Zhu Xi, Moral World and Ethical
Zhu Xi, Moral World and Ethical
Zhu Xi, Moral World and Ethical
Onto-Cosmology as Onto-Morality
whole. This relatedness gains more power when viewed from the
human perspective, the only perspective we have. In other words,
humanity has the ontological status of reality itself, and as such serves
as the justification for human moral action and reasoning, for both
explanatory purposes (via an onto-epistemological perspective) and
practical purposes (via an onto-cosmological perspective). This article
focuses on the onto-cosmological perspective. I focus on Zhou Dunyi
(1017–1073) and Zhu Xi (1130–1200) as key figures in the revival of
Song Confucianism.
The proposed suggestion sheds light on well-known concepts and
on the work of commentators whose philosophy is basically a philos-
ophy of setting terms for ideas rooted in early Confucianism. Neo-
Confucianism is presented in this article as having the sophistication
of tools and ideas for revisiting Confucian views in a way that
strengthens them. The great significance of this feature of Neo-
Confucianism is, however, moral. Before moving on, I would like to
quote Lionel Trilling, who expresses a similar sentiment regarding the
place of “new elements” in a moral system:
Now and then it is possible to observe the moral life in process of
revising itself, perhaps by reducing the emphasis it formerly placed
upon one or another of its elements, perhaps by inventing and adding
itself a new element, some mode of conduct or of feeling which hith-
erto it had not regarded as essential to virtue.2
Humanity is Origination
Heaven uses yang to produce the myriad things and uses yin to
complete the myriad things. To produce is humanity, to complete is
rightness.5
Natural order uses yang for production and yin for completion; in
human beings, accordingly, production is humanity, and completion is
rightness. When Zhu Xi comments on these words, he chooses to
guide the reader to Zhou’s first philosophical treatise, Taijitu shuo, in
which the focus is the idea of the Great Ultimate and its productiv-
ity in the human world. Through a brief and yet concise reference to
major cosmological terms as aspects of one enduring cosmological
process, Zhou provides us with a Confucian picture that illuminates
the significance of the Great Ultimate in the human realm. Zhou
opens the treatise by maintaining that it is the Great Ultimate\ Non-
ultimate (Taiji er wuji), which generates the world by yin-yang’s tran-
quility (jing) and motion (dong). This movement brings about the five
phases (wu xing): water, fire, wood, metal, and earth. These five, being
ultimately the one vital energy (qi), generate harmony and natural
order. In their integration, Qian (Heaven) and Kun (Earth) consti-
tute male and female, whose interaction produces the myriad of
things.
As one can easily see, the subject matter in Taijitu shuo is the
continuity of evolution from the Great Ultimate to all things, and
in particular to human beings. The five cardinal human virtues
(wuchang)—humanity, rightness, propriety, knowledge, and trust
(xin)—are thus explained in this context as one of the aspects of the
five phases, and hence, as a natural product of the Great Ultimate.
The Great Ultimate and the five phases are manifest in us in a way
such that among the myriad things, human beings receive the five
phases in their most complete form as moral virtues. The sage is the
ultimate human model for the attainment of the phases as virtues and
is in perfect harmony with the natural order.
The sense of humanity as origination of a creative process is intrin-
sically related to the central role of benti in Confucianism. Cheng
Chung-ying devoted much time in a comprehensive study, explaining
and illuminating the “most fundamental, most creative term in
Chinese metaphysics, namely the concept of benti (origin-substance,
source substance, originating body, originating substance, fundamen-
tal/original/ultimate reality).”6 Cheng sees the notion of benti, rather
than the notion of Being as the ontological, and as such the ontologi-
cal unifies the base, foundation, and substance (ti), together with
origin and ultimate source (ben). In this way the cosmological in
Chinese philosophy is “ontologicalized.” With this understanding, the
cosmological cannot be put aside as an aspect of the world separate
from other aspects; specifically, it is not separate from the ontologi-
352 galia patt-shamir
example, the justification for one’s giving money to the poor (as a spe-
cific function) is that a moral judgment is inherent in our being, we
are creatures for whom “being in need” and “giving” are innate and
constitutive. In the same way that everything has a shape and a size,
so it has a moral value. Exactly in the way that when I see a chair I
know it as having a certain color, a certain shape legs, and a surface
to sit on, I also know it as something that can be offered to an elderly
person when necessary. The moral quality is innate not just in us but
in objects in the world, in the same way that other object properties
are innate (this also touches an epistemological aspect).19 In this sense
“the substance” of humanity has to be understood, and can only be
understood as enfolding moral-practical significance. It cannot have
reference otherwise.
As for the virtuous way being high and deep, enlightening people
through education without end, and being truly equal with Heaven
and Earth and the four seasons—who else is like that except for
Confucius?21
We read earlier that the Great Ultimate is not only humanity but
also human. In this passage, however, Zhou makes certain that it is
not merely a unidirectional relationship. Zhu Xi completes the iden-
tification in commenting on Zhou’s passage that a single person is the
Great Ultimate:
One whose way is as high as Heaven is yang. One whose virtue is
as profound as Earth is yin. One whose teaching is without end
like the four seasons is the five phases. Confucius must be the Great
Ultimate.22
Regarding Application
From this point on, from the fall of this woman and his undoing,
Clemence is going through his own fall. In the end of the story he
begs:
O young woman, throw yourself into the water again so that I may
a second time have the chance of saving both of us.
The desperate cry for the woman to fall again is in the present
context an example for the horrific absurdity that can be the outcome
358 galia patt-shamir
TEL-AVIV UNIVERSITY
Tel-Aviv, Israel
Endnotes
1. Countless thanks to Prof. Cheng Chung-ying for his invaluable comments on this
article, which helped me in focusing, improving, and reshaping my ideas.
2. Trilling, p. 1.
3. Renshuo, pp. 720–721; see Chan (1963), pp. 593–594.
4. Ibid.
5. Tongshu I.11.1.
6. Cheng Chung-ying (2002), p. 148.
7. Cheng (1989), pp. 174–175.
8. Cheng (2002), p. 152.
9. Zhouzi quanshu, ch. 1–2, pp. 4–32. Chan’s translation; Chan (1963), pp. 463–464.
10. Mou uses the notions “immanence” and “transcendence”. See, Mou, p. 20. For a full
discussion on the dual process, see Lin, pp. 405–416.
11. Lin, p. 419.
12. Mou, p. 21.
13. Tang in Lancashire, p. 49.
14. The Chinese character ti refers initially to “body,” in the verb form “to physically
contain” or “to embody,” and in philosophical discussion it can best be translated as
“substance.” The character ti contains the phonetic li_ “ritual vase,” which etymolog-
ically relates the word with the connotation of “organic form.” For an elaborate expli-
cation of the full sense of ti, see Cheng (2002), pp. 145–147.
15. Cheng (2002), p. 147.
16. Cheng (2002), p. 153.
17. The major gap is between the “dualistic” (or “school of principle,” lixue) and the
“monistic” (“school of the mind,” xinxue) schools. For the various positions toward
substance and function, see Chan (1963), pp. 485–489, 596–597, 696–697.
360 galia patt-shamir
References
*Classical texts: Lunyu, Mengzi, Zhongyong, Taijitu shuo (Zhou Dunyi), Tongshu (Zhou
Dunyi), Zhuzi yulei (Zhu X), Zhuzi juanshu (Zhu X).
Adler, Joseph A. “Chou Tun-I and Moral Responsiveness: Confucian Resources for
Environmental Ethics.” In Confucianism and Ecology—The Interrelation of Heaven,
Earth, and Humans (Religions of the World and Ecology), edited by Mary Evelyn
Tucker and John H. Berthrong. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.
Berthrong, John. “Chu Hsi’s Ethics: ‘Jen’ and ‘Ch’eng.’ ” Journal of Chinese Philosophy
14 (June 1987): 161–178.
——. “Master Chu’s Self-Realization: The Role of Ch’eng.” Philosophy East and West 43,
no. 1 (1993): 39–64.
Camus, Albert. The Fall. Translated by Justin O’Brien. New York: Vintage Books, 1956.
Chan, Wing-tsit. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1963.
——. Reflections on Things at Hand, the Neo-Confucian Anthology. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1967.
——. Chu Hsi and Neo-Confucianism. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1986.
——. Chu Hsi, Life and Thought. Hong Kong: Chinese University Press, 1987.
Chang, Carsun. The Development of Neo-Confucian Thought. New Haven, CT: College
and University Press, 1963.
Cheng, Chung-ying. “Chinese Metaphysics as Non-Metaphysics.” In: Understanding the
Chinese Mind, Allinson, R. E. (ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
——. New Dimension of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press, 1991.
moral world, ethical terminology 361
Chinese Glossary
ben Mengzi
benti Mou Zhongsan
bianhua qi
Cheng Qian
dao ren
dong Renshuo
heng Song
Jiazhi benti Taiji
jing Taiji er wuji
Kongzi Taijitu shuo
Kun ti
li Tongshu
li1 tiyong heyi
2
li wuchang
3
li wuxing
Lixue Xianzhu ren, zangzhu yong
Lunyu
362 galia patt-shamir
Xici yong
xin yuan
1
xin Yulei
xingti zhen
xinti zhi
Xinxue Zhongyong
yi Zhou Dunyi
1
yi Zhouzi quanshu
yinyang Zhu Xi
yiyin yiyang ziran
Yizhuan