The Nature of Agriculture (I) : Joseph B. Mcdonald
The Nature of Agriculture (I) : Joseph B. Mcdonald
The Nature of Agriculture (I) : Joseph B. Mcdonald
2020 11:41
URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1019966ar
DOI : https://doi.org/10.7202/1019966ar
Éditeur(s)
Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval
ISSN
0023-9054 (imprimé)
1703-8804 (numérique)
Découvrir la revue
Tous droits réservés © Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval, Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d’auteur. L’utilisation des
1958 services d’Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique
d’utilisation que vous pouvez consulter en ligne.
https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/
the first place, freely offers to those that labor, all things necessary to the
life of man ; and as if that were not enough, makes further contribution
of a thousand luxuries . . .
Yet she suffers not her gifts to be received effeminately, but inures her
pensioners to suffer gladly, summer’s heat and winter’s cold . . .
For myself, I marvel greatly if it has ever fallen to the lot of freeborn
man to own a choicer possession or to discover an occupation more seductive,
or of wider usefulness than th is. . . But furthermore earth, of her own
will gives lessons in justice and uprightness to all who can understand her
meaning, since the nobler the service of devotion rendered, the ampler the
riches of her recompense. One day perhaps, these pupils of her whose
conversation in times past was in husbandry, shall by reason of the mul
titude of invading armies be ousted from their labors. The work of their
hands may indeed be snatched from them, but they were brought up in a
stout and manly fashion. They stand, each one of them in body and soul
equipped ; and save God himself shall hinder them, they will march into
the territory of those their human hinderers, and take from them the
wherewithal to support themselves.
But there is another lesson to be learned in the public school of hus
bandry — the lesson of mutual assistance. “ Shoulder to shoulder ” we
march to meet the invader ; “ shoulder to shoulder ” stand to compass
the tillage of the soil. . .
It was an excellent saying of his who named hunbandry the “ mother
and nurse of the arts ” for while agriculture prospers all other arts are
vigourous and strong, but when the land is forced to remain desert the
spring that feeds the other arts is dried up ; they dwindle, I had almost
said one and all, by land and sea.1
1. S o b o k i n , Z i m m e r m a n a n d G a l p i n , op. cit., p p .3 7 - 3 9 .
TH E N ATURE OF AGRICULTURE 189
of tilling the earth, the art of sowing. These experiences had been handed
down from his forefathers from time immemorial. Other rules did not
exist ; experience alone was his guide. From observation and tradition
the farmers were able to use the course of nature as an almanac with signs
and symbols. . . . This instinctive certainty of the old time farmer prompt
ed him to take the necessary measures at the right moment by observing
nature’s course. This instinct has been lost. An uncertainty has arisen
and now the successful neighbor is often the only guide for the farmer’s work.
Scientific agriculture has decidedly altered the way of ancient peasan
try. It has told the farmer to abandon his old superstitions ; that he
can obtain better results by turning his fields into a growth factory. The
economic development of the 20th century has transformed the farmer
into the agriculturist who has to calculate costs and output. Concepts
such as “ profitableness ” born of the decline of the old agricultural tradi
tion, have become his “ daily bread ” . . .
Although the farmer was told that by means of scientific methods
he could double his yield, the fact remains that after years of scientific
help, present century farmers are discovering that their “ double yields ”
today are no better than the single yields of previous years .. .
Unfortunately modern science has developed no exact rules to take
the place of the old farming wisdom . . . The farmer has constantly to
complain of the uncertainty of his crops. . . .
Development, under the pressure of profitableness has forced him to
resort to the use of machinery to replace the more expensive hand labor . . .
The machine age has brought great changes to the work of the men whose
business it is to till the soil. It has created the “ growth mechanic ” type
of farmer. This age has also seen the ever increasing use of mineral ferti
lizers . . . The situation today shows that while in comparison with the
time prior to the war, three times as much nitrogen is being used, the
average yield per acre has not increased. In some areas it has actually
decreased. Yet the idea that there may be an uneconomical principle
underlying the fertilizing methods now in use is often considered heretical.
Another problem of the times is the increase in the phenomena of degenera
tion — plant diseases and insect pests. A description of these phenomena
is not necessary, for they are part of the farmer’s daily experience.1
1. These problems are the special concern of the Decentralists and Distributists.
Cf. R o p k e , Wilhem, The Social Crisis of Our Time, Chicago, University of Chicago Press,
1950. Also B e l l o c , Hilaire, The Restoration of Property, el al.
2. S e a r s , op. at., ch.12, Wet Deserts. Also, cf. M t jm f o r d , Lewis, Techniques and
Civilization, New York, Harcourt Brace, 1934.
3. Cf. M t jm f o r d , The Culture of Cities, New York, Harcourt Brace, 1928.
4. In I Politicor., lect.6.
5. Cf. B a r d e t , Gaston, Demain, c’est Van ZOOO, Paris, Plon, 1952.
T H E N A TU R E OF AGRICULTURE 193
has brought it into cultivation and lavished upon it his care and skill
Now when man thus spends the industry of his mind and the strength of
his body in procuring the fruits of nature, by that act he makes his own
that portion of nature’s field which he cultivates — that portion on which
he leaves, as it were, the impress of his own personality.
1. “ For everything that can be known by reason, it is necessary that some doctrine
be given, for the perfection of human wisdom which is called philosophy.”
2. In I Etkicor., lect.2.
3. In I Politicor., lect.8.
4. Q.5, a.l, ad 4.
5. Summa Theologica, la , q.14, a.I6, c.
196 LAV AL TH ÉO LO G IQ U E E T PH ILO SO PH IQ U E
acquires more particular and appropriate knowledge of things in their concretion, and to
consider them in this fashion is not speculative.
(■*>
198 LA V A L THÉO LO GIQU E E T PH ILO SO PH IQ U E
1. De Potentia, q.4, a.3, c. Also, In IV Sent., d.42, q.2, a.l, c. Thepurpose of art
is to supply the things that nature fails to supply, either absolutely speaking, or insome
respect.
2. Q. D. de Veritate, q .ll, a.l, c. ; In I I Physicor., lect.4 and 13.
3. In I I Physicor., lect.4.
4. Ibid.. I, Prooemium. — Perhaps we should point out that ‘ to be like nature ’
and ‘ to be of nature ’ are not the same thing.
200 LAVAL THEO LO GIQU E ET PH ILO SO PH IQ U E
The reason why art cannot make the things in the way nature
does is that the power of art does not extend directly to the substance
of things, but only to the accidents. The substance of things is made
by generation, from a principle that is first and intrinsic to its cause ;
whereas art is a principle that is extrinsic to nature. For art is in the
reason, and reason differs from nature inasmuch as it is above con
traries. For the notion of blindness does not destroy the notion of
sight. The latter is essential to the former. But one cannot in fact
both see and be blind, except successively. In this sense reason and
art are extrinsic to nature. But they can act upon nature by way of
direction and command. The forms produced by art itself are those
of composition, order and figure.1 However, nothing prevents art
from bringing about the substance of a thing by making use of what
is already provided by nature, either proximately, such as wheat to
make bread, or remotely, such as hydrogen to make new types of
atoms. In such cases art makes things by applying natural forces
to produce effects, some of which could be wrought by nature alone,
others only with the help of our own reason.2
not the business of nature alone to supply food for man in conditions
of his own designing, which he is due to create if he is to lead a civilized
life. Under these conditions, art is required to supplement the work
of nature. An appropriate name for these arts is ‘ cooperative arts.’
St. Thomas also calls them ministerial arts. These are described in
many of his works. In the Summa Theologica he says :
. . . Of effects proceeding from an extrinsic principle some proceed
from that principle alone, as the form of a house is produced in the materials
by art alone. But other effects proceed now from an extrinsic principle,
now from an intrinsic principle ; and thus health is caused in a sick man
sometimes by the former [such as medical art], sometimes by an intrinsic
principle [as when a man is healed by the power of nature alone].
In these latter effects two things must be noted. First, that art in its
work imitates nature, for just as nature heals a man by alteration, digestion
and rejection of the matter that caused the sickness, so does art. Secondly,
we must remark that the extrinsic principle, art, acts not as the principal
agent, but as helping the principal agent, which is the interior principle, by
strengthening it, and by furnishing it with instruments and assistance,
of which the intrinsic principle makes use in producing the effects.1
1. Ia, q.117, a.], c. Other passages are found in the commentary on the Meta
physics, VII, lect.6 ; the commentary on the Physics, II, lect.13 ; The Summa Contra Gen
tiles, II, c.75 ; and De Potevtia, q.6, a.3.
2. Q.2, a.l, c.
202 LAVAL THÉO LO GIQU E E T PH ILO SO PH IQ U E
The words of St. Thomas, that these arts operate in the same
way, and by the same means as nature does, deserve further study ;
for, as mentioned above,1 this is a principle which in contemporary
agricultural practice is honored more in the breach than in the observ
ance.
The first and most important things to be remembered about the
cooperative arts is that they cooperate with nature as a secondary
and helping agent, and not as a primary or equal one. The reason is
that the things produced by such arts are things of nature and primari
ly the result of natural causes. The purpose of such art is to help
nature — their operations presuppose those of nature, and art is
unable to duplicate these by its own power alone ; for, as was said
above, the power of art does not extend directly to the substance of
things, but rather to such things as figure, composition and order.
This presupposes an aptitude in the natural substance for such
accidents, which is realized primarily by the active power of the
natural agency, though with help of the art.
There are four ways in which one agent can cooperate with
another : by counsel, help, disposition, or by means of a tool.2 In
reference to nature — the principal agent — a cooperative art like
agriculture cooperates by helping and by disposing. As St. Thomas
says in the De Potentia : “ In some cases art perfects that which
nature cannot make ; in some, however, it produces an order in
nature, as the doctor does to heal, by altering and directing, through
the apposition of those things which have a natural virtue to do this.” 3
But in reference to politics and economics, to which agriculture, and
the other useful arts are subordinated by reason of their end, these
arts cooperate as instruments of the former, or by deliberation, which
is made plain by St. Thomas in his commentary on the Politics.4
In the second place, it should be remembered that inasmuch as
these arts imitate nature, the imitation consists of operating in the
same way and by the same means as nature does — or would, if she
could. The reason for this imitation is the fact that the exemplar
which governs the operations of reason in art must be taken from
nature ; for that which these arts aim at is something which nature
can produce by natural powers. In the commentary on the Meta
physics, St. Thomas gives an example of this characteristic :
It is plain, therefore, that just as in natural things a man is generated
from man, so also in artificial things it happens that in some manner health
comes to be from health, and a house from a house ; namely, when that
which has matter comes from that which exists without matter in the mind.
1. Pp.197-198.
2. In IV Sent., d.5, q.I, a.2, c.
3. Q.6, a.3, c.
4. In I Politicor., lect.8 and 9.
THE N A TU R E OF AGRICULTURE 203
For the art of medicine, which is a principle of healing, is nothing but the
conception of health which is in the mind.
And just as the doctor, who wishes to bring about health, begins by
considering what health is, such as that it is a certain balance, then he
should know what this is, such as a suitable proportion of humors in refer
ence to human nature. But this may occur if the body is made warm, if
the infirmity in question is due to a lack of warmth. And, again, he should
know what this is, namely, to be warmed ; as if he were to say that to
become warmed is to be immuted by a heated medicine. But to give a
heated medicine is something within the immediate power of a doctor to do,
and it is now within his power to provide this remedy.1
beginning of their lives. The embryo which is in the egg makes use
of the rest of the egg’s substance as its food ; and nature provides
food for young mammals in the mother’s milk. And as animals
continue to grow and complete their lives, nature continues to provide
food for them. Thus plants serve as food for some animals, while
others live on animals. Man in turn uses all, or most, of the plants
and the other animals as his food, or to satisfy other needs ; for the
needs of man are manifold, and all of the other things of nature are
at his disposal, for this is their end.1
Though it is the business of nature to supply food for man, it
does not follow that nature, alone, has the completed power to supply
food in the abundance, the regularity, the variety and the places
which are required for life in the political community, which is the
proper mode of human life. By nature man is destined to live in a
civil community ; yet this community and its conditions are not the
work of nature, but of reason and art. Man differs from the other
animals in this respect, for they are directed by instinct in their actions,
whereas man should be directed by reason and art.2 To illustrate
this fact, St. Thomas points out that while the other animals are
naturally endowed with all the equipment and instruments for carrying
on their lives, such as natural clothing, means of attack and defence,
etc., man is not naturally endowed in this way. In place of these he
has reason and hands which are a kind of universal tool, a tool of tools
inasmuch as reason and hand may produce an infinite variety of tools.
The universality of the uses of man’s hands makes them the proper
counterpart for the universality of his reason. And, since man’s
needs spring, not from nature alone, as do those of other animals,
but from reason, which is universal, so also the means of satisfying
these needs arise, not from nature alone, but from reason and art
which is nothing else but right reason about making things.3
Therefore, for the acquisition of food man stands in need of art,
the purpose of which is to supply food in the abundance, the regularity
and the variety needed for life in the civil community. And, among
the food productive arts, only agriculture is equal to this task. Living
beings are generated, nourished and brought to maturity by means of
the vegetative powers of the soul, and these are active and completed
potencies — according to the distinction quoted above known to us
by their observed effects. — They are principles of fertility in nature.
By means of them food is supplied to living beings.
The primitive arts by which man acquires his food, such as
hunting, fishing and shepherding, are arts of interception. In them,
The principles which govern the processes of soil and life in the
prairies, the rivers and the sea are similar to these. In all cases the
result of nature’s farming is a building up of fertility, and a gradual
conquest of bare land by vegetation. The island of Krakatao is a
good example of this law. In 1883 a volcano reduced the island to
bare rock and sand. Twenty years later it was again covered with
vegetation.2
The soundness of any system of agriculture must be judged,
primarily, by the extent to which it adheres to the principles which
are furnished it in the exemplar of nature’s farming. According to
Howard, the agriculture of the Orient has grasped these principles and
adhered to them faithfully. This agriculture, he says, has passed the
supreme test ; the test of time. The small holdings of China, for
example, are still maintaining a steady, and a high output with no
loss of fertility after as much as forty centuries of management.3
To a lesser extent many other peoples have learned to follow nature’s
laws in their farming. In the works we have referred to, Howard
gives many examples of this, taken from his own observations. He
describes the Chinese method of making humus by composting all
vegetable and animal wastes, as a careful imitation of the manner in
which it is made in the forest. It is like rolling up the forest floor and
arranging it in a heap, he says. Another example is the way in which
the peasants of Northern India ward off the threat of the formation
of a hard soil pan under their fields — a condition which leads to the
development of alkali salts in the soil and the end of its fertility.
They plant deep rooting legumes between other crops, and the roots
of these legumes break up the subsoil, thus maintaining its permea
bility and fertility. In another place he tells how he induced the
hop growers in a part of England to add the male hops to their plant
ings, alongside the commercially valuable female plants. The female
plants were then pollinated, as nature intended they should be, and
they acquired the hardiness to throw off the disease which threatened
to destroy them.4
1. An Agricultural Testament, pp. 1-5.
2. M a n g h a m , Sidney, The Earth’s Green Mantle, New York, Macmillan, 1939, p.25.
3. An Agricultural Testament, pp.9-17.
4. The Soil and Health, p.2.
210 LAV AL THEO LO GIQU E E T PH ILO SO PH IQ U E
J oseph B. M cD on a ld .
(To be continued.)