An Introduction To Mathematics
An Introduction To Mathematics
An Introduction To Mathematics
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
Language: English
transcriber’s note
The camera-quality files for this public-domain ebook
may be downloaded gratis at
www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/41568.
AN INTRODUCTION TO
MATHEMATICS
By A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S.
London
WILLIAMS & NORGATE
of all things it is true that two and two make four. Thus
we write down as the leading characteristic of mathematics
that it deals with properties and ideas which are applica-
ble to things just because they are things, and apart from
any particular feelings, or emotions, or sensations, in any
way connected with them. This is what is meant by calling
mathematics an abstract science.
The result which we have reached deserves attention. It
is natural to think that an abstract science cannot be of
much importance in the affairs of human life, because it has
omitted from its consideration everything of real interest. It
will be remembered that Swift, in his description of Gul-
liver’s voyage to Laputa, is of two minds on this point. He
describes the mathematicians of that country as silly and
useless dreamers, whose attention has to be awakened by
flappers. Also, the mathematical tailor measures his height
by a quadrant, and deduces his other dimensions by a rule
and compasses, producing a suit of very ill-fitting clothes.
On the other hand, the mathematicians of Laputa, by their
marvellous invention of the magnetic island floating in the
air, ruled the country and maintained their ascendency over
their subjects. Swift, indeed, lived at a time peculiarly un-
suited for gibes at contemporary mathematicians. Newton’s
Principia had just been written, one of the great forces which
have transformed the modern world. Swift might just as well
have laughed at an earthquake.
But a mere list of the achievements of mathematics is an
unsatisfactory way of arriving at an idea of its importance.
NATURE OF MATHEMATICS 4
ters for the ideas of any number and some number. The
Romans would have stated the number of the year in which
this is written in the form MDCCCCX., whereas we write
it 1910, thus leaving the letters for the other usage. But this
is merely a speculation. After the rise of algebra the differen-
tial calculus was invented by Newton and Leibniz, and then
a pause in the progress of the philosophy of mathematical
thought occurred so far as these notions are concerned; and
it was not till within the last few years that it has been real-
ized how fundamental any and some are to the very nature
of mathematics, with the result of opening out still further
subjects for mathematical exploration.
Let us now make some simple algebraic statements, with
the object of understanding exactly how these fundamental
ideas occur.
(1) For any number x, x + 2 = 2 + x;
(2) For some number x, x + 2 = 3;
(3) For some number x, x + 2 > 3.
The first point to notice is the possibilities contained in
the meaning of some, as here used. Since x+2 = 2+x for any
number x, it is true for some number x. Thus, as here used,
any implies some and some does not exclude any. Again,
in the second example, there is, in fact, only one number x,
such that x + 2 = 3, namely only the number 1. Thus the
some may be one number only. But in the third example, any
number x which is greater than 1 gives x+2 > 3. Hence there
are an infinite number of numbers which answer to the some
number in this case. Thus some may be anything between
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 9
B
x P
1 N
y y
O xM 1 A X
Fig. 1.
VARIABLES 12
P
C
Q
N A
p
O v M V
Fig. 2.
line ABC, which includes all points for which p and v are
positive, and pv = 1. Thus this curved line gives a pictorial
representation of the relation holding between the volume
and the pressure. When the pressure is very big the cor-
responding point Q must be near C, or even beyond C on
the undrawn part of the curve; then the volume will be very
small. When the volume is big Q will be near to A, or be-
yond A; and then the pressure will be small. Notice that
an engineer or a physicist may want to know the particular
pressure corresponding to some definitely assigned volume.
Then we have the case of determining the unknown p when
v is a known number. But this is only in particular cases. In
considering generally the properties of the gas and how it will
behave, he has to have in his mind the general form of the
whole curve ABC and its general properties. In other words
the really fundamental idea is that of the pair of variables
satisfying the relation pv = 1. This example illustrates how
the idea of variables is fundamental, both in the applications
as well as in the theory of mathematics.
CHAPTER III
METHODS OF APPLICATION
The way in which the idea of variables satisfying a re-
lation occurs in the applications of mathematics is worth
thought, and by devoting some time to it we shall clear up
our thoughts on the whole subject.
Let us start with the simplest of examples:—Suppose that
building costs 1s. per cubic foot and that 20s. make £1.
Then in all the complex circumstances which attend the
building of a new house, amid all the various sensations
and emotions of the owner, the architect, the builder, the
workmen, and the onlookers as the house has grown to com-
pletion, this fixed correlation is by the law assumed to hold
between the cubic content and the cost to the owner, namely
that if x be the number of cubic feet, and £y the cost, then
20y = x. This correlation of x and y is assumed to be true
for the building of any house by any owner. Also, the vol-
ume of the house and the cost are not supposed to have
been perceived or apprehended by any particular sensation
or faculty, or by any particular man. They are stated in
an abstract general way, with complete indifference to the
owner’s state of mind when he has to pay the bill.
Now think a bit further as to what all this means. The
building of a house is a complicated set of circumstances. It
is impossible to begin to apply the law, or to test it, unless
amid the general course of events it is possible to recognize
METHODS OF APPLICATION 16
F =W −w
and thus
w = W − F,
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 27
Weights
The crown
Water
Fig. 3.
and
W W
(A) =
w W −F
where W and F are determined by the easy, and fairly pre-
W
cise, operation of weighing. Hence, by equation (A), is
w
W
known. But is the ratio of the weight of the crown to the
w
weight of an equal volume of water. This ratio is the same
for any lump of metal of the same material: it is now called
the specific gravity of the material, and depends only on the
intrinsic nature of the substance and not on its shape or
quantity. Thus to test if the crown were of gold, Archimedes
had only to take a lump of indisputably pure gold and find
its specific gravity by the same process. If the two specific
METHODS OF APPLICATION 28
Sun
Fig. 4.
Force
Sun
Fig. 5.
towards the sun as in the next figure (5). In fact, the force
is the gravitational attraction of the sun acting according to
the law of the inverse square of the distance, which has been
stated above.
The science of mechanics rose among the Greeks from a
consideration of the theory of the mechanical advantage ob-
tained by the use of a lever, and also from a consideration
of various problems connected with the weights of bodies. It
was finally put on its true basis at the end of the sixteenth
and during the seventeenth centuries, as the preceding ac-
count shows, partly with the view of explaining the theory
of falling bodies, but chiefly in order to give a scientific the-
ory of planetary motions. But since those days dynamics has
taken upon itself a more ambitious task, and now claims to
be the ultimate science of which the others are but branches.
The claim amounts to this: namely, that the various qual-
ities of things perceptible to the senses are merely our pe-
culiar mode of appreciating changes in position on the part
of things existing in space. For example, suppose we look
at Westminster Abbey. It has been standing there, grey and
immovable, for centuries past. But, according to modern sci-
entific theory, that greyness, which so heightens our sense of
the immobility of the building, is itself nothing but our way
of appreciating the rapid motions of the ultimate molecules,
which form the outer surface of the building and communi-
cate vibrations to a substance called the ether. Again we lay
our hands on its stones and note their cool, even tempera-
ture, so symbolic of the quiet repose of the building. But this
DYNAMICS 34
D C
A B
Fig. 6.
D C
y
r
m x
A B
Fig. 7.
lelogram law.
Also, according to the laws of motion a force is fully rep-
resented by the vector acceleration it produces in a body
of given mass. Accordingly, forces will be said to be added
when their joint effect is to be reckoned according to the
parallelogram law.
Hence for the fundamental vectors of science, namely
transportations, velocities, and forces, the addition of any
two of the same kind is the production of a “resultant” vec-
tor according to the rule of the parallelogram law.
By far the simplest type of parallelogram is a rectan-
gle, and in pure mathematics it is the relation of the single
vector AC to the two component vectors, AB and AD, at
right angles (cf. fig. 7), which is continually recurring. Let
DYNAMICS 42
(1) x + y = y + x,
(2) (x + y) + z = x + (y + z),
(3) x × y = y × x,
(4) (x × y) × z = x × (y × z),
(5) x × (y + z) = (x × y) + (x × z).
Here (1) and (2) are called the commutative and associa-
tive laws for addition, (3) and (4) are the commutative and
associative laws for multiplication, and (5) is the distributive
law relating addition and multiplication. For example, with-
out symbols, (1) becomes: If a second number be added to
any given number the result is the same as if the first given
number had been added to the second number.
This example shows that, by the aid of symbolism, we
can make transitions in reasoning almost mechanically by the
eye, which otherwise would call into play the higher faculties
of the brain.
It is a profoundly erroneous truism, repeated by all
copy-books and by eminent people when they are making
speeches, that we should cultivate the habit of thinking of
∗
Cf. Note A, p. 207.
THE SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS 46
−3 −2 −1 +1 +2 +3
X′ X
D′ C′ B′ A′ O A B C D E
Y
′
P N P
y y y
M′
X′ x′ O x M X
y′ y′ y′
N′
′′
P P ′′′
Y′
Fig. 8.
P′ N P
+1
−3 +3 M
X′ X
M′ O
−1
P ′′ N′ P ′′′
Y′
Fig. 9.
(−3, −1), and the point P 000 by (+3, −1). More generally
in the previous figure (8), the point P corresponds to the
ordered couple (x, y), where x and y in the figure are both
IMAGINARY NUMBERS 74
R
Y
Q
P
S
X′ O M1 M M′ X
Y′
Fig. 10.
OM 0 = OM + M M 0 = x + x1 ,
RM 0 = SM 0 + RS = y + y1 .
(c, d)
(x, y) = (c, d) ÷ (a, b), or by (x, y) = .
(a, b)
namely
All these conditions (α), (β), (γ), (δ), () can be satisfied
by an interpretation which, though it looks complicated at
first, is capable of a simple geometrical interpretation.
By definition we put
Q
N′
M′ P
R
N1
X′ X
M1 OMN
Fig. 11.
Y R
Q
P
O X
Fig. 12.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 87
x
X′ O M X
Y′
Fig. 13.
coordinate geometry.
When one has once grasped the idea of coordinate ge-
ometry, the immediate question which starts to the mind
is, What sort of loci correspond to the well-known alge-
braic forms? For example, the simplest among the general
types of algebraic forms is ax + by = c. The sort of locus
which corresponds to this is a straight line, and conversely
to every straight line there corresponds an equation of this
form. It is fortunate that the simplest among the geometrical
loci should correspond to the simplest among the algebraic
forms. Indeed, it is this general correspondence of geometri-
cal and algebraic simplicity which gives to the whole subject
its power. It springs from the fact that the connection be-
tween geometry and algebra is not casual and artificial, but
deep-seated and essential. The equation which corresponds
to a locus is called the equation “of” (or “to”) the locus.
Some examples of equations of straight lines will illustrate
the subject.
Consider y − x = 0; here the a, b, and c, of the general
form have been replaced by −1, 1, and 0 respectively. This
line passes through the “origin,” O, in the diagram and bi-
sects the angle XOY . It is the line L0 OL of the diagram.
The fact that it passes through the origin, O, is easily seen
by observing that the equation is satisfied by putting x = 0
and y = 0 simultaneously, but 0 and 0 are the coordinates
of O. In fact it is easy to generalize and to see by the same
method that the equation of any line through the origin is
of the form ax + by = 0. The locus of the equation y + x = 0
COORDINATE GEOMETRY 100
L1 L
Y
A1
′ A X
X O
L′1
′ Y′
L
Fig. 14.
cones. In this case the plane will not meet the other half-cone
at all. Such a curve is called an ellipse; it is an oval curve. A
particular case of such a section of the cone is when the plane
is perpendicular to the axis CV C 0 , then the section, such as
ST U or P QR, is a circle. Hence a circle is a particular case
of the ellipse.
(2) The plane may be parallelled to a tangent plane
touching the cone along one of its “generating” lines as for
example the plane of the curve D1 A1 D10 in the diagram is
parallel to the tangent plane touching the cone along the
generating line V S; the curve is still confined to one of the
half-cones, but it is now not a closed oval curve, it goes
on endlessly as long as the generating lines of the half-cone
are produced away from the vertex. Such a conic section is
called parabola.
(3) The plane may cut both the half-cones, so that
the complete curve consists of two detached portions, or
“branches” as they are called, this case is illustrated by the
two branches G2 A2 G02 and L2 A02 L02 which together make up
the curve. Neither branch is closed, each of them spreading
out endlessly as the two half-cones are prolonged away from
the vertex. Such a conic section is called a hyperbola.
There are accordingly three types of conic sections,
namely, ellipses, parabolas, and hyperbolas. It is easy to
see that, in a sense, parabolas are limiting cases lying be-
tween ellipses and hyperbolas. They form a more special
sort and have to satisfy a more particular condition. These
three names are apparently due to Apollonius of Perga
CONIC SECTIONS 106
(born about 260 b.c., and died about 200 b.c.), who wrote
a systematic treatise on conic sections which remained the
standard work till the sixteenth century.
C′ L′2
P L2 R
Q
A′2
A
B′
B
A′
A1
A2
G′2
D′
S U
C
D1 T G2
Fig. 15.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 107
B
P
N′ N
X′ X
A′ S ′ C M S A
B′
Fig. 16.
P
N
X
A S M
Fig. 17.
their planes are those of the curved lines in the three fig-
ures 16, 17, and 18. The points A and A0 in the figures
are called the vertices and the line AA0 the major axis. It
will be noted that a parabola (cf. fig. 17) has only one ver-
∗
tex.
Apollonius proved that the ratio of P M 2 to AM · M A0
2
PM
i.e. remains constant both for the ellipse and
AM · M A0
the hyperbola (figs. 16 and 18), and that the ratio of P M 2
to AM is constant for the parabola of fig. 17; and he bases
most of his work on this fact. We are evidently advancing
towards the desired uniform definition which does not go out
of the plane; but have not yet quite attained to uniformity.
∗
Cf. Ball, loc. cit., for this account of Apollonius and Pappus.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 109
H1′ H
N
P
S′ A′ A
X′ C X S M
P′
N1′ N1
H′ H1
Fig. 18.
A C
B
Fig. 19.
d2 x2 + 2dexy + e2 y 2 + 2gx + 2f y + c;
A′ B C1 C2 C3 C4 C5 A
1
B1 B2 B3 B4 B5
′ 0 1 2 3 4 5 X
X
Y′
Fig. 20.
Y P3
P4
X ′ M1 M3
M2 0 M4 X
P1
P2 Y′
Fig. 21.
i.e. at the origin O. For the value of the function on the neg-
ative (left) side of the origin becomes endlessly great, but
negative, and the function reappears on the positive (right)
side as endlessly great but positive. Hence, however small
we take the length M2 M3 , there is a finite jump between the
values of the function at M2 and M3 . Indeed, this case has
the peculiarity that the smaller we take the length between
M2 and M3 , so long as they enclose the origin, the bigger is
the jump in value of the function between them. This graph
brings out, what is also apparent in fig. 20 of this chapter,
that for many functions the discontinuities only occur at iso-
lated points, so that by restricting the values of the argument
we obtain a continuous function for these remaining values.
1
Thus it is evident from fig. 21 that in y = , if we keep
x
to positive values only and exclude the origin, we obtain a
continuous function. Similarly the same function, if we keep
to negative values only, excluding the origin, is continuous.
Again the function which is graphed in fig. 20 is continuous
between B and C1 , and between C1 and C2 , and between
C2 and C3 , and so on, always in each case excluding the end
points. It is, however, easy to find functions such that their
discontinuities occur at all points. For example, consider
a function f (x), such that when x is any fractional num-
ber f (x) = 1, and when x is any incommensurable number
f (x) = 2. This function is discontinuous at all points.
Finally, we will look a little more closely at the defini-
tion of continuity given above. We have said that a function
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 127
is, however, through the tides, and not through its phases of
light and darkness, that the moon’s periodicity has chiefly
influenced the history of the earth.
Our bodily life is essentially periodic. It is dominated
by the beatings of the heart, and the recurrence of breath-
ing. The presupposition of periodicity is indeed fundamental
to our very conception of life. We cannot imagine a course
of nature in which, as events progressed, we should be un-
able to say: “This has happened before.” The whole con-
ception of experience as a guide to conduct would be ab-
sent. Men would always find themselves in new situations
possessing no substratum of identity with anything in past
history. The very means of measuring time as a quantity
would be absent. Events might still be recognized as occur-
ring in a series, so that some were earlier and others later.
But we now go beyond this bare recognition. We can not
only say that three events, A, B, C, occurred in this order,
so that A came before B, and B before C; but also we can
say that the length of time between the occurrences of A
and B was twice as long as that between B and C. Now,
quantity of time is essentially dependent on observing the
number of natural recurrences which have intervened. We
may say that the length of time between A and B was so
many days, or so many months, or so many years, accord-
ing to the type of recurrence to which we wish to appeal.
Indeed, at the beginning of civilization, these three modes
of measuring time were really distinct. It has been one of
the first tasks of science among civilized or semi-civilized
PERIODICITY IN NATURE 136
second period is twice that during the first period. Thus the
question as to whether the train has been running uniformly
or not entirely depends on the standard of time which we
adopt.
Now, for all ordinary purposes of life on the earth, the
various astronomical recurrences may be looked on as ab-
solutely consistent; and, furthermore assuming their consis-
tency, and thereby assuming the velocities and changes of
velocities possessed by bodies, we find that the laws of mo-
tion, which have been considered above, are almost exactly
verified. But only almost exactly when we come to some
of the astronomical phenomena. We find, however, that by
assuming slightly different velocities for the rotations and
motions of the planets and stars, the laws would be exactly
verified. This assumption is then made; and we have, in fact
thereby, adopted a measure of time, which is indeed defined
by reference to the astronomical phenomena, but not so as
to be consistent with the uniformity of any one of them. But
the broad fact remains that the uniform flow of time on which
so much is based, is itself dependent on the observation of
periodic events.
Even phenomena, which on the surface seem casual and
exceptional, or, on the other hand, maintain themselves with
a uniform persistency, may be due to the remote influence
of periodicity. Take for example, the principle of resonance.
Resonance arises when two sets of connected circumstances
have the same periodicities. It is a dynamical law that the
small vibrations of all bodies when left to themselves take
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 139
Fig. 22.
A C
Fig. 23.
D′ D
B E′ C E F
Fig. 24.
TRIGONOMETRY 146
A D F
B C E
Fig. 25.
P1
A′1 A′ M
O A A1
Fig. 26.
arc A1 P1
and is the same as the fraction . This fraction
radius OP1
of “arc divided by radius” is the proper theoretical way to
measure the magnitude of an angle; for it is dependent on no
arbitrary unit of length, and on no arbitrary way of divid-
ing up any arbitrarily assumed angle, such as a right-angle.
AP
Thus the fraction represents the magnitude of the an-
OA
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 149
AP
print; so let us put u for the fraction , which represents
OP
the magnitude of the angle AOP , and put v for the frac-
PM OM
tion , and w for the fraction . Then u, v, w, are
OM OP
numbers, and, since we are talking of any angle AOP , they
are variable numbers. But a correlation exists between their
magnitudes, so that when u (i.e. the angle AOP ) is given
the magnitudes of v and w are definitely determined. Hence
v and w are functions of the argument u. We have called v
the sine of u, and w the cosine of u. We wish to adapt the
general functional notation y = f (x) to these special cases:
so in modern mathematics we write “sin” for “f ” when we
want to indicate the special function of “sine,” and “cos”
for “f ” when we want to indicate the special function of
“cosine.” Thus, with the above meanings for u, v, w, we get
v = sin u, and w = cos u,
where the brackets surrounding the x in f (x) are omitted
for the special functions. The meaning of these functions
sin and cos as correlating the pairs of numbers u and v, and
u and w is, that the functional relations are to be found
by constructing (cf. fig. 26) an angle AOP , whose measure
“AP divided by OP ” is equal to u, and that then v is the
number given by “P M divided by OP ” and w is the number
given by “OM divided by OP .”
It is evident that without some further definitions we
shall get into difficulties when the number u is taken too
large. For then the arc AP may be greater than one-quarter
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 151
Y
B
P ′ (x′ , y) P (x, y)
A′
X′ M′ O M A X
B′
Y′
Fig. 27.
√
gree of accuracy required, just as 2 can be so calculated.
Its value has been actually given to 707 places of decimals.
Such elaboration of calculation is merely a curiosity, and of
no practical or theoretical interest. The accurate determina-
tion of π is one of the two parts of the famous problem of
squaring the circle. The other part of the problem is, by the
theoretical methods of pure geometry to describe a straight
line equal in length to the circumference. Both parts of the
problem are now known to be impossible; and the insolu-
ble problem has now lost all special practical or theoretical
interest, having become absorbed in wider ideas.
After this digression on the value of π, we now return to
the question of the general definition of the magnitude of an
angle, so as to be able to produce an angle corresponding to
any value u. Suppose a moving point, Q, to start from A
on OX (cf. fig. 27), and to rotate in the positive direction
(anti-clockwise, in the figure considered) round the circum-
ference of the circle for any number of times, finally resting
at any point, e.g. at P or P 0 or P 00 or P 000 . Then the total
length of the curvilinear circular path traversed, divided by
the radius of the circle, r, is the generalized definition of a
positive angle of any size. Let x, y be the coordinates of
the point in which the point Q rests, i.e. in one of the four
alternative positions mentioned in fig. 27; x and y (as here
used) will either be x and y, or x0 and y, or x0 and y 0 , or
y
x and y 0 . Then the sign of this generalized angle is and its
r
x
cosine is . With these definitions the functional relations
r
TRIGONOMETRY 154
1
π 2π 3π 4π 5π
1 X
O 2
π
Fig. 28.
and then
2π(x + a) 2πx 2πx
sin = sin + 2π = sin .
a a a
1 1 4 1 4 1
Also, 3 and 3+ 10 , and 3+ 10 + 100 , and 3+ 10 + 100 + 1000 , and
1 4 1 5
3 + 10 + 100 + 1000 + 10000 are successive approximations to
the complete result 3.14159. If we read 568, 213 backwards
from right to left, starting with the 3 units, we read it in
the artistic way, gradually preparing the mind for the crisis
of 500, 000.
The ordinary process of numerical multiplication pro-
ceeds by means of the summation of a series, Consider the
computation
342
658
2736
1710
2052
225036
Hence the three lines to be added form a series of which
the first term is the upper line. This series follows the artistic
method of presenting the most important term last, not from
any feeling for art, but because of the convenience gained by
keeping a firm hold on the units’ place, thus enabling us to
omit some 0’s, formally necessary.
But when we approximate by gradually adding the suc-
cessive terms of an infinite series, what are we approximat-
ing to? The difficulty is that the series has no “sum” in
the straightforward sense of the word, because the operation
of adding together its terms can never be completed. The
answer is that we are approximating to the limit of the sum-
SERIES 164
s1 = u 1 , s2 = u1 + u2 , s3 = u1 + u2 + u3 , and
sn = u1 + u2 + u3 + · · · + un .
i.e. the series in which the terms are alternately 1 and −1.
The sum of an odd number of terms is 1, and of an even
number of terms is 0. Hence the terms of the series s1 , s2 ,
s3 , . . . , sn , . . . do not approximate to a limit, although they
do not increase without limit.
It is tempting to suppose that the condition for u1 , u2 , . . . ,
un , . . . to have a sum to infinity is that un should decrease
indefinitely as n increases. Mathematics would be a much
easier science than it is, if this were the case. Unfortunately
the supposition is not true.
For example the series
1 1 1 1
1, , , , ..., , ...
2 3 4 n
is divergent. It is easy to see that this is the case; for consider
the sum of n terms beginning at the (n + 1)th term. These
1 1 1 1
n terms are , , , ..., : there are n of
n+1 n+2 n+3 2n
1
them and is the least among them. Hence their sum is
2n
1 1
greater than n times , i.e. is greater than . Now, without
2n 2
altering the sum to infinity, if it exist, we can add together
neighbouring terms, and obtain the series
1 1
1, 2
, 3
+ 14 , 1
5
+ 16 + 17 + 18 , etc.,
that is, by what has been said above, a series whose terms
after the 2nd are greater than those of the series,
1 1 1
1, 2
, 2
, 2
, etc.,
SERIES 168
where all the terms after the first are equal. But this series
is divergent. Hence the original series is divergent.∗
This question of divergency shows how careful we must be
in arguing from the properties of the sum of a finite number
of terms to that of the sum of an infinite series. For the
most elementary property of a finite number of terms is that
of course they possess a sum: but even this fundamental
property is not necessarily possessed by an infinite series.
This caution merely states that we must not be misled by the
suggestion of the technical term “sum of an infinite series.”
It is usual to indicate the sum of the infinite series
u1 , u2 , u3 , . . . , un , . . .
by
u1 + u2 + u3 + · · · + un + . . . .
We now pass on to a generalization of the idea of a se-
ries, which mathematics, true to its method, makes by use of
the variable. Hitherto, we have only contemplated series in
which each definite term was a definite number. But equally
well we can generalize, and make each term to be some math-
ematical expression containing a variable x. Thus we may
consider the series 1, x, x2 , x3 , . . . , xn , . . . , and the series
x2 x3 xn
x, , , ..., , ....
2 3 n
∗
Cf. Note C, p. 208.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 169
1, x, x2 , x3 , . . . , xn , . . . .
s n = 1 + x + x 2 + x3 + · · · + xn .
xsn = x + x2 + x3 + x4 + · · · + xn + xn+1 .
Now subtract the last line from the upper line and we get
sn (1 − x) = sn − xsn = 1 − xn+1 ,
1 + x + x2 + x3 + · · · + xn + . . . .
1 + x + x2 + x3 + · · · + xn + . . . is non-uniformly conver-
gent over its whole interval of convergence −1 to +1. But if
we take any smaller interval lying at both ends within the in-
terval −1 to +1, the geometric series is uniformly convergent
1
within it. For example, take the interval 0 to + 10 . Then any
n+1
x
value for n which makes numerically less than k at
1−x
these limits for x also serves for all values of x between these
xn+1
limits, since it so happens that diminishes in numer-
1−x
ical value as x diminishes in numerical value. For example,
1
take k = .001; then, putting x = 10 , we find:—
xn+1 ( 1 )2 1
for n = 1, = 10 1 = 90
= .0111 . . . ,
1−x 1 − 10
1 3
xn+1 ( 10 ) 1
for n = 2, = 1 = 900
= .00111 . . . ,
1−x 1 − 10
1 4
xn+1 ( 10 ) 1
for n = 3, = 1 = 9000
= .000111 . . . .
1−x 1 − 10
employed.
It is curious that this important distinction between uni-
form and non-uniform convergence was not published till
1847 by Stokes—afterwards, Sir George Stokes—and later,
independently in 1850 by Seidel, a German mathematician.
The critical points, where non-uniform convergence
comes in, are not necessarily at the limits of the interval
throughout which convergence holds. This is a speciality
belonging to the geometric series.
In the case of the geometric series 1+x+x2 +· · ·+xn +. . . ,
1
a simple algebraic expression can be given for its limit
1−x
in its interval of convergence. But this is not always the
case. Often we can prove a series to be convergent within
a certain interval, though we know nothing more about its
limit except that it is the limit of the series. But this is a
very good way of defining a function; viz.. as the limit of an
infinite convergent series, and is, in fact, the way in which
most functions are, or ought to be, defined.
Thus, the most important series in elementary analysis
is
x2 x 3 xn
1+x+ + + ··· + + ...,
2! 3! n!
where n! has the meaning defined earlier in this chapter.
This series can be proved to be absolutely convergent for
all values of x, and to be uniformly convergent within any
interval which we like to take. Hence it has all the comfort-
able mathematical properties which a series should have. It
SERIES 174
(exp x) × (exp y)
(x + y)2 (x + y)3 (x + y)n
= 1 + (x + y) + + +···+ +....
2! 3! n!
This property (A) is an example of what is called an
addition-theorem. When any function [say f (x)] has been
defined, the first thing we do is to try to express f (x + y)
in terms of known functions of x only, and known functions
of y only. If we can do so, the result is called an addition-
theorem. Addition-theorems play a great part in mathemat-
ical analysis. Thus the addition-theorem for the sine is given
by
sin(x + y) = sin x cos y + cos x sin y,
and for the cosine by
X′ O X
Fig. 29.
X′ O X
Fig. 30.
B O
A C D E F
Fig. 31.
P
(x, y)
Q′
A
O T N M X
Fig. 32.
(x + h)2 − x2
unit increase of the argument is . But
h
(x + h)2 = x2 + 2hx + h2 ,
and therefore
(x + h)2 − x2 2hx + h2
= = 2x + h.
h h
Thus 2x + h is the average increase of the function x2 per
unit increase in the argument, the average being taken over
by the interval x to x + h. But 2x + h depends on h, the
size of the interval. We shall evidently get what we want,
namely the rate of increase at the value x of the argument,
by diminishing h more and more. Hence in the limit when
h has decreased indefinitely, we say that 2x is the rate of
increase of x2 at the value x of the argument.
Here again we are apparently driven up against the idea
of infinitely small quantities in the use of the words “in the
limit when h has decreased indefinitely.” Leibniz held that,
mysterious as it may sound, there were actually existing such
things as infinitely small quantities, and of course infinitely
small numbers corresponding to them. Newton’s language
and ideas were more on the modern lines; but he did not
succeed in explaining the matter with such explicitness so as
to be evidently doing more than explain Leibniz’s ideas in
rather indirect language. The real explanation of the sub-
ject was first given by Weierstrass and the Berlin School
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS 187
A D
B C E F
Fig. 33.
2 × (3 + 4) = (2 × 3) + (2 × 4).
2×7=6+8
1 + 12 + 31 + 14 + etc.
Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
(and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
redistribution.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
States.
1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
1.E.9.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
"Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
- You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
- You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License. You must require such a user to return or
destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ’AS-IS’, WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
LICENSE VII
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate
Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
www.gutenberg.org