2017 - Judgement - 27 Sep 2018 105 181 PDF
2017 - Judgement - 27 Sep 2018 105 181 PDF
2017 - Judgement - 27 Sep 2018 105 181 PDF
JUDGMENT
Index
D Across frontiers
E Confronting patriarchy
1
PART A
Dr Dhananjaya Y Chandrachud, J
and liberties. It envisages the creation of a society where the ideals of equality,
dignity and freedom triumph over entrenched prejudices and injustices. The
constitutional morality. The case at hand enjoins this constitutional court to make
an enquiry into the insidious permeation of patriarchal values into the legal order
2 Law and society are intrinsically connected and oppressive social values
often find expression in legal structures. The law influences society as well but
societal values are slow to adapt to leads shown by the law. The law on adultery
so, the law creates and ascribes gender roles based on existing societal
1
Ratna Kapur and Brenda Cossman, Subversive Sites: Feminist Engagements with Law in India, Sage Publications
(1996) at page 40
2 Ibid at page 41
3 Ibid
2
PART A
3 Over the years, legal reform has had a significant role in altering the
cases, the law operates to perpetuate an unequal world for women. Thus,
depending on the manner in which it is used, law can act as an agent of social
change as well as social stagnation. Scholar Patricia Williams, who has done
considerable work on the critical race theory, is sanguine about the possibility of
The Constitution, both in text and interpretation, has played a significant role in
liberation. Used in a liberal perspective, the law can enhance democratic values.
As an instrument which preserves the status quo on the other hand, the law
important “site for discursive struggle”, where ideals compete and new visions
4
Ibid
5 Patricia Williams, The Alchemy of Race and Rights, Cambridge: Harvard University Press (1991)
6 Ratna Kapur and Brenda Cossman, Subversive Sites: Feminist Engagements with Law in India, Sage Publications
(1996) at page 41
3
PART A
imperative to examine the institutions and structures within which legal discourse
operates:7
In adjudicating on the rights of women, the Court must not lose sight of the
institutions and values which have forced women to a shackled existence so far.
To fully recognise the role of law and society in shaping the lives and identities of
women, is also to ensure that patriarchal social values and legal norms are not
our country.
granting primacy to the right to autonomy, dignity and individual choice. The right
to sexual autonomy and privacy has been granted the stature of a Constitutional
right. In confronting the sources of gendered injustice which threaten the rights
and freedoms promised in our Constitution, we set out to examine the validity of
Section 497 of the Indian Penal Code. In doing so, we also test the
constitutionality of moral and societal regulation of women and their intimate lives
7 Ibid
8 Gayatri Spivak, The Post Colonial Critic: Interviews, Strategies, Dialogies, Routledge (1990)
4
PART B
497 of the Indian Penal Code as well as Section 198(2) of the Code of Criminal
Procedure.
Bombay9, arose from a case where the appellant was being prosecuted for
adultery under Section 497. On a complaint being filed, he moved the High Court
to determine the constitutional question about the validity of the provision, under
5
PART B
Article 228. The High Court decided against the appellant10, but Chief Justice
A narrow challenge was addressed before this Court. The judgment of Justice
Hence, the challenge was only to the prohibition on treating the wife as an
abettor. It was this challenge which was dealt with and repelled on the ground
that Article 14 must be read with the other provisions of Part III which prescribe
the ambit of the fundamental rights. The prohibition on treating the wife as an
abettor was upheld as a special provision which is saved by Article 15(3). The
6
PART B
7 The challenge was to a limited part of Section 497: that which prohibited a
woman from being prosecuted as an abettor. Broader issues such as whether (i)
the punishment for adultery violates Article 21; (ii) the statutory provision suffers
from manifest arbitrariness; (iii) the legislature has, while ostensibly protecting
the sanctity of marriage, invaded the dignity of women; and (iv) Section 497
This Court construed the exemption granted to women from criminal sanctions as
a ‘special provision’ for the benefit of women and thus, protected under Article
remedy. The history of Section 497 reveals that the law on adultery was for the
benefit of the husband, for him to secure ownership over the sexuality of his wife.
It was aimed at preventing the woman from exercising her sexual agency. Thus,
Section 497 was never conceived to benefit women. In fact, the provision is
steeped in stereotypes about women and their subordinate role in marriage. The
7
PART B
v Union of India13, the court proceeded on the basis that the earlier decision in
Yusuf Abdul Aziz had upheld Section 497 against a challenge based on Articles
judgment.
challenge on the ground that after the passage of thirty years, “particularly in the
matters of sex”, it had become necessary that the matter be revisited. Sowmithri
Vishnu arose in a situation where a petition for divorce by the appellant against
her husband on the ground of desertion was dismissed with the finding that it
was the appellant who had deserted her husband. The appellant’s husband then
sued for divorce on the ground of desertion and adultery. Faced with this petition,
the appellant urged that a decree for divorce on the ground of desertion may be
passed on the basis of the findings in the earlier petition. She, however, opposed
the effort of the husband to urge the ground of adultery. While the trial court
accepted the plea of the husband to assert the ground of adultery, the High Court
held in revision that a decree of divorce was liable to be passed on the ground of
desertion, making it unnecessary to inquire into adultery. While the petition for
13 1985 Supp SCC 137
8
PART B
divorce was pending against the appellant, her husband filed a complaint under
Section 497 against the person with whom the appellant was alleged to be in an
of Section 497.
The judgment of the three judge Bench indicates that three grounds of challenge
were addressed before this Court : first, while Section 497 confers a right on the
husband to prosecute the adulterer, it does not confer upon the wife to prosecute
the woman with whom her husband has committed adultery; second, Section
497 does not confer a right on the wife to prosecute her husband who has
committed adultery with another woman; and third, Section 497 does not cover
cases where a man has sexual relations with an unmarried woman. The
submission before this Court was that the classification under Section 497 was
irrational and ‘arbitrary’. Moreover, it was also urged that while facially, the
paternalism “which stems from the assumption that women, like chattels, are the
property of men.”
narrow terms. Chandrachud, CJ speaking for the three judge Bench observed
that by definition, the offence of adultery can be committed by a man and not by
9
PART B
suggestion that the definition should be recast in a manner that would make the
offence gender neutral. The court responded by observing that this was a matter
of legislative policy and that the court could invalidate the provision only if a
constitutional violation is established. The logic of the court, to the effect that
with the legislature. But this only leads to the conclusion that the court cannot
extend the legislative prescription by making the offence gender neutral. It does
not answer the fundamental issue as to whether punishment for adultery is valid
in constitutional terms. The error in Sowmithri Vishnu lies in holding that there
10
PART B
purely from the perspective of the argument that Section 497 is not gender
neutral, in allowing only the man but not to the woman in a sexual relationship to
“commonly accepted that it is the man who is the seducer and not the woman.”
Observing that this position may have undergone some change, over the years,
the decision holds that these are matters for the legislature to consider and that
challenge which was urged before the Court. Under Article 14, the challenge was
that the statutory provision treats a woman purely as the property of her
husband is evidenced in Section 497, in more than one context. The provision
stipulates that a man who has sexual intercourse with the wife of another will not
be guilty of offence if the husband of the woman were to consent or, (worse still,
woman. Whether or not a man with whom she has engaged in sexual intercourse
her husband were to connive at the act, no offence would be made out. The
mirror image of this constitutional infirmity is that the wife of the man who has
engaged in the act has no voice or agency under the statute. Again, the law does
11
PART B
intercourse with a single woman. His wife is not regarded by the law as a person
whose agency and dignity is affected. The underlying basis of not penalising a
sexual act by a married man with a single woman is that she (unlike a married
woman) is not the property of a man (as the law would treat her to be if she is
married). Arbitrariness is writ large on the provision. The problem with Section
497 is not just a matter of under inclusion. The court in Sowmithri Vishnu
that the legislature is entitled to deal with the evil where it is felt and seen the
most. The narrow and formal sense in which the provisions of Article 14 have
The decision of the three judge Bench does not address the central challenge to
the validity of Section 497. Section 497, in its effort to protect the sanctity of
marriage, has adopted a notion of marriage which does not regard the man and
the woman as equal partners. It proceeds on the subjection of the woman to the
will of her husband. In doing so, Section 497 subordinates the woman to a
12
PART B
position of inferiority thereby offending her dignity, which is the core of Article 21.
Significantly, even the challenge under Article 21 was addressed on behalf of the
petitioner in that case in a rather narrow frame. The argument before this Court
was that at the trial involving an offence alleged to have been committed under
Section 497, the woman with whom the accused is alleged to have had sexual
intercourse would have no right of being heard. It was this aspect alone which
was addressed in Sowmithri Vishnu when the court held that such a right of
being heard can be read in an appropriate case. Ultimately, the court held that:
Sowmithri Vishnu has thus proceeded on the logic that in specifying an offence,
it is for the legislature to define what constitutes the offence. Moreover, who can
prosecute and who can be prosecuted, are matters which fall within the domain
of the law. The inarticulate major premise of the judgment is that prosecution for
adultery is an effort to protect the stability of marriages and if the legislature has
could not be questioned. ‘Sowmithri Vishnu’ fails to deal with the substantive
autonomy and privacy and above all gender equality as a cornerstone of a truly
equal society. For these reasons, the decision in Sowmithri Vishnu cannot be
13
PART B
is overruled.
involved a challenge to Section 497 (read with Section 198(2) of the Code of
Criminal Procedure) which disables a wife from prosecuting her husband for
being involved in an adulterous relationship. The court noted that Section 497
permits neither the husband of the offending wife to prosecute her nor does it
permit the wife to prosecute her offending husband for being disloyal. This
formal sense of equality found acceptance by the court. The challenge was
497 and Section 198(2) constitute a “legislative packet”, the court observed that
the provision does not allow either the wife to prosecute an erring husband or a
husband to prosecute the erring wife. In the view of the court, this indicated that
17 (1988) 2 SCC 72
18 Ibid. at page 76
14
PART C
the doctrine of equality and the prohibition against discrimination on the ground
of sex in a formalistic sense. The logic of the judgment is that since neither of the
spouses (man or woman) can prosecute the erring spouse, the provision does
not discriminate on the ground of sex. Apart from reading equality in a narrow
confine, the judgment does not deal with crucial aspects bearing on the
constitutionality of the provision. Revathi, like Sowmithri Vishnu does not lay
14 Section 497 of the Indian Penal Code, 1860 makes adultery a punishable
offence against “whoever has sexual intercourse with a person who is and whom
he knows or has reason to believe to be the wife of another man, without the
consent or connivance of that man.” It goes on to state that, “in such case the
wife shall not be punishable as an abettor.” The offence applies only to the man
15
PART C
“abettor” to the offence. The power to prosecute for adultery rests only with the
Understanding the gendered nature of Section 497 needs an inquiry into the
origins of the provision itself as well as the offence of adultery more broadly. The
history of adultery throws light upon disparate attitudes toward male and female
infidelity, and reveals the double standard in law and morality that has been
against adultery are found in the ancient code of the Babylonian king
Hammurabi, dating from circa 1750 B.C. The code prescribed that a married
woman caught in adultery be bound to her lover and thrown into water so that
private wrong for which the husband or father of the woman committing adultery
Dabhoiwala notes that the primary purpose of these laws was to protect the
20
See David Turner, Adultery in The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History (2008)
21 Ibid
22 James A. Brundage, Law, Sex, and Christian Society in Medieval Europe, at page 10
23 Ibid, at page 11
16
PART C
sexual access to his wife, for which the law allowed for acts of revenge. 25 In 17
B.C., Emperor Augustus passed the Lex Julia de adulteriis coercendis, which
stipulated that a father was allowed to kill his daughter and her partner when
caught committing adultery in his or her husband’s house.26 While in the Judaic
belief adultery merited death by stoning for both the adulteress and her partner, 27
Christianity viewed adultery more as a moral and spiritual failure than as a public
crime.28 The penalties of the Lex Julia were made more severe by Christian
emperors. Emperor Constantine, for instance, introduced the death penalty for
adultery, which allowed the husband the right to kill his wife if she committed
adultery.29 Under the Lex Julia, adultery was primarily a female offence, and the
24 Faramerz Dabhoiwala, The Origins of Sex: A History of the First Sexual Revolution (2012), at page 5
25 David Turner, Adultery in The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History (2008), at page 30
26 Vern Bullough, Medieval Concepts of Adultery, at page 7
27 The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History, (Bonnie G Smith ed.), Oxford, at page 27
28
Martin Siegel, For Better or for Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Vol. 30, Journal of Family Law (1991), at
page 46
29 Vern Bullough, Medieval Concepts of Adultery, at page 7
30 James A. Brundage, Law, Sex, and Christian Society in Medieval Europe, at page 27
17
PART C
fourth and fifth centuries, adultery came to be recognized as a serious wrong that
interfered with a husband’s “rights” over his wife.31 The imposition of criminal
sanctions on adultery was also largely based on ideas and beliefs about sexual
morality which acquired the force of law in Christian Europe during the Middle
Ages.32 The development of canon law in the twelfth century enshrined the
placed new emphasis on marriage as a linchpin of the social and moral order. 33
Several prominent sixteenth century reformers, including Martin Luther and John
Calvin, argued that a marriage was irreparably damaged by infidelity, and they
penalty for committing adultery.35 The strict morality of the early English colonists
child out of wedlock was made to wear the letter A (for adulterer) when she went
out in public; her lover was not so tagged, suggesting that women were punished
31 Jeremy D. Weinstein, Adultery, Law, and the State: A History, Vol. 38, Hastings Law Journal (1986), at page 202;
R. Huebner, A History of Germanic Private Law (F. Philbrick trans. 1918)
32
James A. Brundage, Law, Sex, and Christian Society in Medieval Europe, at page 6
33 David Turner, Adultery in The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History (2008), at page 30
34 Ibid.
35 The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History, (Bonnie G Smith ed.), Oxford, at page 30
18
PART C
more severely than men for adultery, especially when they had a child as
evidence.36
18 In 1650, England enacted the infamous Act for Suppressing the Detestable
Sins of Incest, Adultery and Fornication, which introduced the death penalty for
sex with a married woman.37 The purpose of the Act was as follows:
repealed in 1660 during the Restoration. The common law, however, was still
upon her unsuspecting husband and bringing an illegitimate heir into his
family.”39 Accordingly, secular courts treated adultery as a private injury and a tort
in Seventeenth-Century History Presented to Christopher Hill (Donald Pennington, Keith Thomas, eds.), at page 281
39 Charles E. Torcia, Wharton's Criminal Law, Section 218, (1994) at page 528
19
PART C
for criminal conversation was introduced in the late 17th century, which allowed
their husbands in law, and female adultery was subjected to ostracism far worse
than male adultery because of the problem it could cause for property inheritance
woman’s honor and reputation than of a man’s.42 The object of adultery laws was
not to protect the bodily integrity of a woman, but to allow her husband to
exercise control over her sexuality, in order to ensure the purity of his own
bloodline. The killing of a man engaged in an adulterous act with one’s wife was
that under the common law, “the very being or legal existence of the woman
40 J. E. Loftis, Congreve’s Way of the World and Popular Criminal Literature, Studies in English Literature, 1500 –
1900 36(3) (1996), at page 293
41
Joanne Bailey, Unquiet Lives: Marriage and Marriage Breakdown in England, 1660–1800 (2009), at page 143
42 David Turner, Adultery in The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Women in World History (2008), at page 28
43 Blackstone’s Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book IV (1778), at page 191-192
44 (1707) Kel. 119
20
PART C
consolidated into that of the husband: under whose wing, protection and cover,
she performe[d] everything.”45 In return for support and protection, the wife owed
theft.47 In fact, civil actions for adultery evolved from actions for enticing away a
servant from a master and thus depriving the master of the quasi-proprietary
Faramerz Dabhoiwala notes that a man’s wife was considered to be his property,
and that another man’s “unlawful copulation” with her warranted punishment:
“…[T]he earliest English law codes, which date from this time,
evoke a society where women were bought and sold and
lived constantly under the guardianship of men. Even in
cases of consensual sex, its system of justice was mainly
concerned with the compensation one man should pay to
another for unlawful copulation with his female chattel.”
21 When the IPC was being drafted, adultery was not a criminal offence in
coercion of the Spiritual Court, according to the rules of Canon Law.” 49 Lord
Ashford, Alan Reed and Nicola Wake, eds.) (2016), at page 161
49 Blackstone’s Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book IV (1778), at pages 64-65
21
PART C
adultery in India, and ultimately concluded that it would serve little purpose. 50
According to Lord Macaulay, the possible benefits from an adultery offence could
be better achieved through pecuniary compensation.51 Section 497 did not find a
place in the first Draft Penal Code prepared by Lord Macaulay. On an appraisal
of the facts and opinions collected from all three Presidencies about the
22 The Law Commissioners, in their Second Report on the Draft Penal Code,
disagreed with Lord Macaulay’s view. Placing heavy reliance upon the status of
50
Abhinav Sekhri, The Good, The Bad, And The Adulterous: Criminal Law And Adultery In India, Socio-Legal Review
(2016), at page 52
51 Ibid.
52 Macaulay's Draft Penal Code (1837), Note Q
22
PART C
The Law Commissioners’ decision to insert Section 497 into the IPC was rooted
in their concern about the possibility of the “natives” resorting to illegal measures
53
Second Report on the Indian Penal Code (1847), at pages 134-35, cited from, Law Commission of India, Forty-
second Report: Indian Penal Code, at page 365
54 A Penal Code prepared by The Indian Law Commissioners (1838), The Second Report on the Indian Penal Code,
at page 74
23
PART C
Section 497 and Section 198 are seen to treat men and women unequally, as
women are not subject to prosecution for adultery, and women cannot prosecute
established. In its 42nd Report, the Law Commission of India considered the
legislative history of Section 497 and the purported benefit of criminal sanctions
for adultery. The Committee concluded that, “though some of us were personally
inclined to recommend repeal of the section, we think on the whole that the time
has not yet come for making such a radical change in the existing position.” 55 It
23 In its 156th Report, the Law Commission made a proposal which it believed
removing the exemption from liability for women under Section 497. 56 In 2003,
sexual intercourse with the spouse of any other person is guilty of adultery.” 57
The Committee supported earlier proposals to not repeal the offence, but to
55 Law Commission of India, 42nd Report: Indian Penal Code (1971), at page 326
56 Law Commission of India, 156th Report: Indian Penal Code (1997) at page 172
57 Report of the Committee on Reforms of Criminal Justice System (2003), at page 190
24
PART C
Neither the recommendations of the Law Commission nor those of the Malimath
exempted from prosecution under Section 497, the underlying notion upon which
The power to prosecute lies only with the husband (and not to the wife in cases
where her husband commits adultery), and whether the crime itself has been
committed depends on whether the husband provides “consent for the allegedly
adulterous act.”
prosecuted for committing adultery, nor can they be aggrieved by it, by virtue of
their status as their husband’s property. Section 497 is also premised upon
sexual stereotypes that view women as being passive and devoid of sexual
agency. The notion that women are ‘victims’ of adultery and therefore require the
beneficial exemption under Section 497 has been deeply criticized by feminist
58 Ibid.
59 Abhinav Sekhri, The Good, The Bad, And The Adulterous: Criminal Law And Adultery In India, Socio-Legal Review
(2016), at page 63
25
PART C
and women differently is, ultimately, to act in women’s interests. 60 The status of
25 Throughout history, the law has failed to ask the woman question. 62 It has
character and abilities of the sexes on which laws rest, and how these notions
affect women and their interaction with the law. A woman's ‘purity’ and a man’s
antiquated social and sexual mores of the nineteenth century, but they cannot be
recognized as being so today. It is not the “common morality” of the State at any
time in history, but rather constitutional morality, which must guide the law. In any
are indispensable for the free, equal, and dignified existence of all members of
sex, and dignity, all of which are affected by the operation of Section 497.
60 Brenda Cossman and Ratna Kapur, Subversive Sites: Feminist Engagements with Law in India (1996)
61
Yusuf Abdul Aziz v. State of Bombay, 1954 SCR 930
62 The ‘Woman Question’ was one of the great issues that occupied the middle of the nineteenth century, namely the
social purpose of women. It is used as a tool to enquire into the status of women in the law and how they interact
with and are affected by it; See Katherine T. Bartlett, Feminist Legal Methods, Harvard Law Review (1990)
26
PART D
D Across frontiers
around the world taking measures to decriminalize the offence of adultery due to
the gender discriminatory nature of adultery laws as well as on the ground that
they violate the right to privacy. However, progressive action has primarily been
taken on the ground that provisions penalising adultery are discriminatory against
women either patently on the face of the law or in their implementation. Reform
towards achieving a more egalitarian society in practice has also been driven by
active measures taken by the United Nations and other international human
rights organizations, where it has been emphasized that even seemingly gender-
legislatures and courts. When decisions have been handed down by the judiciary
across the world, it has led to the creation of a rich body of transnational
emanating from the courts of those countries where the provision criminalizing
adultery has been struck down through judicial action. The decisions of these
63 U N Working Group on Women’s Human Rights: Report (18 October, 2012), available at:
http://newsarchive.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=12672&LangID=E
27
PART D
courts reflect how the treatment of the law towards adultery has evolved with the
struck down Article 241 of the Criminal Law; a provision which criminalized
so, South Korea joined a growing list of countries in Asia and indeed around the
world that have taken the measure of effacing the offence of adultery from the
statute books, considering evolving public values and societal trends. The
Constitutional Court had deliberated upon the legality of the provision four times
previously65, but chose to strike it down when it came before it in 2015, with the
The majority opinion of the Court was concurred with by five of the seven
judges66 who struck down the provision. The majority acknowledged that the
the marriage system based on good sexual culture and practice and monogamy
and to preserve marital fidelity between spouses.” However, the Court sought to
strike a balance between the legitimate interest of the legislature in promoting the
64Case No: 2009Hun-Ba17, (Adultery Case), South Korea Constitutional Court (February 26, 2015), available at
http://english.ccourt.go.kr/cckhome/eng/decisions/majordecisions/majorDetail.do
65
Firstpost, South Korean court abolishes law that made adultery illegal, (February 26, 2015), available at
https://www.firstpost.com/world/south-korean-court-abolishes-law-saying-adultery-is-illegal-2122935.html
66 Opinion of Justice Park Han-Chul, Justice Lee Jin-Sung, Justice Kim Chang-Jong, Justice Seo Ki-Seog and Justice
28
PART D
The Court used the test of least restrictiveness, and began by acknowledging
with the societal structure having changed from holding traditional family values
and a typeset role of family members to sexual views driven by liberal thought
unethical, the Court stated that love and sexual life were intimate concerns, and
they should not be made subject to criminal law. Commenting on the balance
remarked:
67 Article 10 of the South Korean Constitution “All citizens are assured of human worth and dignity and have the right
to pursue happiness. It is the duty of the State to confirm and guarantee the fundamental and inviolable human
rights of individuals.”
68 Supra, note 64, Part V- A (3)(1) (‘Change in Public’s Legal Awareness’ under the head of ‘Appropriateness of
29
PART D
whether adultery should be regulated, the Court stated that modern criminal law
dictated that the State should not seek to interfere in an act that is not socially
morality. Moreover, it held that the State had no business in seeking to control
an individual’s actions which were within the sphere of his or her constitutionally
Moving on to the effectiveness of the provision at hand, the Court remarked that
criminalizing adultery did not help save a failing marriage. The Court remarked
that it was obvious that once a spouse was accused of adultery, the
69 Supra, note 64, Part V- A (3)(3) (‘Effectiveness of Criminal Punishment’, under the head of ‘Appropriateness of
Means and Least Restrictiveness’)
30
PART D
concluded that there was no data at all to support these claims in countries
The Court also analysed the argument that adultery provisions protected women:
Finally, the Court concluded its analysis by holding that the interests of enforcing
70 Ibid.
31
PART D
the interference of the State in the rights to privacy and sexual autonomy were
constitutionality of Section 154 of the Penal Code, on, the grounds that it violated
discriminatory treatment between women and men. The law as it stood allowed a
only a man could be guilty of the offence of adultery when he had sexual
married man outside of the marriage. The penalties for the offence also
Ugandan Constitution, which guaranteed equality under the law, Article 24 which
mandates respect for human dignity and protection from inhuman treatment and
74
Article 33(1), which protected the rights of women under the Constitution.
https://www.reuters.com/article/us-uganda-adultery/uganda-scraps-sexist-adultery-law-idUSL0510814320070405
74 Constitutional Petitions Nos. 13 /05 /& 05 /06 in Law Advocacy for Women in Uganda v. Attorney General of
32
PART D
The Respondent prayed that the Court consider making the provision of adultery
equal in its treatment of men and women, instead of striking it down completely.
However, in its holding, the Court denied this request, holding it could not
prescribe a punishment under penal law to change the statute. The Court held
that Section 154 of the Penal Code was wholly unconstitutional as being violative
“...the respondent did not point out to us areas that his Court
can or should modify and adapt to bring them in conformity
with the provisions of the Constitution. The section is a penal
one and this Court in our considered opinion cannot create a
sentence that the courts can impose on adulterous spouses.
aggrieved spouse could no longer seek damages against a third party in cases of
75 Ibid.
76 DE v RH, [2015] ZACC 18
77 Ibid, at para 34
33
PART D
The decisions of the US Supreme Court bearing on the issue of privacy have
been analysed in an incisive article, titled “For Better or for Worse: Adultery,
Crime and The Constitution”78, by Martin Siegel. He presents three ways in which
adultery implicates the right to privacy. The first is that adultery must be viewed
relationships are protected by the freedom of association and finally, that adultery
of the State.
The first privacy interest in adultery is the right to marital choice. The U.S.
choice’ and ‘the ‘right to privacy’ in marriage. With this jurisprudence, the author
matter of marriage and family life as expressed in Cleveland Board80, ‘an act
78 Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
45
79
Ibid, at page 46
80 Cleveland Board of Education v. LaFleur, 414 U.S. 623 (1973)
81 Griswold, 381 U.S. 1 (1967)
82 Carey, v. Population Serv. Int’l, 431 U.S. 678
34
PART D
and family relationships’ and therefore, falls within the domain of protected
private choices. He observes that the essence of the offence is in fact the
married status of one of the actors, and the mere fact that the commission of the
act consisted of a mere sexual act or a series of them is legally irrelevant. If the
Siegel cites Laurence Tribe, on accepting the ‘unconventional variants’ that also
The mere fact that adultery is considered unconventional in society does not
Siegel concludes that the privacy protections afforded to marriage must extend to
83
Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
70
84 Hardwick, 478 U.S.205
85 Ibid, at page 206
35
PART D
Siegel then proceeds to examine the next privacy interest in adultery, that of the
manner. Siegel proceeds to explain that adultery must not simply be looked at as
an act of consensual adult sexual activity, as sexual activity may simply be one
Next, Siegel examines the plausible protection of adultery through the lens of the
interpreted as being expressive, Siegel claims adultery might also implicate First
held that First Amendment rights are not limited to merely verbal expression but
86 Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
74
87 Ibid, at page 77
88 Ibid, at, page 78
89 Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 618 (1984)
36
PART D
In concluding his section on the right to associate, Siegel warns against the
akin to protecting a part of the relationship and criminalizing the other. This would
be manifestly unjust:
Lastly, Siegel discusses the connection between adultery and the right to sexual
privacy found favour with the U.S. Supreme Court, which in Thornburgh v
activity:
90 Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
78
91
Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
82
92 Thornburgh v. American College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists, 476 U.S. 747 (1986)
93 Ibid, at Page 777
37
PART D
choices, necessarily include the adulterous union which must be protected since
In concluding the author states that the foregoing three-layered analysis left no
room for doubt that adultery was a matter of marriage. It therefore deserved to be
protected like all other affairs occurring in marriage and implicated routine
94 Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
at page 85
95 Ibid, at Page 86
38
PART D
While acknowledging the interest that the State has in preserving the institution
or reinforce confidence in the rule of law. There are better ways to signal respect
for the institution of marriage and better uses of law enforcement than policing
96
Eisenstadt v. Baird , 405 U.S. 438, 457 (1972)
97 Martin J. Siegel, For Better or For Worse: Adultery, Crime & the Constitution, Journal of Family Law, Vol.30, (1991)
89
98 Deborah Rhode, Adultery: Infidelity and the Law, (Harvard University Press, 2016)
39
PART E
E Confronting patriarchy
30 The petitioner urged that (i) The full realisation of the ideal of equality
marriage; and (iii) the provision is manifestly arbitrary and amounts to a violation
The act which constitutes the offence under Section 497 of the Penal Code is a
man engaging in sexual intercourse with a woman who is the “wife of another
man”. For the offence to arise, the man who engages in sexual intercourse must
either know or have reason to believe that the woman is married. Though a man
has engaged in sexual intercourse with a woman who is married, the offence of
adultery does not come into being where he did so with the consent or
These ingredients of Section 497 lay bare several features which bear on the
challenge to its validity under Article 14. The fact that the sexual relationship
the ingredients of the offence are established. What the legislature has
99 Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton University Press, 1990
40
PART E
and a woman who is “the wife of another man”. No offence exists where a man
marriage, the legislature did not penalise sexual intercourse between a married
man and a single woman. Even though the man in such a case has a spouse,
That is because the provision proceeds on the notion that the woman is but a
chattel; the property of her husband. The fact that he is engaging in a sexual
woman who is involved in the sexual act is not married, the law treats it with
unconcern. The premise of the law is that if a woman is not the property of a
31 The essence of the offence is that a man has engaged in an act of sexual
intercourse with the wife of another man. But if the man to whom she is married
adultery would not be established. For, in the eyes of law, in such a case it is for
the man in the marital relationship to decide whether to agree to his spouse
engaging in a sexual act with another. Indeed, even if the two men (the spouse
of the woman and the man with whom she engages in a sexual act) were to
41
PART E
autonomy and dignity. If the ostensible object of the law is to protect the
marriage. She can neither complain nor is the fact that she is in a marital
relationship with a man of any significance to the ingredients of the offence. The
law also deprives the married woman who has engaged in a sexual act with
another man, of her agency. She is treated as the property of her husband. That
is why no offence of adultery would be made out if her husband were to consent
to her sexual relationship outside marriage. Worse still, if the spouse of the
woman were to connive with the person with whom she has engaged in sexual
intercourse, the law would blink. Section 497 is thus founded on the notion that a
woman by entering upon marriage loses, so to speak, her voice, autonomy and
42
PART E
The Constitution Bench in Shayara Bano v Union of India102 held the practice of
opinion, applied the test of manifest arbitrariness to hold that the practice does
43
PART E
34 The decision in Shayara Bano, holds that legislation or state action which
is manifestly arbitrary would have elements of caprice and irrationality and would
determines the “act” that is criminalized as well as the persons who may be held
must not be determined by majoritarian notions of morality which are at odds with
constitutional morality.
44
PART E
provision:
35 The hypothesis which forms the basis of the law on adultery is the
which fails to accord with the values on which the Constitution is founded. The
freedoms which the Constitution guarantees inhere in men and women alike. In
enacting Section 497, the legislature made an ostensible effort to protect the
of them is entitled to the same liberty which Part III guarantees. Each of them is
entitled to take decisions in accordance with his and her conscience and each
must have the ability to pursue the human desire for fulfilment. Section 497 is
based on the understanding that marriage submerges the identity of the woman.
enforcing these notions, Section 497 is inconsistent with the ethos of the
Constitution. Section 497 treats a woman as but a possession of her spouse. The
45
PART E
equality – cannot allow such a view of marriage. Section 497 suffers from
manifest arbitrariness.
36 While engrafting the provision into Chapter XX of the Penal Code – “of
implicit assumption about marriage. The notion which the law propounds and to
which it imposes the sanctions of penal law is that the marital tie subordinates
the role and position of the woman. In that view of marriage, the woman is bereft
of the ability to decide, to make choices and give free expression to her
matters of sexuality are reflective of the human desire for expression. Sexuality
attributes, it links up with the human desire to be intimate with a person of one’s
acknowledges that even in the most private of zones, the individual must have
the human personality. For, to be human involves the ability to fulfil sexual
protects the autonomy of the individual in making sexual choices. The sexual
46
PART E
postulating that it is only the man in a marital relationship who can consent to his
spouse having sexual intercourse with another. Section 497 disregards the
subjugated entirely to the will of her spouse. The provision is proffered by the
notion of marriage which is one sided and which denies agency to the woman in
a marital tie. The ability to make choices within marriage and on every aspect
protects. In depriving the woman of that ability and recognising it in the man
alone, Section 497 fails to meet the essence of substantive equality in its
37 The procedural law which has been enacted in Section 198 of the Code of
punishable under Section 497, only the husband of the woman is deemed to be
aggrieved by the offence. In any event, once the provisions of Section 497 are
47
PART E
held to offend the fundamental rights, the procedure engrafted in Section 198 will
disadvantaged groups which effectively undermines their full and equal social,
formalistic notion of equality which disregards social realities, the Court must take
into account the impact of the rule or provision in the lives of citizens.
towards women. The latter links true equality to the realisation of dignity. The
focus of such an approach is not simply on equal treatment under the law, but
106
Kathy Lahey, Feminist Theories of (In)equality, in Equality and Judicial Nuetrality (S.Martin and K.Mahoney (eds.)
(1987)
107 Ratna Kapur On Woman, Equality and the Constitution: Through the Looking Glass of Feminism in Gender and
48
PART E
rather on the real impact of the legislation.108 Thus, Section 497 has to be
examined in the light of existing social structures which enforce the position of a
family sphere, termed ‘‘personal,’’ and view the family as a “crucible of women’s
which considers the husband as the owner of the wife’s sexuality, the law
When all visible and invisible forms of inequality- social, cultural, economic,
can be imagined.
108 Maureen Maloney, An Analysis of Direct Taxes in India: A Feminist Perspective, Journal of the Indian Law Institute
(1988)
109 Catherine A Mackinnon, Sex equality under the Constitution of India: Problems, prospects, and ‘personal laws’,
Oxford University Press and New York University School of Law (2006)
49
PART F
“15. (1) The State shall not discriminate against any citizen on
grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any
of them.”
(Emphasis supplied)
The Petitioners contend that (i) Section 497, in so far as it places a husband and
From a joint reading of Section 497 of the Indian Penal Code and Section 198(2)
ii. In an ‘adulterous relationship’, the man is punished for adultery, while the
iii. Sexual relations by a married man with an unmarried woman are not
criminalized;
iv. Section 497 accords primacy to the consent of the husband to determine
50
PART F
v. A man who has sexual relations with the spouse of another man is relieved
of the offence only if her spouse has consented or, even connived; and
vi. Section 497, IPC, read with Section 198, Cr.PC, gives the man the sole
proceedings.
relations of a woman outside her marriage. A man who has sexual intercourse
liable to be prosecuted under the Section. However, a married man may engage
woman is forced to consider the prospect of the penal action that will attach upon
the individual with whom she engages in a sexual act. To ensure the fidelity of
his spouse, the man is given the power to invoke the criminal sanction of the
State. In effect, her spouse is empowered to curtail her sexual agency. The
consent of the husband serves as the key to the exercise of the sexual agency of
51
PART F
A married man may engage in sexual relations with an unmarried woman who is
not his wife without the fear of opening his partner to prosecution and without the
who engages in sexual relations outside marriage. The effect of Section 497 is to
consent or connivance of her husband. Though Section 497 does not punish a
are placed on different pedestals in respect to their actions. The effect of Section
exempting her from prosecution, the exercise of her sexual agency is contingent
aggrieved party by the law if his wife engages in sexual intercourse with another
man, but the wife is not, if her husband does the same. Viewed from this angle,
Section 497 discriminates between a married man and a married woman to her
places a woman within marriage and the man with whom she shares a sexual
42 Section 497 criminalizes the conduct of the man who has sexual
intercourse with the wife of another without his consent. It exempts women from
criminal liability. Underlying this exemption is the notion that women, being
52
PART F
criminalizing the accused who engages in the sexual relationship, the law
perpetuates a gender stereotype that men, possessing sexual agency are the
seducers, and that women, as passive beings devoid of sexual agency, are the
seduced. The notion that a woman is ‘submissive’, or worse still ‘naïve’ has no
equality and destructive of the dignity of the woman. On this stereotype, Section
43 Pertinent to the present enquiry, is that the provision allows only the
granted permission to exercise her sexual agency with another individual. This
guarantees a degree of control to the husband over the sexual agency of his
spouse. As a relic of Victorian morality, this control over the sexual agency of the
spouse, views the wife as the property of the husband. Fidelity of the woman,
and the husband’s control over it, is seen as maintaining the ‘property’ interest of
a husband in his wife.110 In this view, a woman is confounded with things that can
on adultery seeks to punish a person who attempts theft on the property of the
husband. Coontz and Henderson write that the stabilization of property rights and
110Phyllis Coleman, Who’s Been Sleeping in My Bed? You and Me, and the State Makes Three, Vol. 24, Indian Law
Review (1991)
53
PART F
the desire to pass on one’s property to legitimate heirs, were what motivated men
of the woman, only the husband, as the ‘aggrieved’ party is given the right to
initiate prosecution. The proceedings once initiated, would be geared against the
person who committed an act of ‘theft’ or ‘trespass’ upon his spouse. Sexual
relations by a man with another man’s wife is therefore considered as theft of the
husband’s property. Ensuring a man’s control over the sexuality of his wife was
assumption that a woman contracts away her sexual agency when entering a
with her husband or to refrain from sexual relations outside marriage without the
permission of her husband is offensive to liberty and dignity. Such a notion has
core of the dignity of every individual. At the heart of the constitutional rights
111 Women’s Work, Men’s Property: The Origins of Gender and Class (S Coontz and P Henderson eds.) (1986)
54
PART F
constitutional values.
operation, law “permeates and is inseparable from everyday living and knowing,
reading of the law shows that it influences social practices, and makes
“asymmetries of power seem, if not invisible, natural and benign”. 113 Section 497
existing gender stereotypes and bias and further perpetuates them. Cultural
woman. Women then are expected to be chaste before and faithful during
marriage. In restricting the sexual agency of women, Section 497 gives legal
for a woman were legally and socially permissible when it was within her
112
Rosemary Coombe, Is There a Cultural Studies of Law?, in A Companion to Cultural Studies, Toby Miller (ed.),
Oxford, (2001)
113 Austin Sarat, Jonathan Simon, Beyond Legal Realism?: Cultural Analysis, Cultural Studies, and the Situation of
Legal Scholarship, Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities, (2001), at page 19
55
PART F
In Anuj Garg v Hotel Association of India,114 this Court struck down Section 30
of the Punjab Excise Act, 1914 which prohibited the employment of women in
premises where liquor or other intoxicating drugs were consumed by the public.
Holding that the law suffered from “incurable fixations of stereotype morality and
conception of sexual role”, the Court took into account “traditional cultural norms
as also the state of general ambience in the society” and held that “no law in its
sexual fidelity. In curtailing the sexual agency of women, it exacts sexual fidelity
from women as the norm. It perpetuates the notion that a woman is passive and
incapable of exercising sexual freedom. In doing so, it offers her ‘protection’ from
prosecution. Section 497 denudes a woman of her sexual autonomy in making its
56
PART F
marriage. The provision is grounded in and has a deep social effect on how
structure which demands her controlled sexuality, Section 497 purports to serve
Underlying this exemption is the notion that a woman is the victim of being
seduced into a sexual relationship with a person who is not her husband. In
assuming that the woman has no sexual agency, the exemption seeks to be
protected under Article 15(3) of the Constitution. This is contrary to the remedy
Vijayakumar,115 a two judge Bench of this Court dealt with a challenge to sub-
rule (2) of Rule 22-A of the Andhra Pradesh State and Subordinate Service
57
PART F
for a two judge Bench of this Court, adverted to the drafting history of Article
serves to place women in a cage. Article 15(3) does not exist in isolation. Articles
116
Ibid. at page 525
117 (2017) 10 SCC 800
118 Ibid. at page 837
119 Ibid. at page 837
58
PART G
paternalistic and patriarchal notions cannot claim the protection of Article 15(3).
woman has no sexual agency and that she was ‘seduced’ into a sexual
then granted to the woman in order to ‘protect’ her. The ‘protection’ afforded to
women under Section 497 highlights the lack of sexual agency that the section
imputes to a woman. Article 15(3) when read with the other Articles in Part III,
out substantive equality in the fullest sense. Dignity and autonomy are crucial to
substantive equality. Hence, Article 15(3) does not protect a statutory provision
49 Charles Jean Marie wrote in 1911120 about the central forms of adultery as
59
PART G
The law on adultery is but a codified rule of patriarchy. Patriarchy has permeated
the lives of women for centuries. Ostensibly, society has two sets of standards of
morality for judging sexual behaviour.121 One set for its female members and
Raising a woman to a pedestal is one part of the endeavour. The second part is
all about confining her to a space. The boundaries of that space are defined by
what a woman should or should not be. A society which perceives women as
even accepting of egregious discrimination within the home. This is part of the
right and what is wrong for a woman. The notion that women, who are equally
121
Nandita Haksar, Dominance, Suppression and the Law in Women and the Law: Contemporary Problems (Lotika
Sarkar and B. Sivaramayya eds.), Vikas Publishing House (1994)
122 Ibid
123 Ibid
60
PART G
dictated the social and cultural lives of women, depriving them of the guarantees
essential attributes, Courts must step in to ensure that dignity is realised in the
India124 has recognised the dangers of the “use of privacy as a veneer for
61
PART G
family as the “basis for the secondary status of women in society.”125 Menon
recognise spaces which may be considered personal such as the bedroom and
kitchen. These spaces are immersed in power relations, but with ramifications for
Control over women’s sexuality is the key patriarchal assumption that underlies
family and marriage.128 When it shifts to the ‘public’ as opposed to the ‘private’,
the misogyny becomes even more pronounced.129 Section 497 embodies this. By
number of ways. First, the husband and he alone is enabled to prosecute the
man with whom his wife has sexual relations. Even in cases where the
the reach of penal law if her husband consents to it. The second condition is a
125 Nivedita Menon, Seeing like a Feminist, Zubaan Books (2012) at page 35
126
Ibid.
127 Ibid.
128 Ibid.
129 Ibid.
62
PART G
52 In remedying injustices, the Court cannot shy away from delving into the
rights of women, the Court is not taking on a paternalistic role and “granting”
rights. The Court is merely interpreting the text of the Constitution to re-state
what is already set in ink- women are equal citizens of this nation, entitled to the
protections of the Constitution. Any legislation which results in the denial of these
iteration that misogyny and patriarchal notions of sexual control find no place in a
497 denotes that ‘adulterous women’ virtually exercise no agency; or at least not
criminal nature.131 Not only is there a denial of sexual agency, women are also
not seen to be harmed by the offence.132 Thus, the provision is not simply about
130 Ratna Kapur and Brenda Cossman, Subversive Sites: Feminist Engagements with Law in India, Sage Publications
(1996) at page 119
131 Ibid.
132 Ibid.
133 Ibid. at page 120
63
PART G
In Navtej, one of us (Chandrachud J.) held that the recognition of the autonomy
individual:
64
PART G
access to education and by economic and social progress, women have found
greater freedom to assert their choices and preferences. The law must also
guarantees of privacy and dignity. The opinion delivered on behalf of four judges
65
PART G
In Navtej, Justice Rohinton Nariman countered the assertion that the Court must
“not indulge in taking upon itself the guardianship of changing societal mores” by
holding thus:
female fidelity is enforced by the letter of the law and by the coercive authority of
the state. Such a conception goes against the spirit of the rights-based
jurisprudence of this Court, which seeks to protect the dignity of an individual and
her “intimate personal choices”. It cannot be held that these rights cease to exist
that sense, her identity does not get submerged as a result of her marriage.
Section 497 lays down the norm that the identity of a married woman is but as
the wife of her spouse. Underlying the norm is a notion of control over and
subjugation of the woman. Such notions cannot withstand scrutiny under a liberal
66
PART G
This Court in Puttaswamy has elucidated that privacy is the entitlement of every
in society.
67
PART G
an individual when “acts within their personal sphere” are criminalised on the
The Chief Justice observed that the “organisation of intimate relations” between
the “private protective sphere and realm of individual choice and autonomy” as a
personal right:
In Shakti Vahini, this Court has recognised the right to choose a partner as a
(Chandrachud J) stating:
68
PART G
of Section 497 is a blatant violation of these enunciated rights. Will a trial to prove
adultery lead the wife to tender proof of her fidelity? In Navtej, the principle was
elucidated thus:
In so far as two individuals engage in acts based on consent, the law cannot
In Puttaswamy, it was recognised that a life of dignity entails that the “inner
69
PART G
control by a man over the sexuality of his spouse. In doing that, the statutory
provision fails to meet the touchstone of Article 21. Section 497 deprives a
her right to life and personal liberty by adopting a notion of marriage which
subverts true equality. Equality is subverted by lending the sanctions of the penal
law to a gender biased approach to the relationship of a man and a woman. The
skewed against the woman. The law gives unequal voices to partners in a
relationship.
This judgment has dwelt on the importance of sexual autonomy as a value which
that each will provide to the other the same element of companionship and
founded on the equality between spouses and partners and the recognition by
each of them of the dignity of the other. Control over sexuality attaches to the
contract – does not result in ceding of the autonomy of one spouse to another.
70
PART G
elements of privacy and dignity have a bearing on the role of the state in
genesis lies in the fact that criminalizing an act is not a valid constitutional
course of a subsisting marital relationship may, and very often does question the
relationship of one of the spouses outside of the marriage may lead to the end of
the marital relationship. But in other cases, such a relationship may not be the
cause but the consequence of a pre-existing disruption of the marital tie. All too
often, spouses who have drifted apart irrevocably may be compelled for reasons
personal to them to continue with the veneer of a marriage which has ended for
all intents and purposes. The interminably long delay of the law in the resolution
human existence are too complex to place them in closed categories of right and
wrong and to subject all that is considered wrong with the sanctions of penal law.
Just as all conduct which is not criminal may not necessarily be ethically just, all
wrongdoing.
of marriage. That is the foundation on which the state does regulate rights,
71
PART G
entitlements and duties, primarily bearing on its civil nature. Breach by one of the
When the state enacts and enforces such legislation, it does so on the postulate
that marriage as a social institution has a significant bearing on the social fabric.
But in doing so, the state is equally governed by the norms of a liberal
Constitution which emphasise dignity, equality and liberty as its cardinal values.
The legitimate aims of the state may, it must be recognized, extend to imposing
penal sanctions for certain acts within the framework of marriage. Physical and
emotional abuse and domestic violence are illustrations of the need for legislative
intervention. The Indian state has legitimately intervened in other situations such
harassment of women for dowry within a marital relationship. The reason why
criminalize conduct is because the acts which the state proscribes are
women, the state intervenes to protect the fundamental rights of every woman to
does not question the authority and even the duty of the state to protect the
patriarchal values and subjugates the woman to a position where the law
72
PART H
disregards her sexuality. The sexuality of a woman is part of her inviolable core.
Neither the state nor the institution of marriage can disparage it. By reducing the
woman to the status of a victim and ignoring her needs, the provision penalizing
definitive expression of identity. Autonomy over one’s sexuality has been central
intrinsic to autonomy. It is in this view of the matter that we have concluded that
indeed, the right to pursue a meaningful life within the fold of Articles 14 and 21.
is an anathema to the ideal of dignity. Section 497 denies the individual identity
women as the property of their spouse. It is the duty of this Court to break these
stereotypes and promote a society which regards women as equal citizens in all
or ‘private’.
63 Constitutional values infuse the letter of the law with meaning. True to its
transformative vision, the text of the Constitution has, time and again, been
73
PART H
dignity and equality for its citizens. One of the most significant of the battles for
equal citizenship in the country has been fought by women. Feminists have
existence for future generations. However, the quest for equality continues.
While there has been a considerable degree of reform in the formal legal system,
been considered beyond reproach or remedy. That aspect is the family. Marriage
determine her course of life. The provision seeks to only redress perceived harm
actions in a marriage and the passivity of women. Fidelity is only expected of the
female spouse. This anachronistic conception of both, a woman who has entered
In enforcing the fundamental right to equality, this Court has evolved a test of
74
PART H
preservation of the sexual exclusivity of a married woman – for the benefit of her
husband, the owner of her sexuality. Significantly, the criminal provision exempts
from sanction if the sexual act was with the consent and connivance of the
manifestly arbitrary.
its substantive content. To construe Section 497 in a vacuum (as did Sowmithri
inforces the notion that women are unequal participants in a marriage; incapable
of freely consenting to a sexual act in a legal order which regards them as the
under the Constitution. To shackle the sexual freedom of a woman and allow the
denudes a married woman of her agency and identity, employing the force of law
constitutional morality:
75
PART H
of liberty, dignity and equality, Section 497 does not pass constitutional muster.
of the Constitution;
137Nivedita Menon, Seeing like a Feminist, Zubaan Books (2012) at page 135; quoting Archana Verma, Stree
Vimarsh Ke Mahotsav (2010)
76
PART H
2) Section 497 is based on gender stereotypes about the role of women and
Constitution;
Constitution; and
…..…..….............................................J
[Dr Dhananjaya Y Chandrachud]
New Delhi;
September 27, 2018.
77