says about himself that he studied with Yühannâ ibn Hailân up
to the end of Anal. Post (kitab al-burhan), The part [of the two Analytics] which comes after the
assertoric figures (of the syllogism [i.e., which comes after Anal. Pr., I, 7]) was called "the part
which is not read" [i.e., in the lecture-curriculum] until [the time when] one read that; for it became
standard [in logical study] afterwards. When the matter came to Muslim teachers one read from the
assertoric figures as far as a man was able to read. And thus Abu Nasr [al-Farabi] says that he
himself read [i.e., under a teacher] up to the end of Anal. Post.” Ibn Abi Usaibia, Uyun Al-Anba Fi
Tabaqat Al-Tibba, August Müller ed. (Farnborough: Gregg International Publishers, 1882).
49
should be noted, however, that this need not be al-Farabi’s understanding of Plato.
Indeed, al-Farabi wrote a whole treatise on the harmonization of “the two sages:
Plato the divine and Aristotle” to counter the claim that there is disagreement
between the two ("Harmonization" 125). Thus, he for example analyzes the stance
of Plato and Aristotle on the syllogism. According to Themistius and his school,
Plato would only declare as necessary the conclusions of a syllogism where both
premisses were necessary, while Aristotle accepted that the syllogism whose
premisses are a mixture of necessary and contingent, with the major being
necessary, the conclusion will be necessary too. Al-Farabi’s response was to affirm
Both Najjar and Fakhry ("Reconciliation") have probed this part of al-Farabi’s
corpus. They have suggested that al-Farabi’s goal was to assure Islamic scholars
that the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle were not antithetical to Islam35 and
with that goal he freely interpreted the Greek philosophers adapting their thought
Indeed, his response about the Platonic stance on the enthymeme may not be
very accurate but it shows that al-Farabi did not understand the Plato / Aristotle
the one hand we have rhetoric as an art which mainly uses the enthymeme and
comparison to persuade. On the other, he would posit a political use of the rhetoric
35
In this sense, that al-Farabi’s interpretation goes along the lines of Medieval interpretations of
classical heritage in Europe that try to show the compatibility of classical thought with Christianity
(Saint Augustine, Saint Thomas Aquinas).
50
related to the figure of the Islamic ruler which he would most probably understand
as Platonic. This Platonic inspiration can be seen even in the way he referred to the
ruler: the “king in truth” (“Aphorisms” 37). I will argue, however, that this figure
Al-Farabi delineated his version of the philosopher king all across his work. In
the previous chapter, I outlined his characterization, duties and attributes with a
to lead the community towards happiness through knowledge. I would now like to
emphasize another aspect of this figure: how he should exercise his power:
realizing the particular instances of it in nations and cities. There are two
citizens in doing the acts that issue from the practical states of character by
arousing in them the resolution to do these acts; the states of character and
the acts issuing from them should be as it were enraptured by them. The
35)
For al-Farabi, rhetoric is an art “of major usefulness … that guides the
ruler’s role is that of an instructor. This instructor introduces national and citizen
virtues. I have already pointed out in chapter two the value of community in Islam,
could have been a major influence in al-Farabi’s ruler but it is not the Plato that
Popper criticized in The Open Society. Popper’s Plato created a closed society
where criticism is not given any space. Nevertheless, as it was put forward in
chapters two and three, the Islamic leader in al-Farabi is indeed exposed to
criticism. Perhaps it is the Plato of the Republic who complained that education
was not in the hands of the philosophers (606e1-5), though it has been suggested
that “the political dimension of the philosophical teacher was totally lost on
Neoplatonism” (Morewedge 68) and indeed one of the most common analysis of
a historical point of view, al-Farabi’s Plato or Platonic politics had not existed
One solution to the puzzle could be to look for a different source. In this sense,
Isocrates, the educator, provides us with an excellent match for al-Farabi’s theory.
On the one hand, he shared the Islamic sense of responsibility for which the ruler
pedagogical logos fits very well within Isocrates’ frame of the educated city. Thus
36
Cf. Al-Farabi’s conception of imagination in chapter 3. Hamlet could not have been inspired in
an Islamic country.
52
community.38 His striving for a Pan-Hellenism would very well fit the Arabic
patriotism always in mind, Isocrates, as a teacher, labored to perfect the minds and
the characters of his fellow-citizens” (Neserius 314), the Prophet Muhammad had
136). In both cases, al-Farabi’s and Isocrates’, this idea of a Pan-nation was in
trouble and one can understand their rhetorics and their emphasis on the societal
Medieval Islamic Rhetoric, which as has been presented acknowledges only the
legacy of Plato (or Neo-Platonism) and Aristotle. On the basis of such an influence
questions arise (as the problem of a decidedly political Plato to which Mahdi
referred in the cite above). I suggest that al-Farabi’s pedagogical logos is not fully
between the West and the Middle East. My study advances the study of Muir, who
was the first (and only) scholar to hint in 2001 at a possible relationship between
Isocrates and Medieval Islam. His focus was on politics and on al-Ghazali (1058-
1111) and Ibn Khaldoun (1332-1406), scholars posterior to al-Farabi. I argue that
syllogistic art capable of attaining certainty where the values of the community
and the role of the listener are heightened. I also analyzed the elements that create
with the context was established that posited al-Farabi as a defender of syllogism
relation to Isocrates which helps us better understand both the context and the
rhetorical theory of our Islamic author. In the next chapter, I will not analyze the
external but the internal relations between rhetoric and the other arts and fields of
al-Farabi’s thought.
54
CHAPTER V
In the previous chapter I introduced rhetoric as one of the five syllogistic arts
and probed the relationship between al-Farabi and Greek classical figures. In this
chapter I will analyze first the relations within al-Farabi’s corpus, i.e. between
rhetoric and three other syllogistic arts: philosophy, dialectic, and poetics. Second,
I will explore the relationship between rhetoric, politics and religion. My aim is to
Let us start with philosophy which is one of “the human things through which
nations and citizens attain earthly happiness in this life and supreme happiness in
the life beyond” (Philosophy 13). This goal is not exclusive of philosophy. Indeed,
it permeates the whole of al-Farabi’s corpus. Thus, all the other arts will share the
virtues and practical arts”).39 The contribution of philosophy to that aim is,
however, distinct and essential. As I will try to explain, philosophy is the main
them, if he perceives their ideas themselves with his intellect, and his
imagining them through similarities that imitate them, and assent to what is
39
Apodeictics, sophistics, rhetoric and poetics.
55
Thus, al-Farabi does not limit knowledge to the domain of philosophy. Indeed,
(Philosophy 44). These other types of knowledge will follow philosophy (Letters
89). What is more, philosophy can serve as a touchstone against which we can
measure them.
has a very realistic approach to philosophy and acknowledges that in many cases
sophistry to test its opinions (ibid.). This point is also explained in his treatise on
rhetoric with the assertion that “rhetoric has in common with the dialectic, and
sophistry that, in all the three, one investigates and false points of views are
unveiled” (Deux Ouvrages 62). It can therefore be concluded that while rhetoric
and the other arts reach knowledge and discern false opinions, their intellectual
40
To this extent, Kemal notes how rhetorical ploys in al-Farabi “stand in need of a philosophical
analysis to explain their use by clarifying their nature, validity and potential” Salim Kemal, The
Philosophical Poetics of Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes : The Aristotelian Reception (London ;
New York: Routledge Curzon, 2003) 9.
56
Practice is virtuous and correct only when a human being has become truly
cognizant of the virtues that are truly virtues, become truly cognizant of the
virtues that are presumed to be virtues yet are not like that … This is a state
("Aphorisms" 61)
knowledge. Once people know about what ought to be preferred and avoid what
ought to be avoided, they will prefer and avoid accordingly. Thus, virtue is
dependent upon virtue (2). Al-Farabi’s quotation above also shows the fact that
knowledge needs not be only about the virtues themselves but also about how the
virtues are perceived. This ties very well with the importance of the audience that
al-Farabi introduced in his rhetorical theory. We shall see it also ties very well
The elements that relate rhetoric, philosophy, and politics are again virtue and
[i.e. happiness], unless they are distributed among a very large association
41
“Political science investigates happiness first of all … Then it investigates the voluntary actions,
ways of life, moral habits, states of characters, and dispositions” Al-Farabi, "Book of Religion,"
trans. Charles E. Butterworth, The Political Writings: Selected Aphorisms and Other Texts, ed.
Charles E. Butterworth (Ithaca: Cornell University Press 2001) 101.
57
association in the same way that the organs of a human being cooperate,
through the capacities in each, to perfect the purpose of the whole body.
("Religion" 102)
cooperation among the citizens” (28). Hence the interrelation between philosophy,
politics and happiness: happiness can only be reached in the virtuous city. Next, I
would like to highlight the central role that rhetoric plays in that triangle.
I have already alluded to the fact that rhetoricians are one of the cornerstones
in al-Farabi’s virtuous city. I related it to the figure of the ideal ruler, who should
37). He should also persuade the citizens about “each and every one of the possible
matters that are such as to be preferred or avoided” (Aphorisms 35). Now that al-
complement them. To that extent, it should be noted that knowledge is, using
Paredes Gandía’s term, a collective enterprise that should engage the whole of
society. Thus, it should reach not only the cultural elite but all the citizens.
42
Paredes Gandía (26) notices how this idea of investigation as a shared partnership was already
present in Aristotle but he contends that al-Farabi advanced Aristotle’s idea positing that all races
of all times should be part of this voyage: “He who looks for truth cares for nothing else but it, truth
is not degraded nor loses its value due to whoever pronounces or transmits it” Al-Kindi and A.
Ivry, Al-Kindi's Metaphysics (Albany: SUNY Press, 1974) 58.
58
In this context rhetoric is crucial because “Rhetoric is the best to persuade the
common people about the things that they attend to, to the extent of the knowledge
human good rather than a divine one. Therefore, it is defined in terms of and
serves human happiness and as such it should reach everyone in the virtuous city
(2).
Rulers should make sure knowledge reaches everyone and to that extent al-
integrated within the political structure of the virtuous city. It reflects the
syllogistic art capable of knowledge and its focus towards the listener. Thus al-
Farabi’s corpus creates a coherent and cohesive whole where parts are interrelated
and interdependent. This feature will differentiate him from the situation we have
which philosophy and politics are not separate. I am arguing that such a world can
not only be found in al-Farabi, it can also be expanded if we heed his integration of
Both the art of rhetoric and the art of poetry are syllogistic. The rhetorical
defines it and explains it explicitly. The situation is different with the poetic
syllogism. As Deborah Black has argued, there is no textual proof that al-Farabi
59
dialectical, nor rhetorical, nor sophistical, and which is, despite this,
physiognomy, and the like, among the things having the force of a
252)
The definition is mainly in the negative though al-Farabi makes it clear that
there is such thing as a poetical syllogism. This is of relevance because the logical
status of poetics will not be inferior to the other arts. To this extent, many authors
have noticed how important language is for the Islamic culture, especially for its
leaders. The Prophet Muhammad was born in the Quraishi tribe, which was
famous for the beauty of its Arabic dialect, and was raised by the Banu Saad, who,
again, are reputed for their speech. Also, Muhammad will refer to himself as the
most Arab in the sense that his language is the best cared for (Paredes Gandía 30).
Following Muhammad, the ruler will also be expected to have both an excellent
conceives of rhetoric and dialectic as sister arts of language. He makes this point
explicit in his theory about the specificity of language that relates to the
philosophical fight between grammar (the art of right expression) and logic (the art
of right thinking) over the control of the faculty of language. The Islamic bassoon
60
(al-Farabi) mediated between both sides and posited that logic rules over the
faculty of language in general while grammar rules over the actual implementation
aspects of language while grammar would act in the domain of specific languages
and communities. It is within this second domain of specificity that poetics and
Poetics is thus very closely related to rhetoric but there are also differences
between the binding, cohesive power of rhetoric, which induces assent, as opposed
to the separating force of the imagination, which makes the soul of the hearer to
flee ("Aphorisms" 36). Also, in his Risalah on Logic, al-Farabi deepens on the
differences between poetry and the other syllogistic arts (of which rhetoric is a
part). First, he defines poetical discourse as that which “seeks to represent the
object and suggest it in speech, as the art of sculpture represents different kinds of
animals and other objects by bodily labours” (231). Then, he differentiates it from
The relation of the art of poetry to the other syllogistic arts is as the relation
to the skilful conduct of armies. Similarly those who represent with their
bodies, limbs, and voices represent many things in what they do.
Nevertheless, the relationship between both rhetoric and poetry is very strong; so
61
strong that they sometimes interact. In this sense, as Kemal points out, poetry can
The last syllogistic art whose relationship to rhetoric I will discuss is dialectic.
interlocutor in the things which are known and notorious” (Al-Farabi and Dunlop
231). Thus, both rhetoric and dialectic act on the hearer and their points of view.
This is in line with al-Farabi’s previous affirmation that rhetoric, dialectic and
sophistry can be used to test opinions (Letters 89) because they investigate points
of view discerning those that are false (Deux Ouvrages 62). The difference
between both of them is that while dialectic strives for certainty, rhetoric can work
Another difference between rhetoric on the one hand and dialectic on the other
firmly established credo, both of them will be opposed to religion and will
something and in the refutation of that. When dialectic and sophistry begin
to be applied to the ideas that have been firmly established among the
followers of a religion, these will lose strength, and will be put in doubt.
(Letters 92)
sophistry. But there seems to be a difference between the two latter and the former
in the sense that they can go counter the established beliefs in a community while
rhetoric would work from them. Thus, its domain is circumscribed within the local
62
boundedness of rhetoric is not exclusive; all logical arts are to that extent a
controversy between logic and grammar “where language deals with intelligible
meanings, there it follows the rules of grammar and logic” (al-Farabi, qtd. in 15)
Finally, al-Farabi introduced another syllogistic art: sophistry, but he did not
powers but one does not have enough information as to analyze any further the
the differences and similarities among rhetoric on the one hand and three other
syllogistic arts (philosophy, poetics and dialectic) on the other. Something that all
these arts have in common is their contribution to human happiness, which is al-
Farabi’s major goal. This search for happiness, relates them to religion. In the
remainder of the chapter, I will examine the relationship between religion and the
restricted with stipulations and prescribed for a community by their first ruler, who
seeks to obtain through their practicing a specific purpose with respect to them or
by means of them” ("Religion" 93). Two points should be noticed. First, the
circumscription of religion to the sphere of opinions and actions ties it to the art of
rhetoric: they both occupy themselves with the same material. Second, this
material is related to humans: religion is not focused towards the divinity but
63
with rhetoric but there are differences too, especially the stress al-Farabi places on
the first ruler. While rhetoric made the listener central, it seems that the central
element in religion is the speaker, the first ruler. Nevertheless, the ruler loses
neither the connection to the community nor the responsibility in front of them: “If
the first ruler is virtuous and his rulership truly virtuous, then in what he prescribes
he seeks only to obtain, for himself and for everyone under his rulership, the
ultimate happiness that is truly happiness; and that religion will be virtuous
religion” (ibid.).
The opposite of the virtuous ruler is the ignorant one. He will either pursue
ignorant goods or will pursue them for himself only. This is relevant inasmuch as
focused on: the relationship between knowledge (philosophy) and religion. Also,
assertion that “al-Farabi makes philosophy, not revelation, the judge of truth and
falsehood” (95). Within this frame, religion is, like rhetoric, at the service of
philosophy” (Religion 97). In its turn, religious knowledge is dependent upon the
individual: “Thus the determined opinions in the virtuous religion are either the
truth or a likeness of the truth. In general, truth is what a human being ascertains,
This is another characteristic that relates rhetoric and religion because both share a
The importance of the context and the listener is central in both religion and
rhetoric. This reminds us of the fact that knowledge does not exist in a sterile-ized
vacuum: it breathes and sweats. I argue that it even loves. Gómez Nogales
suggested that “love is the source and goal of knowledge” in al-Farabi (98). He
cites the description al-Farabi made of the soul’s faculties where he put the heart
as the principal organ due to the fact that it regulated the heat that all the other
powers of the human body need to work properly. Al-Farabi equates love and
happiness (happiness being the goal of the syllogistic arts): “the more something
enjoys its own essence and the greater pleasure and happiness it feels about it the
more it likes its essence and the greater is the pride it takes in it” (Perfect State 87).
His study concludes that “none of the faculties can be deemed perfect if it is not
accompanied by love.”43
because it shows that happiness is related to love, and love brings in the socio-
personal element that rhetoric provides in its theory of the enthymeme. The focus
power of rhetoric and as such it contributes not only to the creation of knowledge
but also to the creation of love and a feeling of community. Opposed to this
concrete and earthly love, we have a pan-Arab religious love which is the ultimate
love to be reached in the afterlife. There is a distinction, then, with the more
43
“The reason for the nutritive power in man is no other than service to the body; also, external
senses and imagination serve both the body and intellectual power” Al-farabi, qtd. in Salvador
Gómez Nogales, La Política Como Única Ciencia Religiosa En Al-Farabi, Cuadernos Del
Seminario De Estudios De Filosofía Y Pensamiento Islámicos (Madrid: Instituto Hispano-Arabe de
Cultura, 1980) 99.
65
the one hand and three other syllogistic arts together with religion on the other. To
this extent, rhetoric is related to philosophy in that the latter precedes the former.
Rhetoric usually follows and is checked by philosophy, though this trend can be
reversed. Then, rhetoric is related to poetics in that both arts pertain to the realm of
the specific and the concrete rather than the universal. They however differ in the
fact that rhetoric creates a communal reality while poetics imitates it with a focus
on the individual. Finally, rhetoric is related to dialectic in that both act on the
hearers and their points of view discerning valid from invalid positions. While
dialectic works its discernment in the domain of certainty, rhetoric works both in
certainty and possibility. Also, rhetoric is related to politics in that the former is an
indispensable political tool of the virtuous city that facilitates the sharing of
element, the function of love in al-Farabi’s corpus and its relation to happiness,
which relates rhetoric and religion in their focus on the individual as a member of
CHAPTER VI
Throughout the previous chapters I have analyzed both the argument al-Farabi
constructs and hinted at its implications. This chapter puts together al-Farabi’s
approach to rhetoric with a stronger focus on its implications. At the same time I
position this study in relation to further research possibilities, not only suggesting
My first research question targeted the context out of which al-Farabi’s theory
space for dissent. In this sense, they resorted to Persian and Greek scholarship to
quell the Umayyad cultural background. On the one hand, this had the positive
side effect of introducing Greek classical learning to the Islamic world. On the
other hand, the Abbasids only supported that interpretation of Persian and Greek
flies to wanton boys were any dissenters to the Abbasids. Following Mernissi, I
suggested that rather than for sport, the Abbasids killed their opposition for fear of
loosing their power. What is more, the Abbasids not only killed their opponents,
they also stigmatized them as external to the Islamic tradition. One of the
Throughout this study I have tried to present aspects of al-Farabi which relate
him closely to the Mutazilah. I have especially focused on the third-way approach
67
from which the Mutazilites derive their name. Accordingly, I have defined al-
different stances and elements to create a third-way rhetoric. This merging is made
explicit and clear in his catalog of persuasion devices, his harmonization of Plato
and Aristotle, or his inclusive approach to an Organon that features both the
poetics and the rhetoric. Similarly, al-Farabi’s both-and rhetoric allows for
certainty and possibility, for persuasion and opposition, for the individual and the
community.
These three both-ands define a rhetoric which does not shun knowledge or
reflection upon knowledge: rhetoric is a tool in the quest for and the spread of
knowledge and in this sense the main aspect of al-Farabi’s logos is its pedagogical
nature. Rhetoric instructs civic and national virtues in the inhabitants of the city. It
can be seen, first, in al-Farabi’s demand that persuasion allows space for
presented as in line with the purest etymologically sense of “going to the source of
water;” and, thirdly, in his blend of the individual and the community in his
(rhetoric, dialectic, poetics and sophistry). In its turn, all knowledge is dependent
upon love. Dante ended his Divine Comedy stating in Paradise that it is “love
which moves the sun and the other stars,” a sentence that could have been uttered
by al-Farabi, for whom love is equated to happiness, the ultimate goal of al-
Farabi’s system. Rhetoric contributes to this end first with the creation of a
community; second with a focus on the other; third with the allowance for a space
conceptualized tragedy as
The silence inside you when the roaring crowd acclaims the winner—so
that you think of a film without a sound track, mouths agape and no sound
coming out of them, a clamor that is not more than picture; and you, the
Comedy than to the bleak perspective of Jean Anouilh’s tragedy. A rhetoric whose
intellective and communal power offers a tool for the people, of the people, and by
the people. Such a rhetoric would disquiet Claudius-like Abbasids and their
successors, whose strategy was to impose upon it a scarlet F. I have tried to show
that al-Farabi’s thought is not foreign to the Islamic tradition. Instead, it stands as a
model for modern day Islamic scholars, who can turn to this theory of rhetoric in
order to reflect towards a more open and brighter society which does not lose its
Islamic essence. To this extent, al-Farabi provides us with a model of thought that
matches Mernissi’s and Ramadan’s call for a Humanist Islamic society and
culture.
69
The applicability of al-Farabi’s thought in today’s world shifts the focus of the
study from the past to the present and on to the future. Accordingly, I will now
present two future research possibilities that spring from this study. The first one
leads to other Medieval Islamic scholars such as Avicenna and Averroes. One can
“immediate spiritual disciple and successor” (Fakhry Al-Farabi, Founder 4), would
rhetoric.
learn that his father was “entrusted with the governing of a village in one of the
royal estates of Bukhara” (17). As such, Avicenna was able to benefit from an
also had access to the learned circle of Sultan Nuh ibn Mansur. This friendship
with the ruling class created problems for him when the Turkish Qarakhnids allied
with the governor of Khorasan against Nuh ibn Mansur in 999. Due to the period’s
instability, he had to forsake Bukhara (Avicenna and Jauzajanai 43) and live in
several places of eastern and central Iran for the rest of his life.
a theory closer to Aristotle than the latter. For example, there is a clearer
distinction between artistic and non-artistic proofs and within artistic proofs:
And the proofs can be natural, not artificial, like witnesses and contracts;
and some are non-natural artificial and these are rhetorical proofs. And
rhetorical proofs take place because of three: the speaker’s personality and
70
his appearance and the appearance of his enemy, and the alluring of the
(Kitab Al-Khataba)
the intelligible truths are acquired only when the middle term of a
intuition [divine spirit], which is an act of mind by which the mind itself
immediately perceives the middle term … but sometimes the middle term
In this way, Avicenna introduces a divine element into humans, for their
intuition acts as a divine spark which relates them with the divinity. This divinity
rational soul into “a practical and a theoretical faculty, both of which are
considerations. This faculty has certain correspondence with the animal faculties
(ibid.). On the other hand, theoretical intelligence is the part that “forms the
71
ordinary and commonly accepted opinions concerning actions, as, for instance,
that lies and tyranny are evil and other similar premises which, in books of logic,
have been clearly distinguished from the purely rational ones” (ibid.). Avicenna
finds again within the human soul a double nature: Intuitive and divine on the one
hand (the theoretical faculty); earthly and pragmatic on the other (the practical
one).
endows man not only with divinity but also with self-sufficiency insofar as the
the form of all things contained in the active intelligence are imprinted on
his soul either all at once or nearly so, not that he accepts them merely on
authority but on account of their logical order which encompasses all the
which are known only through their causes possess no rational certainty.
This is a kind of prophetic inspiration, indeed its highest form and the one
most fitted to be called Divine Power; and it is the highest human faculty.
Once again, Avicenna places within a characteristic related to man and his
earthliness (intelligence) a divine element. At the same time, he also lays the
foundations for the fact that the art of rhetoric as persuasion, as a syllogistic
This aspect can also be seen in prophets, who combine judgment and intuition
-rationality and divinity. Indeed they are the paramount of eloquence insofar as
72
The Book which bears no falsehood before or behind it, the revelation of the
Allwise and Allpowerful speaks in much the same sense: Call men unto the
path of thy Lord [God instructs His prophet] –that is, the true religion- with
wisdom –that is by way of proof – that is for those who can handle it – and
with fair persuasion – that is, rhetoric, for those who cannot manage
Persuasion is a requisite for the prophet who, in turn, is the prototype of human
divinity. Both elements are to be heeded. Indeed, one cannot separate the
humanness from the divinity of the prophet and the law. In this sense, Avicenna
comments that anyone who establishes rules and social regulations “must be in the
position to speak to men, and to constrain them to accept the code; he must
therefore be a man” (Theology 42, my emphasis). This concerns the prophet but
also normal citizens.44 In this way, men are made to share God’s divinity and are
to function on their own creating law and regulation based on their society.
more, man is defined by eloquence, which can be seen in how the Koran describes
God’s creation of man with the paratactic structure “He created man, He taught
44
This is the word Avicenna uses. This word relates, again, Avicenna to Isocrates. For Isocrates
and citizenship see L. Massey, "On the Origin of Citizenship in Education: Isocrates, Rhetoric, and
Kairos," Journal of Public Affairs (1997), Takis Poulakos, Speaking for the Polis: Isocrates
Rhetorical Education (Columbia, SC.: University of South Carolina Press, 1997), Takis Poulakos
and David Depew, Isocrates and Civic Education (Austin: University of Texas Press, 2004).
73
him eloquent speech” (The Quran 55.2-3), juxtaposing the creation of man and his
eloquence.45
Thus, I would not claim that Avicenna (nor al-Farabi) make theology
art which is, to a certain extent, needed by religion; and which, again to a certain
extent, validates it.46 Thus the eloquence of the Koran is its hallmark of
authenticity:
And if you are in doubt as to what we have revealed to our servant then
produce a sura like it. (The Quran 2.21-23 qtd. in Makdisi 142)
Or do they say, ‘this man has forged it’? answer them: ‘bring then a sura [a
Koranic verse] like it and call to your aid anyone who can besides God, if it
be it you speak the truth. (The Quran 10.38-9, qtd. in Makdisi 142)
The aspects I have introduced above suggest that there are differences between
al-Farabi and Avicenna -for example, the latter stresses more the divine-intuitive
rhetoric. The figure of Averroes provides us with another step in the investigation.
Another fascinating area of study that could develop from this study is the
influence of Greek classical scholars other than Plato and Aristotle. My hypothesis
is that the Isocratean flavor that I found in al-Farabi can also be savored in other
45
To this respect, Razi claims that “[i]t is as though God performs the act of creating man only
when He has taught him eloquence” In George Makdisi, The Rise of Humanism in Classical Islam
and the Christian West : With Special Reference to Scholasticism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1990) 143. It is also suggested that eloquence is “applied solely to God and to
man as taught by God, [it] is not an attribute of any other creature, not even the angels” (143).
46
“The notion of eloquence in Islam is not simply a literary notion; it is a basic religious doctrine.”
Makdisi, Rise of Humanism 141.
74
values that I have hinted at above resonate with an Isocratean echo. As in al-
Farabi, politics and ethics are intrinsically related in Avicenna. This can be seen in
the control the ideal ruler should exert over the city regarding virtues and vices:
“Some citizens are negligent or spend extravagantly. This man [the ruler] should
prevent this from happening. And he should be able to force them to work and
paternalistic (pedagogical) public control over personal issues that may scare many
scholars which is geared towards the betterment of society and the common
that “laws and orators and private citizens must assimilate themselves to” the soul
of the city (14). To which extent can an Isocratean presence be felt in Medieval
Islam? Which is the channel that connected him with Islamic scholars? These
I do not claim, however, that these directions for further research are obstacle-
free. In the remainder of the chapter I will expose some of the problems I have
found in my own research. A relevant one is the fact that not all texts are extant.
This problem can easily be turned into an asset if we have faith in the possibility of
finding new texts. In this sense, al-Farabi’s Book of Rhetoric was found only sixty
years ago. Also, the texts that we do have are not usually translated into English.
In this study I have translated fragments into English from Spanish, Arabic,
French, German and Latin because there were no English translations. Again, this
to improve my skills in other languages. Still, it is a factor one should take into
study Islamic theories of rhetoric, I had to learn about Islam and Islamic culture
(Fiqh, Sharia, the Mutazilah, etc.) This is not a problem. Somewhat more
point, I have tried to adapt a reflective approach that guards against biases from
my cultural background. I am not all too sure that I managed to escape that
terministic screen -my cultural references are mainly western: Shakespeare, Dante,
etc. In this sense, these references suggest to me that on the one hand, the East is
not so far from the West; on the other hand, my status of outsider can give me an
insight on Islam and Islamic culture that I would lack if I was part of it.
future research possibilities that I find exciting and enriching. Judging from my
experience with this study, it promises thrill and fun for the scholar willing to
Bibliography
---. Deux Ouvrages Inédits Sur La Rhétorique. Trans. Jacques Langhade and
---. El Libro De Las Letras: Kitab Al-Huruf. Trans. José Antonio Paredes Gandía.
---. "The Harmonization of the Two Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato the Divine
---. On the Perfect State: Mabadi Ara Ahl Al-Madinat Al-Fadilah. Trans. Richard
Al-Tabari. The Return of the Caliphate to Baghdad. Trans. Franz Rosenthal. Suny
Series in near Eastern Studies. Vol. 38. 39 vols. Albany, N.Y.: State
Aristotle, Robin Smith, and Aristotle. Topics. Books I and Viii, with Excerpts
Press, 1952.
---. Avicenna on Theology. Arberry, A. J. ed. Westport, CT: Hyperion Press, 1979.
Avicenna, and Abd al-Wahid ibn Muhammad Jauzajanai. The Life of Ibn Sina; a
45 (1959): 399-408.
---. Logic and Aristotle's Rhetoric and Poetics in Medieval Arabic Philosophy.
1990.
Averroes: The Battle between Faith and Reason. 2006. Radio. BBC, October 5,
2006.
---. "The Rhetorician and His Relationship to the Community: Three Accounts of
Fackenheim, Emil L. "Al-Farabi: His Life, Times, and Thought. On the Occasion
(1951): 54-59.
Fakhry, Majid. "Al-Farabi and the Reconciliation of Plato and Aristotle." Journal
Gibbon, Edward. The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire. 3 vols. New York:
Hitti, Philip Khuri. History of the Arabs from the Earliest Times to the Present.
Isocrates. Isocrates: Speeches and Letters. Norlin, George ed. Cambridge, MA:
Kraemer, Joel L. Humanism in the Renaissance of Islam. New York: Brill, 1992.
Makdisi, George. The Rise of Humanism in Classical Islam and the Christian West
Mernissi, Fatima. Islam and Democracy: Fear of the Modern World. Reading,
Muir, James. "Notes on the Isocratic Legacy and Islamic Political Thought: The
Nagy, Albino. "Notize Intorno Alla Retorica D'al-Farabi." Rendiconti della Reale
Netton, Ian Richard. Al-Farabi and His School. Arabic Thought and Culture.
Peters, Francis E. Aristotle and the Arabs: The Aristotelian Tradition in Islam.
Poulakos, Takis. Speaking for the Polis: Isocrates Rhetorical Education. Columbia,
Poulakos, Takis, and David Depew. Isocrates and Civic Education. Austin:
Shakespeare, William. Hamlet. Jenkins, Harold ed. New York: Routledge, 1989.
82
Sluglett, Peter. "The Myth of Monarchy in the Arab World." Issam M. Fares
Smyth, William. "Rhetoric and 'Ilm Al-Balagha: Christianity and Islam." Muslim
Strauss, Leo. "Farabi's Plato." Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume. New York:
Usaibia, Ibn Abi. Uyun Al-Anba Fi Tabaqat Al-Tibba. August Müller ed.