Wittgenstein: Ludwig
Wittgenstein: Ludwig
Wittgenstein: Ludwig
Wittgenstein
Edward Kanterian
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Titles in the series Critical Lives present the work of leading cultural
figures of the modern period. Each book explores the life of the artist,
writer, philosopher or architect in question and relates it to their
major works.
Marcel Duchamp
Caroline Cros
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Edward Kanterian
reaktion books
Dedicated to the memory of Onnig Kanterian and Vlad Clisevici
www.reaktionbooks.co.uk
Introduction 7
1 Family and Early Years, 1889–1911 11
2 Cambridge, Norway and Philosophy, 1911–14 30
3 In the Trenches, 1914–18 61
4 Logic and Mysticism: The Tractatus 73
5 The Wilderness Years, 1918–29 87
6 Return to Cambridge and Philosophy, 1929–39 112
7 Professorship and Wartime, 1939–47 147
8 Nothing is Hidden: Philosophical Investigations 169
9 The Last Years, 1947–51 187
10 The Aftermath 198
References 206
Bibliography 219
Acknowledgements 223
Wittgenstein in the 1940s, photographed by his friend Ben Richards in Swansea.
Introduction
7
even politics. But in fact, what he wrote on these topics, from a
philosophical point of view, amounts to a tiny fragment of a huge
oeuvre. The true coordinates of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus,
Wittgenstein’s first book, to mention one example, are not Joyce,
Schönberg or Picasso (as Terry Eagleton has claimed), but really
Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell, two of the greatest logicians
and philosophers of modern times. There is thus an imbalance
between Wittgenstein’s present-day public persona and the
character of his actual work, which this book attempts to correct.
The qualification comes from the fact that Wittgenstein lived in
the modern age, the age of intellectuals, of charismatic writers,
thinkers and artists whose lives capture the collective imagination,
since they incorporate some of the deepest tensions of modernity,
and maybe even suggest some solutions to them. Wittgenstein is
of course such a charismatic intellectual figure. His lifelong concern
with religious faith, his ethical struggles and failures, his upper-class
background and his later rejection of it in favour of an almost
monkish life, his quest for love and torment with sex, his talent for
engineering and disgust for scientism, his criticism of the modern
way of life, his ambiguous relation to psychoanalysis or commu-
nism, his ultra-modernist taste in architecture and his otherwise
conservative artistic preferences – at least some of these aspects
of his personality bring him close to us. Aristotle’s life, even if we
knew its details, would simply not appeal to us in the same way.
Wittgenstein’s life, by contrast, is of great concern, indeed would be
so even if his manuscripts on language, mind, logic and mathematics
had been lost. This probably explains why Wittgenstein the
intellectual can appeal to wide audiences, even though Wittgenstein
the philosopher is little known outside academia. Wittgenstein
was born, worked, loved, searched for God, suffered and died.
This book tries to find a balance between Wittgenstein the
philosopher and Wittgenstein the intellectual, although the greater
emphasis lies on the latter. It is also the intellectual who will,
8
occasionally, be discussed from a more critical perspective. Two
chapters are dedicated to his major books, the Tractatus and the
Philosophical Investigations, but a critical discussion of his philosophy
cannot be undertaken here. The book owes much to the seminal
biographies by Brian McGuinness and Ray Monk, who have under-
taken a great and ingenious effort to display the unity between
Wittgenstein’s personality and philosophy. If my approach differs
slightly in stressing some discontinuities as well, it has only been
possible through an aspect-shift that takes their biographies as
points of departure.
9
Only from the consciousness of the uniqueness of my life arises religion
– science – and art.
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Notebooks, 1 August 1916
11
The Wittgenstein family’s ancestors were Jewish. Ludwig’s
paternal great-grandfather, Moses Maier, lived in county
Wittgenstein in Germany, now part of North Rhine–Westphalia,
and was a land agent to the princely family Sayn-Wittgenstein. The
family did not have aristocratic roots, although this was rumoured
at times. Rather, Moses Maier took over the name ‘Wittgenstein’
following Napoleon’s decree that all Jews must adopt a surname.
What is certain is that Moses’s son and Ludwig’s grandfather,
Hermann Christian Wittgenstein (1802–1878), converted to
Protestantism, cut off his ties with the local Jewish community and
moved to Leipzig, where he became a successful wool merchant.
He was described as stiff and irascible, but also as determined and
very religious, viewing life as a calling to self-accomplishment. In
1838 he married Fanny Figdor (1814–1890), the daughter of a rich,
highly cultivated Viennese family, who, like him, renounced her
Jewish faith and converted. The break with Judaism seems to have
been so complete that Hermann Christian forbade his children to
marry Jews. Indeed, he seems even to have been known as an anti-
Semite, a state of mind that was not rare among converted Jews at
the time. When they moved from Leipzig to Vienna in the 1850s
the Wittgensteins did not participate in the Jewish community,
but gave their children a thorough Germanic education. Through
Fanny’s family the Wittgensteins maintained close connections
to the Viennese cultural and artistic elite. They were known as art
collectors and as patrons of music. The famous violinist Joseph
Joachim was adopted by Fanny and Hermann at a young age and
sent to Leipzig to study with Felix Mendelssohn. Johannes Brahms
was among numerous famous friends, giving piano lessons to the
Wittgenstein daughters. The playwrights Franz Grillparzer and
Christian Friedrich Hebbel were two other such illustrious friends.
This privileged education and cultural exposure contrasted with
the otherwise frugal regime that the children were deliberately
brought up in.
12
The Wittgenstein
family house,
the ‘Palais
Wittgenstein’
in Vienna.
13
New York, where he worked as a waiter, violinist and teacher of
music, mathematics and other subjects, finally returning home
after two years with some money earned by himself and an invalu-
able experience of the New World. In later years he repeatedly
praised the free market system in newspaper articles, while the
Socialist press criticized his aggressive business methods, denoun-
cing him as an ‘American’. He studied engineering and worked first
as a draughtsman in the railways, then in the construction of ships
and turbines. At 27 he was the managing director of a Viennese
company and from then it took him only two decades to become a
steel magnate, heading several companies and turning into one of
the wealthiest industrialists in Europe, much like Andrew Carnegie
in America, whom he in fact befriended. Indeed, the family had the
byname the ‘Carnegies’ of Central Europe before the war. At the
age of 52 Karl Wittgenstein suddenly retired from business and
transferred most of his fortune into us equities, which would make
his family even richer with the onset of the economic depression
following the First World War, and devoted his time to his family,
to art and to writing sharp-witted political and economic articles
for various periodicals. Although he refused the offer of being
ennobled by adding a ‘von’ to his name (as this would have
betrayed the parvenu), he lived in Vienna with his family in an
aristocratic mansion, known as ‘Palais Wittgenstein’, built in the
nineteenth century by a Hungarian count, and also possessed a
house in Neuwaldegg on the outskirts of the capital, where Ludwig
was born. In the summer the family would retreat to the Hochreit,
Karl’s country estate and hunting lodge in the mountains. As a
patron of the arts he showed sensitivity for innovative develop-
ments, funding, for instance, the famous Sezession building,
befriending the first president of the Vienna Secession group,
Gustav Klimt, and generally surrounding himself and his family
with the crème de la crème of the Viennese elite. ‘The minister of fine
art’, as Klimt called Karl, acquired a large collection of art pieces,
14
Wittgenstein’s
parents. His father
was a leading
industrialist,
his mother an
accomplished
pianist.
15
music. Leopoldine was an extremely gifted pianist and devoted
much time to the musical education of her children. She was also
a merciless critic. Often after a concert of the Vienna Philharmonic a
large circle of music experts would gather in the Palais Wittgenstein
and analyse the performance, with Leopoldine dominating such
occasions, perhaps not unlike Ludwig many years later in
Cambridge’s philosophy circles. She was considered such a good
pianist that some liked her playing better than that of her son
Paul, the celebrated concert pianist. Most of her children were
musically very talented and active, but her two sons Hans and Paul
were exceptional. Hans was a pianist of genius, who gave public
performances even as a child.
But his father was unmoved by this talent and had decided that
his son should follow a business career. The conflict between the
duty felt towards his father and his own calling caused severe
tensions in Hans. Eventually, he ran away from home and ended
up in the United States. He vanished from a boat at the age of 26
in Chesapeake Bay, an event that was interpreted as suicide.
Of Karl’s five sons, two more, Rudolf and Kurt, committed
suicide and Ludwig too would contemplate suicide throughout his
life. Such events suggest that, despite all its cultural sophistication,
there was something tragic, ruptured and morbid about this family,
a good illustration of the thesis Tiefenpsychologie that Freud devel-
oped in Vienna, not by coincidence. As Brian McGuinness once
16
Wittgenstein with his brother Paul and sisters.
put it, the family history ‘contains many anecdotes that may have
figured in the appendices to a treatise on psycho-analysis’.4 Rudolf,
whose greatest interests were literature and theatre, was psycholog-
ically unstable. He suffered from the thought that he was a homo-
sexual (a ‘perverted disposition’, as he described it in his farewell
letter) and when he seemed to be unable to cope with his life in
Berlin he ended it. He walked into a pub, ordered drinks, asked
the pianist to play the song ‘I am lost’ and poisoned himself on the
spot. He too had come into conflict with his father’s expectations.
Although the same is not true of Kurt, who killed himself because
his soldiers deserted him while he was serving as an officer in the
army on the Italian front in 1918, all these suicides betray an almost
unbearable sense of duty, be it towards themselves or towards the
overpowering father figure – a sense of duty that would sooner or
later crush them.
Since the daughters did not experience the same kind of pressure
from their father, their lives followed a more balanced pattern.
Hermine organized musical evenings, helped her father in acquiring
17
Gustav Klimt,
Margarete Stonborough-
Wittgenstein, 1905, oil
on canvas. Margarete
was one of
Wittgenstein’s sisters.
18
considered the most harmonious person in the family. Helene did
marry. She had great musical talents, but did not use them profes-
sionally. She also had a sense of humour that Ludwig could relate
to, since she liked to play nonsensical games with language, which
led to many funny exchanges with her philosopher brother, who
was later to say that one could write a good philosophical book
consisting entirely of jokes. But his closest affinity was with his
youngest sister, Margarete (‘Gretl’), a beautiful woman with a
strong personality, sharp, critical intellect, a predilection for artistic
innovation and passion for new ideas such as psychoanalysis.
She was to become a friend of Sigmund Freud, who psycho-
analysed her and whom she helped to flee the Nazis. Margarete
exercised a great intellectual and artistic influence on her brother
Ludwig. As Hermine wrote about her:
19
alone. He even commissioned special works from composers such
as Richard Strauss, Sergej Prokofiev, Benjamin Britten and espe-
cially Maurice Ravel, who wrote the famous Concerto for the Left
Hand (1932) for Paul. Here is what Ludwig told Maurice Drury
about Paul in 1935:
20
The young
Wittgenstein on
a rocking-horse,
1891.
writes in Mein Kampf that there was a Jewish boy at his school who
was not much to be trusted and of whom Hitler thought little.
Much has been made of this passage by an interpreter who claims
that Wittgenstein was the boy mentioned by Hitler and that we can
see them together in a class photo.7 Moreover, Hitler was suppos-
edly even influenced in his anti-Semitism by the awkward behav-
iour of his schoolmate Wittgenstein. The first claim is simply false
(the boy supposedly identified as Wittgenstein in the photo is not
him) and the second unconvincing speculation. If aspects of Hitler’s
ideology have their roots at this school, then they are more likely to
be found in what the history teacher Leopold Pötsch taught Hitler,
namely that the traditional patriotism for the Austro-Hungarian
empire was obsolete and that the emerging pan-Germanic nation-
alism should be embraced instead.8 The foundations of Hitler’s
anti-Semitism were not laid in Linz, but much more likely in
Vienna, a city in which Austro-German xenophobia and especially
21
anti-Semitism was rife, particularly during the long service of the
populist mayor Karl Lueger (1897–1910), much admired by Hitler.9
With his reclusive character and his elitist background Ludwig
did not adapt well to the new environment. He was later to describe
his three years at the school as a painful experience, which would
have been beset with total loneliness and alienation had it not been
for the son of his host family with whom he developed a close
friendship. As Hermine was later told by one of Ludwig’s former
classmates, he had appeared to them ‘as if blown from an alien
world. He had a completely different life-style from theirs, addressing
his school-fellows . . . with the formal pronoun “Sie”; which created
a barrier.’ He read different books and appeared more mature
and serious than them. ‘Above all he was uncommonly sensitive,
and I can imagine that to him his school-fellows in turn seemed
to stem from another world, from a terrible one!’10 They paid him
back by ridiculing him with jingles such as ‘Wittgenstein wends
his woeful windy way towards Vienna’.11 His performance at school
was mediocre. He did well only in English and Conduct, and in
Religion, where he scored the highest mark. Ironically it was in
these years that he lost the naïve religious faith of his childhood,
especially through conversations with Margarete. Nevertheless,
questions of religious faith were to concern him for the rest of his
life, if only rarely from a philosophical point of view.
Part of the reason that Ludwig was sent to this school was that,
unlike his older brothers, he did not rebel against his father,
although he would have been in the best position to get away with
it. Instead, he seems to have manifested a concern with how he
appeared in the eyes of others and thus a tendency to please every-
body. At least this is how he perceived himself much later in a
written confession addressed to his family:
22
Wittgenstein as a
teenager.
23
An engineering
diagram drawn
by the young
Wittgenstein.
24
was taught the canon of classic German literature, that is, Goethe,
Schiller, Lessing, Mörike, authors he would admire for the rest of
his life. He was also very fond of Lichtenberg’s aphorisms, which
he would quote in his diaries, and of Schopenhauer and Gottfried
Keller. His literary taste could be described as conservative. He
became familiar with the works of nineteenth-century writers such
as Johann Nestroy, Grillparzer and Nikolaus Lenau, and, also,
largely through Margarete’s influence, with Freud’s progressive
ideas and Karl Kraus’s scathing and stylistically brilliant criticism
of moral, intellectual and linguistic decadence. But he never
warmed to the authors of his own generation. The most modern
writers he admired were Tolstoy, Dostoevsky, Kierkegaard and
Nietzsche. All he had to say about Kafka was that this was some-
body who gave ‘himself a great deal of trouble not writing about
his trouble’.13 He did read Thomas Mann, Rainer Maria Rilke and
Georg Trakl, and he did acknowledge genius where he sensed it
(for instance in Trakl), but none of these became favourites.
The same holds for his musical orientation. Although the period
of his youth was a time of great innovation in music, especially
in Vienna, where the Second Viennese School around Arnold
Schoenberg, Alban Berg and Anton Webern developed twelve-tone
music, Wittgenstein’s taste remained more traditional. This was
not because he had no understanding of music. Although he did
not learn to play any instrument in his childhood, he was, like the
rest of his family, musically very gifted and could whistle whole
scores with great accuracy. As an adult he taught himself the
clarinet. Wittgenstein simply detested contemporary music. Even
a composer like Gustav Mahler was too modern and corrupted for
him, and he would enter violent arguments with anybody who
thought otherwise.14 His heroes were Haydn, Mozart, Beethoven,
Schubert, Brahms and Labor (the latter was patronized by Ludwig’s
father). An exception regarding Wittgenstein’s anti-modernist
tastes was architecture, about which more will be said later.
25
There is one further contemporary influence that needs to be
mentioned in this context, and it is one of darker provenance:
Otto Weininger’s Sex and Character (1903). It is difficult for us
today to understand the fascination this misogynistic, racist and
reactionary book exercised, not only on young Wittgenstein but
on a whole generation. Weininger (1880–1903) was a tormented
homosexual and anti-Semitic young Jew who at the age of 23, only
half a year after his book was published (and half a year before
Rudolf Wittgenstein killed himself in a similarly theatrical man-
ner), committed suicide in the house in which Beethoven had died
in Vienna. This suicide made Weininger immediately famous, and
his book became a bestseller, reaching thirteen reprints within four
years. The book pretends to give a complete anthropology, a solution
to all moral problems and an intransigent critique of modernity.
Humans are bipolar beings, torn apart between the pursuit for
higher ideals, such as truth and love, and mere animal instincts
such as sexuality. Love and sex are thus mutually exclusive. The
first corresponds to the Platonic form of ‘Man’, the second to that
of ‘Woman’. All humans are mixtures of these two forms and thus
bisexual, but actual women embody ‘Woman’ to a much larger
degree. Women are therefore akin to animals, entirely concerned
with the ‘main’ aspects of sexuality, procreation and motherhood.
Men are concerned with much more spiritual things, for example,
politics, philosophy, art. Only they possess rationality, morality
and free will, whereas women are immoral and herd animals. Jews
are entirely female (‘the most manly Jew is more feminine than the
least manly Aryan’)15 and thus entirely depraved.
As Ray Monk explains, it could not be Weininger’s anti-Semitism
or ‘theory’ of women that attracted Wittgenstein.16 Later in life
he actually said about this ‘theory’: ‘How wrong [Weininger] was,
my God he was wrong.’17 It was rather Weininger’s views on men
and modernity, and the more general ethical questions Weininger
raised (as Wittgenstein tried to explain later to his puzzled
26
The Austrian
writer Otto
Weininger, an
influence on
Wittgenstein.
If we now turn to the gifted, we shall see that in their case love
frequently begins with self-mortification, humiliation, and
27
Wittgenstein and his friend Eccles experimenting with a kite on the moors near
Glossop, Derbyshire, in 1908.
28
father and one from which he graduated successfully in 1908. In
Berlin he went numerous times to the opera, 30 times alone to hear
Wagner’s Die Meistersinger, if we are to believe him. It was also the
time in which he started writing a diary, ‘thoughts about myself on
slips of paper’, as he wrote in retrospect.
29
2
30
vexed, will cease to ask illegitimate questions’.1 Wittgenstein knew
passages such as this by heart and they became relevant for his
own philosophy.
In any case, such readings show that by the time he went to
Berlin his interests covered questions of a more theoretical nature
than those related to engineering. In Berlin or very soon afterwards
they must have turned into a calling. As Hermine wrote in her
memoirs:
31
Part of a page from the German edition of Frege’s Basic Laws of Arithmetic.
retrospect as the most pivotal, since his own answer to the founda-
tional question led to the greatest revolution in logic since Aristotle.
Frege’s own theory of mathematics, so-called logicism, involved the
idea that all truths of arithmetic are deducible from a few purely
logical truths, which themselves are self-evident, indubitable and
independent of the human mind. Logicism also involved the claim
that numbers are genuine objects, although not physical or mental,
but abstract ones, situated in a ‘Third Realm’. Consequently, state-
ments about numbers, for example, ‘1 + 2 = 3’, are not statements
about physical or mental objects such as a collection of apples on a
table or of mental ideas in our mind or brain, but statements about
certain abstract objects. In any case, in order to prove that arith-
metic is deducible from logical laws alone, Frege devised an ideal
language and a formal logical calculus much more powerful than
the Aristotelian syllogistic available hitherto. He presented this
logic in his Concept Script (1879), argued for his logicism in the
Foundations of Arithmetic (1884) and finally came to develop it fully
in his two-volume masterwork Basic Laws of Arithmetic (vol. i, 1893,
vol. ii, 1903). Both the propositional logic and the predicate logic
32
The philosopher
and mathematician
Gottlob Frege, a
major influence on
Wittgenstein.
33
(1903) and later in Principia Mathematica (1910–13), co-authored
with Alfred North Whitehead. In his famous article ‘On Denoting’
(1905) Russell argued that natural language is misleading and that
its structure can be understood only by means of logical analysis.
Thus he claimed that a sentence like ‘The present king of France is
bald’ only appears to be an ordinary subject-predicate sentence,
whereas in reality it is a much more complicated sentence. Russell
thought that we can apply logic to ordinary sentences to unveil
their real structure, in this way solving any problems that might
arise from troublesome terms. The troublesome term here is ‘The
present king of France’, which according to Russell must be viewed
as meaningless, if it is taken as the grammatical subject, since there
is no present king of France. And if a component of a sentence is
meaningless, then the sentence itself must be meaningless. Thus it
would seem that we must conclude from the meaninglessness of
‘The present king of France’ to the meaninglessness of ‘The present
king of France is bald’! But of course, the sentence ‘The present king
of France is bald’ is not meaningless. We all understand it. Russell
solved this problem by claiming that the sentence actually means
‘There is one and only one king of France and he is bald’ and that
this is its actual, if more complicated form (which in the notation of
mathematical logic looks even more complicated). Here the trouble-
some term ‘the present king of France’ does not even occur and thus
the problem this term posed does not arise anymore. This ingen-
ious argument has some similarity to the way Hertz treated the
term ‘force’, as just seen. With Russell’s article the paradigm of
philosophical analysis, which was to dominate much of twentieth-
century Anglophone philosophy, was born. In his early period
Wittgenstein accepted this paradigm, that is, that we can understand
the real structure of our language only through logical analysis,
and he came to reject it only much later (see chapter Eight).
Wittgenstein came across the works of Frege and Russell in
Manchester for the first time and started very soon to come up
34
Bertrand Russell
in 1918.
35
Part of a page from Whitehead’s and Russell’s Principia Mathematica.
36
I was shown into Frege’s study. Frege was a small, neat man with
a pointed beard who bounced around the room as he talked.
He absolutely wiped the floor with me, and I felt very depressed;
but at the end he said ‘You must come again’, so I cheered up.
I had several discussions with him after that. Frege would never
talk about anything but logic and mathematics, if I started on
some other subject, he would say something polite and then
plunge back into logic and mathematics. He once showed me
an obituary on a colleague, who, it was said, never used a word
without knowing what it meant; he expressed astonishment
that a man should be praised for this!’5
37
resolve the vocational crisis he had been in since he left school.
He asked Russell for advice and Russell told him to give him some
written work first. The essay Wittgenstein produced over the vaca-
tion much impressed Russell. As he wrote to Lady Ottoline, he
thought it was ‘very good, much better than my English pupils do.
I shall certainly encourage him. Perhaps he will do great things.’
He advised him to continue with philosophy, an encouragement
that Wittgenstein perceived as his salvation, ending the uncertainty
about his direction in life. On 1 February 1912 he was admitted as
an undergraduate at Trinity College, with Russell as his supervisor.
But this was no ordinary student. At the end of the term Russell
realized that he had taught his pupil everything he himself knew
and that Wittgenstein was ‘the young man one hopes for’, who
could solve the great philosophical problems Russell himself felt
too exhausted to tackle after completing his masterwork Principia
Mathematica.
38
ever known of genius as traditionally conceived, passionate, pro-
found, intense, and dominating’.8 Russell and Wittgenstein were
soon discussing philosophy as equals. As mentioned, Wittgenstein’s
initial interest had been in the philosophy of mathematics and the
solution to Russell’s Paradox. But in Cambridge he began to think
about more questions, namely the nature of logic itself, its subject
matter, the status of logical truths, the relation between logic and
fundamental language. These questions were to preoccupy him
for several years and he presented his answers in the Tractatus,
completed in 1918.
Like Vienna, Cambridge before the First World War was a place
of many renowned academics and intellectuals, and one could have
expected Wittgenstein to fit well in this context. Given his depres-
sive nature, this was only partly the case. But it was certainly help-
ful for Wittgenstein to be able to exchange with other high-calibre
minds. Apart from Russell he became acquainted with leading
figures such as the mathematician G. H. Hardy, the logician W. E.
Johnson, and the philosophers Whitehead, J. E. McTaggart, George
Edward Moore, and the great economist John Maynard Keynes.
Whitehead and McTaggart did not have a favourable impression
of the young philosopher. Johnson was initially appointed as
Wittgenstein’s personal tutor, but this arrangement was terminated
after a few weeks, since Johnson was estranged by the student’s
patronizing behaviour. Nevertheless, they stayed on friendly terms.
Over time, Wittgenstein also became friends with Moore and
Keynes. Moore (1873–1958) had already published his most impor-
tant contributions to the nascent current of analytic philosophy,
in particular his book Principia Ethica (1903). Wittgenstein did
not think too highly of Moore as a philosopher, but he admired
Moore’s sincerity and truthfulness. Keynes (1883–1946), who at the
time was working on the theory of probability and was influenced
by Russell and Moore, was fascinated by Wittgenstein as soon as
they met. He was certainly Wittgenstein’s intellectual match, quick,
39
sharp, original and open to new ideas, and in his first years in
Cambridge Wittgenstein spent countless hours in discussions with
him. Keynes was also to become one of Wittgenstein’s protectors
on a more practical level, helping him when he became a prisoner
of war in 1918, bringing him back to Cambridge in 1929 and finally
lobbying for his professorship in 1939.
It was partly due to Keynes’s support that Wittgenstein was
made a member of the Apostles in November 1912. This was a
select debating society founded in the nineteenth century, which
was presently led by Keynes and the writer Lytton Strachey, and
somebody like Wittgenstein was just the kind of member they were
after. Around the turn of the century some of the most famous
British intellectuals and writers were its members, including the
Bloomsbury generation. The Apostles adopted Wittgenstein as an
‘embryo’, which was the first step towards full membership. Russell
was opposed to this adoption, arguing that the ‘embryo’ would not
like their intellectual and homoerotic self-affectation. And, indeed,
Wittgenstein was disgusted by the society and left it after only one
term. The one thing the Apostles were not, he said, was apostolic.
A sample of the pretentious tone among the Apostles is given by
the following passage from a letter by Strachey to Keynes, dated
17 May 1912:
40
A group photograph of the Cambridge University Moral Science Club, c. 1913.
41
Wittgenstein’s
friend David
Pinsent, to whom
the Tractatus Logico-
Philosophicus was
to be dedicated,
seen here in
Norway on a trip
with Wittgenstein.
42
Wittgenstein soon confided in Pinsent as in no one else before,
telling him about the loneliness and suicidal thoughts he had
experienced since leaving his parents’ home in 1903, thoughts from
which he was relieved only in Cambridge. The two friends also had
many conversations about philosophy. In May 1912 Pinsent wrote
in his diary: ‘he is reading philosophy . . . but has only just started
systematic reading: and he expresses the most naïve surprise that
all the philosophers he once worshipped in ignorance are after all
stupid and dishonest and make disgusting mistakes!’11 A year later,
in August 1913, Pinsent notes:
Pinsent’s diaries also give insight into some of the more eccen-
tric sides of Wittgenstein’s personality. After he was offered accom-
modation at Trinity College, Wittgenstein went on a shopping tour
for furniture with Pinsent. ‘I went out and helped him interview
a lot of furniture at various shops . . . It was rather amusing: he
is terribly fastidious and we led the shopman a frightful dance,
Vittgenstein [sic] ejaculating “No – Beastly!” to 90% of what he
43
shewed us!’13 Around the same time Wittgenstein told Russell that
‘he dislikes all ornamentation that is not part of the construction,
and can never find anything simple enough’.14 This was of course
the taste of Kraus and Loos, for whom ornament was the expres-
sion of inauthenticity and decadence. Eventually Wittgenstein
decided to have the furniture specially made for him. In an earlier
episode Wittgenstein and Eccles, his friend from Manchester, were
planning to catch a train from Manchester to Liverpool. However,
having missed the train, Wittgenstein suggested hiring an entire
train to bring them to their destination. The plan was eventually
dropped, but he still opted for a costly solution, namely hiring a
taxi. These incidents prove that in his earlier years Wittgenstein
was not quite the hermit he was to become after the First World
War. When he asked Pinsent to accompany him on a trip to
Iceland in September 1912, Pinsent’s reply was that he was unsure
whether he could afford the trip. But Wittgenstein told him not to
worry, because, while he himself had no money either, his father
‘had plenty of it’. He then handed over a considerable amount of
cash to Pinsent. When the journey started, Wittgenstein was
44
suffering), but also some personal ones, which were always started
by Wittgenstein. Unlike Pinsent, he was irascible and could perceive
innocent acts as entirely offensive. Thus when Pinsent entered a
conversation with another traveller on the train and went to have a
smoke with him in another carriage, Wittgenstein became furious,
throwing what can only be described as a fit of jealousy and telling
Pinsent that if he pleased he could travel the whole day with the
other man. Thanks to Pinsent’s frankness and friendliness they
soon made up again, but there were other occurrences of what
Pinsent called ‘sulky fits’ during the trip. It has been suggested that
the two friends were really lovers, but there is no evidence for this.
It seems more accurate to say that for Wittgenstein, his relationship
with Pinsent had a very different significance than it had for the
latter. As McGuinness has suggested, for Pinsent the friendship
was following a conventional pattern; it was the kind of friendship
a former public schoolboy like him would have with a person
he had known only for a few months.16 There may have been
suppressed erotic undertones on Wittgenstein’s side – a leitmotif
in Wittgenstein’s relations with other young men, in which the
homoerotic charge was often only experienced by Wittgenstein,
and rarely expressed. Of far greater, indeed tremendous, impor-
tance to him was closeness on both a spiritual and personal level.
Wittgenstein was a very intense human being, ‘he had the idea
of perfection in every area, in the serious matters of everyday life,
in his work, or in the choice of a handkerchief for a present’.17
Once, when he was pacing ‘up and down in my [Russell’s] room
like a wild beast for three hours in agitated silence’, Russell asked
him whether he was thinking about logic or his sins, to which
Wittgenstein replied ‘Both.’ He could only tolerate total sincerity
and did not accept compromises about anything, be it personal,
philosophical or aesthetic matters. If such disagreements arose, he
would not only be entirely frank with the other person to the point
of disregarding their feelings, but even try to change their life. It is
45
reported that when, during his first year in Cambridge, he found
out that a certain undergraduate was a monk, Wittgenstein, disap-
proving of the dishonesty he saw in any organized form of religion,
fiercely attacked the man in the presence of others, telling him
that he should read some good book on exact science to see what
honest thought really is. Or again, after attending Moore’s lectures
in October 1912, Wittgenstein, officially only an undergraduate,
sharply criticized the much more senior philosopher. ‘He told me
these lectures were very bad – that what I ought to do was to say
what I thought, not to discuss what other people thought; and he
came no more to my lectures.’18
This frankness, paired with his quick-tempered and overbearing
nature, was not tolerated by everybody. In Wittgenstein’s second
year in Cambridge personal frictions emerged between him and
Russell. One immediate reason was Wittgenstein’s disapproval of
Russell’s essay ‘The Essence of Religion’ (1912), in which he attempted
to formulate a new mysticism based on the ‘infinite part of our
life’. Wittgenstein fiercely attacked Russell for betraying the spirit
of exactness and speaking in public in a fuzzy way about very
intimate issues. ‘Wittgenstein’s criticism disturbed me profoundly.
He was so unhappy, so gentle, so wounded in his wish to think well
of me.’19 Soon after they went to watch a boat race. Wittgenstein’s
reaction, according to Russell, was to say that ‘all was of the devil’:
he suddenly stood still and explained that the way we had spent
the afternoon was so vile that we ought not to live, or at least
he ought not, that nothing is tolerable except producing great
works or enjoying those of others, that he has accomplished
nothing and never will, etc. – all this with a force that knocks
one down. He makes me feel like a bleating lambkin.20
But eventually these scenes became too much even for Russell. On
one occasion he told his pupil to stop thinking so much about him-
46
self, and on another he suggested that Wittgenstein read some
French prose in order to escape the ‘danger of becoming narrow and
uncivilised’ by focusing only on logic. Wittgenstein took such advice
badly. Some months later, in June 1913, Wittgenstein came to Russell
to analyse their relationship, pointing out what he thought was going
wrong between them. After unsuccessfully trying to calm down his
pupil Russell finally said sharply: ‘All you want is a little self-control.’
Upon this Wittgenstein left the room ‘in an air of high tragedy’,
failed to show up at a concert they planned to attend together,
and Russell had to look for him, fearing he might commit suicide.
What also strained the relationship was the fact that the
younger philosopher became more and more critical of Russell’s
ideas and began to develop an increasingly original account of
logic. So dominating and dismissive was Wittgenstein in their
conversations that Russell stopped talking about his work at one
point. When he did show Wittgenstein a manuscript on the theory
of knowledge he was working on, the reaction was merciless:
47
1912–13, which he spent in the family retreat on the Hochreit and
thus far removed from any academic environment, proved to be
fruitful, and upon his return he reported his progress to Russell.
In March 1913 Wittgenstein’s first publication came out, a short
review of a logic textbook by P. Coffey written for the Cambridge
Review. The sharply critical review, the only one of its kind he ever
wrote, smacked of overconfidence:
48
henceforth, is telling.24 Initially, the two friends had planned to go
to Spain, but the philosophical progress he had achieved on the
Hochreit led Wittgenstein to a change of mind. He now preferred
a quiet holiday allowing for opportunity to work to a voyage full
of distractions, during which he might have been surrounded ‘by
crowds of American tourists, which he can’t stand’ (as Pinsent
reports). The trip was more enjoyable than the previous one to
Iceland. Wittgenstein was now a more amicable companion,
although some ‘sulky fits’ still occurred. They travelled comfort-
ably, mostly in first class, and eventually found a quiet village,
Øystese, in a fjord near Bergen, where they spent three weeks. They
played dominoes, went on walking tours, but also spent a consider-
able amount of time working. Wittgenstein was trying to solve
certain difficult problems about the foundations of logic and this
visibly required all his concentration. As Pinsent describes it,
Wittgenstein would mutter ‘to himself in a mixture of German
and English’ and ‘stride up and down the room all the while’.25
The progress Wittgenstein made during this vacation gave him
some confidence that he was doing something worthwhile. He felt
that his ideas were original and significant enough to be important
to others. But this progress also gave him reason to agonize; for his
valuable ideas could be lost. In his letters to Russell he wrote:
49
At the beginning of October 1913 they met and Wittgenstein gave
Russell a lengthy account of his work on logic. Fortunately, Russell
had ordered a typist to be present, so Wittgenstein’s summary
survived and was eventually published in 1961 as Notes on Logic.
The text formulates fundamental criticisms of Frege’s and Russell’s
conception of the nature of logic, which were later incorporated
in the Tractatus. Notes on Logic is the earliest philosophical text
by Wittgenstein that has been preserved and it provides clear
evidence that his primary interest at the time was the foundations
of logic, and not ethics and mysticism, as it has become fashionable
to claim. Ethics and mysticism were added only at a later stage,
as we shall see, and any interpretation of the Tractatus must take
this genealogy of his interests into account.
50
Wittgenstein’s and Pinsent’s postcard to William Eccles from Skjolden, Norway, 1913.
51
More importantly, he soon started to work, feeling that he had
found his much-needed inspiration. He corresponded with both
Russell and Frege on the foundations of logic. The letters he wrote
to Frege have been lost, but their content can be partly inferred
from Frege’s surviving replies and Wittgenstein’s subsequent writ-
ings. Those to Russell were equally important, for they contained
not only his ideas about logic, but also formulated serious objec-
tions to Frege’s views on language and thought. For instance, Frege
held that every simple declarative sentence like ‘Tom is American’
has a sense and a reference. The sense is the thought expressed by
the sentence, in our case the thought that Tom is American.
Thoughts are not material objects; they do not have spatio-temporal
and physical properties, but are ‘abstract’, like numbers. The
reference is the truth-value of the sentence, ‘The True’ or ‘The
False’, which are also abstract objects. Thus every true sentence
refers to the object the True. But, as Wittgenstein noted, this com-
mits the mistake of assimilating sentences to names, for it is the
primary function of names to refer to objects. Sentences are very
unlike names, be it only for the reason that you can negate a sen-
tence, but not a name (what is ‘not Charlie Chaplin’ supposed to
mean, taken by itself?). Wittgenstein also rejected Frege’s account
of intentionality, of the directedness of our thoughts and how they
reach out to reality. Against Frege’s claim that the sentence ‘Tom
believes that it is raining’ signifies a relation between a person
(Tom) and a thought (‘It is raining’), Wittgenstein contended that
when Tom thinks that it is raining, and it is indeed raining, then
what Tom thinks is precisely what is the case, namely that it is rain-
ing. It is not true that there is a third entity, a thought, which is
standing between Tom and reality, between Tom and what is the
case. Rather, Tom’s thought reaches right up to reality and is not
an abstract object, as Frege believes. (Wittgenstein’s theory is
more complicated, since it purports to account for false sentences
as well.)
52
On his way from Norway to Vienna Wittgenstein visited Frege
in Jena for a few days and had several intensive discussions with
him. The two philosophers did not come to an agreement on any
substantial issue, but while his first visit in 1911 had ended with a
feeling of defeat, Wittgenstein now believed that it was he who
‘wiped the floor with Frege’.28 They never met again. Nevertheless,
Wittgenstein continued to admire Frege and always kept some of
his writings with him, especially Frege’s masterwork, Basic Laws of
Arithmetic, from which he could recite whole passages by heart.
In one of his last diary entries Wittgenstein wrote in 1951: ‘Frege’s
style of writing is sometimes great; Freud writes excellently and it
is a pleasure to read him, but his writing is never great.’29
After his Christmas vacation in Vienna, Wittgenstein returned
to Skjolden and stayed there till June 1914. The problems of logic
and language he was working on were very difficult and he felt he
was making only very slow progress. His mood during these
months seems to have been very dismal, verging on total despair,
if not madness. During no other year did he spend more time con-
templating suicide than in 1914. The circumstances were particularly
severe. He was now not looking for approval from others any more,
as he had done just two years before, but felt that he was expected,
indeed that it was his calling, to solve the hardest problems of
philosophy. Moreover, his brief stay in Vienna, where his family
had commemorated his father’s passing away the previous year
(Karl had died of cancer in January 1913), deeply unsettled him
and only added further to his inner torture. It was ‘logic and sins’
once again. We get a good sense of this double-edged pressure
from his letters to Russell during this time:
53
eruption once and for all, so that I can turn into a different
person. I can’t write you anything about logic today. Perhaps
you regard this thinking about myself as a waste of time – but
how can I be a logician before I’m a human being! Far the most
important thing is to settle accounts with myself!30
It is VERY sad, but I have once again no logical news for you. The
reason is that things have gone terribly badly for me in the last
weeks. . . . Every day I was tormented by a frightful Angst and by
depression in turns and even in the intervals I was so exhausted
that I wasn’t able to think of doing a bit of work. . . . I never
knew what it meant to feel only one step away from madness.31
54
not simply a result of your sensitiveness or my inconsiderate-
ness. It came from deeper – from the fact that my letter must
have shown you how totally different our ideas are, E.G. [sic]
of the value of a scientific work. . . . I can see perfectly well that
your value-judgements are just as good and just as deep-seated
in you as mine in me, and that I have no right to catechize you.
But I see equally clearly, now, that for that very reason there
cannot be any real relation of friendship between us. I shall be
grateful to you and devoted to you with all my heart for the whole
of my life, but I shall not write to you again and you will not see me
again either. Now that I am once again reconciled with you I
want to part from you in peace . . . Goodbye!32
55
March to April 1914. The stay was not without pleasant aspects,
as they went on walks rich in stimulating conversations and played
the piano with the Draegni family. But when it came to discussing
philosophy and logic, Wittgenstein was entirely dominant, leaving
to Moore the passive role of the audience. Moore made the best out
of this role and wrote down most of what Wittgenstein said to him.
These Notes Dictated to G. E. Moore in Norway comprise some fifteen
pages and were published in 1961. Given how little else survives from
Wittgenstein’s earliest period, these dictations are of great value.
They contain the earliest occurrence of the distinction between
saying and showing, which is not only central to the Tractatus but
has also gained some popularity outside of his philosophy, indeed
outside of philosophy.
Upon his return to Cambridge Moore enquired with a university
official whether it was possible for Wittgenstein, who was still
nominally a ‘research student’, to submit his treatise on logic as a
dissertation to obtain the ba degree. The answer was positive, but
the condition was that the dissertation should fulfil the standard
academic requirements, that is, contain a preface specifying what
was original in the work and endnotes indicating the sources the
author had used. Moore forwarded these requirements, which he
had not stipulated, to Wittgenstein, who then became furious –
not so much with the university as with Moore.
56
The hermit’s
retreat:
Wittgenstein’s
house in Skjolden,
Norway, built
before the First
World War.
57
such ascetic circumstances says much about his tormented soul
and the positive effect loneliness seemed to have on him. Other
philosophers come to mind who chose to live in a hut far from
the machinations of society, most notably Martin Heidegger and
Constantin Noica.34 But while in the case of Heidegger the hut was
only the holiday retreat of a philosophy professor who otherwise
lived in a comfortable villa in his hometown Freiburg, and thus
mere bourgeois romanticism disguised as metaphysics, and in the
case of Noica the seclusion was that of a passive dissident who cul-
tivated his own philosophical school far away from the communist
authorities, in Wittgenstein’s case the seclusion was neither choice
nor external constraint, but came out of inner necessity.
To avoid the impending tourist season, Wittgenstein left
Norway in July 1914 for a visit home. He was not to return until
1921. Wittgenstein was at this moment a very wealthy man, since
he had inherited, like his brother and sisters, a huge fortune from
his father. His income amounted to at least £120,000 per year
(translated into today’s currency, and this might have been just the
interest). But true to the charitable activities of his family, he sought
ways of donating considerable amounts of it. As mentioned earlier,
he was a keen reader of Karl Kraus’s journal Die Fackel, indeed so
keen that he had issues of it sent to Skjolden. It was in one of these
issues that he had come across an article by Kraus on Ludwig von
Ficker, a writer and editor of another Austrian literary journal, Der
Brenner. In his typical satirical tone, Kraus wrote about Der Brenner:
‘That Austria’s only honest review is published in Innsbruck
should be known, if not in Austria, at least in Germany, whose only
honest review is also published in Innsbruck.’35 It was, whether or
not honest, a leading avant-garde journal, in which poets like Else
Lasker-Schüler, Hermann Broch and Georg Trakl, probably the
greatest expressionist poet of the German language, were publish-
ing. The fact that Kraus admired Ficker gave Wittgenstein enough
confidence to offer Ficker £40–50,000 for distribution among
58
artists in need of it. Ficker was at first incredulous of this unexpected
benefaction, but after a few letters were exchanged, he realized
that Wittgenstein’s intentions were genuine. They agreed that the
beneficiaries should be Trakl, Lasker-Schüler, the painter Oskar
Kokoschka, the architect Adolf Loos, the poets Theodor Däubler,
Theodor Haecker, Rainer Maria Rilke and several others.
Wittgenstein did not know the works of most of them. When
Ficker sent him Trakl’s poems, he commented: ‘I do not under-
stand them, but their tone makes me happy. It is the tone of true
genius.’ Remarkably, Wittgenstein almost met Trakl in 1914. While
he was stationed in Krakow as an Austrian soldier, Wittgenstein
learnt that Trakl, also an Austrian soldier, was in hospital there.
He rushed to the hospital where Trakl was treated, but learnt,
much to his consternation, that the poet had killed himself with
an overdose of cocaine just three days before.
Wittgenstein did know and indeed appreciated Rilke’s early
work, which was written in a late nineteenth-century neo-Romantic
style, and was moved by Rilke’s letter of thanks:
[It] both moved and deeply gladdened me. The affection of any
noble human being is a support in the unsteady balance of my
life. I am totally unworthy of the splendid present which I carry
over my heart as a sign and remembrance of this affection. If you
could only convey my deepest thanks and my faithful devotion to
Rilke.36
59
the mediation of von Ficker, the philosopher immediately engaged
the architect, who was something of a controversial celebrity in the
capital, in a heated discussion about modern architecture. But there
was no deep-seated disagreement, since both had much in com-
mon, in particular an abhorrence of any kind of ornament. Loos
had displayed his radical minimalism when erecting a much disputed
building opposite the imperial palace, which was known as ‘the
house without eyebrows’, because it lacked even dripstones above
the windows.37 For Loos this was not a purely stylistic choice, but
expressed an ethical position as well. As a vehement opponent to
Art Nouveau he wrote in his essay ‘Ornament and Crime’ (1908) that
ornament was immoral and degenerate, the best sign that a civiliza-
tion was decadent. Something is ornament when it is uselessly
attached to a useful object, thus depriving art of its essence – a true
‘crime’. ‘The evolution of culture is synonymous with the elimina-
tion of ornament from objects of daily use.’38 We can see how this
austere minimalism appealed to Wittgenstein’s ideal of purity as
a quality he had found so appealing in Weininger’s writings. Loos
soon became a reference point for Wittgenstein and was to influ-
ence his own architectural endeavours when he helped build a
mansion for his sister Margarete in the 1920s. However, after the
war he came to dislike Loos, because in his eyes Loos had become
infected with ‘virulent bogus intellectualism’. This pattern of attrac-
tion and disaffection, of interest and disappointment, characterized
many of Wittgenstein’s relationships; if the person in question was
not up to his standards, ethical or otherwise, he was simply not able
to meet them any more. Wittgenstein had to accept their entire
personality or discontinue the friendship.
60
3
61
– cannot lose. We, however, can lose and shall lose, if not this
year, then next year. The thought that our race is going to be
beaten depresses me terribly, because I am completely German.1
Patriotism aside, the other reason for going to war was a feeling
typical of others as well, especially for intellectuals: the feeling that
Europe was decadent and dead, that one had to do something real,
reconnect to ‘life’. As his sister Hermine explains in her memoirs,
Wittgenstein ‘had the intense wish to assume some heavy burden
and to perform some task other than purely intellectual work’.
He viewed the war, like other contemporaries, as a personal test,
believing he would only discover his worth by facing death.
Wittgenstein got a first taste of the war very soon. Initially
assigned to an artillery regiment, he was, ten days after his enlist-
ment, transferred to a small gunboat, the Goplana, which ventured
down the Vistula river into enemy territory. Here is his account of the
first assignment, in his nightwear, a day after his arrival on the boat:
The task of manning the searchlight was that of a private and rela-
tively dangerous. The real problem, however, was his shipmates,
and later his comrades at the Eastern front, whom he found
unbearable. With a few exceptions they were, from his point of
view, ‘a company of drunkards, a company of vile and stupid people’,
‘malicious and heartless’, ‘appallingly limited’, indeed lacking
humanity, as he wrote in his diary in the spring of 1916. Most of
62
them were working-class men with whom Wittgenstein had little
in common. But the life on a crammed ship in a limiting situation
brought out the differences between them and him much more
strongly. He felt hated by them and in turn hated them. His man-
ners and mannerisms, his fastidiousness and refinement were only
a liability in these circumstances, especially as these distinctive
features did not correlate with higher rank. As in the school in
Linz, he felt ostracized and betrayed. He tried repeatedly to exercise
Christian humility, urging himself to understand and tolerate his
comrades. But even when the hatred was overcome, his disgust
persisted. Nevertheless, and this was a typical Wittgensteinian
self-torture, he did not seek relief from this situation; although
he was entitled to certain privileges having graduated in Linz,
Wittgenstein refused to make use of them for a prolonged period.
Wittgenstein was caught up in the ill-fated Eastern campaign
of 1914, which came to a halt, if not retreat, in early November,
and his diary gives an accurate depiction of disintegrating Austrian
morale. It also gives us, through encoded notations, an invaluable
insight into his philosophical progress, and into more intimate
matters. We also get an understanding of his general state of mind,
the phases of heavy depression interspersed with almost mystical
outbursts. These were a novelty, since Wittgenstein was not reli-
gious before the war, having lost his childhood faith in Linz. The
war changed him. It is hard to say whether we can speak of a prop-
er conversion. But it would be certainly wrong to describe him as
non-religious after August 1914. It was some time early in his service
that he went into a bookstore in Tarnow, discovering that apart
from postcards it contained only one book: Tolstoy’s Gospel in
Brief. He bought it, read and re-read it, and kept it on him at all
times (which earned him the byword ‘the one with the Gospels’
from his comrades). As McGuinness sees it, Wittgenstein found in
Tolstoy’s version of Christianity a path to happiness that seemed
to suit his wretched situation in the army, if not even his earlier
63
Wittgenstein’s military identity card.
The news gets worse and worse. Tonight there will be instant
readiness. I work every day, more or less, and with fair confi-
dence. I say Tolstoy’s words again and again in my head. ‘Man
is powerless in the flesh but free because of the spirit.’ May the
spirit be in me! . . . How will I behave when it comes to shoot-
ing? I am not afraid of being shot but of not doing my duty
properly. God give me strength! Amen. Amen. Amen.3
64
He wrote a day later: ‘Now I may have the opportunity to be a
decent human being, because I am face to face with death.’ No
doubt a religious voice is speaking here, but it is Christian only in
so far as it is mediated through Tolstoy’s interpretation. After all,
Wittgenstein’s prayers were brief and invoked the ‘spirit’, not Jesus.
Was this not rather an intellectual’s rationalized version of religion,
a refined version of the ‘duty to oneself ’ urged by Weininger? Not
so much a real belief in Jesus’ teachings, his crucifixion and the mys-
tery of his resurrection, but the acceptance of Tolstoyan inwardness
as the best recipe to cope with serious existential difficulties? Such
a ‘streamlined’ form of religion had its own tradition in Western
thought, having precursors in David Friedrich Strauss, Schopenhauer
and Ralph Waldo Emerson (the latter two read by Wittgenstein
during the war as well). These are difficult questions. In any case,
he felt Christian enough to be troubled by Nietzsche’s The Anti-Christ,
a book he read towards the end of 1914:
65
abyss, Wittgenstein did not seek salvation through the solution
of Russell’s Paradox and did not pray to the Muse of Logic or the
Great Quantifier, but to the God of Tolstoy’s Gospel. To claim some
kind of unity between his logical investigations and his religious
problems is to romanticize the former and trivialize the latter.
Wittgenstein spent 1915 in relative safety in an artillery workshop
in Krakow, where his skills as an engineer were much relied upon.
In the summer he suffered a minor injury from an explosion in the
workshop and had to spend some time in hospital. He then returned
to another artillery shop, located on board a train close to Lvov.
Finally, at his own request, he was transferred to a howitzer regiment
on the Russian front in Galicia in March 1916. Here he volunteered for
service at the artillery observation post at night, the place and time of
maximal risk. McGuinness describes this phase as ‘one of the hardest
times of his life’ and this is not exaggerated.5 Wittgenstein contracted
food-poisoning and other illnesses, felt ostracized by his comrades
and, finally, towards the end of April experienced his first combat
situation at an observation-post where he came under direct fire.
Nevertheless, he felt that he would commit suicide if he were to be
sent away. ‘Perhaps nearness to death will bring light into my life.’6
There is something moving and inspiring in the way Wittgenstein
exhorts himself in this period of grave danger. Despite what his sister
Hermine believed at times, he was certainly not a saint. But there is a
disarming authenticity in his diary entries, an authenticity that many
of those who met him have observed. In the midst of battles he finds
consolation in prayers, in soliloquies with himself and God. ‘My soul
shrivels up. God give me light! God give me light! God give light to
my soul!’7 ‘God is all that man needs.’8 How different is this man from
the arrogant student in Cambridge, who, in Russell’s own words,
was more terrible with Christians than Russell himself!
66
only for a short time (then you will become burdensome to
them). Help yourself and help others with your strength. And at
the same time be cheerful. But how much strength ought one to
use for oneself and how much for others? It is difficult to live a
good life. But the good life is something fine. Yet not my will
but thine be done.9
It was only after spending several months under the most dan-
gerous circumstances that these personal notes began to connect
with the philosophical system he was developing, in the form of
uncoded general remarks about God, ethics and the meaning of life,
some of which made it into the last pages of the Tractatus. They
reflect not only his recent experiences, but also his readings of
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Emerson, Tolstoy, Dostoevsky (he read
The Brothers Karamazov so many times that he knew whole pas-
sages from it by heart). Here is a sample of these powerful remarks:
67
Fear in face of death is the best sign of a false, i.e. – a bad, life.11
When a general ethical law of the form ‘Thou shalt . . .’ is set up,
the first thought is: Suppose I do not do it? – But it is clear that
ethics has nothing to do with punishment and reward. So this
question about the consequences of an action must be unim-
portant. At least these consequences cannot be events. For there
must be something right about the question after all. There
must be a kind of ethical reward and of ethical punishment but
these must be involved in the action itself. – And it is also clear
that the reward must be something pleasant, the punishment
something unpleasant. – I keep on coming back to this! simply
the happy life is good, the unhappy bad. And if I now ask
myself: But why should I live happily, then this of itself seems
to me to be a tautological question; the happy life seems to be
justified, of itself, it seems that it is the only right life. – But this
is really in some sense deeply mysterious! It is clear that ethics
cannot be expressed!12
68
that is, the real objects in the world and their properties, must
be expressible in terms of scientific language, it follows that the
content of ethics cannot be expressed. It can only be shown. We
encounter here the distinction between what can be said and what
only shown that is crucial for his logical and metaphysical doctrines
as well, as we will see. But, we may already ask, has Wittgenstein
himself not just told us, at least to some extent, what ethics consist
in? Has he not just said that values are not part of this world, that
the good deed finds reward in itself etc., indeed that ethics is that
very thing about which one cannot talk? There is something para-
doxical about this saying/showing distinction, as applied to his
views on ethics and those on logic and metaphysics.
Wittgenstein was aware that the scope of his investigation had
widened. As he put it towards the end of the summer of 1916: ‘My
work has extended from the foundations of logic to the nature of
the world.’13 His diary entries in this period are much more sparse
than before, but it remains an amazing fact that he managed to
do any philosophy under the given circumstances. For this was no
ordinary summer. His division had been caught up in the Russian
Brusilov offensive and forced to retreat with very heavy losses
(around 80 per cent, according to some calculations). His division
then fought in the Bukovina and in the battle of Kolomea. His con-
duct during the fighting was exemplary, as we know from reports
by his officers. One such report states that ‘Ignoring the heavy
artillery fire on the casemate and the exploding mortar bombs
[Wittgenstein] observed the discharge of the mortars and located
them. . . . By this distinctive behaviour he exercised a very calming
effect on his comrades.’ 14 He received two medals and was promoted
to the rank of corporal.
Owing to his conduct at the front Wittgenstein was sent to an
officers’ school in Olmütz, Moravia, in October 1916. Here he met
Paul Engelmann, a young Jewish architect, pupil of Loos and friend
of Kraus, who shared much of Wittgenstein’s artistic outlook and
69
occasionally published in Die Fackel. They soon became close friends.
It was a remarkable friendship, which lasted for well over a decade
and would eventually lead to their cooperation on building the
famous mansion for Margarete Wittgenstein in the late 1920s.
In Olmütz Wittgenstein started to participate in Engelmann’s
literary circle, made up mostly of cultivated young Jews, literati,
artists, etc. He immediately became the centre point of the circle,
indeed something of a star. He was member of a famous Viennese
family, had a refined sense of culture, had studied philosophy and
logic with Russell in Cambridge, was developing his own philo-
sophical system and, last but not least, had just returned from the
Eastern front, where he had been face to face with death. The mem-
bers of the circle staged A Midsummer Night’s Dream and Molière’s
Le Malade imaginaire; they read classic German poets such as
Goethe and Schiller (on one of these occasions Wittgenstein praised
Schiller’s love for freedom); they performed Salonmusik, for instance
by Schubert and Brahms; they engaged in conversations about
ethics, aesthetics and authors dear to Wittgenstein, such as
Schopenhauer, Tolstoy, Dostoevsky and Weininger; and they
read the New Testament together. Wittgenstein even made them
read some Frege and he explained his philosophical system to
Engelmann. Compared to the moral and existential morass of the
Front these encounters were bliss. But Olmütz provided him not
only with relaxation for his battered soul; this encounter with a
select group of intellectuals led also to a heightened interest for
questions of aesthetics, reflections on which resurfaced in the
Tractatus. It was here that he finally managed to make a connec-
tion between logic, ethics and aesthetics, and thus confirm
Weininger’s idea that all three were one and the same, an idea that
actually goes back to antiquity.15 He wrote in his diary: ‘The work
of art is the object seen sub specie aeternitatis and the good life is
the world seen sub specie aeternitatis. This is the connection
between art and ethics.’16
70
The encounter with the Olmütz circle can be seen as noteworthy
in another respect: it was Wittgenstein’s only encounter with a
Jewish environment. But the Jewishness of these young men was
not very substantial. What connected both parties was ‘the need
for a self-made religion’.17 As McGuinness sees it, Wittgenstein was
looking for a substitute for his traditional Christian upbringing,
while the Olmütz intellectuals were looking for an alternative to
a Jewishness that had lost its traditional meaning.18
In January 1917 Wittgenstein returned to the Eastern front as
an officer. He had just donated 1 million crowns to the Austrian
government for the development of a 12-inch howitzer. He was
soon involved in heavy fighting again, in the Kerensky Offensive,
awarded another medal for gallantry and recommended for further
promotion. In February 1918 he was promoted to lieutenant, and in
March he was transferred to the Italian front. In the Austrian June
offensive he behaved with outstanding courage and saved the lives
of several comrades. He was recommended for the gold medal for
valour (the Austrian equivalent of the Victoria Cross), but was
eventually awarded a slightly lesser distinction. In a report about
him we read: ‘His exceptionally courageous behaviour, calmness,
sang-froid, and heroism won the total admiration of the troops.
By his conduct he gave a splendid example of loyal and soldierly
fulfilment of duty.’19
The year 1918 was important for Wittgenstein in several
respects. First, the war came to an end, for him in fact a week earlier
than the final Armistice, since he was taken prisoner by the Italians
near Trento. Second, it was the year in which he lost his dear friend
David Pinsent. Pinsent had not been called up for active duty
during the war, but had trained as a test pilot. He crashed with
his plane on a test flight in May 1918. This was a grave loss for
Wittgenstein and may explain his subsequent plan to kill himself
while on leave in Austria. There is some indication that his uncle
Paul Wittgenstein saved his life. Paul, an estate manager, painter
71
and patron of the arts, who had a weakness for his nephew,
bumped into Ludwig at Salzburg train station when Ludwig was
contemplating suicide.20 Pinsent and Wittgenstein had exchanged
letters during the war (via Switzerland) and Pinsent’s letters were a
great source of comfort. When he received Pinsent’s first war letter
in 1914, Wittgenstein kissed it out of excitement. He had a great
desire to see his friend again, addressing him as ‘My dear Davy’ and
writing in his diary ‘Lovely letter from David. . . . Answered David.
Very sensual.’21 These passages suggest that Ludwig may indeed
have felt unrequited love for David, a fact of which he was not
unaware, writing in his diary: ‘I wonder whether he thinks of me
half as much as I think of him.’
Last but not least, 1918 was also the year in which Wittgenstein
completed his book, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. He dedicated
it to David Pinsent.
72
4
The Tractatus was the fruit of six years of intense labour and the
only philosophical book published in Wittgenstein’s lifetime. He
initially called it Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung and it was only
later that the English translation received, on Moore’s suggestion,
the Latin title Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, by which it is known
today. How the book was finally put together is not fully docu-
mented. As mentioned, in the period 1914–18 he filled several note-
books, which he then unified in a single manuscript. The last man-
uscript (MS 104) is the most important one, as it largely prefigures
the actual book, save the ordering of its proposition and the
Preface. Now known as the Prototractatus, it was published in 1971.
The Tractatus is a unique book in the history of philosophy, if only
because of its style. It is short, around 90 pages in the English
translation. It consists of the following seven main propositions:
73
Each of these propositions, apart from the last one, is further
explained by other numbered entries, and so on. For instance,
proposition 1 is explained by 1.1 (‘The world is the totality of facts,
not things’), which in turn is explained by two further propositions,
1.11 and 1.12. This gives the book the impression of a precisely
structured investigation, almost like a mathematical proof, and
indeed the numbered propositions bear some similarity to the
proofs in the Principia Mathematica. Probably the only other book
in European philosophy that surpasses its aspiration to mathematical
beauty and simplicity is Spinoza’s Ethics (1677), which has defini-
tions, axioms and lemmas, just like an actual mathematical proof.
But the Tractatus is probably more difficult to understand, not least
because it is dense with the technical terminology and formalism
of modern mathematical logic, which is not penetrable without
familiarity with the logic of Frege and Russell. Also, Wittgenstein,
unlike Spinoza, does not define many of his key notions and does
not indicate how he has arrived at his propositions. The readers are
left to figure out for themselves what these propositions mean and
what the arguments leading to them consist of. We would have
probably been at a loss if none of his notebooks had survived.
The understanding of the book is further complicated by the
fact that in composing it Wittgenstein followed a certain aesthetic
ideal. It is certainly not true, as some interpreters have suggested,
that the Tractatus must be seen as a work of art, a ‘poem’.1 And it
is not correct, as Terry Eagleton has it, that the ‘true coordinates’
of the Tractatus are really Joyce, Schönberg and Picasso, and not
Frege and Russell.2 The true coordinates of the book are Frege and
Russell, and their investigations into the nature of logic. It contains
a complex philosophical system, based on predominantly implicit
arguments, but arguments nevertheless. But it is true that there is
a strongly artistic side to the book. Wittgenstein was always drawn
to writing fragments and aphorisms, partly through the influence
of Schopenhauer and Lichtenberg, and this explains the fragmen-
74
tary character of many of his writings. In addition, he was attracted
to Loos’s and Weininger’s ideal of purity and minimalism, an ideal
that, as discussed earlier, denounced any ornament as a ‘crime’. In
the Preface Wittgenstein writes: ‘If this work has any value, it con-
sists in . . . [the fact] that thoughts are expressed in it, and on this
score the better the thoughts are expressed – the more the nail has
been hit on the head – the greater will be its value.’ Wittgenstein
subjected his philosophical prose to the perfectionist ideal of find-
ing the most precise expression, ‘the liberating word’3 that would
be ‘setting the carriage precisely on the rails’.4 He looked at his
writing with the eyes of a poet; no word or sentence should be
superfluous or casual. ‘I think I summed up my attitude to phil-
osophy when I said: philosophy ought really to be written only as a
poetic composition.’5 He wrote this around 1933, but it is represen-
tative of his lifelong attitude to the composition of philosophical
texts. This attitude was particularly extreme with respect to the
Tractatus. For in this book Wittgenstein sought to eliminate any
redundancy by keeping his prose condensed to a bare minimum.
Many propositions of the Tractatus exhibit therefore the character
of definitive oracular pronouncements. As he self-critically
acknowledged later, ‘[e]very sentence in the Tractatus should be
seen as the heading of a chapter needing further exposition’.6
Wittgenstein was not interested in writing a book for an academic
audience, but in reaching a kind of crystalline beauty. We find
confirmation of this self-imposed aesthetic requirement in an early
report by Russell:
I told him he ought not simply to state what he thinks true, but
to give arguments for it, but he said arguments spoil its beauty,
and that he would feel as if he was dirtying a flower with muddy
hands. I told him I hadn’t the heart to say anything against that,
and that he had better acquire a slave to state the arguments. I
am seriously afraid that no one will see the point of anything he
75
writes, because he won’t recommend it by arguments addressed
to a different point of view.7
76
objects, which are not further divisible. Save for some uncertain
examples, such as the smallest visible spot in the visual field,
Wittgenstein does not indicate what these atomic objects might be.
Again, we are only given a general description: for example, that an
elementary fact consists of certain atomic objects being related to
each other in a certain way, or that ordinary physical objects are not
atomic objects, but composed out of atomic objects. Of course, facts
may come and go, but the atomic objects remain just the same. They
can occur in various different facts, but they are indestructible, since
they are not further divisible. They are what Wittgenstein calls ‘the
substance of the world’ – that of which everything there is consists.
Every atomic object has a metaphysical essence. What is it? It is the
totality of all facts in which it can occur. This may sound mysterious,
but it is not really. For instance, the metaphysical essence of the
broomstick (assuming, to illustrate, that it is an atomic object) con-
sists of all the possible facts of which it might be a part. For it is part
of the broomstick’s essence not only that it is stuck into the brush,
as it actually is, but also that it could be lying on the left of the brush,
on the right of it, on top of it, etc. All these possibilities are already
inscribed into the inner essence of the broomstick and thus fully
determine its nature. Imagine we have a list of all atomic objects in
the world. In that case we would be able to determine any possible
course of the world, that is, every possible fact, everything that
might be the case – all possible worlds. No possibility could ever
be surprising in this glacial and crystalline Tractarian world.
Wittgenstein had initially given his treatise the working title
‘Der Satz’ (‘The proposition’ or ‘The sentence’), a clear proof that
the nature of propositions occupies the centre stage of the book.
Wittgenstein’s focus on propositions, that is, declarative state-
ments like ‘Ronaldo is a football player’ or ‘The moon is 239,000
miles away from Earth’, is not arbitrary. For the main function of
language is to describe the world, and propositions are the smallest
units of communication. His theory of proposition consists of two
77
Wittgenstein’s annotated bilingual edition of Tractatus.
78
Every proposition is a description of a possible fact. Giving an
account of what a proposition is, what makes it meaningful and
how it manages to describe a fact, is of pivotal importance for
understanding how any discourse about the world, and in
particular scientific discourse, is possible. Legend has it that
Wittgenstein thought of the picture theory when he read in
a newspaper about a Parisian trial in which toys were used to
depict a car accident. For example, one could use a blue toy car
to depict a real blue car and a red toy bus to depict a real bus. In
addition, one could draw an intersection on a paper depicting the
real intersection and then place the toy cars in a way that depicts
the way the real cars were related to each other. Wittgenstein
took this to be the essence of pictures in general and of linguistic
pictures, that is, propositions, in particular. The elements of
a picture stand for the objects they depict, and the way the
elements are ordered in the picture mirrors the depicted fact.
Similarly, the elements of a proposition, the words, stand for the
objects they depict. A proposition is true if the expressions con-
tained in it are arranged in a way similar to the way in which the
objects for which they stand are arranged. To give a very simplified
example: the proposition ‘Ronaldo is standing left of Maradona’
is true in a situation in which Ronaldo is standing left of
Maradona, since the name ‘Ronaldo’ is also standing left of the
name ‘Maradona’. The connection between language and reality
is established via private mental acts of meaning by a given word
‘w’, the object ‘w’ is meant to stand for. It follows that the meaning
of every word is the object it stands for, and thus that every word
is the name of an object. If a word does not stand for an object, it
is meaningless. Propositions, we can conclude, consist of names,
and if a proposition contains at least one meaningless word, then
the proposition is meaningless as well. This is how we can visualize
the picture theory:
79
language world
consist of consist of
configurations of
80
false. (The only exception to this rule are the propositions of logic,
i.e. tautologies such as ‘Either it is raining or it is not raining’,
which, given that they are necessarily true, cannot be false even in
principle.)
This aspect of Wittgenstein’s theory of proposition has dramatic
consequences, not least for his own theory. For it means that a
proposition that tries to depict some non-contingent fact, for
example a ‘metaphysical fact’, which could not be otherwise, is
simply meaningless. Any proposition whose negation is inconceiv-
able is of this kind. Take for instance the statement ‘Red is a
colour’. Could red not be a colour? What would this mean? How
could we find out that red is not a colour? This seems to be a sheer
impossibility. Or take ‘This table is an object’. Sentences of this
kind only look like genuine propositions, but are in fact pseudo-
propositions. It follows that all the metaphysical propositions of
traditional philosophy, for example Spinoza’s theory about the
identity of God with nature or Schopenhauer’s claim that the world
is the product of will, are meaningless. Equally, Russell’s state-
ments about the essence of the world that he needed in order to
defend his logic turn out to be without meaning. And last, but not
least, the propositions of the Tractatus themselves prove now to be
totally meaningless, indeed pure nonsense! For is it not the case
that they are trying to describe the metaphysical, unchangeable
essence of the world and of language? Indeed, this is what they are
trying to do. Take the first proposition of the Tractatus, ‘The world
is everything that is the case’, and assume that it is true. For it to be
meaningful, according to the picture theory, this proposition must
depict a contingent fact. It should be at least intelligible to imagine
that the world is not everything that is the case. But this is precisely
what is not possible, since the proposition does attempt to describe
a non-contingent, essential feature of the world. The ontological
propositions of the Tractatus thus turn out to be nonsensical (not:
false). The semantic theory of the book does not fare better. Take
81
A page of
Wittgenstein’s
annotations to the
typescript of the
English translation
of the Tractatus.
82
expressed it, ‘What we can’t say we can’t say, and we can’t whistle
it either’ (a humorous hint to Wittgenstein’s remarkable ability to
whistle any tune).
Wittgenstein helps himself out of this impasse by making a
distinction between what can be said, that is, contingent facts
about the world, which are the subject matter of science, and
what cannot be said, but shows itself – the metaphysical essence
of language and the world. This is the actual justification of the
famous distinction between saying and showing. It follows that
there are no philosophical propositions, no philosophical claims
that can be expressed. All deep truths can only be shown.
Philosophy is not a science and not in competition with science,
offering doctrines and hypotheses about the world, whether
empirically testable or justified through a priori reasoning. It does
not add to the sum of human knowledge. Rather, philosophy is a
discipline in its own right, ‘above or below the natural sciences,
not beside them’ (Tractatus 4.111). It is an activity, and to a large
degree a critical one, namely the clarification of language by
means of logical analysis.
83
philosophy the rigorous method philosophers had always been
looking for. Unlike his predecessors, Wittgenstein envisaged this
method to consist of the analysis of language, not the world. The
sole task for future philosophy is to monitor the bounds of sense in
order to delimit science from the nonsense of metaphysics, namely
by elucidating the hidden logical forms of philosophically problem-
atic sentences. Some aspects of this linguistic turn had been formu-
lated by Frege and Russell as well, but it was really the Tractatus
that heralded this paradigm change in an explicit manner. It was a
paradigm that remained very influential in philosophy, at least in
the Anglophone world, until the 1970s.
The philosophy of the Tractatus can be seen as defending sci-
ence against metaphysics. Nevertheless, the book itself is highly
metaphysical, indeed mystical. It delimits what can be genuinely
said, namely by means of science, from what cannot, but the latter
is not a chimera. There are deep metaphysical truths, although they
are strictly ineffable and can only be shown, indeed felt. In a line
reminiscent of certain mystics Wittgenstein writes: ‘To view the
world sub specie aeterni is to view it as a whole – a limited whole.
Feeling the world as a limited whole – it is this that is mystical’
(Tractatus 6.45). Linguistic analysis is not meant to deny these
truths, but make room for them, in other words make room for
metaphysics, ethics, aesthetics, God, in short for all that which
Wittgenstein subsumes under the label ‘the Higher’. Thus we do
find remarks about the Higher at the end of the Tractatus. We can
speak only about what is in the world, for example, the World Cup
of 2006, stockmarkets, 9/11, climate change, social policy, molecu-
lar genetics, the solar system, etc. But ‘[h]ow things are in the world
is a matter of complete indifference for what is the Higher. God
does not reveal himself in the world’ (Tractatus 6.432). It is in this
context that Wittgenstein presents several of his remarks on ethics
and the meaning of life he wrote in the trenches in 1916. The mean-
ing of life, the primary subject of ethics, is radically transcendent
84
and cannot be expressed. The most important things are ineffable.
‘We feel that even when all possible scientific questions have been
answered, the problems of life remain completely untouched. Of
course there are then no questions left, and this itself is the answer’
(Tractatus 6.52). ‘There are, indeed, things that cannot be put into
words. They make themselves manifest. They are what is mystical’
(Tractatus 6.522). Thence the famous concluding remark that
what we cannot speak about we must pass over in silence.
Ironically, it is this remark and the previous ones on ethics that
have generated a massive secondary literature. But if we are to take
Wittgenstein seriously, then silence should mean silence. As he
explained to Ludwig von Ficker in a letter from October 1919,
85
same year to a very different addressee, namely Russell, he empha-
sized that the main point of the book
86
5
87
If I were only somewhere else than in this shitty world!’ he wrote
to von Ficker. The content of the book appeared not only to be
unsayable, but even unprintable. By 1920, after yet another
rejection, he had become so disillusioned that he wrote to Russell
saying that he was giving up, leaving the manuscript to Russell to
do with as he pleased. Russell commissioned one of his former
pupils, the mathematician Dorothy Wrinch, to see to the
publication of the book. After one last rejection, this time by
Cambridge University Press, she approached several German
journals and received a particularly positive reply from Annalen der
Naturphilosophie, a journal now largely remembered because the
Tractatus appeared there for the first time. As the journal’s editor
made clear to Wrinch, the typescript was accepted only because it
was accompanied by a lengthy and sympathetic introduction by
Russell, a celebrity by any estimate. The Tractatus was thus finally
published in the first half of 1921, three years after its completion.
Ironically, the Annalen stopped its publication with the Tractatus,
as if to prove the point of the book’s last proposition. Wittgenstein,
who was not sent the proofs, disapproved of this first edition,
calling it a pirated version because of the many printing mistakes
concerning the logical notation. The Tractatus came out in a form
acceptable to him only in 1922, this time published by Routledge
and Kegan Paul, with an English translation accompanying the
German original. The translation, reviewed and improved by
Wittgenstein, was made by C. K. Ogden, a linguist, with assistance
by Frank Ramsey, one of the most promising British philosophers
of his generation.
For all its frustrating aspects, the publishing affair was only the
first of many difficulties Wittgenstein would encounter in his post-
war life. At the end of the war we find him in an Italian prisoner-of-
war camp near Como. He remained in captivity for another eight
months and was transferred to a camp in Cassino in January 1919.
Naturally, circumstances in these camps were very different from
88
those in the trenches. There was much idle time to kill, for instance
through concerts, lectures, discussions, even exhibitions that the
captives would organize. Wittgenstein participated in this camp
life and established friendships with the sculptor Michael Drobil,
the writer Franz Parak and the teacher Ludwig Hänsel. With the
latter Wittgenstein discussed logic and read Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason. They were to remain lifelong friends. Parak has provided us
with the following description of Wittgenstein in the camp:
89
mediocrity of an academic career did not appeal to him. On his
return from captivity, in August 1919, he decided to dispose of the
fortune inherited from his father and did so immediately by dis-
tributing it among his sisters and brother, much to the dismay of
his financial adviser, who considered this simply an act of suicide.
According to Parak he briefly contemplated becoming a priest.3
But the compromises of institutionalized religion were still unac-
ceptable to him. Thus he settled for becoming a primary school
teacher, because as a teacher he could ‘read the gospel with the
children’.4 His family was not pleased with this decision and felt
that Ludwig was wasting his talent on a mediocre profession – we
can imagine how much less pleased his father Karl would have
been, had he been alive. As Hermine put it: it was as if one used a
precision tool to open a packing case! But Wittgenstein felt that
he was not understood, as a striking simile in a reply to Hermine
indicates: ‘You remind me of someone looking through a window
who can’t make sense of the strange movements of a passer-by
outside. He has no idea of the violence of the storm outside nor
of the difficulty the other has simply in staying on his feet.’5
So in September 1919 he enrolled in a teacher’s training college
in Vienna, and at the end of the course in July 1920 the man whom
Russell had expected before the war to make the next big step in
philosophy was a certified primary school teacher. The course itself
was easy. Given his educational background, he was respected by
the college faculty and was spared most academic subjects. But the
experience of sitting in a schoolroom again was actually very
humiliating. ‘The benches are full of boys of 17 and 18 and I’ve
reached 30. That leads to some very funny situations – and many
very unpleasant ones too! I often feel miserable.’6 As in Linz or on
the Goplana he felt once again ostracized, although this time his
misery was self-inflicted.
The period was generally one of great depression, causing him
to contemplate suicide once more. He felt not at ease with himself,
90
being in a ‘terrible state of mind’ and having ‘no faith’, as he
described it in letters to Paul Engelmann:
91
The veteran: Wittgenstein in the early post-war years.
92
refuge as therapy would go too far, but it certainly had relaxing
effects on his battered soul. The gardening work was purely manual
and simple, but exhausting enough to distract him from plunging
into the ever-threatening inner abyss. One particular reason for his
overall depressive state can be gathered from a letter to Russell he
wrote from here: ‘Every day I think of Pinsent. He took half my life
away with him. The devil will take the other half.’9
In September 1920 Wittgenstein was offered a position as
a teacher in a prosperous town near Vienna, which he rejected
because it had ‘a park with a fountain’ and was thus not rural
enough for his taste. Instead, he settled for Trattenbach in the
mountains of Lower Austria, a poor and remote village. One might
think that he now had a chance to realize his Tolstoyan ideal and
thus actually become happy. But his six years as a schoolteacher in
Austria (1920–26) were overall of little joy and self-realization. This
was in part due to Tolstoy’s ill-conceived romantic ideal of serving
the so-called simple people, an ideal that has exerted a seductive
power on many modern intellectuals. Wittgenstein was not
immune to it. In addition, his friend Hänsel encouraged him to
join the Reform School Movement that was taking shape within
a wider social reform in post-war Austria. Although Wittgenstein
was not an explicit advocate of this movement (in contrast to, say,
the philosopher and later opponent Karl Popper, who was also a
schoolteacher in Austria during the same period), he was not
opposed to the movement’s focus on new techniques of teaching,
in particular the focus on learning by doing instead of learning by
drilling. Wittgenstein intended to ‘better’ simple people by teach-
ing them mathematics, the German classics and the Bible, proba-
bly a far too idealistic project, ignoring the real-life concerns of
rural people. Additional handicaps that doomed the experiment
from the outset were Wittgenstein’s irascible character and his
wealthy origin. He was soon revolted by the peasant society in
which he found himself, and the dislike was reciprocated.
93
Initially, however, Wittgenstein was rather pleased with his new
home, describing it as beautiful and tiny. To Russell, who was guest
lecturing through China at the time, he wrote: ‘It must be the first
time that the schoolmaster at Trattenbach has ever corresponded
with a professor in Peking.’10 Friends like Hänsel, Drobil and
Sjögren visited him at weekends, contributing to his improving
mood. He also befriended the local priest, Alois Neururer, to whom
he read aloud Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov. As for his
pupils, he managed to fascinate them, at least initially. His teaching
methods were unconventional. Instead of forcing them to learn
something by heart, he tried to raise their interest about a problem
and motivate them to find out the correct solution by themselves.
The greatest successes were achieved when he could take advantage
of his various skills, teaching them how to build a steam engine or
a tower, draw human figures in motion, assemble a cat’s skeleton,
identify the architectural style of buildings during a trip to Vienna,
etc. His sister Hermine witnessed her brother in action:
In one case, his engineering skills even helped him earn some
recognition from the villagers. This was when, after failed attempts
by several engineers, Wittgenstein managed to repair the engine
in the local textile factory simply by directing four workers each
to hit a particular spot with a hammer in the order dictated by
and comprehensible only to him. This incident became something
of a legend in Trattenbach and was referred to as a ‘miracle’.
Unfortunately, however, such successes did not suffice to gain
the trust of the villagers. He was viewed as an awkward stranger, a
94
‘rich baron’ visited by wealthy people from Vienna. They found his
decision to live in their community baffling. Their opinion wors-
ened when Wittgenstein began to show weaknesses in his teaching.
He demanded high standards from his pupils and was willing to
give them time and attention without stint if they seemed promis-
ing. With the best pupils, who revered him, he even arranged extra
tuition. But he showed much less patience with weak students.
Since he was irascible and believed in the effectiveness of corporal
punishment, contrary to the doctrines of the Reform Movement,
he often hit his pupils for misbehaviour, but often also for what
seemed to him to be stupidity. This was especially the case if they
were girls and failed in his beloved subject, mathematics, taught
not only for two hours every morning, but also at a level higher
than required by the curriculum.12 He was soon feared by his
pupils, disliked by their parents and disapproved of by his
colleagues. Here is a vivid recollection by one of his victims:
95
The schoolteacher and his pupils: Wittgenstein and schoolchildren in Puchberg am
Schneeberg, Austria.
96
become meaningless and so it consists only of futile episodes.
The people around me do not notice this and would not under-
stand; but I know that I have a fundamental deficiency.14
97
life. Russell, who had by now given up theoretical philosophy
and was, through popular lectures and writings on politics and
ethics, in the course of becoming the famous public intellectual
as which he is still known, was partly amused, partly repelled by
Wittgenstein’s attempts to convince him ‘with great earnestness
that it is better to be good than clever’.16 Wittgenstein, on the other
hand, must have been repelled by what he considered to be a frivo-
lous lifestyle on the part of Russell. Shocked by the disaster of the
war, Russell believed in the urgency of changing the world, while
Wittgenstein was more introverted, seeking primarily to change
himself. When Heinrich Postl, a local coalminer from Puchberg,
expressed his wish to improve the world, Wittgenstein replied:
‘Just improve yourself; that is the only thing you can do to better
the world.’ In short, crucial things separated Russell and
Wittgenstein. Whether it was Wittgenstein or Russell who broke
off the contact is not entirely clear, although the evidence suggests
it was Russell, since he did not reply to Wittgenstein’s subsequent
letters. In any case, the clash produced by these different ethical
outlooks was definitive: they were never again to address each
other as friends, but only as colleagues. Years later Wittgenstein
is reported to have said apropos of Russell’s ethical writings,
in particular those on marriage and free love:
98
Postl and Rudolf Koder, a gifted pianist with whom he could play
music, preferably Brahms. One other welcome digression was the
visit of his English translator Frank Ramsey in September 1923.
There could hardly have been a more suited discussion partner
for Wittgenstein. Ramsey was the most able young philosopher
in Cambridge and author of an insightful, if critical, review of the
Tractatus. He stayed for two weeks in Puchberg, during which they
spent several hours every day reading and discussing the Tractatus.
Wittgenstein even made some corrections to both the English
and the German versions of his book following these discussions.
Ramsey much admired Wittgenstein. He wrote in 1924 to his
mother: ‘We really live in a great time for thinking, with Einstein,
Freud and Wittgenstein all alive, and all in Germany or Austria,
those foes of civilisation!’ From Ramsey’s point of view
Wittgenstein’s schoolteacher career was, as he wrote to Keynes,
a ‘ridiculous waste of his energy and brain’. Together with Keynes
Ramsey tried to convince Wittgenstein to come back to Cambridge
and continue philosophy. Keynes offered to fund his trip, while
Ramsey enquired about Wittgenstein’s formal requirements for
obtaining a phd. But it was to no avail.
99
Wittgenstein’s
philosopher friend
Frank Ramsey,
who died at a
tragically young
age.
100
pilgrimage locations. Philosophical symposia, attended by
Wittgenstein experts from all over the world, take place every
summer in Kirchberg. One can trace Wittgenstein’s steps by
following designated paths which are marked by quotes from
the Tractatus at intervals. And with some luck one can still meet a
village elder who can remember Wittgenstein. In any case, it was
here that Wittgenstein’s teaching career ended in an ungraceful
manner in April 1926. Once again he was not in control of himself
in class and hit a boy on the head several times. The boy, who was
of weak health, collapsed. Wittgenstein called in panic for a doctor
and then left the school in a hurry. There was a public hearing of
the case, apparently at his own request, but Wittgenstein was
acquitted, partly because he lied about the extent to which he had
applied corporal punishment in his classes.19 Humiliated and
morally defeated, he decided to give up teaching for good.
There has been some speculation that despite its sorry ending,
Wittgenstein’s career as a schoolteacher was of great significance
for his philosophical development. Indeed, it is claimed that his
time as a teacher is visible on almost every page of his Philosophical
Investigations.20 However, although there are several passages
discussing infant language acquisition in his later book, this claim is
widely exaggerated. Nevertheless, there remains the possibility that
the teaching experience shifted his focus away from the abstract,
mathematical approach to language of Frege and Russell toward
the more down-to-earth and applied aspects of language as they
characteristically arise in the teaching of children. Paul Engelmann
has suggested that the experience of teaching is reflected in the less
sibylline and more unassuming style of Wittgenstein’s later writings.
When this man, who until then – for all the depth of his insight
into the essence of life and humanity – had been frighteningly
unworldly and hopelessly foreign to human society, was sud-
denly brought face to face with its grisly reality, he was luckily
also brought into direct contact with children.21
101
Be this as it may, there is one more palpable result of his teaching
experience. Wishing to improve his pupils’ spelling, Wittgenstein
considered introducing dictionaries in his classes, but realized that
the ones available on the market were too expensive. Thus he set
out to write a short and affordable spelling dictionary for primary
schools, partly based on spelling lists he compiled with his pupils.
The dictionary, which was tailored to the needs of primary schools
and even reflected some peculiarities of the local dialect, proved
very effective and quickly improved the children’s spelling. It was
the second, and last, book Wittgenstein would publish in his life-
time.22 The 40-page dictionary appeared in 1926 and had a notable
circulation, but was not a commercial success and therefore was
not reprinted. Nevertheless, it was a remarkable attempt by
Wittgenstein and proof of how seriously he approached any field
of activity. It is almost comical that he has been portrayed recently
as a dyslexic and that aspects of his philosophical work have been
attributed to this alleged disability.23 A dyslexic who wrote a
spelling dictionary?
His lack of success as a teacher greatly depressed Wittgenstein
and gave him, once again, the feeling that there was no Sitz im
Leben, no place for him in this world. He contemplated again the
possibility of becoming a monk, but was told that this was not the
right motive for joining monastic life. Instead he started working as
a gardener for the monks in Hütteldorf outside Vienna, living there
for three months in almost hermitic conditions in a shed in the gar-
den of the monastery. Despite appearances, this episode marked the
beginning of his gradual return to society. In June 1926 his mother
died in Vienna. This event seems to have overcome his estrange-
ment with the family, which dated back to at least 1913, when his
father died.24 Wittgenstein began now to participate enthusiastically
in family life. Moreover, he was given the ideal opportunity to inte-
grate fully with society when his sister Margarete commissioned
Paul Engelmann to design and build a mansion for her in the
102
Kundmanngasse in Vienna. Spurred on by an interest in architec-
ture and the artistic ideals he shared with Engelmann, Wittgenstein
accepted an invitation to join the project. Although Engelmann had
already largely designed the plan of the building, Wittgenstein soon
dominated the actual building process, making several changes to
the building, especially the interiors.
This new task, which occupied him until the end of 1928, was
taken very seriously by Wittgenstein. Indeed, he saw it as his new
vocation. Despite having no diploma, he was listed in the city
directory as a professional architect, and his letters bore the
letterhead ‘Paul Engelmann & Ludwig Wittgenstein Architects’.
Under Wittgenstein’s careful eye, the doors and door handles
were all made entirely of metal and designed according to strict
mathematical relations referring to the dimensions of the rooms.
The design also reflected Wittgenstein’s hermitic lifestyle: bulbs
were supposed to hang naked from the ceiling, and small, l-shaped
radiators, which took a year to produce and were placed discreetly
in the corners, remained unpainted. Every piece was uniquely
crafted, in stark contrast to modern mass production.25 There
were also technical innovations, such as 150-kilogram metal
screens that replaced curtains and could be lowered effortlessly
to the floor. Wittgenstein’s attention to detail was so fanatical
that just when everybody thought the building was finished,
he ordered the workers to raise the ceiling of one of the big rooms
by 30 millimetres to satisfy his desired proportions. He was asked
by a worker: ‘Tell me, Herr Ingenieur, does a millimetre here or
there really matter so much to you?’ To which Herr Ingenieur
thundered ‘Yes!’26 Needless to say there were other occasions on
which he drove the builders to despair.
Being of plain shape and having no external decoration, it may
seem obvious to say that the house strictly followed, indeed radical-
ized, Loos’s rejection of any ornament. It has also been compared to
buildings in the Bauhaus style. However, recent interpretations have
103
The house Wittgenstein designed for his sister Margarete in Kundmangasse,
Vienna.
Within all great art there is a WILD animal: tamed. Not, e.g.,
in Mendelssohn. All great art has primitive human drives as its
ground bass. They are not the melody (as they are, perhaps, in
Wagner), but they are what gives the melody depth & power. In
this sense one may call Mendelssohn a ‘reproductive’ artist. – In
the same sense: my house for Gretl is the product of a decidedly
104
sensitive ear, good manners, the expression of great understand-
ing (for a culture, etc.). But primordial life, wild life striving to
erupt into the open – is lacking. And so you might say, health is
lacking (Kierkegaard). (Hothouse plant.)28
105
the room distribution of the Palais Wittgenstein, to have an entry
hall and haute-bourgeois furnishings, such as carpets, curtains,
Rococo chairs, statues, Chinese vases and plants.30 It is telling that
despite this Stilbruch there was no disagreement between the sib-
lings. Two years before his death, Wittgenstein wrote to his sister,
‘Yesterday I thought . . . of the Kundmanngasse house and how
delightfully you furnished it and how comforting. In these matters
we understand each other.’31
After the Second World War the house went through a troubled
history, including its partial devastation by Soviet soldiers, who
used it as barracks in 1945. In the 1970s it was saved in the last
moment from demolition and declared a national monument. In
1975 Communist Bulgaria bought it and turned it into a cultural
centre. It can be visited today, although little of the original interior
remains. Ironically, it stands not far away from the more famous
Hundertwasser House, which, with its biomorphic and colourful
design, could not be more diametrically opposed to Wittgenstein’s
architecture. Hundertwasser rejected even the idea of a straight
line, calling it ‘the devil’s tool’. One wonders how an encounter
between Wittgenstein and Hundertwasser would have turned out.
Not long after completing the house, Wittgenstein’s and
Engelmann’s friendship deteriorated. The reasons for this are a
matter of speculation, but one plausible explanation is that in 1928
Wittgenstein was introduced to a wealthy young Swiss woman
and art student, Marguerite Respinger, who had an aversion to
Engelmann. Respinger was a friend of the family and Wittgenstein
courted her for around three years – his only heterosexual
relationship that we know of. The nature of the relationship was
peculiar, given their remarkable differences. Marguerite was almost
half Ludwig’s age and had no interest in philosophy and spiritual
matters, but rather in an entertaining lifestyle. Their only common
interest was art. Nevertheless, encouraged by Margarete, who saw
in Marguerite’s indifferent attitude to intellectual matters precisely
106
the distraction needed for her brother’s tortured mind, they began
dating, meeting almost daily for the cinema or in some Viennese
café. Wittgenstein even sculpted a bust inspired by her in the
studio of his friend Michael Drobil, in whose work he took a
critical interest. Wittgenstein has sometimes been portrayed as a
homosexual, but judging from his relationship with Marguerite
this may be not entirely accurate. Not only did they kiss, but his
diaries from this period show that Ludwig was clearly in love with
Marguerite, taking the relationship very seriously, probably more
so than she.
I love Marguerite very much & am very anxious that she might
not be healthy since I haven’t gotten a letter from her in more
than a week. When I am alone I think of her again & again but
at other times too. Were I more decent, my love for her would
be more decent too. And yet I love her now as tenderly as I can.32
I am very much in love with R., have been for a long time of
course, but it is especially strong now. And yet I know that the
matter is in all probability hopeless. That is, I must be braced
that she might get engaged & married any moment. And I know
that this will be very painful for me. I therefore know that I
should not hang my whole weight on this rope since I know
that eventually it will give. That is I should remain standing
with both feet on firm ground & only hold the rope but not
hang on it. But that is difficult. It is difficult to love so unselfishly
that one holds on to love & does not want to be held by it.33
107
Two significant women in Wittgenstein’s life: Marguerite Respinger and Margarete
Stonborough, 1931.
108
praying and preparing mentally for the holy act of marriage. She
on the other hand went swimming, took walks, socialized with
the villagers, and ignored the copy of the Bible he had slipped into
her luggage.34 How could they ever have lived up to each other’s
expectations? After two weeks she left Norway disenchanted and
that was the end of the relationship. But they stayed good friends.
In 1933 Marguerite married one of the Sjögrens, a decision
Wittgenstein was very unhappy with, but which he came to accept.
Marguerite wrote later in her memoirs:
109
flower or blade of grass’. Finally, he applies this cliché to himself,
writing (note, incidentally, the interesting list of influences):
The saint is the only Jewish ‘genius’. Even the greatest Jewish
thinker is no more than talented. (Myself for instance.) I think
there is some truth in my idea that I am really only reproductive
in my thinking. I think I have never invented a line of thinking
but that it was always provided for me by someone else & I have
done no more than passionately take it up for my work of clari-
fication. That is how Boltzmann, Hertz, Schopenhauer, Frege,
Russell, Kraus, Loos, Weininger Spengler, Sraffa have influenced
me . . . It is typical of the Jewish mind to understand someone’s
else work better than he understands it himself.38
Not all his diary notes on Jews display this negative attitude.
For instance, Wittgenstein also writes: ‘The Jew is a desert region,
but underneath its thin layer of rock lies the molten lava of spirit
and intellect.’39 Nevertheless, what surprises one about all these
passages is his readiness to make sweeping remarks about ‘the Jew’.
It contrasts sharply with the much more critical attitude towards
this kind of talk that he himself displayed in later years. Norman
Malcolm reports that when in 1939 he remarked to Wittgenstein
that the British national character was incompatible with plotting
a bomb against Hitler (as rumour had it at the time), Wittgenstein
was so outraged that he stopped seeing his friend for a while. Even
after five years he remained shocked by the primitiveness of
Malcolm’s remark:
110
This critique could also have been levied against Wittgenstein’s
1931 remarks on Jews. One possible explanation for those remarks,
advanced by Monk, is that throughout his life Wittgenstein con-
stantly questioned and doubted himself, from both a philosophical
and a moral point of view, and that during that brief period under
Respinger’s spell he voiced his doubts in the language of anti-
Semitism.41 This is a plausible, if charitable interpretation of a man
who placed the independence of his judgements above everything
else. Note that even after 1931 Wittgenstein held an ambiguous atti-
tude to his Jewish origins – despite a cryptic remark to Maurice
Drury in 1949 that his thoughts are ‘one hundred percent Hebraic’.
Thus in his 1936 confession, presented to close friends and family
members, he admitted that he had let many people believe he was
only one-quarter Jewish. This proves not only that Wittgenstein
felt Jewish, but that he perceived Jewishness as a matter of shame
and concealment. After all, he had grown up in a virulently anti-
Semitic city, Karl Lueger’s Vienna, and it is implausible to assume
that this had no effect on his self-perception. To give just one
example, when young Ludwig wanted to join a gym in Vienna,
which was open only to ‘Aryans’, he was determined to lie about
his Jewish background in order to obtain membership until dis-
suaded by his brother Paul.42 A good way of concluding the matter
was offered by David Stern:
111
6
112
onwards headed a group of academics, mostly philosophers, but also
mathematicians, logicians and physicists, later known as the Vienna
Circle. Some of their most prominent members were Rudolf Carnap,
Otto Neurath, Hans Reichenbach, Herbert Feigl, Kurt Gödel and
Friedrich Waismann. After the Nazis came to power, some of them
emigrated to the usa and had a major impact on the rise of analytic
philosophy there. What united them from the outset was a strictly
scientific world-view. They venerated natural science, epitomized by
modern physics, as the only way to gain knowledge about the world
and achieve social progress, and they rejected religion and the
metaphysical systems of traditional philosophy as unscientific and
irrational. As logical empiricists (or logical positivists) they believed
that all knowledge can be reduced to sensory experience and can be
given a precise formulation by means of logical analysis. They hugely
admired the Tractatus because in their view it had formulated the
programme for a strictly scientific method in philosophy for the first
time. In their manifesto of 1929, The Scientific Conception of the World:
The Vienna Circle, they hailed Einstein, Russell and Wittgenstein as
the main representatives of the scientific world-view. It seems that
the members of the Vienna Circle did not fully realize, or chose to
ignore, that the author of the Tractatus did not share their world-view
at all. He too believed that the statements of traditional metaphysics
were nonsensical, but not because there were no metaphysical
truths, rather because such truths were ineffable. His view was:
everything that can be said, can be said clearly, and we must pass
over the rest in silence. Their view was: everything that can be said,
can be said clearly, and there is nothing else. Moreover, Wittgenstein
did not share their belief in social progress by means of science. In
fact his view in this matter was diametrically opposed to the Vienna
Circle and more akin to the pessimism of Oswald Spengler’s The
Decline of the West, a book he read avidly in 1930. It was in this year
that he wrote a lengthy preface for a planned book, Philosophical
Remarks, in which he stated:
113
This book is written for those who are in sympathy with the
spirit in which it is written. This spirit is, I believe, different
from that of the prevailing European and American civilization.
The spirit of this civilization the expression of which is the indus-
try, architecture, music, of present day fascism & socialism, is a
spirit that is alien & uncongenial to the author. . . . Even if it is
clear to me then that the disappearance of a culture does not
signify the disappearance of human value but simply of certain
means of expressing this value, still the fact remains that I con-
template the current of European civilization without sympathy,
without understanding its aims if any. So I am really writing for
friends who are scattered throughout the corners of the globe.
It is all one to me whether the typical western scientist under-
stands or appreciates my work since in any case he does not
understand the spirit in which I write. Our civilization is charac-
terized by the word ‘progress’. Progress is its form, it is not one
of its properties that it makes progress. Typically it constructs.
Its activity is to construct a more and more complicated struc-
ture. And even clarity is only a means to this end & not an end
in itself. – For me on the contrary clarity, transparency, is an
end in itself – I am not interested in erecting a building but in
having the foundations of possible buildings transparently
before me. – So I am aiming at something different than are
the scientists & my thoughts move differently than do theirs.2
114
is falling into a trap. It is by no means obvious that this is not
how things are.3
115
guru and his disciples. He could talk and behave as he wanted –
and he did. Sometimes he talked about religion, art and ethics.
In one instance Wittgenstein turned his back to his audience and
recited poems by Rabindranath Tagore, hardly an exponent of the
scientific world-view! (Wittgenstein thought so highly of Tagore
that later he translated a part of a play by the Indian poet for
private use.) It was almost as if he was teaching them a lesson very
different from that of positivistic philosophy.
With time, however, valuable philosophical discussions devel-
oped between them, some of which were recorded by Waismann
and published as Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle (1967). Most
of these discussions focused on themes from the Tractatus such as
the nature of language, logic, mathematics. But they also covered
metaphysical themes, which the Vienna Circle members abhorred.
Thus, he surprised his audience by expressing his sympathy
with Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard and Heidegger. Heidegger, for
instance, wrote in his Being and Time (1927): ‘That in the face of
which one has anxiety is Being-in-the-world as such . . . That in the
face of which one has anxiety is not an entity within-the-world . . .
the world as such is that in the face of which one has anxiety.’5
Sentences like these are according to the Tractatus pure nonsense,
and Rudolf Carnap, faithfully executing the programme of logical
analysis, famously ridiculed Heidegger for such philosophical prose
in an article in 1931. But Wittgenstein did not. For what Heidegger
was trying to say could not be said, but it was, contrary to Carnap’s
belief, the most essential matter.
116
we do run up against the limits of language. Kierkegaard too saw
that there is this running up against something and he referred
to it in a fairly similar way (as running up against paradox).
This running up against the limits of language is ethics . . . But
the inclination, the running up against something, indicates
something. St Augustine knew that already when he said: What,
you swine, you want not to talk nonsense! Go ahead and talk
nonsense, it does not matter!6
117
none other than Moore and Russell, the very philosophers to
whom he had explained and dictated parts of his book years ago.
Now the roles were reversed, if only formally. The situation was
described by Russell as the most absurd he ever experienced. The
exam started with a casual chat between the friends. After a while
Russell said to Moore: ‘Go on, you’ve got to ask him some ques-
tions – you’re the professor.’ Some discussion about the Tractatus
ensued, with Russell complaining about the supposed nonsensicality
of the propositions of the book. Eventually, Wittgenstein ended the
session by clapping his examiners’ shoulders and saying ‘Don’t
worry, I know you’ll never understand it.’7
Wittgenstein started working on philosophy almost immediately
after his arrival in Cambridge. He began to write down his
thoughts in the first of the eighteen large-format manuscript vol-
umes he was to complete by 1940, each amounting to 300 pages.
First he tried to execute the programme of the Tractatus, for example,
to determine what the postulated atomic objects might be. But he
failed in this, as he acknowledged himself in ‘Some Remarks on
Logical Form’, the only journal article he ever published, written in
July 1929. This failure prompted him to look increasingly critically
at his logical atomism and gradually to reject more and more of
his old ideas, until he finally discarded the whole conception of
language in the Tractatus and replaced it with a new one. This
conception was given its ultimate formulation in his masterwork,
the Philosophical Investigations, completed only in 1946 and published
posthumously (see chapter Eight). The years 1929–32 laid the
foundation for this new philosophy, although in this transitional
period we find him toying with all kinds of other ideas.
In Cambridge, as elsewhere, Wittgenstein was inclined to soli-
tude, although exchange with others was always vital for him, both
intellectually and psychologically. Fortunately, there were enough
brilliant minds around he could befriend. Russell was not teaching
in Cambridge any more, but Moore was. More importantly there
118
Wittgenstein’s
friend, the left-
wing Italian
economist
Piero Sraffa.
119
Gramsci. Despite not being a philosopher, he was not afraid of
challenging Wittgenstein head-on, unlike so many others. Indeed,
Wittgenstein acknowledged that during his discussions with
Sraffa he often felt like a tree robbed of its branches. Most of their
exchange was about philosophy, although Sraffa also informed
Wittgenstein, who disliked reading newspapers, about current
affairs. Sraffa was, unlike Ramsey, interested in the broader
picture and could help Wittgenstein see things in totally new ways.
A famous incident illustrating Sraffa’s impact on Wittgenstein
occurred when they were travelling by train and discussing logic.
Wittgenstein was defending the idea expressed in the Tractatus that
all propositions must be pictures and must have the same logical
form. In response to this Sraffa made the Neapolitan gesture of
contempt that consists of brushing the underneath of one’s chin
with the finger-tips and asked: ‘What is the logical form of that?’
According to Wittgenstein, this incident broke the spell that had
seduced him to believe for so long that propositions must have a
uniform essence.9 Language is embedded in our ways of life and
does not have only one purpose or essence – an insight that
became part and parcel of his later philosophy. Sraffa and Ramsey
were the only two people who were mentioned and thanked in the
Preface of the Philosophical Investigations.
Another important Cambridge friend was J. M. Keynes, who
assisted in integrating Wittgenstein into the university’s social life
again, including the society of the Apostles, which he had left in
disgust in 1913. Through his Tractatus Wittgenstein had become in
the meantime a legendary figure and the Apostles were thrilled to
welcome him back. Equally, he came in touch with the Bloomsbury
group and possibly Virginia Woolf, although we find hardly any
references to each other in their writings.10 Wittgenstein, with all
his monkish tendencies, did not feel comfortable in these circles,
especially if women were present, in which case he chose not to
discuss any serious matter, but made shallow conversation and
120
shallow jokes. He once walked out from a lunch because sex was
discussed in the company of women. Obviously he felt more at
home with individual people, especially young men, if they struck a
particular chord in him. A good example of this is Gilbert Pattison,
an undergraduate who later became a chartered accountant in
London. Pattison had no interest in philosophy or in tormenting
himself with ethical questions. Nevertheless, he was a close friend
of Wittgenstein for over ten years, since they shared a predilection
for trivia and ‘talking nonsense by the yard’. This involved watch-
ing Hollywood movies together at Leicester Square, ridiculing
advertisements in magazines and shops, and exchanging silly
letters, in which they would address each other with ‘Dear Blood’,
sign with ‘Yours bloodily’ and generally use the word ‘bloody’ ad
nauseam. Here is a typical exchange:
121
like C. D. Broad, Professor of Moral Philosophy, stopped their
attendance in protest against Wittgenstein regularly ‘going through
his hoops’ while his followers ‘wondered with a foolish look of
praise’.12 According to Monk, the reason why Wittgenstein chose
predominantly young men as his disciples and friends was the fact
that he preferred being surrounded by ‘childlike innocence and
first-class brains’ than by stiff professors.13 He was working on
what he considered a revolutionary conception of philosophy and
hoped that his new ideas would be better understood by the
younger generation. His charisma was overwhelming and left a
permanent mark on many of his pupils. As one of them, Desmond
Lee, has pointed out, Wittgenstein was in this respect similar to
Socrates; they both had a numbing and hypnotic effect on young
men.14 This effect was not always to the students’ benefit. He
demanded absolute loyalty and expected tolerance of his irascible
character, while he was in no way tolerant towards others. As Mary
Midgley puts it:
122
that was based on his own attitude to death in the First World War:
‘If it ever happens that you get mixed up in hand-to-hand fighting,
you must just stand aside and let yourself be massacred.’ One may
wonder whether he had any right to use his authority in such an
irresponsible way. In all fairness, it should be mentioned that his
friends probably would have not accepted such criticism. Drury
himself has publicly disputed that Wittgenstein was a ‘rather can-
tankerous, arrogant, tormented genius’. On the contrary, for Drury
Wittgenstein was ‘the most warm-hearted, generous, and loyal
friend anyone could wish to have’.16
Another well-known Cambridge society was The Heretics.
Wittgenstein seems to have attended only one of its sessions, in
November 1929, but it was here that he presented what is his most
accessible text, ‘Lecture on Ethics’ (posthumously published). It is
also his only contribution to philosophical ethics, apart from the
remarks at the end of the Tractatus. In this lecture he tried to
counter the impression that he was a positivist and anti-religious
thinker, as many of his readers thought, by stressing again that
absolute values, for example, those that make an action such
as murder evil, are not facts in this world, but transcendent.
Consequently, there can be no science of ethics, since science deals
with facts in the world. Absolute values can only be experienced.
Any attempt to express them ends in nonsense. So far, so Tractatus.
Where the lecture goes beyond the book is to give a veritable
phenomenology of religious experience. He discusses three such
experiences, namely those summarized by the phrases ‘How extra-
ordinary that anything should exist’ (the wonder of the world), ‘I
am safe, nothing can injure me whatever happens’ (absolute safety)
and ‘God disapproves of our conduct’ (absolute guilt), but only to
demonstrate that these very phrases are meaningless. He writes:
123
safe if I have had whooping cough and cannot therefore get it
again. To be safe essentially means that it is physically impossi-
ble that certain things should happen to me and therefore it is
nonsense to say that I am safe whatever happens. Again this is
a misuse of the word ‘safe’ as the other example was of a misuse
of the word ‘existence’ or ‘wondering’.
And he concludes:
124
A college
photograph of
Wittgenstein at
Cambridge.
125
When asked by Richard Braithwaite under what title his first
lectures should be announced, Wittgenstein, after remaining silent
for a long while, finally replied that the subject would be philosophy.
‘What else can be the title of the lectures but Philosophy.’ This was
to remain the title of all his lectures in Cambridge, save those for
1932–3, which were announced as ‘Philosophy for Mathematicians’.
Wittgenstein’s ‘career’ as a lecturer lasted from 1930 to 1947, with the
exception of 1936–8 and some of the war years. In the course of these
years he lectured on a wealth of topics, including the nature of phil-
osophy, the philosophy of logic and language, the intentionality of
thought and language, the critique of metaphysics, solipsism and
idealism, the philosophy of mathematics, sense data and private
experience, cause and effect, aesthetics, religious belief and Freudian
psychology. Fortunately, extensive student notes of some of these
classes have survived. Wittgenstein’s lectures soon became legendary
and contributed to the aura of genius that already surrounded him.
Over the years many students and colleagues attended them, for
instance, Alice Ambrose, Elisabeth Anscombe, Max Black, Peter
Geach, Norman Malcolm, G. E. Moore, Iris Murdoch, Rush Rhees,
John Wisdom, Stephen Toulmin, Alan Turing,19 Georg Henrik von
Wright and many others. Several of his students were to become dis-
tinguished philosophers themselves, and it was through these pupils
that Wittgenstein’s new ideas were transmitted to the rest of Britain,
and to the usa, Australia and the Scandinavian lands.
When he started lecturing in 1929 Wittgenstein was concerned
that he had to switch from German to English, given that his manu-
scripts were all drafted in German, but this worry soon vanished,
as Wittgenstein spoke excellent English with no accent. His lectures
were informal and were quite unlike those in today’s universities.
They were held in his sparsely furnished rooms in Whewell’s Court
in Trinity College. But they made a lasting impression on anybody
who attended them. Here is how Iris Murdoch, not a regular student,
remembered Wittgenstein in retrospect:
126
He was very good-looking. Rather small, with a very, very intel-
ligent, shortish face and piercing eyes – a sharpish, intent, alert
face and those very piercing eyes. He had a trampish sort of
appearance. And he had two empty rooms, with no books, and
just a couple of deck chairs and, of course, his camp bed. Both
he and his setting were very unnerving. His extraordinary
directness of approach and the absence of any sort of parapher-
nalia were the things that unnerved people. I mean with most
people, you meet them in a framework, and there are certain
conventions about how you talk to them and so on. There isn’t
a naked confrontation of personalities. But Wittgenstein always
imposed this confrontation on all his relationships. I met him
only twice and I didn’t know him well and perhaps that’s why I
always thought of him, as a person, with awe and alarm.20
127
The view from Wittgenstein’s window in Trinity College, Cambridge.
128
have complete understanding. He drove himself fiercely. His whole
being was under a tension. No one at the lectures could fail to
perceive that he strained his will, as well as his intellect, to the
utmost. This was one aspect of his absolute, relentless honesty.
Primarily, what made him an awesome and even terrible person,
both as a teacher and in personal relationships, was his ruthless
integrity, which he did not spare himself or anyone else.22
129
extremely productive in this period; by the summer of 1932 he had
completed the tenth volume of his new manuscripts. His overall
project consisted in dismantling the philosophy of the Tractatus
and replacing it with his new ideas on the nature of language, logic
and mathematics (see chapter Eight). He had also been cooperat-
ing, since 1929, with Friedrich Waismann on a book-length system-
atic presentation of his main ideas, announced as Logic, Language,
Philosophy. The book was Schlick’s idea. It was to be written by
Waismann in a lucid and accessible style, thus contrasting with
Wittgenstein’s oracular writing. Waismann met Wittgenstein on
many occasions, mainly during the latter’s holidays in Austria,
but the book was doomed, because Wittgenstein’s philosophy
was undergoing profound and unforeseeable changes, which made
him periodically reject Waismann’s drafts. As Waismann acknowl-
edged, ‘[Wittgenstein] has the marvellous gift of always seeing
everything as if for the first time. But I think it’s obvious how diffi-
cult any collaboration is, since he always follows the inspiration of
the moment and demolishes what he has previously planned.’25
When Schlick, the spiritus rector of the project, was murdered by a
disgruntled student in Vienna in 1936, Wittgenstein abandoned it.
It was nevertheless completed by Waismann, and finally published
in 1965 as The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy. The book remains
one of the most readable introductions to Wittgenstein’s thinking.
In 1931 Wittgenstein also worked on a series of remarks about
James Frazer’s monumental study in comparative anthropology
and religion, The Golden Bough (12 volumes, 1911–15). The study
was, despite its enormous scholarship, typical of the positivism
at the turn of the century insofar as it took the myths of so-called
primitive people to be primitive indeed, namely primitive science.
According to Frazer, myth and magic are based on false beliefs.
They are superstitions about natural phenomena, which were over-
come in the West through the scientific revolution. Wittgenstein
started reading the first volume of Frazer’s book with Drury, but
130
they did not get very far, since Wittgenstein stopped frequently to
express his disapproval. His main contention was that Frazer was
not attempting to understand primitive myths, but to give a merely
genetic explanation of their historical origins (and even that
explanation was mistaken). But this is to miss the actual meaning
of the myths, their depth, their similarity to our own mythical and
metaphysical ways of thinking. Frazer’s explanations of primitive
practices are more primitive than the practices themselves,
Wittgenstein contended. In reality, ‘[a]ll religions are wonderful’,
he said to Drury, ‘even those of the primitive tribes.’
131
on Frazer’s part! As a result: how impossible it was for him to
conceive of a life different from that of the England of his time!
Frazer cannot imagine a priest who is not basically a present-
day English parson with the same stupidity and dullness . . .
Frazer is much more savage than most of his savages.27
132
Wittgenstein with
his close friend
Frank Skinner in
Cambridge.
133
Masturbated last night. Pangs of conscience. But also the con-
viction that I am too weak to resist the impulse and temptation
when certain images enter my mind, and I am not able to take
refuge in other ones. And only yesterday evening I had thought
about the necessity of the purity of my development! (I was
thinking about Marguerite and Francis.)31
Love is a joy. Maybe joy with pain, but joy nevertheless. If the
joy is missing or it shrinks to a tiny flame, then love will be
missing . . . Love is connected to one’s nature . . . Love is that
pearl of great value which one holds to the heart, which one
does not exchange for anything else, which one deems the most
valuable thing. It shows one, when one has it, the meaning of
great value itself. One learns what this means: to know the
134
value. One learns what this means: to separate precious metal
from the rest.33
Think a lot about Francis, but always only with remorse over
my lovelessness; not with gratitude. His life and death seem
only to accuse me, for I was in the last two years of his life very
135
often loveless and, in my heart, unfaithful to him. If he had not
been so boundlessly gentle and true, I would have become totally
loveless towards him.35
Ask yourself this question: when you die, who will grieve for
you; and how deep will this grieving be? Who is grieving for
Francis; how deeply do I grieve for him, I, who have more rea-
son for grieving than anybody else? Does he not deserve that
somebody grieves for him for the rest of his life? If anybody,
then he does. Here one is inclined to say: God will save him and
give him what a bad person has denied him.36
136
the main interests of his later work. The Big Typescript was evidently
intended as the draft of a major book, containing chapter headings
and a table of contents, but upon completion he was so dissatisfied
that he called it a ‘rubbish bin’, attempting to redraft it at least
three times. This is surely a misjudgement, since the text is philo-
sophically extremely rich. Many remarks in his later masterwork,
Philosophical Investigations, are adopted straight from it. The Big
Typescript can be read as an independent book and is at times more
transparent and explicit than the Philosophical Investigations,
containing illuminating reflections that he did not exploit later,
for reasons nobody will ever know. After discarding the Big Typescript,
Wittgenstein worked on other attempts to formulate his new
philosophy and, finally, in 1936, he started a manuscript that would
lead to the Philosophical Investigations.
The only other significant events of these years were his journey
to the Soviet Union in 1935 and his stay in Norway in 1936. Both
can be seen as attempts to flee from his academic existence in
Cambridge. Moreover, his attraction to the Soviet Union was based
on escaping the West, a civilization he perceived as doomed and
decadent. Wittgenstein had read Keynes’s essay A Short View of
Russia. Although Keynes was very critical of the economic system
in the Soviet state, he expressed admiration for the Communists’
ability to found a quasi-religious faith. This is what Wittgenstein
was probably drawn to when reading Keynes’s description – the
prospect of a radically new life, of religious renewal on Tolstoyan
terms. Wittgenstein’s reasoning is not entirely transparent, however.
For, as Ray Monk has pointed out, the Soviet Union in the 1930s
was not Tolstoy’s idyllic country but the Moloch of Stalin’s Five
Year Plans.37 Was Wittgenstein also influenced by his surround-
ings? After all, in the early 1930s Cambridge was going through a
communist frenzy. There were not only the Apostles, a playground
and recruiting ground for Marxists, but also the Cambridge
Communist Party and the Cambridge Communist Cell. There
137
were people like the art historian Anthony Blunt and the under-
graduate Kim Philby, who later formed the notorious spy-ring of
the Cambridge Five. W. W. Bartley III has even alleged, without
proof, that Wittgenstein was a recruiter of these spies. Last, but
not least, Wittgenstein had several Marxist friends, such as Piero
Sraffa, Nikolai Bakhtin, Fania Pascal and George Thompson. But
it is unlikely that somebody as uncompromising as Wittgenstein
could have been influenced by such an indoctrinated context.
Whatever sympathy Wittgenstein had for communism, it
was probably not based on ideological reasons. He once said to
Thompson, a classicist and member of the Communist Party, ‘I am
a Communist’, but immediately added ‘at heart’. By contrast, to
Fania Pascal, an Ukrainian philosopher settled in Britain, he spoke
in such a deprecatory way about Marxist ideology that on one
occasion he managed to outrage her. It seems that his aversion to
anything doctrinal and organized affected not only his attitude to
religion, but also to politics, and Marxism could not be excepted
from this. An episode with Pascal confirms this:
138
as Martin Heidegger, who around the same time saw communism,
fascism and even democracy originating from one and the same
source, namely ‘the universal rule of the will to power’.40
Heidegger, perversely, joined the party lines of National Socialism.
Since joining a party and ideology was not a route available to
Wittgenstein, the only explanation we can find for his attraction
to the Soviet Union is his romantic longing for a new life – paired
with political naïvety and ignorance about the situation in the
Soviet Union.41
Thus in the early 1930s Wittgenstein considered settling in
Russia for good, ideally with Francis, where they would take up
medical training or work as simple labourers. He even learned
Russian to this end (which enabled him to read Dostoevsky in the
original). Provided with contacts to Soviet officials and academics
through Keynes, Wittgenstein finally went on a reconnaissance trip
in September 1935. We do not know much about this journey. He
stayed for two weeks, travelled to Leningrad and Moscow, and met
many people, especially scientists and Marxist philosophers. They
seemed to misunderstand the purpose of his stay; they offered him
academic posts, in one case a professorship at Kazan University
(where his idol Tolstoy had studied in 1844!), but not the simple
work he sought for himself and Francis. When he introduced
himself to Sophia Janovskaya, a philosopher from Moscow, she
exclaimed ‘What, not the great Wittgenstein?’ For a while after his
return from Russia Wittgenstein toyed with the idea of accepting
the academic posts. However, his enthusiasm for the Soviet Union
was gone. Why exactly, we do not know, since he remained almost
completely silent about his experience, apparently so as not to have
his name used for anti-Soviet propaganda. A plausible explanation
could be that he was simply disillusioned by the realities of the
Soviet Union, given that he now compared Soviet life to being a
private in an army.42 But this is at odds with the fact that even after
his trip Wittgenstein did not make much of the justified criticism
139
of Stalin’s totalitarianism. ‘Tyranny doesn’t make me feel indig-
nant’, he said to Rush Rhees. He continued to express his sympathy
with the Soviet experiment, presumably because it seemed to be so
different from the decaying West, indeed even after the show trials
during the Great Purge of 1936, not to mention the organized mass
starvation of millions of Ukrainian peasants in the early 1930s. As
late as 1939 he said to Drury: ‘People have accused Stalin of having
betrayed the Russian Revolution. But they have no idea of the
problems that Stalin had to deal with; and the dangers he saw
threatening Russia.’43 The irony is that Stalin himself cited such
‘problems’ and ‘dangers’ to justify his Gulag camps. This understand-
ing for the mass-murderer Stalin is incomprehensible, if we are to
take Wittgenstein’s otherwise firm ethical commitments seriously.
At least he did not make a fool of himself publicly like other
intellectuals in Britain, for instance George Bernard Shaw, who in
1934 described Stalin as the most candid and honest man, and the
Soviet people as well-fed – just when they were suffering the most
terrible famines.44
Wittgenstein’s fellowship at Trinity was extended for one more
year and finished with the summer term of 1936, which left him
without any income and again with the feeling of being an outcast.
He decided to go to Norway, as in 1913, to finish his work, but pos-
sibly also to get away from the slightly suffocating relationship
with Francis. At the end of August he was again in his old house
near Skjolden. For well over a month he attempted to rework his
latest manuscript (the Brown Book), but eventually became exasper-
ated with it and gave up, considering the result ‘worthless’, ‘boring
and artificial’. He then started a new version of his book, which,
as mentioned earlier, later made up a significant portion of the
Philosophical Investigations. Once again, Norway proved to be the
right environment for him to do serious philosophical work. But it
also proved to be the right place to deal with his sins. Feeling that
he was morally depraved, he wrote up a very personal confession,
140
which he distributed among friends and family. Among the
addressees were Skinner, Moore, Drury, Engelmann and Pascal.
We do not know exactly what the confession contained, since most
of his intimates never revealed anything about it. From Pascal we
know that it dealt with Wittgenstein’s denial of his Jewishness and
his maltreatment of a pupil during his time as a schoolteacher.
According to another source it also dealt with his sexuality.
Apart from several visits to Vienna and Cambridge, Wittgenstein
stayed in Norway until Christmas 1937. There is a kind of romantic
cult surrounding Wittgenstein’s trips to Norway,45 but in reality his
stays were always accompanied by loneliness and despair. This was
particularly true this time around. The thought of having to live on
his own in his hut frightened him so much that for a while he chose
to live in the house of Anna Rebni, an old woman he knew from the
pre-war years. This anxiety gave him reason to reflect, once again, on
his ethical standing. His impression was that, despite the personal
confession he had written only the previous year, he was losing grip
of himself again. He felt weak, shabby, depressed, seeing his own life
as a problem. To use a phrase by Flaubert: his life was not ‘dans le
vrai’. And this brought him to reflect on religious faith again. This
time he described himself as irreligious, for ‘a man who lived rightly
won’t experience the problem [of life] as sorrow’. He admitted to not
understanding the Christian faith. In February 1937 he wrote: ‘Let me
confess this: After a difficult day for me I kneeled during dinner
today & prayed & suddenly said, kneeling & looking up above:
“There is no one here.” That made me feel at ease as if I had been
enlightened in an important matter.’46
This passage, written in code, may be seen as a turning point in
his attitude to religion. Clearly, the religious fervour of his former
years had vanished. As he later said of his Catholic friends: ‘I could
not possibly bring myself to believe all the things that they believe.’
In the strict sense of the word he was probably no longer religious.
But in a sense there were still elements of religiosity in him. After
141
all, he was conscious that he was living a life of sin and sorrow,
a consciousness that in his earlier ‘Lecture on Ethics’ he had
described as one of the three basic religious experiences. And there
were still moments when he found the Christian faith attractive.
Concerning this there is an intriguing passage in his diary from
December 1937. He was on the ship returning from Skjolden to
Bergen and came, while reading the Bible, across a passage in
Corinthians 12:3: ‘No man can say that Jesus is the Lord, but
through the Holy Ghost.’ While he agreed with this passage,
because he felt that talk about Jesus as the Lord coming to judge
him was meaningless to him, he also wrote:
142
able to look at religion as such, its function in human life, at the
role of religious beliefs in people’s lives. This decidedly anthropo-
logical stance became explicit in three lectures he gave on religious
belief when he returned to Cambridge in 1938. What we know
about these lectures is based only on notes by his students, but
even so they give insight into his ideas on a topic that always pre-
occupied Wittgenstein, although he wrote very little on it.48 In these
lectures he sets out to defend religion against the attack under
which it has come in modern times, especially through the rise of
science. Religion is radically different from science and therefore
does not stand in competition with it. In particular, religious state-
ments are not empirical statements or theories about the (after-)
world competing with scientific ones. They are not held on the
basis of evidence, as is for instance some hypothesis about our
galaxy, and it is therefore a grave mistake to treat them on a par
with scientific theories, as both atheists and certain theologians do.
The physicist who rejects the existence of God or the Christian doc-
trine of the Resurrection because there is no evidence for it and the
theologian who accepts God’s existence on the basis of supposed
evidence (or even ‘proofs’) are making the same mistake. Rather,
religious beliefs, and notions such as ‘God’, ‘resurrection’, ‘sin’, etc.
have no theoretical function at all. They only crystallize primordial
ways of life, and are in this sense secondary. ‘the words you utter or
what you think as you utter them are not what matters, so much as
the difference they make at various points in your life . . . Practice
gives the words their sense.’49 Religious statements express an atti-
tude to life as a whole, for example, guilt, and only have meaning
with reference to a certain form of life, to certain existential experi-
ences. Note that religious statements now are described as having
a meaning, while in his earlier philosophy he had dismissed them
as meaningless. ‘A religious question is either a question of life and
death or it is (empty) babble. This language-game, one might say,
gets played only with questions of life and death. Much like the
143
expression “Ouch” only has a meaning as a cry of pain.’50 A believer
saying ‘There will be a Judgement Day and this is when I shall be
judged’ is not like a meteorologist predicting that it will rain
tomorrow. It is more like the cry for help of a man fighting for
his life against a raging fire. His actions will not be based on form-
ing hypotheses through judicious inductive inferences (e.g. ‘Fire
has hurt me in the past. This is a fire. Therefore this fire will hurt
me now’), but on terror.51 Religious beliefs and rituals express this
terror, among other things (they also express awe for the fact of
life, etc.). Since they are not based on opinions and hypotheses,
there is nothing right or wrong about them, and believers are
neither rational nor irrational.
144
religious.) It follows that there can be no science of religion, no
scientific explanation of religious beliefs in terms of other factors,
such as sexuality (Freud), society (Marx) or evolution (Darwin).
All we can and should do is describe religious life, not explain it.
Wittgenstein’s understanding of religion stands in sharp opposition
to contemporary attempts to explain religion away, like now
fashionable neuroscientific theories based on ‘brain scanning’.
It has affinities with other non-reductive investigations into the
nature of religion that emerged in the early twentieth century, for
example, Rudolf Otto’s or Mircea Eliade’s phenomenologies of reli-
gion. Last but not least, given the non-theoretical status of religious
statements, one cannot use rational discourse to make somebody
believe in them. But what would make one believe in a religious
doctrine then? On this, Wittgenstein does not say anything sub-
stantial, indeed presents himself as agnostic:
However, towards the end of his life we find the following intrigu-
ing entry in his diary:
Life can educate one to a belief in God. And experiences too are
what bring this about; but I don’t mean visions and other forms
of sense experience which show us the ‘existence of this being’,
but, e.g., sufferings of various sorts. These neither show us God
in the way a sense impression shows us an object, nor do they
give us rise to conjectures about him. Experiences, thoughts, –
life can force this concept on us.54
145
So perhaps ‘life’ itself gives reasons to be a believer. But it is charac-
teristic of Wittgenstein in his later years that he did not say that life
has educated him to believe in God. At least, he continued to take
religion immensely serious and also to pray occasionally. As he
confessed to Drury: ‘I am not a religious man but I cannot help
seeing every problem from a religious point of view.’55
146
7
147
rallies of the [Austrian] Nazis’ taking place all over the country. On
12 March 1938 Drury informed Wittgenstein about the Anschluss.
Wittgenstein and his family were now no longer Austrians, but
Germans or, more precisely, German Jews, which made them sub-
ject to the racist Nuremberg Laws. Wittgenstein wrote on the same
day in his diary: ‘What I hear about Austria disturbs me. Am
unclear what I should do, whether to go to Vienna or not.’ And
a few days later, contemplating the various external and internal
dilemmas, including his own Jewishness, involved in possessing
a Judenpaß, he wrote:
148
Sraffa in Cambridge for advice. Sraffa urged him ‘you must not go to
Vienna’, for he would not have been allowed to leave the country
again. Fortunately, Wittgenstein complied. Within days he decided
to renounce his Austrian citizenship, accepting that he would be an
immigrant from now on. ‘But the thought of leaving my people
alone is dreadful.’4 On Sraffa’s advice he first sought permanent
employment with the university, asking for Keynes’s support:
149
Wittgensteins struck a financial deal with the Nazis. As Jews they
were forced to sign over most of their assets to the Reichsbank.
But since most of the family fortune was deposited in funds in us
banks, the Nazis needed the cooperation of the family to access this
money. The negotiations were brought to completion in August
1939. Hermann Christian Wittgenstein was declared of ‘German
blood’, which made all his grandchildren, including Ludwig and his
sisters, into Mischlinge (‘hybrids’) of first degree. This status could
be lost if they were to marry a Jewish person, but they were soon
excepted even from this condition. In return, the Wittgensteins
transferred a staggering 1.7 tons of gold to the Nazi state, no less
than 2 per cent of Austria’s gold reserves at the time. Ludwig,
who was very worried about his family during this period, became
involved in the negotiations as soon as he received his British pass-
port, and travelled to Berlin, Vienna and even New York to help out
with the transaction. One may wonder about the ethical implica-
tions of this deal. A vast fortune was given to the Nazi machine,
which was soon to wreck millions of people’s lives, just so that the
two women’s ‘perverse desire to stay in Austria’ could be satisfied.
How could Wittgenstein, given his strict opposition to unethical
compromises, justify such a transaction? However, his opposition
to compromises primarily applied to his own life. Here others were
involved, over whose actions he had no control. He entered the
negotiations at a comparatively late stage, when his sisters had
already decided to stay in Austria and compromise with the Nazis.
He did not oppose their decision, as his brother Paul did (which
led to serious tensions in the family), but the main responsibility
was still his sisters’. Moreover, despite the totalitarian character of
Hitler’s regime in the late 1930s, the war and the Holocaust had not
yet taken place. And even if they had, who would not have acted
just like him in similar circumstances? Who would not have given
any available sum to save his beloved ones? The deal with the Nazis
did involve a moral dilemma, but its horns were straight from hell.
150
Despite the worries about his family, Wittgenstein continued to
work on philosophy after his return to Cambridge in 1938. In the
summer he prepared the material he had written in Norway for
publication, and offered it to Cambridge University Press under
the title Philosophical Remarks. It was the earliest version of the
Philosophical Investigations. The edition was supposed to be bilin-
gual, including the German original and an English translation
provided by one of his pupils, Rush Rhees. Wittgenstein withdrew
his manuscript from Cambridge University Press within a month,
being dissatisfied with both the content and Rhees’s translation.
The main reason for attempting this publication was his growing
dissatisfaction with the fact that since 1929 ideas connected to his
new philosophy had been disseminated by his colleagues and
pupils in a watered-down form. In 1932 he accused Rudolf Carnap
of plagiarism in letters to Schlick, not entirely without justification,
but in a much too ferocious manner. In 1933 he wrote a furious
letter to Mind, protesting against the inaccurate description of
his ideas in a rather innocuous article by Richard Braithwaite.
In 1935 Alice Ambrose, a gifted pupil, incurred his wrath because
she decided to publish an article summarizing his philosophy of
mathematics. He tried to convince her to abandon its publication,
but after both she and the editor of Mind, G. E. Moore, refused to
do so, Wittgenstein resigned as Ambrose’s phd examiner and
broke off all contacts with her.6
Rhees’s translation was not completely worthless, however. In
early 1939 Wittgenstein applied for the chair in philosophy recently
vacated by Moore, and submitted it as a token of his work. He was
convinced that he would not be elected because the Oxford philoso-
pher R. G. Collingwood, whom he suspected of hostile sentiments,
was on the election committee. But as C. D. Broad, who was person-
ally not fond of Wittgenstein either, remarked at the time: ‘To refuse
the chair to Wittgenstein would be like refusing Einstein a chair of
physics’, a remark that apparently amazed Wittgenstein.7 He was
151
elected professor on 11 February 1939. This was the highest profes-
sional distinction for an academic philosopher (and one denied to
other great thinkers, e.g., Schopenhauer and Frege), but it meant
little to him: ‘having got the professorship is very flattering & all
that but it might have been very much better for me to have got a
job opening & closing crossing gates. I don’t get a kick out of my
position (except what my vanity & stupidity sometimes gets).’8
He was to remain in the position till 1947.
His first lectures as a professor were on philosophy of mathe-
matics (published in 1976), a topic on which he worked almost
exclusively during the entire war. A year later, in 1940, he gave
seminars on his Philosophical Investigations and on aesthetics. As
in his lectures on religious belief, he argued in those on aesthetics
against the idolatry of ‘Science and the Scientist’.
152
etc.’, it would be a mockery to say ‘Because of this and that brain
process!’ or ‘Because 70 per cent of my relatives do!’ But what does
then define aesthetic appreciation? Wittgenstein’s answer is typical
of his later philosophy: don’t assume there must be a unique
answer to this question. Aesthetic appreciation is a very complex
phenomenon, Wittgenstein argues, indeed not one phenomenon,
but an ‘immensely complicated family of cases’. To be sure, in an
entry from his later diaries Wittgenstein does venture to indicate
a unique or at least central feature of art: ‘We might say: art
discloses the miracles of nature to us. It is based on the concept
of the miracles of nature.’10 But in his lectures Wittgenstein
is more careful: what art is cannot be indicated by a singular
definition, since there is not one single feature that unifies all
our aesthetic experiences or all those things we treat as works
of art. Hence, there can be no theory of art that subsumes every-
thing under general laws and causal explanations. What we need
in aesthetics are not theories and explanations, but (sympathetic)
descriptions.
By 1940 the Second World War was well under way and
Wittgenstein, now a British citizen, was anxious to be involved in
war work of some kind, being frustrated with his confinement to
academic life, which he dreaded more than ever. For several years
he had been friends with Gilbert Ryle (1900–1976), a philosopher
with whom he shared many ideas and who later was to become one
153
of Oxford’s most prominent thinkers and editor of Mind. Gilbert
Ryle introduced Wittgenstein to his brother, John Ryle, who had
been professor of medicine in Cambridge, but was now working
at Guy’s Hospital in London. To John Ryle Wittgenstein said: ‘I
feel I will die slowly if I stay [in Cambridge]. I would rather take a
chance of dying quickly.’12 As in the First World War he wished to
be placed ‘where the bombs are falling’. It was the old will to feel
alive in the face of great danger, to be pulled out of lethargy and
depression by the presence of death. But there was also a genuine
concern with his new homeland, as he told Drury:
154
On the whole, his time at the hospital did not lift Wittgenstein’s
mood. At 52 he felt old and worn-out. Moreover, he was heartbroken
over Francis’s death in October 1941. He made a few friends, includ-
ing John Ryle and his wife Miriam, who took him for a weekend
to their house in Sussex. When, in April 1942, he had a gall-stone
removed from which he had suffered for years, Ryle held his hand
during the operation – a peculiar event, since Wittgenstein, dis-
trusting the surgeons, refused general anaesthetic and observed
the whole process through special mirrors installed for him. In the
hospital Wittgenstein also befriended Roy Fouracre, a colleague
at the dispensary. The latter was a simple, good-humoured young
man from Hackney, who had a calming effect on Wittgenstein.
When Wittgenstein was in a state of agitation, Fouracre would
calm him down by saying ‘Steady, Prof ’. As with Gilbert Pattison,
there was no intellectual dimension to their friendship. Nevertheless,
or maybe because of this, the ‘Prof ’ stayed friends with Fouracre to
the end of his life, and when the young man was sent to the Front
in the Far East, Wittgenstein wrote him many light-hearted letters,
urging him to come back soon so that they could ‘talk nonsense
by the yard’ again. At the hospital he also met Naomi Wilkinson,
a cousin of the Ryles, who organized gramophone recitals in which
Wittgenstein participated with much interest.
It was during his time at the hospital that Wittgenstein started
to preoccupy himself in more depth with Freudian psychology.
In the years 1942–6 he had several conversations with Rush Rhees
about Freud, of which Rhees took extensive notes.15 This was not
his first encounter with psychoanalysis. Not only did he know
about Freud from his sister Margarete, but Wittgenstein himself
had discussed psychoanalysis in his lectures on aesthetics in 1938.
Back then he expressed his admiration for those practical aspects of
Freud’s work which he considered illuminating, for example, Freud’s
imaginative interpretations of jokes in Jokes and Their Relation to the
Unconscious (1905). But his attitude to Freud’s theories was highly
155
critical. Not only did he disapprove of Freud’s dogmatic reduction
of dreams to purely sexual contexts, but he rejected the underlying
principle of explanation that posits hidden causal mechanisms in
the human psyche. In his view the main reason why people find
Freud’s ‘theory’ of the unconscious so plausible is the idol-worship
of science in our culture, the overwhelming attraction of the scien-
tific mode of thinking, of reducing everything to cause and effect.
In making such a reduction, one thinks that one finds out what
things ‘really’ are. Dreams ‘really’ are repressed sexual desires,
actions ‘really’ are caused by childhood experiences, people ‘really’
chatter because they are sexually unfulfilled, etc. To stress what
things ‘really’ are empowers the individual, makes him feel as a
destroyer of the prejudices of other, more naïve humans. For, as
Wittgenstein puts it, ‘It is charming to destroy prejudice.’16
In his conversations with Rhees he stressed again what he found
appealing in Freud, such as certain interpretations of dreams,
or the therapeutic, self-healing effects an interpretation of one’s
life in terms of Greek tragedy might have.
156
a method that is prior to the formation of scientific hypotheses.
Through free association one could always find some ‘hidden’
meaning in any kind of phenomena, not just in dreams. Take
some table with random objects on it, for example, some papers,
pens, a mug, a phone, some books and cds. None of them has
been put there through your dream activity. Now fix your mind
on some problem of major significance in your life. It would not
be too difficult to connect the objects through some pattern in such
a way that the whole arrangement could be seen as a visualization
or interpretation of your problem. Horoscopes or the reading of
tea leaves are based on this kind of ‘method’. But this pattern-
creating interpretation does not prove anything, especially not
how things are ‘in reality’. We have not given a scientific explanation
of how the objects on the table are connected, but just superimposed
a certain story by pressing each object into its scheme. This activity
is similar to that of creating a myth. Indeed, Wittgenstein contends,
Freud’s stories are not scientific explanations, but actually new
myths.18 He writes:
157
(Now any ass has these pictures available to use in ‘explaining’
symptoms of illness.)20
158
research project (published in 1951). The device has been lost,
but Wittgenstein’s contribution is visible in Dr Grant’s report:
159
found it more fruitful to talk to a non-philosopher about his
ideas. Also, Bakhtin had a very lively and flamboyant personality.
Wittgenstein was fond of him precisely because they were so differ-
ent. The philosopher was ‘unusually happy and gay in [Bakhtin’s]
presence, and never dropped him as easily as he did others’.23 There
might have been even some intellectual affinities. Bakhtin was a
fierce opponent of uniformity and generality, of what he called
‘the tyranny of abstract ideas and dogmas over life’, which he saw
embodied in Plato’s philosophy, and endorsed instead Aristotle’s
preference for multiple distinctions, for ‘continuous transitions
of shades and qualities’, which fitted well with Wittgenstein’s new
philosophical orientation.24 However, to claim, as Terry Eagleton
has done, that Wittgenstein’s ideas were somehow related to the
Marxist aesthetics of Mikhail Bakhtin via this broad affinity with
brother Nikolai is to overlook subtle and not so subtle differences
between Wittgenstein and Marxist thought.25 ‘Like primitive
peoples, we are much more inclined to say “All these things,
though looking different, are really the same” than we are to say
“All these things, though looking the same, are really different.”’26
Wittgenstein left Newcastle in February 1944 and after an inter-
mezzo in Cambridge went to stay with Rhees in Swansea, where he
had been in the previous two summers, and where he was to return
several times in the following years.27 Rhees, who was teaching
philosophy at Swansea, had been one of his favourite pupils and was
now one of his closest friends. Rhees’s wife was a psychoanalyst
of the Jungian school. Hence, Wittgenstein was in good company.
He stayed in Swansea for almost half a year. It was here that he
stopped working on philosophy of mathematics, a topic that not
only had brought him to philosophy in the first place and made
him return to it, but one that he had pursued tirelessly since 1929
(around half of his manuscripts from 1929 to 1944 are dedicated to it).
Instead he now became interested in the philosophy of psychology
(or philosophy of mind, as we would say today), and it is due to
160
this shift of interest that the final manuscript of the Philosophical
Investigations contains no philosophy of mathematics, but plenty
of philosophy of psychology.28
In Swansea Wittgenstein worked intensively on his book, gave
lectures at the university and made friends with several locals, as
he found he could get along better with them than with people in
England. ‘The weather’s foul, but I enjoy not being in Cambridge . . .
I feel much more often like smiling, e.g. when I walk in the street,
or when I see children, etc.’29 He lodged with several locals, including
a Methodist minister, whom Wittgenstein teased with the remark
that the numerous books in the house were not bought to be read,
but to impress the flock. When the minister asked him whether he
believed in God, Wittgenstein replied: ‘Yes I do, but the difference
between what you believe and what I believe may be infinite.’30
Another incident involved one of the daughters of his neighbours,
whom he befriended. He had supervised her progress in school.
One day she came home in tears. Hearing that she had been failed,
Wittgenstein replied ‘Damn it all! We’ll see about that!’ and went
in a rage to see the responsible teacher. He told the latter: ‘I am
stunned that you say she failed and I can tell you on authority that
she must have passed.’ And indeed, she had. The teacher checked
the records and discovered that there had been a mistake.31
In October 1944 Wittgenstein was back in Cambridge, resuming
his lecturing, mostly on philosophy of psychology, and continuing
work on his book. He moved again into his old lodgings in
Whewell’s Court at Trinity College. During the Christmas vacation
of 1944–5, which he spent in Swansea, he must have felt that he was
nearing the end of his labours, for he drafted the final preface to
the still unfinished book. It was, he wrote, ‘the precipitate of philo-
sophical investigations which have occupied me for the last sixteen
years’, adding grimly: ‘It is not impossible that it should fall to the
lot of this work, in its poverty and in the darkness of this time, to
bring light into one brain or another – but, of course, it is not likely.’
161
Opus magnum:
The typescript of
Wittgenstein’s
Philosophical
Investigations.
162
over 32 million civilians alone. But Wittgenstein did not have only
the war in mind and, indeed, when it was over in August 1945,
he saw no reason to join in the celebrations of victory, as he was
appalled by what he considered ‘the triumphant beastliness of the
Allies in Germany & Japan’. Already during the war he had written:
‘Things will be terrible when the war is over, whoever wins. Of
course, very terrible, if the Nazis won, but terribly slimy if the
Allies win.’33 And after the ceasefire:
Perhaps I ought to feel elated because the war is over. But I’m
not. I can’t help feeling certain that this peace is only a truce.
And the pretence that the complete stamping out of the ‘aggres-
sors’ of this war will make this world a better place to live in,
as a future war could, of course, only be started by them, stinks
to high heaven &, in fact, promises a horrid future.34
163
to every realm of thought, be it language, mathematics, psychology,
religion, anthropology or aesthetics. He had attempted to undermine
this multifaceted idolatry of science by showing that important
aspects of these disciplines are inaccessible to scientific theory-
building. His philosophy was thus opposed not only to particular
philosophical doctrines, but really to a much larger current, as he
had made clear in the preface to the Philosophical Remarks (1930):
This book is written for such men as are in sympathy with its
spirit. This spirit is different from the one which informs the
vast stream of European and American civilization in which all
of us stand. That spirit expresses itself in an onwards move-
ment, in building ever larger and more complicated structures;
the other in striving after clarity and perspicuity in no matter
what structure.
The hysterical fear over the atom bomb now being experienced,
or at any rate expressed, by the public almost suggests that at
last something really salutary has been invented. The fright at
least gives the impression of a really effective bitter medicine . . .
But perhaps this too is a childish idea. Because really all I can
mean is that the bomb offers a prospect of the end, the destruc-
tion, of an evil, – our disgusting soapy water science . . . but
who could say what would come after this destruction?36
164
Wittgenstein with
his friend Ben
Richards in
London.
who was over 35 years younger than Wittgenstein. Ben had similar
qualities to Francis: he was kind, gentle, good-looking. Wittgenstein
fell deeply in love with him. Since Francis there had been nobody
else in his life, if we discount the case of Keith Kirk, a working-class
colleague of Francis to whom Wittgenstein gave lessons in mechan-
ics and mathematics in 1940. Wittgenstein was infatuated with
Kirk, but kept his feelings secret and nothing ever developed. With
Ben, however, the feelings seem to have been more mutual, leading
to a relationship that lasted, with ups and downs, for several years.37
Given that he felt old and worn-out this unexpected emotional out-
burst reinvigorated and inspired him, and made him forget about
his daily worries, in particular the dreaded duties of his academic
position. No doubt Ben’s love was very precious to him, a ‘great rare
165
gift’ and a ‘rare gem’, as he described it in his diary. But this love
also led to new trouble, since it made him depend again on another
human being. It seems that he was now less capable than before
to bear the hazards of love, experiencing despair and anxiety at the
slightest uncertainty, such as a missing letter.
166
act by which the human race is perpetuated? Not every religion
has to have St Augustine’s attitude to sex.’40 Can we take this as
evidence that Wittgenstein really changed his attitude to sex? It
may well be so, but since we do not know of other similar episodes
the evidence seems thin.
His love for Ben notwithstanding, Wittgenstein now found
life in Cambridge increasingly intolerable. ‘Everything about the
place repels me’, he noted in his diary. ‘The stiffness, the artifi-
ciality, the self-satisfaction of the people. The university atmos-
phere nauseates me.’41 More generally, he perceived the English
civilization as ‘disintegrating and putrefying’. He also felt much
lonelier now. Francis, Ramsey, Keynes were all dead, while Drury,
Malcolm and Rhees had left Cambridge. With Russell he had
nothing to do any more, neither personally nor philosophically.
Moore had suffered a stroke and his wife allowed him to talk to
Wittgenstein for at the most one-and-a-half hours, which enraged
Wittgenstein. Why should Moore not talk as much as he pleased?
‘If he became very excited or tired and had a stroke and died –
well, that would be a decent way to die: with his boots on.’42 In
addition, Wittgenstein was far from convinced that his teaching
was doing any good. ‘The only seed I am likely to sow is a certain
jargon’, he said in a lecture. And there was much truth to this,
since there was a cult surrounding Wittgenstein in Cambridge,
now considered the greatest living philosopher. As Gilbert Ryle
described his visits to the Moral Sciences Club: ‘veneration for
Wittgenstein was so incontinent that mentions, for example my
mentions, of other philosophers were greeted with jeers’.43 This
attitude was partly enforced by Wittgenstein himself, since he
apparently not only prided himself with not having studied much
history of philosophy, but also ridiculed those who had done so
as ‘academic philosophers’.
In the summer term of 1947 Wittgenstein decided to retire.
He planned to leave England and live by himself. The summer he
167
spent in Swansea, partly joined by Ben Richards, contemplating
where to go next, Ireland or Norway. Eventually he chose Ireland.
In September and October he visited his family in Vienna for the
first time in eight years. Knowing about the post-war depression
he dreaded seeing his native city again, and was indeed shocked
by its devastation. The capital of the old empire in whose army he
had once served was never to be the same again. What demoralized
him in particular was the brutality of the Russians in their sector,
where a lot of looting and raping was taking place. The Soviet
troops had also vandalized the house he had built for Margarete. If
Wittgenstein still had any illusions about the Soviets, he certainly
lost them now. Back in Cambridge, he officially resigned his chair
as from the end of the year, spent several more weeks at Trinity
College preparing a typescript on the philosophy of psychology,
and finally left for Dublin at the beginning of December. As he told
Malcolm, ‘I am in no way optimistic about my future but as soon
as I had resigned I felt that it was the only natural thing to have
done.’44
168
8
‘The fox knows many things, but the hedgehog knows one big
thing.’ Isaiah Berlin once used this fragment by the Greek poet
Archilocus to explain the deep divide between two kinds of writers
and thinkers, indeed between two kinds of human beings. On the
one hand, there are the hedgehogs – those who have a central
vision, a coherent system, a universal principle, and relate every-
thing to it. There are, on the other hand, the foxes – those whose
thought moves on many levels, who are aware of the prodigious
richness of phenomena and who do not try fitting it all into
one unifying framework. Berlin classified Plato, Dante, Hegel,
Dostoevsky as hedgehogs, Aristotle, Shakespeare, Goethe,
Joyce as foxes, and Tolstoy as a cross of both.1 But what about
Wittgenstein? He, too, cannot be unequivocally placed into one or
other category. By nature, he was a hedgehog, and his early work
bears witness to this. For in the Tractatus he strived, like all great
European metaphysicians, to encompass everything in a unifying
system, everything from the foundations of logic to the nature of
the world. But, as Peter Hacker has suggested, in his later work
Wittgenstein transformed himself through great intellectual effort
into a fox.2
Wittgenstein’s early work was a paradigmatic example of system-
building philosophy – his atomistic account of the essence of the
proposition was the foundation upon which he built his theory of
logic, language, ontology, mind and ethics. Everything was meant to
169
hang together through one key assumption, namely that the essence
of every elementary proposition is to describe a possible fact and to
be independent of any other elementary proposition. Consequently,
every statement had to be interpreted as a picture, even those that
at face value did not seem to be picturing anything. The early philos-
ophy was therefore analytical in a more literal sense: things are not
as they seem to be; their hidden real essence is revealed to us when
we step below the realm of appearances and analyse, that is, decom-
pose the statement or a fact we are interested in into its actual con-
stituents. True, the method employed for this, logical analysis, was
new, but the aim, or rather the dream, of revealing the essence of
things was as old as philosophy itself. It was the dream of establish-
ing philosophy as metaphysics, a super-science discovering the most
fundamental features of the world by means of the most rigorous
method. And it was a dream that the early Wittgenstein thought had
come true in his Tractatus.
But when, in 1929, he attempted to work out the programme of
logical analysis announced in the book, he realized that his dream
had been a chimera. His fundamental assumption proved to be
wrong: there is no such thing as the essence of proposition, no such
thing as the essence of language. And with it the entire logical,
semantical and ontological edifice so meticulously developed in the
Tractatus collapsed like a house of cards. By 1932 Wittgenstein had
abandoned most of his old doctrines. But it was not only his specific
doctrines that he came to reject – he demolished much of his earlier
conception of philosophy itself. The main point that remained
unchanged was his continuing belief that philosophy is not a
science about the world, but consists in the a priori clarification of
language. Among the major differences, by contrast, was his rejec-
tion of the metaphor of depth and the idea of a hidden essence,
for ‘Nothing is hidden’ (Philosophical Investigations [pi] §435). All
the philosopher is interested in lies in plain view. He need not dig
down beneath the phenomena, but must stay on the ground level
170
and draw a map of it. Geography replaces geology. This ground
level consists of our language and the concepts expressed by it,
including philosophically problematic ones like ‘proposition’,
‘meaning’, ‘knowledge’, ‘ability’, ‘intention’, ‘number’, etc. These
basic notions constitute our conceptual framework, the grid
through which we obtain knowledge about the world in both life
and science. But since Wittgenstein now believes that none of these
notions is more basic than the others, there can be no analysis in
the older sense of the word, that is, there is no building of a system
resting on one fundamental notion (‘proposition’ in the Tractatus),
with all the others being reduced to, derived from or explained by
it. All the philosopher has to do now instead is describe. He has to
describe how the philosophically relevant concepts are related to
each other, how ‘proposition’ and ‘meaning’, ‘knowledge’ and ‘abil-
ity’, etc., connect with one another. The new descriptive–connec-
tive method is really more like the drawing of a map. Wittgenstein
employs the geographical metaphors himself in his Preface to the
Philosophical Investigations, for he says that the nature of his investi-
gation ‘compels us to travel over a wide field of thought criss-cross
in every direction. – The philosophical remarks in this book are, as
it were, a number of sketches of landscapes which were made in
the course of these long and involved journeyings.’3 Later he writes:
‘Our language can be seen as an ancient city: a maze of little streets
and squares, of old and new houses, and of houses with additions
from various periods; and this surrounded by a multitude of new
boroughs with straight regular streets and uniform houses’ (pi §18).
This relates to another simile Wittgenstein gave his students in a
lecture:
171
have taken you many journeys through the city, in all sorts
of directions, we shall have passed through any given street
a number of times – each time traversing the street as part of
a different journey. At the end of this you will know London;
you will be able to find your way about like a Londoner.4
172
the nature of his thinking: ‘I destroy, I destroy, I destroy’. Second,
in philosophy we do not investigate the world in a trivial sense. We
uncover or ‘show’ the metaphysical essence of the world, but only
understand how our language works by giving what Wittgenstein
calls a ‘perspicuous representation of its grammar’. Since this
involves giving an account of how individual expressions are
employed in various everyday contexts in life and the sciences,
knowledge about how and for which purpose words are used will
involve knowledge about the world. But this is knowledge that we
already have and that we simply recall or make explicit through
the realization of affinities and differences in the familiar grammar
of expressions. ‘Learning in philosophy is really recollecting. We
remember that we really did use words that way.’ This is a far cry
from traditional metaphysics and the metaphysics of the Tractatus.
173
been done for the past 2,500 years is to a large extent miscon-
ceived. Wittgenstein was aware of these historical implications,
despite his claim not to care about history. Thus, in a lecture in
1930 he described his philosophy as a new subject, a kink in the
development of human thought. ‘The nimbus of philosophy has
been lost. For we now have a method of doing philosophy, and
can speak of skilful philosophers. Compare the difference between
alchemy and chemistry; chemistry has a method and we can speak
of skilful chemists.’ And around the same time he wrote in his
diary: ‘If my name survives, then only as the terminus ad quem of
the great philosophy of the West. As the name of him who burnt
the library of Alexandria.’8 Unsurprisingly, this conception of
philosophy has met with much resistance since Wittgenstein’s
death and it is at the moment to a large extent rejected by analytic
philosophers. It is, contrary to the confidence in science character-
istic of our time, a conception that greatly narrows the range of
what we humans can know about the world through abstract
thought. It resembles to some extent Immanuel Kant’s critical phil-
osophy, that is, the denial that pure reason is capable of answering
the great metaphysical questions (about the existence of God, the
immortality of the soul, the freedom of the will). Wittgenstein,
however, is more radical than Kant, since he does not believe that
our cognitive powers are too restricted to answer metaphysical
questions, but that these very questions do not even make sense.
Not even God could answer such questions. Il faut cultiver notre
jardin – the modesty of Voltaire’s Candide, which appealed so
much to Kant, remains valid, but from Wittgenstein’s point of
view only because there is nothing else for philosophers outside
the garden of grammar.
This view of philosophy is sketched in some fifteen pages of the
Philosophical Investigations and applied in the rest of the book. Being
the fruit of sixteen years of hard work the book is overly complex
and cannot be summarized here in any detail.9 It may suffice,
174
however, to describe the character of the book and give a few exam-
ples of how philosophy is done in it. To begin with, it is short, just
over 250 pages long in the English translation. From the ten thou-
sands of remarks Wittgenstein made in his manuscripts since 1929
he selected only a tiny fragment and grouped them in 693 apho-
rism-like sections. We could thus view the Investigations as the tip
of a massive iceberg. Three main areas are covered in the book:
philosophy of language (meaning, understanding, following a rule,
etc.), philosophy of mind (thinking, remembering, imagining,
intending, etc.) and the already mentioned nature of philosophy.
His extensive investigations into the philosophy of mathematics
are only touched upon.
The style of the book is very different from that of the Tractatus.
The prose is not so sibylline, but limpid and non-technical, with
striking metaphors and analogies, thought experiments, invented
language-games, rhetorical questions, soliloquies, etc. There are
also several fragments of dialogue between a ‘voice of error’ and
the ‘voice of correctness’ (which can often be construed as an
exchange between young Ludwig and his present self ), but it
would be a mistake to view the entire book as a Socratic dialogue
as some interpreters have done. For Wittgenstein was not a fan of
the genre: ‘Reading the Socratic dialogues one has the feeling; what
a frightful waste of time! What’s the point of these arguments that
prove nothing and clarify nothing?’10 Despite its clear style, the
book has a dark side, a side that has fascinated and exasperated
many readers. This is partly due to Wittgenstein’s preference for
‘the liberating word’ and his aversion to redundancy. His remarks
intimate more than they explicitly say, providing the reader with
the seed of a thought, not with a spelled-out argument. Nevertheless,
and despite his own liking of aphorists like Lichtenberg and Karl
Kraus, it would not be accurate to regard the Investigations as a
book of aphorisms, since it is a systematic and argumentative work
in theoretical philosophy. But one often loses sight of its system-
175
aticity, because it is not always clear how the remarks connect and
which topic, target or philosopher they specifically address. There
is, in other words, no easily surveyable linear ‘narrative’, no imme-
diate transparency of the author’s intentions and convictions. This
poses serious although not insurmountable challenges to the reader.
The Investigations deals with a very wide range of subjects,
including the nature of the mind, intention, knowledge, thinking,
etc. But the central theme of the book is the nature of language.
It attempts to correct a hugely influential conception of language
that has dominated European philosophy for centuries, indeed a
conception that comes naturally to most humans when they begin
to reflect on language. According to this conception, which was
manifest in the Tractatus as well, the essence of language is to
depict and describe reality. More precisely, this conception can
be broken down into three main theses. First, the essential role
of words is to name objects; the meaning of a word is the object it
stands for. Second, language gets connected to the world via funda-
mental acts of naming; we point ostensively at an object and give
the word ‘A’ a meaning by saying ‘This is A’. Third, the essential
function of propositions is to describe how things are.
Wittgenstein argues in great detail against these theses and
their ramifications, not only in the Investigations, but also in his
writings on the philosophy of mathematics. First, he points out
that names are not the fundamental type of word, contrary to what
was explicitly assumed in the Tractatus or by Russell. Words do not
fulfil only the function of naming or referring to objects. Their
meaning is their use, roughly speaking (pi §43), and they can very
well have a use without referring to anything. ‘However’, ‘phlogis-
ton’ and ‘gone with the wind’ do not stand for any kind of object,
despite having a well-established use. Russell’s analysis of ‘The
present king of France is bald’ (see chapter Two) arose out of des-
peration: since the subject-term ‘the present king of France’ does
not refer to anything, he concluded that either it is meaningless,
176
and thus the whole sentence is meaningless, or ‘the present king of
France’ is a pseudo-referring expression and the real structure of
the sentence is a totally different one, to be uncovered by logical
analysis. But once we realize that ‘the king of France’ has a perfectly
decent use whether or not it stands for anything, Russell’s problem
disappears and there is no need for his Theory of Descriptions.
Second, the act of naming is, although important, not funda-
mental. Indeed, it already presupposes mastery of a language.
177
describing, but equally fundamental, and it is a grave mistake to
try to assimilate them to the language-game of describing. The
declarative subject-predicate sentence is not the fundamental form
of proposition.
178
games, much that is common is retained, but much is lost. –
Are they all ‘amusing’? Compare chess with noughts and crosses.
Or is there always winning and losing, or competition between
players? Think of patience. In ball games there is winning and
losing; but when a child throws his ball at the wall and catches
it again, this feature has disappeared [pi §66].
179
extend our concept of number as in spinning a thread we twist
fibre on fibre. And the strength of the thread does not reside in
the fact that some one fibre runs through its whole length, but
in the overlapping of many fibres. But if someone wished to say:
‘There is something common to all these constructions – name-
ly the disjunction of all their common properties’ – I should
reply: Now you are only playing with words. One might as well
say: ‘Something runs through the whole thread – namely the
continuous overlapping of those fibres’ [pi §67].
180
historical influence. Witness for instance Locke in his Essay
Concerning Human Understanding (1690): ‘Words, in their primary
or immediate signification, stand for nothing but the ideas in the
mind of him that uses them . . . nor can anyone else apply them as
marks, immediately, to anything else but the ideas that he himself
hath’.11 Humpty Dumpty puts it in Alice in Wonderland in a more
straightforward manner: ‘When I use a word, it means just what
I choose it to mean – neither more nor less.’
Through powerful arguments Wittgenstein demonstrates not
only that our ordinary language does not function in this way,
but also that there cannot be any private language, since this is an
incoherent idea (we shall skip his arguments here). Moreover, he
attacks the idea of privacy itself and thus a pivotal assumption of
European thought, showing how it rests on a misunderstanding
of the function of psychological notions. Not only does he reject
the idea that only I know what I am feeling, but he claims that really
only other people can know what I am feeling. In other words, he
actually rejects the claim that I know at all what I am feeling! By
this, however, he does not mean that I am ignorant of my feelings
either. Rather, it does not make sense to ascribe to me knowledge
of my inner states. He demonstrates this claim by means of the
descriptive method mentioned above. In other words, instead
of taking it as basic or explaining it in terms of other concepts,
Wittgenstein draws a map of the connections between knowledge
and related concepts. For instance, he shows that knowledge is con-
nected to the possibility of evidence, doubt, error, ignorance, etc. If
these possibilities are excluded, so is knowledge. If they are included,
so is knowledge. Take a case in which I have a headache and say
‘I am in pain’ while holding my head. It would surely make sense
for you to look for evidence (my facial expression, for instance)
whether I have a headache, but also to doubt this fact, err or
be ignorant about it. Hence, it makes sense to ascribe to you the
knowledge that I am in pain. But what about myself? Well, could I
181
have a headache, but be ignorant about it and then find out about
it through evidence offered to me? What could such evidence be?
In what situation would it make sense to say of myself ‘I may be in
pain, but I doubt it’? And would it really be intelligible if I told my
doctor in all seriousness ‘Sorry, I was so sure a minute ago that I
am in pain, but I have just discovered that I am mistaken’? None of
this seems to work. The origin of the mistaken idea of privacy arises
through misunderstanding the role of statements like ‘I am in
pain’. For they look like ordinary descriptions of a state of affairs,
as in ‘I am at Marble Arch’. It is, of course, possible to find out that
or err that or doubt whether I am at Marble Arch and hence to
know that I am at Marble Arch. But for all the similarity between
‘I am at Marble Arch’ and ‘I am in pain’, the latter sentence serves
a very different function. ‘Pain’ is not the name of an inner, private
state, and the sentence therefore is not a description of an inner,
private state. Rather, ‘I am in pain’ is typically the expression or
avowal of pain.
A child has hurt himself and he cries; and then adults talk to him
and teach him exclamations and, later, sentences. They teach the
child new pain-behaviour. ‘So you are saying that the word “pain”
really means crying?’ – On the contrary: the verbal expression of
pain replaces crying and does not describe it [pi §244].
182
thoughts into a train of words’.12 Indeed, this seems to explain how
a child learns the meaning of ‘thinking’ or ‘thought’: it hears these
words, looks inside itself and whatever it finds there is what ‘think-
ing’ refers to. This conception also allows for animals and computers
to think, even though they might not have a language comparable
to ours, if any. Again, Wittgenstein argues that this model of our
cognitive life and the relation between thought and language
resulting from it is not just simplistic but deeply mistaken. In
conjuring up this model we are fixated on a certain way words
receive their meaning, namely by pointing at something and then
giving it a name, and we try to press the concept of thinking into
this schema as well. But, Wittgenstein argues, this concept is nei-
ther learned nor used in this way, and unless we look carefully at
the diverse and complex contexts in which the concept of thinking
is actually used, we will at best achieve a caricature of this concept.
‘It would be as if without knowing how to play chess, I were to try
and make out what the word “mate” meant by close observation
of the last move of some game of chess’ (pi §316). We should be
much more careful about the limited applications of the concept
of thinking. ‘We only say of a human being and what is like one
that it thinks’ (pi §360).
183
the back and so on. What is it like to say something to oneself;
what happens here? – How am I to explain it? Well, only as you
might teach someone the meaning of the expression ‘to say
something to oneself ’. And certainly we learn the meaning of
that as children. – Only no one is going to say that the person
who teaches it to us tells us ‘what takes place’ [pi §361].
184
Equally, the relation between thought and language is a very
complex one. If the translation model were correct, then our
thoughts must already be language-like, for how else could there be
a translation? Thinking would be a kind of speaking, only to one-
self, to one’s soul (an influential idea in the history of philosophy).
That would immediately open up the possibility of a person who
constantly and unintentionally mistranslates their own thoughts –
an absurdity. And would that ‘language of thought’ also have verb-
like, noun-like and preposition-like elements? How did they receive
their meaning? But if thoughts are not language-like, how are they
like? What are they made of? Let us take the thought expressed by
the following Cockney sentence: ‘Iran’s hard-line president on
Saturday inaugurated a heavy-water produckshun plant, a facility
th’ Wess fears will be used t’develop a nucular bomb, as Tehran
remained defiant ahaid of a un daidline thet c’d lead t’sanckshuns.’13
How could anybody even be able to entertain such a thought
without speaking Cockney or at least some related language?
Language is not just the clothing of thought, as Frege and the
young Wittgenstein believed, but actually a presupposition for
being able to have the articulate thoughts that we humans can
have. The limits of thought are the limits of its possible expression.
To put it in the extreme: there can be no thought without language.
If correct, this claim is of major significance for any understanding
of our mind, indeed for any anthropology. ‘We say a dog is afraid
his master will beat him; but not, he is afraid his master will beat
him tomorrow. Why not?’ (pi §650).
There are many other arguments and topics in the Philosophical
Investigations. But we get a sense of how philosophy is done in this
book and in general in Wittgenstein’s later work. It is done for the
purpose of preventing us from philosophical confusion by clarify-
ing our language. This clarification, however, is not trivial in any
way, but belongs to the most difficult intellectual activities.
185
Philosophy unravels the thoughts in our thinking; hence its
result must be simple, but its activity as complicated as the
knots it unravels . . . You ask why grammatical problems are so
tough and seemingly ineradicable. – Because they are connected
with the oldest thought habits, i.e. with the oldest images that
are engraved into our language itself . . . Human beings are
deeply embedded in philosophical, i.e. grammatical, confu-
sions. And freeing them from these presupposes extricating
them from the immensely diverse associations they are caught
up in. One must, as it were, regroup their entire language . . .
An entire mythology is laid down in our language.14
186
9
Don’t let grief vex you! You should let it into your heart. Nor
should you be afraid of madness. It comes to you perhaps as
a friend and not as an enemy, and the only thing that is bad
is your resistance . . . Think a great deal of the last time with
Francis, of my odiousness towards him. I was at that time very
unhappy; but with a wicked heart. I cannot see how I will ever in
my life be freed from this guilt.1
187
Killary Bay, Connemara, Co. Galway, c. 1890–1900, a haunt of Wittgenstein’s in
Ireland.
188
After Connemara, Wittgenstein spent most of the time between
October 1948 and June 1949 in Dublin. There he lodged in Ross’s
Hotel, content that he had a comfortable and quiet room, and was
closer to Drury. Nevertheless, there were several other trips during
this period. He visited Richards in Uxbridge a few times and also
went to Cambridge. There he completed several manuscripts and
visited Georg Henrik von Wright, a former student now successor to
his chair in philosophy and fast becoming one of the most eminent
philosophers of his generation. In September 1948 Wittgenstein
travelled for three weeks to Vienna, where his sister Hermine was
terminally ill. ‘Mining is dying’, he wrote in his diary in February
1949. ‘A great loss for me and for everyone. Greater than I thought.’
And a few weeks later: ‘The roots on which my own life depend are
being severed all around me. My soul is filled with pain. She had
many and varied talents. Not exposed to the day, but hidden. As a
person’s qualities should be.’4 He visited Vienna twice more, once
in spring 1949 and finally from December 1949 to March 1950.
Wittgenstein’s own health was failing. Having intestinal trouble,
he went through a full check-up in Dublin in May 1949 and was
diagnosed with an atypical form of anaemia. Nevertheless,
Wittgenstein decided to undertake one final journey, this time to
Ithaca in the United States. Norman Malcolm, who was teaching at
Cornell University, had invited him on repeated occasions. To one
of these invitations Wittgenstein jokingly replied that he would
accept the invitation only if Malcolm would introduce him to Betty
Hutton, Wittgenstein’s favourite actress. Wittgenstein embarked
on the Queen Mary to New York in July, travelling third class.
Insisting, to no avail, that Malcolm should not pick him up on
arrival, Wittgenstein wrote to his friend: ‘Maybe, like in the films,
I’ll find a beautiful girl whom I meet on the boat & who will help
me.’ Wittgenstein stayed with the Malcolms for three months.
Overall, he enjoyed his stay. He wrote to Rhees in Swansea:
189
Wittgenstein
with his Finnish
philosopher friend
Georg Henrik von
Wright.
There are some nice walks here though nothing compared with
the [G]ower coast. Nature here doesn’t look as natural as in
Wales. The only thing I really enjoy here is the engineering; that’s
superb. I like to see American machines. The people I’ve met
were often very nice but mostly, though not always, very foreign
to me.5
190
difficult. I was absolutely exhausted when we concluded the
discussion.6
191
a Cartesian philosopher, who first takes the sceptic’s radical doubt
seriously and then looks for true propositions, known with absolute
certainty, to counter the radical doubt. G. E. Moore, for instance,
argued that common-sense propositions like ‘This is a hand’ (while
raising his hand), ‘That’s a tree’ (while standing in front of one) or
‘The world has existed for many years’ are such absolutely certain
propositions which we can employ against the sceptic. Wittgenstein’s
answer is that in philosophical contexts these propositions do not
express any knowledge at all, but belong to our conceptual frame-
work, our world picture. Rejecting them is not like rejecting ‘Sushi is
increasingly popular in London’ or ‘Iran has peaceful intentions’,
rather it is like upsetting the entire world picture and thus the frame-
work within which the language-games of knowing and doubting
make sense at all. ‘If Moore were to pronounce the opposite of those
propositions which he declares certain, we should not just not share
his opinion: we should regard him as demented.’8 In short, what both
the sceptic and his Cartesian opponent really achieve is not radical
doubt and absolute knowledge respectively, but the dismissal of
rationality itself – not an insignificant insight in an age of far-reaching
conspiracy theories and historical revisionisms that have a lot in
common with the sceptic’s attitude to knowledge.
Wittgenstein’s discussions with Bouwsma touched on more
general issues as well. For instance, he stressed that there are some
similarities between his philosophy and psychoanalysis, in both
positive and negative respects. He thought that his teachings, like
Freud’s, had done more harm than good, seducing students to
believe in an all-solving ‘formula’. Wittgenstein also expressed his
dislike of Plato’s dialogues to Bouwsma:
192
ninnies, never have any arguments of their own, say ‘Yes’ and
‘No’ as Socrates pleases they should. They are a stupid lot.9
Dear Norman, Thanks for your letter! The doctors have now
made their diagnosis. I have cancer of the prostate. But this
sounds, in a way, much worse than it is, for there is a drug
(actually some hormones) which can, as I’m told, alleviate the
symptoms of the disease, so that I can live on for years. The
doctor even tells me that I may be able to work again, but I can’t
imagine that. I was in no way shocked when I heard I had cancer,
but I was when I heard that one could do something about it,
because I had no wish to live on. But I cou[l]dn’t have my wish.
I am treated with great kindness by every one & I have an
193
immensely kind doctor who isn’t a fool either. I think of you &
[your wife] often with gratitude . . . Affectionately, Ludwig12
194
Wittgenstein’s last
entry in his diary,
two days before
his death.
195
wanted to talk to a priest and did not wish to discuss philosoph-
ical problems. He knew he was very ill and wanted to talk about
God, I think with a view to coming back fully to his religion, but
in fact we had, I think, only two conversations on God and the
soul on rather general terms.17
196
Wittgenstein’s
grave in
Cambridge.
197
10
The Aftermath
Over the next decades many more volumes of his writings, lectures
and conversations came out. Finally in 2001 his entire Nachlass,
including facsimiles of all his manuscripts, was published in a
cd-rom version.
Up to the 1970s Wittgenstein’s influence upon the development
of philosophy was decisive, especially in Oxford, a stronghold of post-
198
war analytic philosophy, where some of his pupils and collaborators,
such as Anscombe, Toulmin and Waismann, taught side by side with
a generation of younger thinkers influenced by or sympathetic to
Wittgenstein’s works. In Cambridge he was succeeded in his chair
first by von Wright, then by John Wisdom and finally by Anscombe.
Wittgenstein’s influence spread from Britain to the rest of the English-
speaking world. In the US Norman Malcolm and Max Black trans-
formed the philosophy faculty at Cornell into one of the leading
departments in the country. Erik Stenius, Georg Henrik von Wright
and Jaakko Hintikka ensured the transmission of his ideas in
Scandinavia. On the Continent interest in his work arose more slowly,
partly due to lack of interest in analytic philosophy and the influence
of other philosophers, such as Husserl and Heidegger. His work was
also well received in Asia, particularly in Japan and more recently in
China. At the time of his greatest influence in the Anglo-Saxon world
many branches of philosophy were affected by his work, including
some about which he had written little to nothing, such as the
philosophy of the social sciences and moral, legal and political
philosophy. His strongest impact, however, affected the core
disciplines of theoretical philosophy, especially philosophy of logic,
language and mind (not, however, philosophy of mathematics). His
conception of philosophy as a non-scientific linguistic investigation
of our conceptual framework was also influential. In those days
there was an assumption among his supporters that armed with
Wittgenstein’s method one could finally get down to business and
solve the great problems of philosophy. As Anthony Kenny has put
it in retrospect, they ‘had imagined that once his philosophical ideas
had been absorbed, thinkers in various disciplines would begin to
apply them, with beneficial effect, to work in their own field’.2
Ironically, however, just when Wittgenstein’s oeuvre became
more and more accessible, the influence of his ideas declined
among academic philosophers. The most important reason for this
is the fact that his ideas were submerged by the rise of new meta-
199
physics and scientifically inspired philosophy, which emanated
particularly strongly from the US, where philosophers such as
Willard van Orman Quine, Donald Davidson, David Lewis, Saul
Aaron Kripke and Noam Chomsky were active. Equally important
for the development of Anglo-American philosophy was the
emergence of new scientific disciplines such as computer science,
molecular and evolutionary biology, neuroscience and cognitive
psychology. It is likely that Wittgenstein would have perceived
such scientification of philosophy as symptomatic of the malaise
of modernity. He once said to Drury: ‘My type of thinking is not
wanted in this present age; I have to swim so strongly against the
tide. Perhaps in a hundred years people will really want what I am
writing.’3 The future will tell. To be sure, the Tractatus and the
Investigations are today regarded as classics. In a 1998 poll among
professional philosophers, Wittgenstein was ranked fifth among
the all-time greats, after Aristotle, Plato, Kant and Nietzsche, and
ahead of Hume and Descartes. And another poll, conducted in
2000, resulted in the Philosophical Investigations being voted as
the most important philosophical work of the twentieth century,
with the Tractatus ranking as fourth. But nominal popularity does
not mean philosophical dominance. On the contrary: a glance at
the leading philosophy journals will show that his philosophy,
particularly his later philosophy, is today being marginalized.
In the light of the 10,000 books and articles published on
Wittgenstein by the end of the twentieth century such claims may
seem implausible. After all, Wittgenstein’s works need to be edited
and interpreted just as much as, for instance, Aristotle’s or Kant’s
works. But the ‘Wittgenstein industry’ goes beyond what is necessary
and almost obscures access to Wittgenstein’s thought by producing
countless competing interpretations, philological debates, new
‘readings’, introductions, textbooks for students, collections of
papers, conference proceedings, dissertations, etc. This industry pro-
duces with remarkable regularity titles such as The New Wittgenstein,
200
Wittgenstein’s Poker, Wittgenstein’s Ladder, The Third Wittgenstein,
Wittgenstein in 90 Minutes, Wittgenstein Flies a Kite, etc. Looking at
this scholastic output, one sometimes gets the impression that it is
diametrically opposed to what Wittgenstein hoped to achieve. For
he surely did not want to create a branch of specialists writing about
him and his works, but to revolutionize philosophy itself.
However, the fact that Wittgenstein scholarship is flourishing,
while Wittgensteinian philosophy has withered, may also be due
to the problem ‘of seeing clearly what the author’s views are’, as
Strawson put it in the review mentioned above. For a major difficulty
with Wittgenstein’s work lies in the unusual character of his writ-
ings, which invite conflicting readings and endless controversies. We
may wonder whether Wittgenstein’s attitude to philosophical prose,
the intrusion of aesthetic criteria into his discourse, has not been
detrimental to the reception of his work. It is noteworthy that he
was himself more critical of his style than some of his contemporary
supporters, as a sequence of remarks from the 1940s demonstrates.
In 1941 he wrote in his diary ‘My style is like bad musical composi-
tion’, while in 1945 he admitted in the Preface to the Philosophical
Investigations that the best that he could write would never be more
than philosophical remarks. In 1948 he noted down a striking simile:
Raisins may be the best part of a cake; but a bag of raisins is not
better than a cake; & someone who is in a position to give us a
bag full of raisins still cannot bake a cake with them, let alone
do something better. I am thinking of Kraus & his aphorisms,
but of myself too & my philosophical remarks. A cake is not as
it were: thinned out raisins.4
201
The opening page
from Elizabeth
Lutyens’s piece
of 1952–3 for
unaccompanied
voices, Motet
Excerpta Tractati
Logico-Philosophici
(known as the
‘Wittgenstein
Motet’).
202
So much for Wittgenstein’s standing within academic philoso-
phy at present. Like Freud’s, however, Wittgenstein’s impact
reached far beyond academia. Already a legend in his own lifetime,
in the age of pop culture Wittgenstein has become almost a pop
star, ‘the thinking man’s hero’, as a television programme put it.
A motet based on the Tractatus was composed by Elizabeth Lutyens
and a Tractatus Suite by M. A. Numminem. Eduardo Paolozzi
etched a set of prints entitled ‘Wittgenstein in New York’, while
Derek Jarman directed the successful film Wittgenstein, based on
a script by Terry Eagleton. Several novels inspired by his life were
published, such as Wittgenstein’s Nephew by the congenial Austrian
writer Thomas Bernard, Malina by the equally congenial Austrian
poet Ingeborg Bachmann (who also lectured on Wittgenstein and
Heidegger) and The World as I Found It by Bruce Duffy. Moreover,
the sibylline remarks of the Tractatus, especially those on ethics,
and the numerous striking aphorisms from his later period have
appealed to a wide audience and are often quoted. Alas, they are
rarely understood, given that they are mostly not self-sufficient
aphorisms, but the rhetorical tips of a vast iceberg of systematic
thought. More recently, Wittgenstein has been also portrayed as
a postmodernist, a relativist, a poet (or even as a Pyrrhonist, Zen-
Buddhist or rabbinical thinker). These are strange interpretations
of a man who towards the end of his life said that his chief contri-
bution had been in the philosophy of mathematics:6 a man who in
his youth vowed that he did not intend ‘to prove this and that, but
to find out how things really are’7 and who later said: ‘I know my
method is right. My father was a businessman, and I am a business
man: I want my philosophy to be businesslike, to get something
done, to get something settled.’8 All this does not square well with
postmodernist wariness, insecurity and quietism.
Nevertheless, there is something understandable about the
popular fascination with Wittgenstein, the alluring archetype of
a tormented thinker.
203
From time to time in our culture, literary and artistic figures
become objects of veneration in circles far wider than the reach
of their works. Their lives are held to be of deeper significance
than the mere fascination of their biography. Their travails and
their intellectual and spiritual strivings are inchoately sensed to
incorporate and to represent the deepest tensions and conflicts
within the culture of their times. So, perhaps, it has been with
Ludwig Wittgenstein.9
204
Karl Johnson in the title role of Derek Jarman’s 1983 film Wittgenstein, shown
in a cage – with a parrot in another cage.
References
1 For more, see E. Timms, Karl Kraus: Apocalyptic Satirist. Culture and
Catastrophe in Habsburg Vienna (New Haven, ct, and London, 1986),
pp. 3–39.
2 U. Weinzierl, ‘Der Fluch des Hauses Wittgenstein’, Die Welt (5 July 2003).
3 R. Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London, 1990), p. 13.
This is based on what Wittgenstein had told Rush Rhees, who in turn
told it to Ray Monk.
4 B. McGuinness, Young Ludwig: Wittgenstein’s Life, 1889–1921 (Oxford,
2005), p. 26.
5 M. Nedo and M. Ranchetti, Wittgenstein: Sein Leben in Bildern und Texten
(Frankfurt, 1983), p. 54.
6 M. Drury, ‘Conversations with Wittgenstein’, in Ludwig Wittgenstein:
Personal Recollections, ed. R. Rhees (Oxford, 1981), p. 27.
7 K. Cornish, The Jew of Linz (London, 1998).
8 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 15.
9 See B. Hamann, Hitler’s Vienna: A Dictator’s Apprenticeship (Oxford,
1999).
10 Rhees, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 2.
11 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 16.
12 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, pp. 47–8.
13 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 498.
14 Ibid., p. 78.
15 Ibid., p. 23.
16 Ibid., pp. 23ff.
17 Drury, ‘Conversations with Wittgenstein’, in Rhees, Ludwig Wittgenstein,
p. 106.
206
18 O. Weininger, Sex and Character (London, 1906), p. 147.
19 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, p. 54.
207
23 L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Occasions (Indianapolis, in, 1993),
pp. 2–3.
24 For Wittgenstein’s relation to Norway, see K. S. Johannessen,
R. Larsen and K. O. Åmås, Wittgenstein and Norway (Oslo, 1994).
25 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 86.
26 L. Wittgenstein, Cambridge Letters, ed. B. McGuiness and G. H. von
Wright (Oxford, 1995).
27 Letter to Lucy Mary Donnelly, 19 October 1913; McGuinness, Young
Ludwig, p. 184.
28 Goodstein, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophy and Language, ed.
A. Ambrose and M. Lazerowitz (London, 1972), pp. 271–2.
29 L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (Oxford, 1980), p. 87e.
30 Letter to Russell, presumably December 1913, in Wittgenstein,
Cambridge Letters.
31 Letter to Russell, January 1914, ibid.
32 Letter to Russell, February 1914, ibid.
33 Letter to Moore, 7 May 1914, ibid.
34 Constantin Noica (1909–1987), Romanian philosopher. See G. Liiceanu,
The Paltinis Diary (Budapest, 2000).
35 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 107.
36 Letter to Ficker, 13 February 1915, ibid., p. 110.
37 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, p. 209.
38 A. Sarnitz, Adolf Loos (London, 2003).
208
9 ms 103, 30 March 1916.
10 ms 103, 11 June 1916.
11 ms 103, 6 July 1916.
12 ms 103, 30 July 1916.
13 ms 103, 28 August 1916.
14 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, p. 242.
15 Ibid., p. 252.
16 ms 103, 7 October 1916. Sub specie aeternitatis means ‘under the aspect
of eternity’.
17 B. McGuinness, Approaches to Wittgenstein: Collected Papers (London,
2002), p. 34.
18 Ibid., pp. 34–5.
19 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, p. 263.
20 Ibid., p. 264.
21 ms 102, 16 March 1915.
209
5 The Wilderness Years, 1918–29
210
sold for £75,000.
23 See J. Hintikka, On Wittgenstein (Belmont, ca, 2000).
24 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 235.
25 Funnily enough, companies now sell door handles à la Wittgenstein.
26 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 236.
27 See B. Leitner, The Wittgenstein House (New York, 2000); H. Eakin, ‘In
Vienna, a New View of Wittgenstein Home’, New York Times (28 August
2003).
28 L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (Oxford, 1980), pp. 37e–38e.
29 ‘Architekturzentrum Wien’, www.nextroom.at/building_article.
php?building_id=2338&article_id=2967 (accessed June 2006). See also
Leitner, The Wittgenstein House, for this reading.
30 See W. Wang, ‘The Wittgenstein House – Review’, Architectural Review
(September 2001); P. Wijdeveld, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Architect (London,
1994).
31 Letter to Margarete, September 1949; quoted in Wang, ‘The
Wittgenstein House’.
32 L. Wittgenstein, Public and Private Occasions (Lanham, md, 2003), p. 25.
33 Ibid., pp. 33–4.
34 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 318.
35 Ibid., p. 339.
36 Ibid., p. 239.
37 Ibid., p. 314.
38 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, pp. 18e–19e.
39 Ibid., p. 13e.
40 N. Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (Oxford, 2001), p. 35.
41 See Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, pp. 316–17.
42 McGuinness, Young Ludwig, pp. 48–9.
43 D. Stern, ‘The Significance of Jewishness for Wittgenstein’s Philosophy’,
Inquiry, xliii (2000), p. 398. See also Stern, ‘Was Wittgenstein a Jew?’, in
Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy, ed. J. Klagge (Cambridge, 2001).
211
3 Ibid., p. 56e.
4 M. Heidegger, Introduction to Metaphysics (New Haven, ct, and London,
2000), pp. 40–41.
5 M. Heidegger, Being and Time (Oxford, 1962), pp. 230–31.
6 Wittgenstein quoted in F. Waismann, Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle:
Conversations (Oxford, 1979), p. 68.
7 R. Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London, 1990), p. 271.
8 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 17e.
9 N. Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (Oxford, 2001), pp. 57–8.
10 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 256.
11 Both letters from 12 March 1933; Ludwig Wittgenstein: Briefwechsel
(Innsbruck, 2004).
12 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 263.
13 Ibid., p. 262.
14 Ibid., p. 263.
15 M. Midgley, The Owl of Minerva: A Memoir (London, 2005).
16 K. T. Fann, ed., Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Man and His Philosophy
(New York, 1967), p. 67.
17 L. Wittgenstein, ‘Lecture on Ethics’, in Philosophical Occasions
(Indianapolis, in, 1993), pp. 42ff.
18 B. Russell, Autobiography (London, 2000), p. 440.
19 Wittgenstein’s exchanges with Turing are recorded in L. Wittgenstein,
Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939 (Ithaca,
ny, 1976).
20 V. Mehta, Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounters with British Intellectuals
(Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 52.
21 Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 25.
22 Ibid., p. 26.
23 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 57e.
24 L. Wittgenstein, Public and Private Occasions (Lanham, md, 2003),
p. 31.
25 F. Waismann, Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations
(Oxford, 1979), p. 26.
26 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Occasions, p. 119.
27 Ibid., pp. 123, 125, 131.
28 Letter to Wittgenstein, 20 October 1933, in Wittgenstein, Briefwechsel.
29 Letter to Wittgenstein, 6 December 1936, in Wittgenstein, Briefwechsel.
212
30 Only one such encounter is mentioned, in ms 118, 22 September
1937.
31 ms 120, 2 December 1937.
32 See Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Appendix.
33 ms 133, 26 October 1946.
34 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 427.
35 ms 125, 28 December 1941.
36 ms 133, 10 November 1946.
37 See Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 342.
38 R. Rhees, ed., Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections (Oxford, 1981),
p. 35.
39 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 6e.
40 M. Heidegger, Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universität (Frankfurt,
1982), p. 25.
41 One of his students, Casimir Lewy, is said to have described
Wittgenstein as politically naïve.
42 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 353.
43 R. Rhees, ed., Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections (Oxford, 1981),
p. 158.
44 M. Amis, Koba the Dread: Laughter and the Twenty Million (London,
2002), p. 21.
45 See K. S. Johannessen, R. Larsen and K. O. Åmås, Wittgenstein and
Norway (Oslo, 1994).
46 ms 183, 19 February 1937.
47 ms 120, 12 December 1937.
48 See L. Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology
and Religious Belief (Oxford, 1966), on these lectures.
49 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 85e.
50 Wittgenstein, Public and Private Occasions, p. 211.
51 Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations, p. 56.
52 Wittgenstein, Public and Private Occasions, p. 203.
53 Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations, p. 70.
54 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 86e.
55 M. Drury, ‘Conversations with Wittgenstein’, in Rhees, Ludwig
Wittgenstein, p. 79.
213
7 Professorship and Wartime, 1939–47
214
Wittgenstein on Freud, see J. Bouveresse, Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The
Myth of the Unconscious (Princeton, nj, 1995).
21 Helen Andrews to Ray Monk; see Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein,
pp. 449–50.
22 N. Bachtin, Lectures and Essays (Birmingham, 1963).
23 Rhees, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 28.
24 See his essay ‘Aristotle versus Plato’ in Bachtin, Lectures and Essays.
25 See T. Eagleton, ‘Wittgenstein’s Friends’, New Left Review, i/35 (1982).
26 L. Wittgenstein, Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge,
1939 (Ithaca, ny, 1976), p. 15.
27 Today the university hosts a Centre for Wittgensteinian Studies
and edits a journal dedicated to the philosopher, Philosophical
Investigations.
28 See also his Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology and Last Writings on
the Philosophy of Psychology, posthumously published in four volumes.
29 Letter to Malcolm, 15 December 1945.
30 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 463.
31 Ibid.
32 Letter to Malcolm, 20 September 1945; Wittgenstein, Briefwechsel.
33 B. McGuinness, Approaches to Wittgenstein: Collected Papers (London,
2002), p. 51.
34 Letter to Malcolm, around 20 August 1945.
35 Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 480.
36 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, pp. 48e–49e.
37 Currently, Wittgenstein’s diary entries are the only source of informa-
tion about the relationship. There are twenty letters from Richards to
Wittgenstein deposited in the Austrian National Library, but they will
not be accessible until 2020.
38 ms 131, 14 August 1946.
39 ms 130, 22 July 1946.
40 Rhees, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 162; Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein, pp. 453–4.
41 ms 132, 30 September 1946.
42 N. Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (Oxford, 2001), p. 56.
43 O. P. Wood and G. Pitcher, eds, Ryle (London, 1970), p. 11.
44 Letter to Malcolm, 16 November 1947; Wittgenstein, Briefwechsel.
215
8 Nothing is Hidden: Philosophical Investigations
216
9 The Last Years, 1947–51
10 The Aftermath
217
2 A. Kenny, Wittgenstein (Oxford, 2005), p. xii.
3 R. Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London 1990), p. 486.
4 L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (Oxford, 1980), p. 66e.
5 For two conflicting views on this issue, see G. H. von Wright, The Tree of
Knowledge and Other Essays (Leiden, 1993), and H.-J. Glock, ‘Was
Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?’, Metaphilosophy, xxxv/4 (2004).
6 See R. Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London 1990),
p. 466.
7 B. McGuinness, Young Ludwig: Wittgenstein’s Life, 1889–1921 (Oxford,
2005), p. 100.
8 R. Rhees, ed., Recollections of Wittgenstein (Oxford, 1984), pp. 125–6.
9 P. Hacker, ‘Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann (1889–1951)’, Oxford
Dictionary of National Biography (Oxford, 2004).
10 Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, p. 46e.
218
Bibliography
Secondary literature
‘Architekturzentrum Wien’,
www.nextroom.at/building_article.php?building_id=2338&article_id=2967
(accessed June 2006)
Ambrose, A., Essays in Analysis (London, 1966)
219
––, and M. Lazerowitz, eds, Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophy and Language
(London, 1972)
Amis, M., Koba the Dread: Laughter and the Twenty Million (London, 2002)
Anscombe, E., and P. Geach, Three Philosophers (Oxford, 1967)
Bachtin, N., Lectures and Essays (Birmingham, 1963)
Baker, G., and P. Hacker, An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical
Investigations, 4 vols (Oxford, 1980–96)
Bartley, W. W., Wittgenstein, iii (La Salle, il, 1986)
Berlin, I., Russian Thinkers (London, 1979)
Bouveresse, J., Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The Myth of the Unconscious
(Princeton, nj, 1995)
Bouwsma, O. K., Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949–1951 (Indianapolis, in, 1986)
Brod, M., Franz Kafka: A Biography (New York, 1995)
Cornish, K., The Jew of Linz (London, 1998)
Drury, M., ‘Conversations with Wittgenstein’, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal
Recollections, ed. R. Rhees (Oxford, 1981)
Eagleton, T., ‘Wittgenstein’s Friends’, New Left Review, i/35 (1982)
––, ‘Introduction to Wittgenstein’, in Wittgenstein: The Terry Eagleton Script;
The Derek Jarman Film (Worcester, ma, 1993)
Eakin, H., ‘In Vienna, a New View of Wittgenstein Home’, New York Times,
28 August 2003
Engelmann, P., Letters from Ludwig Wittgenstein with a Memoir (Oxford, 1967)
Fann, K. T., ed., Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Man and His Philosophy (New York,
1967)
Gasking, D.A.T., and A. C. Jackson, ‘Wittgenstein as a Teacher’, in Ludwig
Wittgenstein: The Man and His Philosophy, ed. K. T. Fann (New York 1967)
Glock, H.-J., A Wittgenstein Dictionary (Oxford, 1996)
––, ‘Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?’, Metaphilosophy, xxxv/4
(2004)
Hacker, P., Wittgenstein’s Place in Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy
(Oxford, 1996)
––, Insight and Illusion (Bristol, 1997)
––, ‘Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann (1889–1951)’, Oxford Dictionary of
National Biography (Oxford, 2004)
––, ‘Gordon Baker’s Late Interpretation of Wittgenstein’, in Wittgenstein and
His Interpreters, ed. G. Kahane, E. Kanterian and O. Kuusela
(forthcoming)
220
Hamann, B., Hitler’s Vienna: A Dictator’s Apprenticeship (Oxford, 1999)
Hargrove, E. C., ‘Wittgenstein, Bartley, and the Glöckel School Reform’,
Journal of the History of Philosophy, xviii (1980)
Heidegger, M., Being and Time (Oxford, 1962)
––, Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universität (Frankfurt, 1982)
––, Introduction to Metaphysics (New Haven, ct, 2000)
Hertz, H. R., The Principles of Mechanics (London, 1899)
Hintikka, J., On Wittgenstein (Belmont, ca, 2000)
Janik, A., and S. Toulmin, Wittgenstein’s Vienna (New York, 1973)
Johannessen, K. S., R. Larsen and K. O. Åmås, Wittgenstein and Norway (Oslo,
1994)
Kahane, G., E. Kanterian and O. Kuusela, eds, Wittgenstein and His Interpreters
(forthcoming)
Kenny, A., Wittgenstein (Oxford, 2005)
Klagge, J., ed., Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy (Cambridge, 2001)
Leitner, B., The Wittgenstein House (New York, 2000)
Liiceanu, G., The Paltinis Diary (Budapest, 2000)
McGuinness, B., Approaches to Wittgenstein: Collected Papers (London, 2002)
––, Young Ludwig: Wittgenstein’s Life, 1889–1921 (Oxford, 2005)
Malcolm, N., A Religious Point of View? (London, 1993)
––, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (Oxford, 2001)
Mehta, V., Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounters with British Intellectuals
(Harmondsworth, 1965)
Midgley, M., The Owl of Minerva: A Memoir (London, 2005)
Monk, R., Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London, 1990)
Nedo, M., and M. Ranchetti, Wittgenstein: Sein Leben in Bildern und Texten
(Frankfurt, 1983)
Pascal, F., ‘Wittgenstein: A Personal Memoir’, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal
Recollections, ed. R. Rhees (Oxford, 1981)
Pears, D., The False Prison: A Study of the Development of Wittgenstein’s
Philosophy (Oxford, 1987–8)
Perloff, M., Wittgenstein’s Ladder: Poetic Language and the Strangeness of the
Ordinary (Chicago, il, 1996)
Redpath, T., Wittgenstein: A Student’s Memoir (London, 1990)
Rhees, R., ed., Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections (Oxford, 1981)
––, Recollections of Wittgenstein (Oxford, 1984)
Rozema, D., ‘Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: A “Poem” by Ludwig
221
Wittgenstein’, Journal of the History of Ideas, lxiii/2 (2002)
Russell, B., Autobiography (London, 2000)
Sarnitz, A., Adolf Loos (London, 2003)
Schroeder, S., Wittgenstein: The Way out of the Fly-Bottle (Cambridge, 2006)
Stern, D., ‘The Significance of Jewishness for Wittgenstein’s Philosophy’,
Inquiry, xliii (2000)
––, ‘Was Wittgenstein a Jew?’, in Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy,
ed. J. Klagge (Cambridge, 2001)
Strawson, P. F., Freedom and Resentment, and Other Essays (London, 1974)
Timms, E., Karl Kraus: Apocalyptic Satirist: Culture and Catastrophe in Habsburg
Vienna (New Haven, ct, and London 1986)
Waismann, F., Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations (Oxford, 1979)
––, The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy (Basingstoke, 1997)
Wall, R., Wittgenstein in Ireland (London, 2000)
Wang, W., ‘The Wittgenstein House – Review’, Architectural Review
(September 2001)
Weininger, O., Sex and Character (London, 1906)
Weinzierl, U., ‘Der Fluch des Hauses Wittgenstein’, Die Welt, 5 July 2003
Wijdeveld, P., Ludwig Wittgenstein, Architect (London, 1994)
Wilson, C., The Misfits: A Study of Sexual Outsiders (London, 1988)
Wittgenstein, H., ‘Recollections’ (1948), unpublished
––, ‘My Brother Ludwig’, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections,
ed. R. Rhees (Oxford, 1981)
Wood, O. P., and G. Pitcher, eds, Ryle (London, 1970)
Wright, G. H. von, The Tree of Knowledge and Other Essays (Leiden, 1993)
Websites
222
Acknowledgements
223