Wickberg, What Is The History of Sensibilities
Wickberg, What Is The History of Sensibilities
Wickberg, What Is The History of Sensibilities
DANIEL WICKBERG
White Male: Some Recent Inversions in American Cultural History,” Journal of American History 92,
661
662 Daniel Wickberg
been the dominant interpretive direction of the new cultural history, alongside it has
existed another direction, owing as much to the “old” cultural history as to the new:
what, using Lucien Febvre’s nomenclature, if not his precise meaning, can be called
the history of sensibilities.2 If the cultural history of representation focuses on the
primacy of the objects being represented—for example, the body as a site of cultural
meaning, or the study of blackface minstrelsy as racial representation—the history
of sensibilities focuses on the primacy of the various modes of perception and feeling,
the terms and forms in which objects were conceived, experienced, and represented
in the past. To give an example from modern American cultural history, the history
no. 1 (2005): 136–157; Geoff Eley, A Crooked Line: From Cultural History to the History of Society (Ann
Arbor, Mich., 2005).
2 Lucien Febvre, “Sensibility and History: How to Reconstitute the Emotional Life of the Past,” in
A New Kind of History: From the Writings of Febvre, ed. Peter Burke, trans. K. Folca (New York, 1973),
12–26.
3 David R. Roediger, The Wages of Whiteness: Race and the Making of the American Working Class
(London, 1991); Grace Elizabeth Hale, Making Whiteness: The Culture of Segregation in the South, 1890–
1940 (New York, 1998); Matthew Frye Jacobson, Whiteness of a Different Color: European Immigrants
and the Alchemy of Race (Cambridge, Mass., 1998); David R. Roediger, Colored White: Transcending the
Racial Past (Berkeley, Calif., 2002); Roediger, Working toward Whiteness: How America’s Immigrants
Became White—The Strange Journey from Ellis Island to the Suburbs (New York, 2005); Neil Foley, The
White Scourge: Mexicans, Blacks, and Poor Whites in Texas Cotton Culture (Berkeley, Calif., 1997); Peter
Kolchin, “Whiteness Studies: The New History of Race in America,” Journal of American History 89,
no. 1 (2002): 154 –173; Eric Arnesen, “Whiteness and the Historians’ Imagination,” International Labor
and Working-Class History, no. 60 (2001): 3–32.
4 Ann Douglas, The Feminization of American Culture (New York, 1977); Jane P. Tompkins, Sen-
sational Designs: The Cultural Work of American Fiction, 1790–1860 (New York, 1985); Shirley Samuels,
ed., The Culture of Sentiment: Race, Gender, and Sentimentality in Nineteenth-Century America (New
York, 1992); Andrew Burstein, Sentimental Democracy: The Evolution of America’s Romantic Self-Image
(New York, 1999); Mary Chapman and Glenn Hendler, eds., Sentimental Men: Masculinity and the Pol-
itics of Affect in American Culture (Berkeley, Calif., 1999); Bruce Burgett, Sentimental Bodies: Sex, Gen-
der, and Citizenship in the Early Republic (Princeton, N.J., 1998); John Phillips Resch, Suffering Soldiers:
Revolutionary War Veterans, Moral Sentiment, and Political Culture in the Early Republic (Amherst, Mass.,
1999); Kristin Boudreau, Sympathy in American Literature: American Sentiments from Jefferson to the
Jameses (Gainesville, Fla., 2002); Elizabeth White Nelson, Market Sentiments: Middle-Class Market Cul-
ture in Nineteenth-Century America (Washington, D.C., 2004); Lori Merish, Sentimental Materialism:
Gender, Commodity Culture, and Nineteenth-Century American Literature (Durham, N.C., 2000).
and not a reflection of the fact that sentimentalism arises out of an inherent or
primary interest in motherhood, death, gender, or race itself; there are, in fact, all
kinds of texts that we would deem “sentimental” that fail to make motherhood cen-
tral. In other words, the cultural sensibility we label “sentimental” is the primary
reality, and the objects represented in various sentimental genres are secondary.
Many antislavery texts partake of a sentimental sensibility, but that does not mean
that slavery is a core feature of the sensibility; sentimentalism is an important aspect
of liberal Protestant theology, but not all sentimental representations are theolog-
ical.5 The sensibility is anterior to the objects it represents in various concrete man-
When the world was half a thousand years younger all events had much sharper outlines than
now. The distance between sadness and joy, between good and bad fortune, seemed to be
much greater than for us; every experience had that degree of directness and absoluteness
that joy and sadness still have in the mind of a child. Every event, every deed was defined
in given and expressive forms and was in accord with the solemnity of a tight, invariable life
style. The great events of human life—birth, marriage, death—by virtue of the sacraments,
basked in the radiance of the divine mystery. But even the lesser events—a journey, labor,
a visit—were accompanied by a multitude of blessings, ceremonies, sayings, and conventions.7
5 On slavery as an object of sentimental texts, see, for instance, Shirley Samuels, “The Identity of
Slavery,” in Samuels, The Culture of Sentiment, 157–171. On liberal Protestantism and sentimentalism,
see, for instance, James Turner, Without God, Without Creed: The Origins of Unbelief in America (Bal-
timore, Md., 1985), 73–113.
6 Robert F. Berkhofer, Jr., “Clio and the Culture Concept: Some Impressions of a Changing Re-
lationship in American Historiography,” in Louis Schneider and Charles Bonjean, eds., The Idea of
Culture in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, Mass., 1973), 77–100; Gene Wise, American Historical Ex-
planations (Homewood, Ill., 1973); John Higham, “The Cult of the ‘American Consensus’: Homoge-
nizing Our History,” Commentary 27 (1959): 93–100; Higham, “Beyond Consensus: The Historian as
Moral Critic,” American Historical Review 67, no. 3 (April 1962): 609–625. For an example of the use
of the term “counterprogressive history,” see David W. Noble, The End of American History: Democracy,
Capitalism, and the Metaphor of Two Worlds in Anglo-American Historical Writing, 1880–1980 (Minne-
apolis, 1985).
7 Johan Huizinga, The Autumn of the Middle Ages, trans. Rodney J. Payton and Ulrich Mammitzsch
(Chicago, 1996), 1. On the significance of Huizinga, see William J. Bouwsma, “The Waning of the Middle
Ages Revisited,” in Bouwsma, A Usable Past: Essays in European Cultural History (Berkeley, Calif., 1990),
325–335.
Leaving aside for the moment the question of whether “everyone” experienced the
world in these terms, and the generalizing propensity of this older style of cultural
history, it is significant that Huizinga defines as the object of historical study not the
events, nor the ideas, nor the social structures of the past, but the modes of per-
ception and feelings, which are pictured as collective and historically variable. This
brand of cultural history looks not at the content of thought, but at the forms in which
that content is perceived, given, and expressed. History, in Huizinga, goes beyond
the level of external circumstances that vary from society to society and through time;
the internal states and structure of feeling and consciousness, and not just the objects
Raymond Williams, Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society (New York, 1983), 87.
8
On the different forms of cultural history, see Peter Burke, Varieties of Cultural History (Ithaca,
9
N.Y., 1997), especially 183–212; Lynn Hunt, ed., The New Cultural History (Berkeley, Calif., 1989); Hunt
and Victoria Bonnell, eds., Beyond the Cultural Turn: New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture
(Berkeley, Calif., 1999).
N. Robinson (1855; repr., Washington, D.C., 1977), 122; George Henry Lewes, The Physical Basis of
Mind: Being the Second Series of Problems of Life and Mind (Boston, Mass., 1877); E. Hamilton, “Mr.
Lewes’s Doctrine of Sensibility,” Mind 4, no. 14 (1879): 256–261; Edgar A. Singer, Jr., “On Sensibility,”
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 14, no. 13 (1917): 340.
11 Erik Erämetsä, A Study of the Word “Sentimental” and of Other Linguistic Characteristics of Eigh-
In both Britain and the United States, the Victorian extension of this idea of
sensibility as a moral quantity amounted to the definition of a kind of intrinsic char-
acter element of the socially refined and cultivated person. Sensibility in the nine-
teenth century was something that one had or one lacked in varying degrees, in the
same way that Victorians saw culture as something possessed in quantities. To have
sensibility was to have a capacity for sensitivity to moral and aesthetic experience.
To lack sensibility was to be a moral and/or social idiot, unable to discriminate right
from wrong, good art from bad, things to be valued from those to be deplored. In
some ways, this notion of sensibility is similar to what today would be described in
teenth Century Sentimentalism in England (Helsinki, 1951), 88–90; Janet Todd, Sensibility: An Introduc-
tion (London, 1986), 7–8, 23–31, 88–109; John Mullen, Sentiment and Sociability: The Language of Feeling
in the Eighteenth Century (Oxford, 1988); G. J. Barker-Benfield, The Culture of Sensibility: Sex and Society
in Eighteenth-Century Britain (Chicago, 1992); Markman Ellis, The Politics of Sensibility (New York,
1996); G. S. Rousseau, Nervous Acts: Essays on Literature, Culture, and Sensibility (New York, 2004). For
an examination of sensibility in the eighteenth-century American context, see Sarah Knott, “Sensibility
and the American War for Independence,” American Historical Review 109, no. 1 (February 2004):
19– 40.
12 Williams, Keywords, 280–283.
13 Ibid., 89–91; Adam Kuper, Culture: The Anthropologists’ Account (Cambridge, Mass., 1999); Regna
Darnell, Invisible Genealogies: A History of Americanist Anthropology (Lincoln, Neb., 2001); Clifford
Geertz, “The Impact of the Concept of Culture on the Concept of Man,” in Geertz, The Interpretation
of Cultures (New York, 1973), 33–54; George W. Stocking, Jr., Race, Culture, and Evolution: Essays in
the History of Anthropology (New York, 1968); Stocking, A Franz Boas Reader: The Shaping of American
Anthropology, 1883–1911 (Chicago, 1989); Richard Handler, “Boasian Anthropology and the Critique
of American Culture,” American Quarterly 42, no. 2 (1990): 252–273.
discrimination, but now also included an expressive element: works of art embodied
or expressed underlying sensibilities. On the other hand, the notion of sensibilities
implied a kind of cultural pluralism. For the Victorians, the question was whether
one had or did not have sensibility. For the modernists of the first half of the twen-
tieth century, the question was what kind of sensibility one had; after all, everybody
had a sensibility, and differences were differences in kind rather than in quantity.
The result was potentially to democratize the concept of sensibility by making it, like
culture, relative to the specific social groups, artistic movements, and individuals who
possessed it. This notion of sensibility would be dominant in art circles until the 1960s
The sensibility of an era is not only its most decisive, but also its most perishable, aspect. One
may capture the ideas (intellectual history) and the behavior (social history) of an epoch
without ever touching upon the sensibility or taste which informed those ideas, that behavior.
Rare are those historical studies—like Huizinga on the late Middle Ages, Febvre on 16th
century France—which do tell us something about the sensibility of the period.16
Hence the concept of what was sometimes called “the modern sensibility,” in which
the modes of feeling and experiencing the world in modern societies were marked
off from the modes characteristic of past ages. Art and literature were where sen-
sibility was expressed, or given a codified or articulated form, but the larger notion
14 See, for instance, Henry-Russell Hitchcock, “Food for Changing Sensibilities,” Perspecta 6 (1960):
2–3.
15 Lionel Trilling, Beyond Culture: Essays on Literature and Learning (New York, 1965). See especially
the reference to “the modern spiritual sensibility” on p. 78. Trilling, The Liberal Imagination: Essays on
Literature and Society (1950; repr., New York, 1976). See Thomas Bender, “Lionel Trilling and American
Culture,” American Quarterly 42, no. 2 (1990): 324 –347.
16 Susan Sontag, Against Interpretation and Other Essays (New York, 1966), 276.
36–54, 94 –120.
18 On the influence of Geertz on the new cultural history, see Ronald G. Waters, “Signs of the Times:
Clifford Geertz and Historians,” Social Research 47, no. 3 (1980): 537–556; Lynn Hunt, “Introduction:
History, Culture, and Text,” in Hunt, The New Cultural History, 12–13; Aletta Biersack, “Local Knowl-
edge, Local History: Geertz and Beyond,” ibid., 72–96; Richard Biernacki, “Method and Metaphor after
the New Cultural History,” in Hunt and Bonnell, Beyond the Cultural Turn, 62–92; Jean-Christophe
Agnew, “History and Anthropology: Scenes From a Marriage,” Yale Journal of Criticism 3, no. 2 (1990):
29–50. Probably the most widely cited of Geertz’s essays on historical writing are “Thick Description:
Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture,” in Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, 3–30; and “Deep
Play: Notes on the Balinese Cockfight,” ibid., 412– 453.
19 T. S. Eliot, “The Metaphysical Poets” (1921), in Eliot, Selected Essays, 1917–1932 (New York,
1932), 241–250, quotation from 246. F. W. Bateson, “Contributions to a Dictionary of Critical Terms:
that while it retained the notion of sensibility as a singular, unitary entity (the sev-
enteenth century had it; we have lost it), it made explicit the linkage between ideas
and emotions contained in the concept. A sensibility was not what would come to
be called an ideology; nor was it simply what Raymond Williams would later call a
structure of feeling. Rather, it was a pattern in which idea and emotion were bound
up with one another.
Given its history, then, it is understandable why the concept of sensibility has
proved to be a fruitful one for contemporary cultural historiography: by bringing
together the elements of sense perception, cognition, emotion, aesthetic form, moral
II. Dissociation of Sensibility,” Essays in Criticism 1 (1951): 301–312; Frank Kermode, Romantic Image
(New York, 1961), 138–166.
BUT WHY IS SENSIBILITY PREFERABLE TO OTHER CONCEPTS that historians have used and
developed in the past half-century to describe the systematic and collectively held
mental maps or dispositions of persons? Given its history, it is a broader concept that
integrates ideas, emotions, beliefs, values, and perceptions in a way that terms such
as “ideology,” “mentalité,” and “paradigm” do not, or at least have not, in their
application. The term “ideology,” for instance, has been used in a number of ways
and has proved itself significant, particularly for historians of political thought and
language. While Marxists and others have used the concept in a fairly narrow way
to designate a formal body of political ideas that reflect social structures and/or guide
20 On the Marxist concept of ideology, see Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford,
1977), 55–71. On the use of the notion of ideology by historians of republicanism and political thought,
see Daniel T. Rodgers, “Republicanism: The Career of a Concept,” Journal of American History 79, no.
1 (1992): 11–38. On Geertz’s notion of ideology, see Geertz, “Ideology as a Cultural System,” in Geertz,
The Interpretation of Cultures, 193–233.
21 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York, 1971);
Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago, 1962). On Kuhn and his use by historians,
see David A. Hollinger, “T. S. Kuhn’s Theory of Science and Its Implications for History,” in Hollinger,
In the American Province: Studies in the History and Historiography of Ideas (Baltimore, Md., 1985),
105–129; Robert Berkhofer, Jr., Beyond the Great Story: History as Text and Discourse (Cambridge, Mass.,
1997), 112; Peter Novick, That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical
Profession (Cambridge, 1988), 526–537.
instance, or popular religious beliefs and ideas about manners and social behavior.
Following Febvre’s groundbreaking work on the cultural limits of belief and on the
cultural history of emotions, it also conceptualized the history of mind and psy-
chology in terms of culture, belief, and feeling.22
The tendency of the history of mentalités, however, was to draw an invidious
distinction between social, political, and intellectual elites—who appeared to have
ideas and to approach the world rationally through formal bodies of thought—and
the broader populace of all eras—who had mentalités, or subrational compounds of
attitudes, beliefs, and prejudices. The notion of sensibility, on the other hand, can
22 As most commentators on the idea of a history of mentalities or mentalités note, there has been
a great deal of vagueness in the use of the term. Some seem to use it as a synonym for “popular attitudes,”
others for “informal thought,” others for “cultural psychology.” See Burke, Varieties of Cultural History,
162–182; Roger Chartier, Cultural History: Between Practices and Representations, trans. Lydia G.
Cochrane (Ithaca, N.Y., 1988), 19–52; Patrick H. Hutton, “The History of Mentalities: The New Map
of Cultural History,” History and Theory 20, no. 3 (1981): 237–259; Hutton, “Philippe Ariès and the
Secrets of the History of Mentalities,” Historical Reflections 28, no. 1 (2002): 1–19. The most widely
known example of Febvre’s work on the limits of cultural belief is Lucien Febvre, The Problem of Unbelief
in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais, trans. Beatrice Gottlieb (Cambridge, Mass., 1982).
23 William James, “The Sentiment of Rationality” (1882), in James, The Will to Believe and Other
has proved much more popular with students of literary and cultural studies than with historians. For
a work that uses Williams’s concept, see Glenn Hendler, Public Sentiments: Structures of Feeling in Nine-
teenth-Century American Literature (Chapel Hill, N.C., 2001).
distinctions between practice and theory, low and high, informal and formal, art and
philosophy; all embody sensibilities. The historian of sensibilities takes her objects
where she can find them—which is everywhere. Formalism, in fact, is a specific el-
ement of some sensibilities, so much so that we might distinguish between formalist
and anti-formalist sensibilities.25 In addition, the term “structure of feeling” is some-
what misleading, as Williams himself admits, for on the surface it seems to partake
of the sharp distinction between emotion and thought that it is intended to overcome.
A related concept that has been taken up by some cultural studies scholars, and
in a very limited way by a few historians, is the sociologist Pierre Bourdieu’s concept
Ann Taves, Fits, Trances, and Visions: Experiencing Religion and Explaining Experience from Wesley to
James (Princeton, N.J., 1999). Formalism and anti-formalism have been treated much more extensively
by intellectual historians. See Morton White, Social Thought in America: The Revolt against Formalism
(Boston, 1957); Wilfred McClay, The Masterless: Self and Society in America (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1994),
149–188; Thomas L. Haskell, Objectivity Is Not Neutrality: Explanatory Schemes in History (Baltimore,
Md., 1998), 307–367.
26 Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, trans. Richard Nice (Cam-
bridge, Mass., 1984), 170; Donald Fleming, “Attitude: The History of a Concept,” Perspectives in Amer-
ican History 1 (1967): 287–365.
classes (groups) and fields all, in some way, ‘have’ distinctive and characteristic habituses?
The criterion of embodiment makes habitus a reasonable enough individualistic concept—
allowing for its problems of definition—but a wholly implausible attribute of collective or
abstract social entities.
For those historians, social theorists, and cultural analysts who are concerned with
the classic antinomies of agency and structure, power and resistance, dominance and
subalterity, Bourdieu’s habitus seems to provide a way to talk about cultural dis-
positions that is consistent with these theoretical concerns.27 One of the virtues of
of habitus, see Linda Young, “ ‘Extensive, Economical and Elegant’: The Habitus of Gentility in Nine-
teenth Century Sydney,” Australian Historical Studies 24 (2004): 201–220. On issues of structure, agency,
and power in social theory and history and how Bourdieu fits into those issues, see William H. Sewell,
Jr., Logics of History: Social Theory and Social Transformation (Chicago, 2005), 137–139. For an inter-
pretation that stresses Bourdieu’s consistency with the political outlooks of social history and distin-
guishes habitus from mentalité in terms of agency, see Julian Vincent, “The Sociologist and the Republic:
Pierre Bourdieu and the Virtues of Social History,” History Workshop Journal 58 (2004): 140.
of culture, and the ways in which culture is implicated in power relations. That would
seem to be the nature of this criticism.28
What this brand of criticism might see as a fundamental flaw, however, can ac-
tually be regarded as a virtue. The overwhelming focus on instrumentalizing culture
as a tool of power in some of the dominant forms of cultural history finds no room
for those elements of culture that cannot be implicated in power relations. Culture
is not power, nor is power the only or the most important element of culture. Power
is but one dimension of culture, a dimension that might be more or less important
for the historian and analyst, depending upon the concrete specifics of the cultural
counts, goes deep into the history of historiography and the philosophy of history. Perhaps its most
explicit formulation was in the debate between Carl Hempel and William Dray over “covering laws” in
historical explanation, in which Hempel argued that all historical accounts involve causal explanations
deduced from general laws, while Dray followed Collingwood and others in emphasizing that historical
accounts involve a rethinking of the motives and understandings of historical actors, or a kind of de-
scriptive explication of meaning. The issue thus speaks to whether history is to be understood as a
nomothetic or ideographic discipline, as a social science or a humanistic discipline. See Hempel, “The
Function of General Laws in History,” Journal of Philosophy 39 (1942): 35– 48; Dray, Laws and Expla-
nations in History (New York, 1957); Novick, That Noble Dream, 393– 400; Haskell, Objectivity Is Not
Neutrality. On the shift in the social sciences from causal mechanics to interpretive understandings, see
Geertz, “Blurred Genres: The Refiguration of Social Thought,” in Geertz, Local Knowledge, 19–35.
approach to history is on explicating what makes the cultures of the past different
from those of the present, and not on applying causal mechanics to cultures. The
history of sensibilities seeks to understand what and how other peoples have per-
ceived, thought, and felt, and sometimes that understanding requires a willingness
to avoid the necessary reductionism and instrumentalism that all causal accounts
require. The history of sensibilities involves a kind of interpretation that is analytical
and descriptive in its orientation and imaginative in its capacity to understand oth-
erness, but that gives secondary importance to causal explanation.
The history of sensibilities is compatible with various kinds of historical expla-
30 Marxist and Foucauldian approaches seem equally obsessed with the idea that power—however
abstractly defined—is necessarily situated in culture; the analysis of cultural forms becomes a means of
situating those forms and meanings in relationship to power. This view often leads back to the analysis
of social categories, identities, and objects such as race, class, and gender as at the core of culture, since
these social categories express power relations most explicitly. The foregrounding of such categories,
however, may tell us much more about the sensibilities of contemporary analysts than about the sen-
sibilities of those people in the past we are trying to understand. On the idea of power in cultural history,
see Dirks, Eley, and Ortner, Culture/Power/History; Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Inter-
views and Other Writings, ed. Colin Gordon (New York, 1980); Jeffrey C. Alexander, “Understanding
the Relative Autonomy of Culture,” in Alexander and Steven Seidman, eds., Culture and Society: Con-
temporary Debates (Cambridge, 1990), 21–25.
political and social conflicts, the history of sensibilities pulls us back to the substance
of culture. It asks us not about how people used culture for social and political ends,
but about the terms in which they experienced the world. It does, however, require
us to recognize the diversity of sensibilities and to avoid making unsubstantiated
generalizations about “the spirit of the age.”
The notion of a history of sensibilities might also be associated in a narrow way
with literary or art history. Given its provenance—its ties to modern conceptions of
taste and aesthetics—this association makes sense. But there is no reason why sen-
sibilities should necessarily be understood in this narrow way, and for historians they
31 For an example of the ways in which account books can be used, in conjunction with the writings
of political economists and novelists, to unpack a cultural sensibility, see Mary Poovey’s discussion of
double-entry bookkeeping in A History of the Modern Fact: Problems of Knowledge in the Sciences of
Wealth and Society (Chicago, 1998), 29–65.
issue, or object. The connections between these dispositions, feelings, and habits of
thinking are not matters of logic or necessity in the way that James describes them.
The tender-minded is not to be argued into tough-mindedness by appeal to argu-
ment, or vice versa; these are dispositions and ways of feeling that exist prior to
argument, and they are the ground upon which argument can take place.32 In one
important sense, however, these are not sensibilities as the concept is being used
here. For James, these dispositions are not culturally specific; in fact, he indicates
that one finds persons of these two dispositions in all times and places—a claim that
many historians would be inclined to dispute. For him, these are psychological habits
THERE ARE A NUMBER OF AMERICAN HISTORIANS who have taken up the history of
sensibilities, going back, in fact, to an era prior to the social history revolution of the
1960s and 1970s. One of the best early examples is Richard Hofstadter, who shared
many of the prevailing post–World War II liberal tendencies of contemporaries such
as Lionel Trilling, particularly Trilling’s concern with liberalism as a temperament,
a way of imagining, a set of dispositions. One of the primary architects of postwar
“consensus history,” the prolific Hofstadter is probably best remembered today for
his interpretations of Populism and Progressivism in The Age of Reform (1954), on
which several generations of graduate students cut their teeth, and for his incisive
and ironic portraits in The American Political Tradition and the Men Who Made It
(1948).33 His contribution to the history of sensibilities is best exemplified in his
analysis of what he called “the paranoid style” in American history. Looking at a long
tradition of American conspiratorial thinking—from the anti-Masonic movement of
the Jacksonian era, through Populism in the 1890s, nativist and anti-Catholic or-
32 William James, Pragmatism and Other Writings, ed. Giles Gunn (New York, 2000), 7–12.
33 Richard Hofstadter, The Age of Reform: From Bryan to F.D.R. (New York, 1955); Hofstadter, The
American Political Tradition and the Men Who Made It (New York, 1974). For discussions of Hofstadter
and his role in American historiography, see David S. Brown, Richard Hofstadter: An Intellectual Bi-
ography (Chicago, 2006); Christopher Lasch, “Foreword,” in Hofstadter, The American Political Tra-
dition, vii–xxiv; Alan Brinkley, “In Retrospect: Richard Hofstadter’s The Age of Reform—A Reconsid-
eration,” Reviews in American History 13, no. 3 (1985): 462– 480; Daniel Joseph Singal, “Beyond
Consensus: Richard Hofstadter and American Historiography,” American Historical Review 89, no. 4
(October 1984): 976–1004.
34 See Alan Brinkley, Voices of Protest: Huey Long, Father Coughlin, and the Great Depression (New
York, 1983); Leo Ribuffo, The Old Christian Right: The Protestant Far Right from the Great Depression
to the Cold War (Philadelphia, 1983); Glenn Jeansonne, Gerald L. K. Smith: Minister of Hate (New Haven,
Conn., 1988); Kathleen M. Blee, Women of the Klan: Racism and Gender in the 1920s (Berkeley, Calif.,
1991); Rick Perlstein, Before the Storm: Barry Goldwater and the Unmaking of the American Consensus
(New York, 2001); Lisa McGirr, Suburban Warriors: The Origins of the New American Right (Princeton,
N.J., 2001).
35 Richard Hofstadter, The Paranoid Style in American Politics and Other Essays (Chicago, 1965),
3– 40.
36 David Brooks, “The Prosecutor’s Diagnosis: No Cancer Found,” New York Times, October 30,
2005, 13; William Kristol, “The Paranoid Style in American Liberalism,” The Weekly Standard 11, no.
16 (2006): n.p.
managerial rationality resulted in a separation of the desiring self from the embodied
world of fertile forces, and an alienation of the consumer from his or her own body.
Compare the opening paragraph of Fables of Abundance to that of Huizinga’s
Autumn of the Middle Ages, cited earlier: “For centuries the hungry peasant bent to
face the earth. Homo and humus were twinned. Death and rebirth mingled in the
dung heap; filth and fecundity merged in formless, inchoate matter. Intimate ac-
quaintance with dirt shaped dreams of deliverance from want. Ethereal visions of
paradise were touched with significant soil.”37 Like Huizinga’s romantic image of a
non-alienated past, this is another variant of “the world we have lost,” a trope that
37 Jackson Lears, Fables of Abundance: A Cultural History of Advertising in America (New York, 1994),
17. See also Lears, Something for Nothing: Luck in America (New York, 2003).
38 The expression “the world we have lost” comes from Peter Laslett, The World We Have Lost (New
York, 1973), but of course the idea of a golden age from which the present represents a falling away
or a decline goes back at least to Hesiod and finds expression in central cultural symbols such as the
Garden of Eden. Its use in modern historical argument derives more immediately from nineteenth-
century sociology and its variety of binary distinctions between the social forms of medieval and modern.
For an interesting discussion of the relationship between modern historical consciousness and the sense
of a lost past, see Peter Fritzsche, “Specters of History: On Nostalgia, Exile, and Modernity,” American
Historical Review 106, no. 5 (December 2001): 1587–1618.
39 The list of works that partake of some facet of the approach I am describing as the history of
sensibilities is extensive. Some other exemplary works include Miles Orvell, The Real Thing: Imitation
and Authenticity in American Culture, 1880–1940 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1989); John E. Crowley, The In-
vention of Comfort: Sensibilities and Design in Early Modern Britain and Early America (Baltimore, Md.,
2001); Keith Thomas, Man and the Natural World: A History of the Modern Sensibility (New York, 1983);
Lawrence Levine, Black Culture and Black Consciousness: Afro-American Folk Thought from Slavery to
Freedom (New York, 1977); Rhys Isaac, The Transformation of Virginia, 1740–1790 (Chapel Hill, N.C.,
1982); James W. Cook, The Arts of Deception: Playing with Fraud in the Age of Barnum (Cambridge, Mass.,
2001); Daniel Wickberg, The Senses of Humor: Self and Laughter in Modern America (Ithaca, N.Y., 1998);
David Shi, Facing Facts: Realism in American Thought and Culture, 1850–1920 (New York, 1995).
40 This debate, with contributions by John Ashworth, David Brion Davis, and Thomas L. Haskell,
is compiled in Thomas Bender, ed., The Antislavery Debate: Capitalism and Abolitionism as a Problem
in Historical Interpretation (Berkeley, Calif., 1992).
with suffering, and a revulsion from pain. The humanitarian sensibility united an
ethics of feeling with an empiricist epistemology, a moral universalism and a notion of
necessary action to alleviate suffering. Antislavery was a matter not only of a new set
of ideas or an intellectual perspective, but of a new way of perceiving and feeling.41
It is ironic, then, that Thomas Haskell’s well-known critique of Davis, which in
fact made the term “humanitarian sensibility” central to the debate and to historians’
vocabulary, had so little to say about the historically specific sensibility it purported
to examine. The central debate about the causal relationship between the antislavery
movement and the rise of capitalism—was it a matter of class interest and “hege-
41 David Brion Davis, “What the Abolitionists Were Up Against,” in Davis, The Problem of Slavery
in the Age of Revolution, 1770–1823 (Ithaca, N.Y., 1975), 45– 46; also in Bender, The Antislavery Debate,
22–23. For the more detailed argument, of which this is a summary and restatement, see Davis, The
Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca, N.Y., 1966), 333– 493.
if the prescription were itself self-evident and unchanging and required only new
application to a world of imagined possibilities.42
Those who followed Haskell in discussing the humanitarian sensibility were more
concerned with analyzing the modes of perception, feeling, and being contained in
the humanitarian sensibility. Thomas Laqueur, for instance, showed that realistic
representation of concrete details in medical and reform texts, by foregrounding the
specific and empirical, drew a moral connection between concreteness, immediate
sensation, and ameliorative action. The rise of realism and descriptive empiricism,
in this account, fosters not a fatalistic detachment, but a moral impulse to inter-
Bender, The Antislavery Debate, 107–135, and “Capitalism and the Origins of the Humanitarian Sen-
sibility, Part II,” ibid., 136–160; Haskell, “Convention and Hegemonic Interest in the Debate over An-
tislavery: A Reply to Davis and Ashworth,” ibid., 200–259, especially 224, where Haskell argues that “The
rule of reciprocity that the Golden Rule embodies is so central to moral judgment that everything else
that can be said by way of prescribing moral duty is gilding the lily. The idea of reciprocity was not new;
it has been available in the form of biblical precept for at least two millennia, and by itself it provided
an adequate prescriptive basis for devoting one’s entire life to the liberation of slaves . . . [T]he sudden
surge of humanitarian activism in the eighteenth century was not fundamentally a matter of prescription,
no matter how indispensable prescription may have been to the outcome.” For an alternative reading
of the prescriptive orientation of the Golden Rule in proslavery thought, see Eugene Genovese and
Elizabeth Fox-Genovese, The Mind of the Master Class: History and Faith in the Southern Slaveholder’s
World View (Cambridge, 2005), 613–624. The Haskell articles originally appeared, respectively, in the
American Historical Review 90, no. 2 (April 1985): 339–361; 90, no. 3 (June 1985): 547–566; and 92, no.
4 (October 1987): 829–878.
43 Thomas W. Laqueur, “Bodies, Details, and the Humanitarian Narrative,” in Hunt, The New Cul-
tural History, 176–204; Karen Halttunen, “Early American Murder Narratives: The Birth of Horror,”
in Richard Wightman Fox and T. J. Jackson Lears, eds., The Power of Culture: Critical Essays in American
History (Chicago, 1993), 67–101; Halttunen, “Humanitarianism and the Pornography of Pain in Anglo-
American Culture,” American Historical Review 100, no. 2 (April 1995): 303–334; Elizabeth B. Clark,
“ ‘The Sacred Rights of the Weak’: Pain, Sympathy, and the Culture of Individual Rights in Antebellum
America,” Journal of American History 82, no. 2 (1995): 463– 493. See also Michael Meranze, Laboratories
of Virtue: Punishment, Revolution, and Authority in Philadelphia, 1760–1835 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1996);
Susan M. Ryan, The Grammar of Good Intentions: Race and the Antebellum Culture of Benevolence
(Ithaca, N.Y., 2005).
history of what I am calling sensibilities. For developments in the last twenty-five years, see Peter N.
Stearns and Carol Z. Stearns, “Emotionology: Clarifying the History of Emotions and Emotional Stan-
dards,” American Historical Review 90, no. 4 (October 1985): 813–836; Carol Zisowitz Stearns and Peter
N. Stearns, Anger: The Struggle for Emotional Control in America’s History (Chicago, 1986); Peter N.
Stearns, American Cool: Constructing a Twentieth-Century Emotional Style (New York, 1994); Karen
Lystra, Searching the Heart: Women, Men, and Romantic Lives in Nineteenth-Century America (New York,
1989); Jan Lewis and Peter N. Stearns, eds., An Emotional History of the United States (New York, 1998);
William M. Reddy, The Navigation of Feeling: A Framework for the History of Emotions (Cambridge,
2001); John C. Spurlock and Cynthia A. Magistro, New and Improved: The Transformation of American
Women’s Emotional Culture (New York, 1998); Barbara H. Rosenwein, “Worrying about Emotions in
History,” American Historical Review 107, no. 3 (June 2002): 821–845; Joanna Bourke, “Fear and Anx-
iety: Writing about Emotion in Modern History,” History Workshop Journal 55 (2003): 111–133; Andrew
Cayton, “Insufficient Woe: Sense and Sensibility in Writing Nineteenth-Century History,” Reviews in
American History 31, no. 3 (2003): 331–341.
45 Alain Corbin, The Foul and the Fragrant: Odor and the French Social Imagination (Cambridge,
Mass. 1986); Corbin, Village Bells: Sound and Meaning in the Nineteenth-Century French Countryside,
trans. Martin Thom (New York, 1998); Constance Classen, David Howes, and Anthony Synott, Aroma:
The Cultural History of Smell (New York, 1994); Mark M. Smith, Listening to Nineteenth-Century America
(Chapel Hill, N.C., 2001); Emily Thompson, The Soundscape of Modernity: Architectural Acoustics and
the Culture of Listening in America (Cambridge, Mass., 2002); George H. Roeder, Jr., “Coming to Our
Senses,” Journal of American History 81, no. 3 (1994): 1112–1122; Mark M. Smith, “Making Sense of
Social History,” Journal of Social History 37, no. 1 (2003): 165–186; Peter Charles Hoffer, Sensory Worlds
in Early America (Baltimore, Md., 2003); Richard Cullen Rath, How Early America Sounded (Ithaca,
N.Y., 2003); Leigh Eric Schmidt, Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment
(Cambridge, 2000); Mark M. Smith, “Making Scents Make Sense: White Noses, Black Smells, and De-
segregation,” in Peter N. Stearns, ed., American Behavioral History: An Introduction (New York, 2005),
181–198; Smith, How Race Is Made: Slavery, Segregation, and the Senses (Chapel Hill, N.C., 2006).
46 See, for instance, Donald M. Lowe, History of Bourgeois Perception (Chicago, 1982). But Leora
history of the senses of taste or touch. The starting point for much of the history of
the senses is a consciousness that modern cultures have privileged the visual and
made the sense of sight the primary source of knowledge; those societies in which
vision was not primary have been evaluated in terms of the visual, rather than the
significance of the other senses. So we have yet another version of the world we have
lost. Rath says in his introduction: “My hope is that by attending to sound I have
been able to open up parts of these worlds, not to get a glimpse of them but to listen
in. These were worlds much more alive with sound than our own, worlds not yet
disenchanted, worlds perhaps even chanted into being.”47 The notion that the sig-
SKEPTICS WILL SAY THAT SENSIBILITIES CAN BE FOUND only in representations, that it
is only in discourse or texts of various kinds that sensibilities achieve any defini-
tion—and they are right. But instead of assembling a group of texts defined by their
content, and then saying that these texts are all part of a discourse that is about that
content in some fundamental way, that its terms of representation are somehow
central to the object being depicted, historians might try to move away from the
object and find the perceptual, emotive, and conceptual frameworks that make it
possible for that object to be represented in that way. For instance, cultural studies
of the discourse of slavery begin with the idea that slavery is an object of repre-
sentation, and assemble various depictions, images, and discussions of slavery with
the assumption that the discourse of slavery is defined by the common subject matter
at the center of it, and not by preexisting sensibilities. The assumption is that the
discourse of slavery is a response to slavery itself, rather than part of a broader set
of perceptual orientations that make slavery visible.48 To use James’s categories, the
tough-minded and the tender-minded will see and feel objects through different
lenses; the detached scientist encounters a different world from that of the human-
itarian sentimentalist. In order to see the object at all, we need to have the equipment
for seeing; in order to find emotional response, we need to identify the orientation
toward feeling. The humanitarian sensibility is not a response to slavery, for instance,
even if slavery comes to be important in giving shape and content to that sensibility.
Rather, slavery comes to be represented as a moral evil in the eighteenth and nine-
Auslander and others have argued that vision is denigrated as a source of knowledge in contemporary
intellectual discourse by a relentless focus on language and abstraction. The advocates of “visual culture”
are arguing that we have overlooked the visual, at the very moment that the advocates for a history of
hearing or smelling are arguing that we have given primacy to the visual over the other senses. See
Auslander, “Beyond Words,” American Historical Review 110, no. 4 (October 2005): 1015–1045.
47 Rath, How Early America Sounded, 9.
48 For an example of an influential work that takes slavery as an object of representation around
which to orient its cultural analysis, see Saidiya V. Hartman, Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery, and
Self-Making in Nineteenth-Century America (New York, 1997).