10.1007@978 3 030 39954 2 PDF
10.1007@978 3 030 39954 2 PDF
10.1007@978 3 030 39954 2 PDF
Edited by
Antonio Oliva
Ángel Oliva
Iván Novara
Marx, Engels, and Marxisms
Series Editors
Marcello Musto
York University
Toronto, ON, Canada
Terrell Carver
University of Bristol
Bristol, UK
The Marx renaissance is underway on a global scale. Wherever the critique
of capitalism re-emerges, there is an intellectual and political demand for
new, critical engagements with Marxism. The peer-reviewed series Marx,
Engels and Marxisms (edited by Marcello Musto & Terrell Carver, with
Babak Amini and Kohei Saito as Assistant Editors) publishes monographs,
edited volumes, critical editions, reprints of old texts, as well as transla-
tions of books already published in other languages. Our volumes come
from a wide range of political perspectives, subject matters, academic dis-
ciplines and geographical areas, producing an eclectic and informative col-
lection that appeals to a diverse and international audience. Our main
areas of focus include: the oeuvre of Marx and Engels, Marxist authors
and traditions of the 19th and 20th centuries, labour and social move-
ments, Marxist analyses of contemporary issues, and reception of Marxism
in the world.
Marx and
Contemporary Critical
Theory
The Philosophy of Real Abstraction
Editors
Antonio Oliva Ángel Oliva
National University of Rosario National University of Rosario
Rosario, Argentina Rosario, Argentina
Iván Novara
National University of Rosario
Rosario, Argentina
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer
Nature Switzerland AG 2020
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the
Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of
translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on
microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval,
electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now
known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this
publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are
exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information
in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the
publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect
to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made.
The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and
institutional affiliations.
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature
Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Titles Published
1. Terrell Carver & Daniel Blank, A Political History of the Editions of
Marx and Engels’s “German Ideology” Manuscripts,
2014.
2. Terrell Carver & Daniel Blank, Marx and Engels’s “German Ideology”
Manuscripts: Presentation and Analysis of the “Feuerbach chap-
ter,” 2014.
3. Alfonso Maurizio Iacono, The History and Theory of Fetishism, 2015.
4. Paresh Chattopadhyay, Marx’s Associated Mode of Production: A
Critique of Marxism, 2016.
5. Domenico Losurdo, Class Struggle: A Political and Philosophical
History, 2016.
6. Frederick Harry Pitts, Critiquing Capitalism Today: New Ways to
Read Marx, 2017.
7. Ranabir Samaddar, Karl Marx and the Postcolonial Age, 2017.
8. George Comninel, Alienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl
Marx, 2018.
9. Jean-Numa Ducange & Razmig Keucheyan (Eds.), The End of the
Democratic State: Nicos Poulantzas, a Marxism for the 21st
Century, 2018.
10. Robert Ware, Marx on Emancipation and the Socialist Transition:
Retrieving Marx for the Future, 2018.
11. Xavier LaFrance & Charles Post (Eds.), Case Studies in the Origins of
Capitalism, 2018.
12. John Gregson, Marxism, Ethics, and Politics: The Work of Alasdair
MacIntyre, 2018.
v
vi TITLES PUBLISHED
13. Vladimir Puzone & Luis Felipe Miguel (Eds.), The Brazilian Left in
the 21st Century: Conflict and Conciliation in Peripheral
Capitalism, 2019.
14. James Muldoon & Gaard Kets (Eds.), The German Revolution and
Political Theory, 2019.
15. Michael Brie, Rediscovering Lenin: Dialectics of Revolution and
Metaphysics of Domination, 2019.
16. August H. Nimtz, Marxism versus Liberalism: Comparative Real-
Time Political Analysis, 2019.
17. Gustavo Moura de Cavalcanti Mello and Mauricio de Souza Sabadini
(Eds.), Financial Speculation and Fictitious Profits: A Marxist
Analysis, 2019.
18. Shaibal Gupta, Marcello Musto & Babak Amini (Eds), Karl Marx’s
Life, Ideas, and Influences: A Critical Examination on the
Bicentenary, 2019.
19. Igor Shoikhedbrod, Revisiting Marx’s Critique of Liberalism:
Rethinking Justice, Legality, and Rights, 2019
20. Juan Pablo Rodríguez, Resisting Neoliberal Capitalism in Chile: The
Possibility of Social Critique, 2019
Titles Forthcoming
vii
viii TITLES FORTHCOMING
This volume has been something of a miracle for us. Twenty years ago, the
logistics of publishing such a global contributor list and of bringing
together scholars from the many countries represented in this table of
contents would have made this book impossible. And although this vol-
ume is a result of our respect for and conviction in a work that we feel
continues to offer the deepest and most complete explanation of how our
old and battered world works, this miraculous project could not have been
realized without the invaluable help of many people. As the nobility
obliges, here go our thanks.
In the first place, we thank each and every one of the authors whose
contributions really make the Marxist theory come alive again. To Palgrave
Macmillan, represented by North American Politics & Political Theory
Editor Michelle Chen, for trusting that this project had a future, and for
its tireless management. We thank comrades Terrell Carver and Marcello
Musto who, with their reading and unconditional support, monitored the
entire process to its completion. To the editorial review staff whose sug-
gestions made the project executable and possible. To Anahí Prucca (who
has translated the articles of Pablo Nocera, Sergio Tischler and Mario
Duayer), Sol Golzman (who has translated the articles of Cristián Sucksdorf
and Mauricio Vieira Martins), Santiago Soulignac (who has translated the
articles of Alberto Bonnet), Alex Locascio (who has translated the articles
of Ingo Enlbe and Wolfgang Fritz Haug) and Renata Farías (who has
translated the introduction) for their hard work translating many of the
articles in this volume, and especially to Andrés Pacheco (who has trans-
lated the introduction), who involved himself lovingly in the project and
ix
x ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
whose selfless and professional work was more than just a translation. To
our fellow countrymen and collaborators of this volume—Cristián
Sucksdorf, Pablo Nocera, and Alberto Bonnet—as well as our fellow col-
laborators in Brazil—Mauricio Vieira Martins, Mario Duayer and Ricardo
Gaspar Muller—who, because of their proximity, supported the project
directly and enthusiastically. To our partner and friend Juan Pablo Lewis
who monitored as native speaker more than one translation that appears
here. Our huge thanks to Yael Geisner who read these texts critically even
before they were a book. A special acknowledgment also to each and every
one of the people who worked on the MEGA2 volume which made the
immeasurable work of Marx and Engels available, now, to the world. A
special mention to our families who make our intellectual work have a
concrete and affective sense. Finally, and although it seems obvious, we are
indebted to the works of Marx and that of Engels, without which the
specificity and importance of the issues that are put into play here would
not make sense.
Contents
1 Introduction 1
Antonio Oliva, Ángel Oliva, and Iván Novara
xi
xii CONTENTS
xv
xvi NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS
Introduction
capital, which destroys life. On the other, we see the loss of theoretical and
political references at an international scale required to restrain it in order
to establish a society founded on bases other than wealth as value. This
capitalism does not allow us to envision a hopeful future for the large
majorities and pauperized peoples. Despite this, and in significant con-
trast, during these last three decades, the most fruitful and non-dogmatic
rereadings of Marx’s oeuvre and, to a lesser extent, of Marxism as a whole
have proliferated at a global scale, conforming for the first time since the
late nineteenth century a true corpus of interpretations that begin to be
connected to current non-conformist movements.
Regarding the analysis and interpretation of Marxian works, the differ-
ent current rereadings, reinterpretations, and theoretical and political
reconsiderations are, without a doubt, heterogeneous, but they all com-
prise three aspects which, in our consideration, unify them.
To begin with, new approaches, both collective and individual, to Marx’s
oeuvre, have been forged from outside—and often stemmed from a devas-
tating critique of—the main two Marxist currents of the twentieth century,
that is, social democracy and Soviet-style Marxism–Leninism, which, even
when they represented an alternative to capitalism, not only failed, but to a
certain extent fostered the theoretical and practical sustainment of capitalist
regimes. Notwithstanding the undeniable contribution of both currents to
the reconstruction and dissemination of Marx’s ideas and, more preva-
lently, to the elaboration of political programs and interpretations within
clearly revolutionary contexts, some of them successful, it is also undeni-
able that their partial and dogmatic approach to as well as religious canon-
ization of Marxian works precluded the development of a true political
alternative capable of overcoming capitalism. As a result, they have both
stalled and fossilized since at least the 1970s.
In this sense, the aforementioned new contributions, freed from such
dogmatism, have carried out novel rereadings of Marx’s oeuvre by address-
ing some of its most overlooked aspects and through the critical analysis of
its better-known theoretical premises. At the same time, they have
attempted to reconstruct Marx’s oeuvre, something significantly difficult,
due not only to the vicissitudes of Marx’s writings after his death, but also
to their constant mutilation and distortion by the aforementioned social–
democratic and Marxist–Leninist currents of Marxian thought.
The most ambitious contemporary project to reconstruct Marx and
Engel’s oeuvre is the Marx–Engels–Gesamtausgabe (MEGA2), which aims
at producing a new comprehensive edition of Marx’s and Engels’s com-
1 INTRODUCTION 3
plete works. It started in the 1970s and is still ongoing. Initially published
by the Marxism–Leninism Institutes of the Socialist Unity Party of
Germany (SED) in Berlin and the Communist Party of the Soviet Union
(CPSU) in Moscow, under the direction of Dietz Verlag (Berlin), MEGA
includes all works published during the life of Marx and Engels and many
previously unpublished manuscripts and letters. All texts in MEGA are in
their original language: the majority in German, but with many in English
and French. Being an academic, historical and critical edition, most of the
volumes in MEGA include appendices that provide additional information
about each text. After the fall of the Berlin Wall, the publication of the
MEGA project was transferred to the Internationale Marx–Engels–
Stiftung (IMES) in Amsterdam, which is still working on it. So far, 65
MEGA volumes have been published, and the whole project is expected to
comprise 114 volumes (Musto 2011; Fineschi 2013).
Secondly, the emphasis in the critique of Marx’s oeuvre, in our opinion,
has conveniently moved from highlighting the most traditional aspects of
the theory, such as exploitation in capitalist systems (the theory of surplus
value and its developments) and the subjects who bear emancipating
essences within a class structure (the working class, the proletariat), toward
the production of several readings which focus on the critique of political
economy and review the critique to the ideology of mercantile society.
More specifically, these readings emphasize the validity of the theory of
value-labor, the objective character of capital’s social domination through
the abstract forms of value and the articulation between such abstract
forms and Marx’s specific method of analyzing capitalism.
Precisely, beyond their heterogeneity, the emphasis of contemporary
approaches has been on the specific character of each historical era and on
readings that understand the forms assumed by social wealth through
value in capitalism as non-transhistorical,1 as well as on the structural char-
acter of abstract and social labor as first-order determinations in the theory
of value, and even the analytical method adopted by Marx when rereading
Hegel. Furthermore, there has been a painstaking effort to delimit, mainly
through the idea of crisis sketched by the different contributions to the
critique of political economy, the possible ‘passages’ to societies not gov-
erned by class divisions and not determined by the forms of wealth based
on value-labor (Kurz 2000; Jappe 2003).2
Thirdly, with different degrees of accuracy and adherence to Marx’s
oeuvre, Marxist scholarship of the last 30 years has become increasingly
more transnational, something which so far has not received enough
4 A. OLIVA ET AL.
On the other hand, there were new readings of Marxism that, as we have
seen, reread the Marx of the critique of political economy and, more spe-
cifically, the qualitative analysis of value which, through the simple form of
the commodity and its unfolding into use value and value, are presented
as objective forms of exchange products.3
Since then, many theoretical problems have derived from Sohn-Rethel’s
thesis. This volume attempts to trace them throughout the debates of the
last few decades which are regarded as central to Marxian thought.
First, Sohn-Rethel’s theoretical position regarding the transhistorical
character of real abstraction differ from the way it was conceived by the
mature Marx. When Sohn-Rethel restricts the synthetic operations of
abstraction to the transactional moment of exchange, making even the
conversion of human labor into abstract labor, he removes the conver-
gence of practical determinations that Marx establishes to explain the set
of abstract forms—from the simplest ones, led by the genesis of value in
commodities, to the more concrete ones, like the production of the form
of capital—which make up mercantile production in contemporary societ-
ies. In this sense, the transhistorical character of the concept restricts
abstract social relations to the synthetic field of the market, excluding the
phenomenic character where exchanges appear in capitalist societies. In
this manner, the determinant character of abstract human labor as labor
time, considered as the substance of the value of commodities, is blurred
as the determination of the abstract character of commodities. Thus, in
Sohn-Rethel we see a true inversion of the determinations presented by
Marx already in the Grundrisse of 1857. The best recent productions
about real abstraction, some of them included in this volume, resume a
critique of Sohn-Rethel, recovering perspectives such as those found in
Isaak Rubin’s groundbreaking Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value (1973) by
or in Hans Georg Backhaus’s classic Dialektik der Wertform (1997). They
adopt the Marxian analysis of abstract labor and socially mediated labor in
capitalism as key and historically determined concepts, fundamental to
understanding social forms abstracted at the moment of exchange.
Second, Sohn-Rethel establishes an identity and an unmistakable kin-
ship between abstract processes occurring in the conformation of practical
relations between people in exchanges and cognitive faculties resulting
from said practical relations, something fundamental to delimit the prob-
lem. Attempting to enlighten the epistemic differences between the con-
ceptual elements in Kantian philosophy and in a Marxian materialistic
approach, Sohn-Rethel sets out to demonstrate that the relation between
1 INTRODUCTION 7
inherited from our philosophical traditions. This maneuver is, in turn, elu-
sive with regard to the idealist matrix with which said ontology constructed
the duality of idealism and materialism. With a specific utilization of
Foucaultian epistemology, centered in the notion of discourse, Sukdorf
attempts to prove that Marx expanded the field of the real, regarding
philosophical tradition, to ‘include in it the meaning as articulation of the
bodies’. If Marx deals mainly with an investigation related to the specific
articulation between bodies and representations in capitalist society, the
question is, then, ‘to account for the differential ways in which representa-
tions—the meaning—constitute real practices and thus modify the bodies
and their interrelations, but also, how that meaning forms in the active
life—in actual, concrete practices—of the many interrelated bodies’. The
real contradiction—bound to practices whose meaning for mercantile
society is, in principle, potency—is not a contradiction residing within the
concept or a contradiction in general. It is instead the specific support,
namely the source, of the abstractions of a historical intertwining between
bodies and representations. In this sense, contradiction is also an attribute
of the universalization of dynamics in a social system based on abstract
forms of sociability. The cellular form of this contradiction, which inocu-
lates into real life its abstracting poison, is on the one hand the double
contradictory condition within its body of the commodity as use value,
that is as the product of concrete labor, and as value, that is as the product
of abstract labor; and, on the other, that in the horizon of representation,
we deal with physical and metaphysical, sensible and suprasensible, indi-
vidual and universal, private and social elements as we appreciate its repro-
ductive generalization. The isomorphism in the experience of subjects,
with its unsolvable duality in the field of capitalist relations present in the
body of the commodity, locates the subjective aspect of abstract thought
in consistency with the hidden hardness of the contradiction that subtends
it. This isomorphism of the forms of consciousness with the contradictory
and hidden nature of the commodity locates Marx’s analysis of the com-
modity in a place that overcomes inherited philosophical dualities.
Ingo Elbe’s text addresses the risk of Lukacs’s drift toward idealism due
to the lack of systematization of the Marxian concept of reification in his
oeuvre. The fact that Lukacs treated several topics present in Marx over-
looking the importance of this key concept ‘had fatal consequences for the
entire history of the reception of the term, since this conceptual diffuse-
ness, paired with a Hegelian metaphysics of spirit, led to an idealist (all
social interrelations are mental things) and irrational social ontology
1 INTRODUCTION 17
also focuses on two topics which are key to our purpose: first, the episte-
mological consequences for the type of critical social theory which includes
in its several fields of application the fact of conceiving phenomena as
objective when they are of an abstract nature, and second the considerable
differentiation between an abstraction which corresponds to the objective
occurrence of social phenomena and another one which corresponds to
the critical exercise which chases such social phenomena.
The tight relation between the categories of political economy revealed
by Marx and the reconstruction of the contextual field category by cate-
gory which he undertakes pose the question of the effectiveness of the
‘method’ in A Critique of Political Economy. This relation is surrounded
by an objectivity whose specific historical condition is to conceal its sub-
stance. The Marxian method, therefore, operates as a path of genetic
reconstruction of said concealments, which requires the exercise of
abstraction itself to fulfill the passage from the abstract to the concrete. As
it proceeds, it accounts for the systemic causes by means of which political
economy produced a process of resubjectivation of the general historical
categories in the mode of production. Wolfang Fitz Haug’s contribution
reconstructs the saga of the reconstruction the workings of political econ-
omy from outside until the question which political economy itself had
not put forth is revealed: Why does material content historically adopt the
form of value? At the same time, this reconstruction of the categorical
array of political economy poses the question of why the latter has stopped
reasoning before stating this issue. A central aspect of Fitz Haug’s contri-
bution consists of signaling that this process of pursuing the nature of
things themselves through hardened categories is present in Marx since
the critique to Feuerbach. Another central aspect of his analysis consists of
highlighting that the genetics intrinsic to the form of value requires an
abstraction, in principle, of the effective exchange, in order to demon-
strate that this is its condition of possibility. The connection between both
aspects takes place in the fundamental conclusion for social theory that
genetic and historical explanations are not the same, because in the
categorical subjectification typical of the unveiling of political economy
there is a kind of abstraction equivalent to the way in which value works in
the concrete sphere of the social system. Therefore, ‘the abstraction of the
category “labor” [is] not to be confused with the concept of “abstract
labor”’, since here ‘[t]he truth of the abstraction here stands for the fact
that—as Adorno says in the appropriate context—it clings to (schmigtsich
an) a practical reality’. Yet, if the simple form of value proceeds toward the
1 INTRODUCTION 19
more complex forms in the abstract sphere, always in relation to but sepa-
rated from the continuous phenomenon of exchange, the ‘interest in
exchanges’ always presents a mercantile aesthetics (presented here as the
conceptual innovation of the Haug’s contribution) which can only stand
on the other leg of the contradiction intrinsic to the commodity: the use
value of things. A mercantile aesthetics which creates images of use value
becomes the condition that underpins exchange, as a consequence of
goods being compelled to be valued as commodities. If this is the case,
then, ‘[t]he abstraction from use value manifests itself as the aesthetic
promise of use value and leads to the formation of aesthetic monopolies of
use value. In short: real abstraction appears here as illusory concreteness
for the purchasing masses’.
Oliver Schlaudt and Peter McLaughlin’s chapter deals with the episte-
mological implications of real abstraction. Thinking of the problem as a
conceptual field for application, the authors attempt to derive the notion
to the field of the natural sciences, in particular, to an epistemology of
physics rooted in the history of technology, a sphere where there are
extensive experiences of the operation of practical abstraction. Taking into
consideration that the kind of abstraction analyzed by Sohn-Rethel in
exchange sphere points out to a ‘special’ kind of real abstraction from a
‘more general’ set of practical abstractions, the authors highlight a general
morphology of abstraction in technological experience that proceeds by
‘analogous types of abstractions’. At stake here is Sohn-Rethel’s assump-
tion that the experience of exchange defines the general form of science,
as it provides, by means of mimetic procedures which remain hidden, a
base of experience for the emergence of the categorical base of Kantian
subjectivism. According to Schlaudt and McLaughlin, by resorting to the
history of technology, it is possible to grasp a more significant experience
in these procedures, based on the diversification of “technical devices”
which put to different uses resulted in applied abstractive practices. It is
stated that when Marx undertakes the genetic explanation of value, he also
proceeds with diverse elements that can be made analogous for different
ends. The aim of Schlaudt and McLaughlin is ‘to discuss the extent to
which abstraction, understood in this way, can be regarded as a common
phenomenon in the history of science, and thus as a useful key to concept
formation in the science’.
Finally, the implications in the substratum of social domination that these
forms of abstraction imply regarding the systemic dynamics of the commod-
ity-producing society in relation to the homogenization of socialized life and
20 A. OLIVA ET AL.
Notes
1. Perhaps it is Michael Postone’s (1993) already classic work that has most
emphasized his criticism of transhistoric planks in Marx’s work.
2. This group is part of the ‘wertkritik’ (value criticism) movement, and pub-
lishes a magazine of the same name, Krisis, in the German language. Its
main references are known: Robert Kurz, Roswitha Scholz, Ernst Lohoff,
Franz Schandl, Norbert Trenkle y Claus-Peter Ortlieb.
1 INTRODUCTION 21
References
Arthur, C. (2004). The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Backhaus, H. G. (1997). Dialektik der Wertform. Freiburg: ç ́a ira.
Elbe, I. (2013). Between Marx, Marxism, and Marxisms–Ways of Reading Marx’s
Theory. Retrieved August 10, 2019, from https://www.viewpointmag.com/.
Fineschi, R. (2013). Karl Marx después de la edición histórico-crítica (MEGA2):
Un nuevo objeto de investigación. Laberinto, no. 38.
Heinrich, M. (2004). An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital.
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Jappe, A. (2003). Les Aventures de la marchandise, pour une nouvelle critique de la
valeur. Paris: Ed. Denoël.
Kurz, R. (2000). Marx Lesen. Die wichtigsten Texte von Karl Marx für das 21.
Jahrhundert. Frankfurt am Main: Eichborn.
Moseley, F., & Smith, T. (2014). Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic. A
Reexamination. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Musto, M. (Coord.). (2011). Tras las huellas de un fantasma. México: Siglo XXI.
Musto, M. (2015). De regreso a Marx. Nuevas lecturas y vigencia en el mundo
actual. Buenos Aires: Octubre Ed.
Postone, M. (1993). Time, Labor and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of
Marx’s Critical Theory. New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Reichelt, H. (2007). Marx’s Critique of Economic Categories: Reflections on the
Problem of Validity in the Dialectical Method of Presentation in Capital.
Historical Materialism, 15(4), 3–52.
Rubin, I. I. (1973). Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value. Montreal: Black Rose.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (2001). Trabajo intelectual y trabajo manual. Critica de la episte-
mología. Barcelona: Ed. Viejo Topo.
PART I
John Milios
The Marxist concept of value is radically different from the Ricardian con-
cept of value as ‘labor expended’. Unlike the Ricardian theory of value, the
Marxist theory of value is a monetary theory. In the Marxist system, the value
of a commodity cannot be defined in isolation, but exclusively in relation to
all other commodities, in the process of exchange. In this relation of exchange,
value is materialized in money. The essential feature of the ‘market econ-
omy’ (of capitalism) is thus not simply commodity exchange but monetary
circulation and money. Barter is for Marx non-existing, as all exchange
transactions are made up of separate acts of exchange of commodities
with money.
J. Milios (*)
Department of Humanities Social Sciences and Law, National Technical
University of Athens, Athens, Greece
unskilled laborer, the two types of work must already constitute ‘qualita-
tively similar’ (i.e. abstract) labor.
In conclusion: The products of labor are commodities, values and
exchange values, not simply because they are products of labor but because
they are products of abstract labor, that is ‘capitalist labor’ (labor which is
performed under capitalist conditions, within the framework of the capitalist
mode of production), labor creating products-for-exchange-and-for-profit:
commodities. Abstract labor produces value-carrying commodities. Value
constitutes the relation of general exchangeability of commodities, and is
expressed through money—their common measure, which lacks every pred-
icate beyond that of size.
Here it is worth noting two points:
(a) Abstract labor (and consequently ‘abstract labor time’) is not a
straightforward (empirically verifiable) property of labor but an ‘abstrac-
tion’, that is a social form which expresses the social homogenization of
labor in the capitalist mode of production. Marx’s notion of abstract labor
renders thus comprehensible this very process of social homogenization of
labor under the capitalist mode of production: ‘Universal labor-time itself is
an abstraction which, as such, does not exist for commodities’ (Marx
1981: 45).
That which empirically exists is merely the specific commodities which
are bought and sold on the market (and so exchanged with money).
(b) Abstract labor, as the concept which conveys the specifically social
(capitalist) character of the labor process, does not have to do with each
separate productive procedure but with the social interrelation of all the
separate, institutionally unrelated, capitalist productive processes, as this
interrelation reveals itself in the market-place: ‘Social labour-time exists in
these commodities in a latent state, so to speak, and becomes evident only
in the course of their exchange […]. Universal social labour is conse-
quently not a ready-made prerequisite but an emerging result’ (Idem: 45).
These two issues suggest why the whole weight of the analysis must be
placed on the manifestation of value as exchange value (the ‘form of
appearance’ of value) and this is where Marx places it: he does not close
his analysis of value with the concept of abstract labor but on the contrary
devotes by far the greatest part of his analysis (107 of the 120 pages of Part
I of Vol. 1 of Capital) to the value form, or value as an exchange relation
between commodities, and to money.
The price expressing the general exchangeability for any commodity
with all others is the sole objective materialization (form of appearance) of
30 J. MILIOS
The reality of the value of commodities differs in this respect from Dame
Quickly, that we don’t know “where to have it”. The value of commodities
is the very opposite of the coarse materiality of their substance, not an atom
of matter enters into its composition. Turn and examine a single commod-
ity, by itself, as we will, yet in so far as it remains an object of value, it seems
impossible to grasp it. […]. Value can only manifest itself in the social relation
of commodity to commodity. In fact, we started from exchange-value, or the
exchange relation of commodities, in order to get at the value that lies hid-
den behind it. We must now return to this form under which value first
appeared to us. (Marx 1990: 138–139, emphasis added)
Marx’s whole analysis makes clear that the notion of abstract labor does
not mainly refer to a process of subjective or intellectual appropriation of
reality (by Marx or any other intellectual), but to an objective process: the
formation of an aspect of the structure of capitalist reality, the typical con-
figuration of certain elements of this reality. Deciphering this reality is
then characteristic of Marx’s analysis, which conveys the causal relation-
ships that regulate reality without ever themselves appearing as such in the
realm of empirical reality and of appearance, since they do not belong to
the tangible entities and phenomena (Marx 1990: 433, 680).
The conclusion that may be inferred from the above theses is that the
value of commodities never appears as such, as an immediately perceivable
(empirically observable) and thus measurable entity. It finds expression
only through the form of its appearance, that is commodity prices. This
form of appearance of value does not, as we have argued, relate to each
commodity separately, that is to say, it is not a matter of isolated, of ini-
tially mutually independent expressions of the value of each commodity.
The form registers the relationship of exchange between each commodity
and all other commodities.
first three chapters of the first volume of Capital before offering a defini-
tion of capitalism (the capitalist mode of production—CMP). This method
of exposition, aiming at the gradual maturation of concepts, has led cer-
tain Marxists to the view that value is not a constituent category of the
concept of the CMP but that it gives a preliminary description of a (sup-
posed) historical epoch of commodity production, which preceded
capitalism.
As argued above, Marx introduces this concept of generalized com-
modity production only as an intellectual construct that will help him to
approach and then to establish the concept of capitalist production.
In one of his latest texts, Marx himself describes his method as follows:
De prime abord, I do not proceed from ‘concepts,’ hence neither from the
‘concept of value,’ and am therefore in no way concerned to ‘divide’ it.
What I proceed from is the simplest social form in which the product of
labour presents itself in contemporary society, and this is the ‘commodity.’
This I analyse, initially in the form in which it appears. […] The mere form
of appearance is not its own content. […] For this reason when analysing the
commodity, I do not immediately drag in definitions of ‘capital,’ not even
when dealing with the ‘use-value’ of the commodity. Such definitions are
bound to be sheer nonsense as long as we have advanced no further than the
analysis of the elements of the commodity. (Marx 1881)
been generally realized’ (de Ste. Croix 1981: 258). Perry Anderson also
writes along these lines:
In ancient societies, apart from the dominant classic slave mode of pro-
duction, there also existed the following forms and modes of production:
In the words of Aristotle, the process has ‘no limit to the end it seeks;
and the end it seeks is wealth of the sort we have mentioned […] the mere
acquisition of currency […] all who are engaged in acquisition increase
their fund of money without any limit or pause’ (cited by Meikle 1995: 59).
Marx clearly differentiates the money-begetting slave mode of produc-
tion from the classic (or ‘patriarchal’) slave mode of production (of the
absentee slave-owner, who is dissociated from the management of the
means of production): on different occasions he repeatedly stresses the
2 VALUE FORM AND ABSTRACT LABOR IN MARX: A CRITICAL REVIEW… 35
It is true that the capitalist mode of production is the only social organiza-
tion of the economy which implies generalized commodity production. It
would thus be completely mistaken to consider for example Hellenistic slave
society or the classical Islamic Empire—two forms of society with strongly
developed petty commodity production, money economy and international
trade—as being ruled by the ‘law of value’. Commodity production in these
pre-capitalist modes of production is intertwined with, and in the last analy-
sis subordinated to, organizations of production (in the first place agricul-
tural production) of a clearly non-capitalist nature, which follow a different
economic logic from that which governs exchanges between commodities
or the accumulation of capital. (Mandel 1991: 14–15)
Notes
1. ‘The specific economic form in which unpaid surplus labour is pumped out
of the direct producers determines the relationship of domination and ser-
vitude, as this grows directly out of production itself and reacts back on it
in turn as a determinant’ (Marx 1991: 927).
2. ‘The concept of value is entirely peculiar to the most modern economy,
since it is the most abstract expression of capital itself and of the production
resting on it. In the concept of value, its secret is betrayed […]. The eco-
nomic concept of value does not occur in antiquity’ (Marx 1993: 776 ff.).
3. ‘The value form of the product of labour is the most abstract, but also the most
general form of the bourgeois mode of production as a particular kind of
social production of a historical and transitory character’ (Marx 1990: 174).
4. As Christopher Arthur writes: ‘What is extraordinary about Sohn-Rethel is
that he shows that social abstraction occurs as a result of the practical
action of exchangers and obtains with objective validity regardless of
whether they are aware of it’ (Arthur 2010: 1).
5. ‘I was the first to point out and examine critically this twofold nature of the
labour contained in commodities’ (Marx 1990: 132).
6. A characteristic instance is that of Rosdolsky. In his book The Making of
Marx’s Capital, which had a significant influence on post-World War II
Marxist theoretical analysis, he maintains that decline from the ‘craftsman-
ship’ of the pre-capitalist artisan led to concrete labor becoming ‘abstract
labor’. He writes: ‘Marx accepted the thesis of Ricardo, which is confirmed
by the workings of the market, that what is involved is a reduction of spe-
cialised labour to unspecialised’ (Rosdolsky 1969: 609. Also see Rosdolsky
1977: 510 ff.).
7. ‘By the end of the fifth century, as we know from the Erechtheum accounts,
wage rates of one drachma per day were common. The daily pay of sailors
38 J. MILIOS
in the fleet was also between one drachma per day […] and half a drachma
[…] and the daily pay of dicasts was half a drachma from 425 onwards’ (de
Ste. Croix 2004: 43). ‘The poorer women of Athens and, presumably, of
other cities also worked for wages’ (Kyrtatas 2011: 105).
8. In the Grundrisse Marx makes clear that he refers to economic forms which
function ‘not as themselves forms of capital, but as earlier forms of wealth,
as presuppositions for capital’ (Marx 1993: 504).
9. In the antiquity, ‘no single statesman is known to have been a practising
merchant, and no merchant is known to have played a prominent part in
politics, even at Athens. The merchants were not all […] both non-citizens
and men of little or no property; but […] their influence on politics, as
merchants, was certainly infinitesimal’ (de Ste. Croix 2004: 356).
10. Karl Marx has also stressed this view: ‘Do we never find in antiquity an
inquiry into which form of landed property etc. is the most productive,
creates the greatest wealth? Wealth does not appear as the aim of produc-
tion, although Cato may well investigate which manner of cultivating a
field brings the greatest rewards, and Brutus may even lend out his money
at the best rates of interest. The question is always which mode of property
creates the best citizens’ (Marx 1993: 487).
References
Anderson, P. (1974). Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism. London: New
Left Books.
Arthur, Ch. (2010). Abstraction, Universality and Money. 7th Annual Conference,
Marx and Philosophy Society, Institute of Education, University of
London, June 5.
Keynes, J. M. (2013). The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes (Vol. XXVIII,
Social, Political and Literary Writings) (pp. 253–254). Cambridge University Press.
Kyrtatas, D. (2002). Domination and Exploitation. In P. Cartledge, E. E. Cohen,
& L. Foxhall (Eds.), Money, Labour and Land: Approaches to the Economies of
Ancient Greece (pp. 140–155). London and New York: Routledge.
Kyrtatas, D. (2011). Slavery and Economy in the Greek World. In B. Keith &
P. Cartledge (Eds.), The Cambridge World History of Slavery (pp. 91–111).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mandel, E. (1991). Introduction. In K. Marx (Ed.), Capital (Vol. 3). London:
Penguin Classics.
Marx, K. (1881). Notes on Adolph Wagner’s ‘Lehrbuch der politischen Ökonomie’
(2nd ed., Vol. I), 1879. Retrieved December 2, 2017, from https://www.
marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1881/01/wagner.htm.
Marx, K. (1981). A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. London:
Lawrenceand Wishart.
2 VALUE FORM AND ABSTRACT LABOR IN MARX: A CRITICAL REVIEW… 39
Pablo Nocera
Introduction
By the end of 1841, a young Engels irascibly contested, under a pseud-
onym and from the pages of the Telegraph für Deutschland, the attempt by
an old Schelling—with the royal support of Frederick William IV of
Prussia—to give an end to the menace that Hegelian philosophy repre-
sented to the state and to the manner in which it was growing at the time
within a group of radical epigones. The so-called positive philosophy that
Schelling presented in his first Berlin lecture seemed to offer, from the
point of view of Marx’s future companion, only an update to the previous
works that, beyond their clear intention to be old-fashioned, were not able
affect the power of Hegelianism and its philosophy of negativity. Such
contestation was replicated diversely in an auditorium full of Hegelians,
including the young Søren Kierkegaard, Mijail Bakunin and Arnold Ruge.
Even though it was questioned because of the political context in which it
emerged, Schelling’s position made visible a distrust that a young
P. Nocera (*)
Buenos Aires National University (UBA), Buenos Aires, Argentina
Hegelianism would start to elaborate within the following five years. The
practical results emerging from the theoretical power of Hegel’s dialectics
were being made evident in a conservative political horizon. The return to
Fichte by referents such as von Cieszkowski and Moses Hess served as
warning that praxis had been gradually devaluated, and that thought was
being favored as a superior activity, making it impossible for German phi-
losophy to acquire a practical concretion that, in France and Great Britain,
had been embodied in respective revolutionary processes.
This chapter explores the notion of abstraction in the brief, prolific
course in which the young Hegelian heritage deploys it, to a great extent,
as a true detachment from the legacy of its master. The purpose of this
chapter is, in particular, to address the initial uses by Feuerbach as an ana-
lytical support of his critique of the forms of alienation, to explore later the
statements by a young Marx in his Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts
of 1844, but noting between both positions a specificity not always prop-
erly appreciated. It is well known that, for Feuerbach, alienation is a
denunciation nurtured by a critique of religion and (Hegelian) philoso-
phy, thus providing an analytical matrix that can very well be projected to
the state and to private property, with an emphasis on labor. This was the
exercise consummated by Marx during those years. Nonetheless, a more
careful reading makes evident the importance of the reflection by Moses
Hess as an impulse for this displacement, a sample of which can be traced
to the pages of a brief text entitled Über das Geldwesen (The Essence of
Money). Specifically, we attempt to look at the reasons for Feuerbach to
invoke the notion of abstraction and the manners in which he mentions it
to account for alienation, in order to later expose the appropriations and
displacements offered by Hess’ exploration. This journey gives way to a
reflection about the senses in which Marx uses the term in an early analysis
of money, as they not only directly set forth his position but also help us
to explore an early reflection about a form of social abstraction that deploys
a logic of exchange and whose realization only materializes in the dyna-
mism of a central aspect of the organizations of capitalist forms of
production.
3 MONEY AS A PRACTICAL ABSTRACTION: FROM FEUERBACH TO MARX… 43
critique: man has been estranged in the Christian god, and it only subjects
itself to its own estrangement: ‘Religion is the division [Entzweiung] of
man from himself; he considers God as a being opposed to him. God is
not man, man is not God […] In religion, man objectivizes his secret
essence. It is therefore necessary to demonstrate that this opposition, this
division between God and man with which religion begins is a division
between man and his own essence’ (Feuerbach 1960: 41/tr. 1995: 85). At
a distance from Hegelian statements, religion is far from being a media-
tion that serves to reach infinity. Rather, as an expression of human inver-
sion, of an essence which is not recognized, man as a generic essence
[Gattungswesen] is estranged from his condition, placing in the figure of a
deity the whole potential to which he is subsumed and does not recognize
as his own: ‘The absolute being, the God of man, is his own essence. The
power that the object [Gegenstandes] has over him is, therefore, the power
of his own essence’ (Feuerbach 1960: 6/tr. 1995: 57).
Man’s alienation implies that this reality in which he is trapped is
unknown. Feuerbach’s arguments are focused on the relation between
man and God as a relation between subject and predicate: the subject is
the condensation of all its predicates. If the predicate is true of the subject,
it is possible to understand why the figure of God can only be a human
creation. The predicates attributed to the deity are only human character-
istics brought to their ultimate expression, therefore, ‘[…] if the divine
predicates are determinations of the human essence, their subject would
also be a human being’ (Feuerbach 1960: 30/tr. 1995: 76). The manner
in which Feuerbach conceives the division (i.e. alienation) does not
imply—as opposed to a Hegelian perspective—a provisional moment that
projects, inevitably, a reconciliation in experience. Opposed to Hegel, for
whom experience as a departure from the self (a loss of the self) consti-
tutes a precondition for a richer formative process in the subject’s consti-
tution, for Feuerbach alienation implies a negative process, a loss,
something close to straying, which departs from the potency of negativity
circumscribed by the master’s statement. This estrangement is embodied
in the generic condition. The mantle of religion ends up hiding, under the
divinity, the original human condition: ‘Man—this is the mystery of reli-
gion—objectivizes his essence and becomes in turn an object of this objec-
tive being, transformed into a subject, into a person; he is thought as an
object of an object, as an object of another being’ (Feuerbach 1960: 37/
tr. 1995: 80). Once the estrangement is consummated, religion cannot be
the space of containment of collective life. The generic essence may
3 MONEY AS A PRACTICAL ABSTRACTION: FROM FEUERBACH TO MARX… 45
Self-taught and detached from academic circles, Moses Hess started devel-
oping, by the end of 1830, an early concern about the transformations in
Europe under the Restoration. Against the main role assigned by many of
his Hegelian contemporaries to the German spirit as a future interpreter of
human revolution, Hess defended a wider perspective (introduced in
1841 in European Triarchy), supported by the conviction that Europe had
a culture and a past, which provided it with a unity that would not be
necessary to impose. The historical conditions to overcome national
boundaries were there. From a philosophical standpoint, Europe’s union
was sealed in Saint-Simon and Hegel: ‘One of them [Saint-Simon] per-
ceived the future, was full of the action and of the enthusiasm of a passion-
ate heart; the other one [Hegel] perceived the past, inclined toward
contemplation and possessed by a logical and cold spirit’ (Hess 1961:
148). To this he adds, in a third place, the English contribution, the core
of the most significant social transformations brought by industrial society.
In a stylized history of national protagonisms, Hess places England as the
latest and most evident display of a future already perceivable in its reach
and sufferings: ‘In the same manner in which the German Reformation—
the origin of our new age—reached its full potential in France, now the
fruit of the French Revolution (unless we make a wrong conclusion based
on all hints) is about to ripen in England. The English nation is the most
practical in the world. England is to our century what France was to the
previous one’ (Hess 1961: 117).
In the series of articles he would write in the years after the publication
of his last book, Hess’ socialism matures together with the theoretical
exchanges in French thought, particularly in the line of Saint-Simonian
traditions. Socialismus und Communismus takes depth on a line started in
the previous book and which relates the comparison of French and German
thoughts: ‘[T]he absolute unity in life appeared for the first time as abstract
idealism in Germany and as abstract communism in France […] German
philosophy was, until Hegel, an esoteric science; nowadays, as a specula-
tive atheism, it begins to have an influence in life. The same happens with
French social philosophy, which, in a similar manner, begins to emanci-
pate, after Saint-Simon and Fourier, from scholasticism, and begins to get
involved with the people as scientific communism [wissenschaftlicher
Kommunismus]’ (Hess 1961: 200). Thus, where is the potency that Hess
48 P. NOCERA
The connection goes much further than a relation based on reason and
love. The terms of these relations, as long as they are established only as a
necessary passage through the collective to reach an individual end (i.e.
the market), will never be able to conform what Hess calls an organic com-
munity (organische Gemeinschaft).
It is quite suggestive that Hess criticizes all expressions (both material
and spiritual) in which the inverted form of the communal is expressly
invoked: ‘In other terms, politics and economics had the task of perform-
ing, at the level of a practical life, that which religion and theology had
carried out at the level of a theoretical life: the practical alienation (prak-
tische Entäußerung) of man had to be elevated to the dignity of a princi-
ple, as with his theoretical alienation’ (Hess 1961: 339). This practical
alienation consummates the mercantile world, whose reality affects the
human dimension of relations, inverting, under the blanket of individual
freedom and independence, the set of relations that conform humanity as
a collective. Money is the ultimate expression of this estrangement, with
the appearance of isolated individuals whose respective acknowledgment
only happens in the provisional sphere of a commercial relation. Hess pos-
tulates a parallel between money and the divinity, and allows us to con-
ceive a form of alienation which is practically deployed in exchange, in
addition to enabling an abstraction, as it does not appear as a consequence
of the subject’s positioning regarding an act of knowledge, or in the sphere
of consciousness, but requires a material connection as a support. Money
consummates an abstraction, with exchange as its social context, and
whose deployment makes invisible (abstract) the material character, not
just bodily, as Feuerbach stated, but as a producing subject: ‘The object
that for man is God in heaven, the superhuman good, in earth is the inhu-
man good, the material good, tangible, the thing, property; this is, the
product appropriated from its producer, its creator; the abstract essence of
commerce, money’ (Hess 1961: 339). Although Hess does not provide at
this moment an alternative which would serve as an answer to this diagno-
sis (something he would later do), the foundation for the displacement of
German philosophical discourse is set forth, integrated to political projec-
tions, with scenarios that would question the forms of statism, the market
and the order of private property. Marx’s critique goes into this direction.
52 P. NOCERA
The first and only volume of the German-French Annals (Paris, 1844)
allowed Marx to develop an initial synthesis of the path from previous
years, after the frustration of his career as a university professor (under the
probable sponsorship of Bruno Bauer) shortly after he submitted his doc-
toral dissertation. Noticing, after his writings in the Rheinische Zeitung
(1842), that the problem of German censorship emerged from more than
the country’s backwardness regarding political freedoms, and that it was
also necessary to (re)think the theoretical question on itself (i.e. the
Hegelian concept of the state), he devoted part of the summer of 1843 in
Kreuznach to meditate about Hegel’s positions published in 1821
(Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts). Although these detailed manu-
scripts were published well into the twentieth century, the writing origi-
nally conceived as his Introduction to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right was part, eventually, of the Annals. They are quite significant in our
journey. In his pages, Marx acknowledges the critique of religion as a man-
datory starting point, and he points out that such a task has already con-
cluded in Germany (although he does not expressly mention it) with
Feuerbach’s works about Christianity. This allows him to acknowledge
that the deployment of estrangement, once its development is revealed in
the religious/philosophical sphere, can also be recreated under its ‘profane
forms’ (Marx & Engels 1981: 379/tr. 1982: 492).
If alienation can be perpetrated in earthly forms—as perceived early by
Hess—Marx would set forth his first reflections about it taking into con-
sideration the functioning of the state. Beyond any potential debate about
conservatism or backwardness in a Hegelian perspective, let us keep the
central aspect objected by Marx. The state, under a superior universal
class, bureaucracy, is not able to place itself above the contradictions of
civic society in the sphere of the market (Hegel calls it system of needs). The
opposed interests of agricultural production and industry were thought as
solved by an illustrated class that would control, from a universal/univer-
salist perspective, the restrictions of a social standpoint, which may not be
perceived by the logic that rules its own operation: a partial perspective
infinitely replicated in the market’s atomic multiplicity. Marx acknowl-
edges, when he puts into perspective Hegel’s statement, not only that the
state is not able to recreate a true universality when it leaves untouched the
foundation of civic society but also that the political emancipation which
3 MONEY AS A PRACTICAL ABSTRACTION: FROM FEUERBACH TO MARX… 53
France has been trying for almost half a century is useless. Here, Hess’
perspective supplements Feuerbach’s in an essential sense. The state as
conceived by Hegel recreates an earthly form of political alienation in
which individuals are subject to a power that they respect and fear, without
realizing that its operation is intertwined with the roots of the civic society
that they compose and support.
Without Marx expressly defining yet the class character of the state, his
observations are recognized in Hess, in the depth in which he read the
European map. In a few words, Germany must not aspire to realize itself
in the political universe with which the Revolution had provided France
(singularity in the diagnostics of his—now former—comrade, Bauer) with
political and civic freedoms. Germany can think an even more substantial
horizon, with a revolutionary program beyond the boundaries of a partial
revolution (i.e. political) to establish a radical program implying human
emancipation.
If it is about a practical revolution/liberation, which would avoid the
typically German speculative exit to the poignant problems of the times, a
part of society, a class within society, should provide thrust to the whole
process. For the first time, in this brief text, Marx attributes to the prole-
tariat the conditions of possibility of a positive overcoming of the status
quo (as opposed to a negative one, understood as a merely speculative
overcoming). Its peculiarity resides, in that it is the only one focused on its
condition, the strictly human dimension expressed by labor. In other
words, Marx starts to reflect upon the possibility of finding a different
perspective in order to rescue a universal dimension that would effectively
replace a state that only reproduces some profane forms of alienation.
It is not by chance that the stay in Paris had a significant theoretical
influence on those perspectives. The sensitivity about the so-called social
question is nurtured by the impact of the exchange with referents of French
socialism. Cabet, Proudhon, Leroux, the Saint-Simonians, the romantics
and the philo-Catholics provided the thinker from Trier with a suggestive
breeding ground to reflect that society is supported, as a whole, by a major
actor which, in spite of holding it materially, is marginalized not only by
republican power but from any minimum spillage of wealth. The novelty,
in comparison with his French comrades, is the peculiar manner in which
he perceives the relation between philosophy and revolution. A philoso-
phy without the proletariat is mere speculation without a body; the prole-
tariat without a philosophy is just action without a direction.
54 P. NOCERA
through money. In Marx’s words: ‘The product of labor is labor which has
been embodied in an object, which has become material: it is the objecti-
fication of labor. Labor’s realization is its objectification. This realization
of labor, as presented in political economy, appears as a loss of realization
for the worker; objectification as loss and subjection of the object; appro-
priation as estrangement, as alienation’ (Marx & Engels 1968: 511–512/
tr. 1982: 596). The fact on which Marx’s reflection begins is the impover-
ishment of workers, which increases to the same extent to which the pro-
duction of wealth increases. An analysis shows that this fact expresses an
essence. The progressive impoverishment of workers is the process whose
general and human form is alienation. In this manner, the economic fact
manifests a certain elaboration, which allows it to reveal its hidden mean-
ing. Under the statement of economic facts, there is an anthropological
critique, which expresses the process of alienation.
According to Feuerbach, man produces God: he objectivizes in God
the predicates that constitute his essence. Now, when it is stated that a
worker produces an object, the starting point is the concept of produc-
tion. Marx’s critique thinks about the relation between the worker and his
product, in the same manner in which the relation between God and man
was given in a religious context. Nonetheless, unlike Feuerbach, Marx
demonstrates that productive activity is identified with generic activity
(activity by man in that with it he is making an affirmation of his own
essence) and the object produced with the objectivization of man’s generic
essence. The fact that this product increases the possibility of more wealth
for the capitalist appears as a manifest consequence of alienation, in which
man becomes an object of its object. The first manuscripts conclude cate-
gorically in two spheres. The alienation of workers through labor is what
remains hidden in private property When this estrangement happens as a
practical process, it can only be overcome practically as well. It is not
enough with denouncing the phenomenon. It is not enough with a com-
prehension and a subsequent critique. It can only be modified as a result
of a practice which, as we have seen, includes within itself a revolutionary
program.
In the Manuscripts, Marx develops a brief history of the circumstances
which ended up in estranged labor and have as their context civil society
and, particularly, the organization of industry. The basis for a possible
overcoming of the status quo are formulated there, including a materialist
aspect of communism, making historical to a certain extent what
Feuerbach’s Gattungswesen stated somehow abstractly. It is clear that
56 P. NOCERA
Marx avoids specificities about the future, but he still acknowledges: ‘But
to overcome real private property, it is necessary the real action of com-
munism. It will be carried out by history, and this movement that we ide-
ally represent as our own overcoming will be a very long and very hard
process’ (Marx & Engels 1968: 553/tr. 1982: 632). The emphasis in this
real dimension recovers overtones from Hess and increases the distance
with Feuerbach. It is not by chance that in the pages of this third manu-
script, Marx specifically addresses money.
Without disregarding the references to Shakespeare (Timon of Athens)
and Goethe (Faust) in the lament of their characters for the evils and pow-
ers of money, Marx reflects about them in a manner related to Hess’, link-
ing the problem of estranged labor to its essential note: ‘The inversion and
confusion of all natural and human qualities, the conjunction of two
impossible aspects, the divine strength of money resides in its own essence,
as it is the alienating, estranging, and estranged generic essence of men’
(Marx & Engels 1968: 565/tr. 1982: 643). As a ‘power of inversion’,
money has the virtue of conjugating the general confusion in a social
world, with an inversion that makes it become an end, which subjugates
its holders, instead of being under their control.
Nonetheless, the aspect in which Marx deepens and extends Hess’ for-
mulations with greater power is exposed in the allusions of mutation that
money introduces in the sphere of representation and the sphere of reality.
Money ‘allows to convert representation into reality and reality into a mere
representation, it converts the essential real forces of man and nature in
purely abstract representations […]’ (Marx & Engels 1968: 566/tr. 1982:
644). The term chosen by Marx as a counterpart to ‘reality’ is ‘representa-
tion’. In German, the term Vorstellung has a long and weighing history in
idealism (Kant, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel himself), whose allusion sup-
poses an acknowledgment of a cognitive aspect, which is, in general,
opposed to presentation/exposition [Darstellung] or event of reality itself,
and that in consequence appears, in general, as a kind of partial, provisional
or incomplete knowledge. Money is able to achieve in these dynamics not
only an inversion but also a certain flow between the sphere of thought and
the sphere of the real, overlapping the forms in which alienation is expressed.
Briefly stated, when divinity was the alienating release that sublimated real
poverty, whose perpetuity was politically assured by the state, money pro-
vides the necessary abstraction that expresses a counterpart to estranged
labor and private property. Even in the practical dimension of exchange,
money is able to reproduce an abstraction removed from its holders and is
3 MONEY AS A PRACTICAL ABSTRACTION: FROM FEUERBACH TO MARX… 57
imposed into them with the same force as the divinity falls over the believ-
ers. Marx’s critical journey will bring him, shortly afterwards, to think that
this specific phenomenon connecting both specificities may begin to be
reflected upon if ideology is taken into consideration. By then, the journey
of exploration and critique of political economy will project him to a much
broader and complex approach than these initial formulations.
Coda
In Karl Marx’s bicentennial, even this early aspect of his oeuvre, as ana-
lyzed here, proves to be very current. By exploring the contributions of a
young Hegelianism that affected his first reflections about how commer-
cial society works and how capitalist production is organized, we were able
to reconstruct a connection not always properly appreciated in the recur-
ring exegesis of different parts of his vast reflections. Within the scope of
a denunciation emerging in the specific situation of the German political
context, Marx’s perspective though about a phenomenon, which, beyond
national boundaries, cultural expressions and religious specificities, was
able to warn about the emancipatory outlook in the social and economic
transformations of the nineteenth century.
The development of a critique of alienation, reconstructed in this text,
to eventually reach his perspectives about the logic of money, warn the
modern reader about the contemporary processes of abstraction that
monetary dynamics weave increasingly faster, deploying a potential for the
visualization of social relations, and whose implications seem difficult to
analyze and, even more so, to anticipate. Money is a general equivalent, a
driving force by definition, the ethereal expression of an age in which
images seem to wrap around the flows (of information, capital, popula-
tions, etc.), that condense with a particular plasticity the manner in which
social relations are set forth beyond the control of their protagonists.
Marx’s early diagnosis warns about the secular forms that recreate the
religious, where there are equivalents to deity which, surreptitiously, give
shape to social relations in order to deploy in its spectral objectivity—as he
would state in Capital—a materiality that, not for being intangible, is less
present or less determinant. Money and its theological connotations,
aspects to which Marx would return, in his maturity, with a tangential
recurrence, set forth in these early texts a suggestive intersection between
discursive traditions that his own thought was able to encompass in a tran-
scendent manner. At the crossroads of German idealism, French socialism
58 P. NOCERA
Notes
1. ‘The idea is produced and testified not by means of a really different other—
which may not be other than an empiric-concrete intellectual intuition;—it
is produced based on a formal and apparent opposite […] Beyond this, the
other of pure thought is, in general, sensible understanding. An attempt in
the domain of philosophy is, therefore, to overcome the contradiction
between sensible understanding and pure thought […]’ (Feuerbach 1959:
183/tr. 1974: 41–42) [Emphasis in the original. Unless specifically stated,
the translations are our own.]
2. It is in a community that the conditions of the specifically human are real-
ized: ‘Only life in a community is true divine life that satisfies itself; this
simple thought, this truth, natural and innate to man, is the secret of the
supernatural mystery of the trinity. But religion also expresses this truth, as
any other, in an indirect and inverted manner, as it also turns a general truth
into a particular one, and the true subject into a predicate […]’ (Feuerbach
1960: 38/tr. 1995: 118).
3. Thus, it can be stated that: ‘In the same manner in which theology divides
and alienates man, in order to subsequently identify with him the alienated
essence, also Hegel multiplies and disperses the simple essence of nature and
man, self-identical, to mediate later through violence that which was sepa-
rated by means of violence’ (Feuerbach 1959: 226/tr. 1976: 24).
4. ‘Just as the abstraction of everything sensible and material had been a neces-
sary condition for theology, it was the same for speculative philosophy, with
the only difference that abstraction is, in turn, a sensible abstraction, as its
object, even when reached through abstraction, is again represented as a
sensible being, while abstraction in speculative philosophy is a spiritual
abstraction: when thought, it only has a scientific or theoretical significance,
but not a practical one’ (Feuerbach 1959: 254/tr. 1976: 58).
5. ‘To abstract means to place the essence of nature outside nature, the essence
of thought outside the act of thinking. Hegelian philosophy has estranged
3 MONEY AS A PRACTICAL ABSTRACTION: FROM FEUERBACH TO MARX… 59
man, as its whole system rests in these acts of abstraction’ (Feuerbach 1959:
227/tr. 1976: 25).
6. Although Hess published The Essence of Money in 1845, Marx had a previous
version, which he intended to include in the Annals. The same year in which
the only number of the Annals was published, Hess included in the Vorwärts
(December of 1844) the Red Catechism, where there were some preliminary
reflections about money. In the third section (questions and answers from
14 to 19), his statements were still very much in consonance with the
Weitling’s positions in Garantien der Harmonie und Freiheit (1842).
7. Marx uses the practical connotation of the term ‘alienation’ (as a sale)
[Veräußerung] to deploy with an eloquent play on words the peculiar trans-
mutation performed by money: ‘The sale is the practice of estrangement
[Die Veräußerung ist die Praxis der Entäußerun]. Just as man, when he
remains subject to religious constraints, is only able to objectivize his
essence, turning it into a fantastic being alien to him, and can only practi-
cally behave under the rule of selfish need; only in this manner can he practi-
cally produce objects to be sold, placing his products and activity under an
alien power and giving them the significance of an alien essence, which is
money’ (Marx & Engels 1981: 376–377/tr. 1982: 489).
References
Feuerbach, L. (1959). Sämtliche Werke – Band 2. Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt:
Fromman Verlag.
Feuerbach, L. (1960). Sämtliche Werke – Band 6. Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt:
Fromman Verlag.
Feuerbach, L. (1974). Aportes para la crítica de Hegel. La Pléyade: Buenos Aires.
Feuerbach, L. (1976). Tesis provisionales para la reforma de la filosofía.
Barcelona: Labor.
Feuerbach, L. (1995). La esencia del cristianismo. Madrid: Trotta.
Hess, M. (1961). Philosophische und sozialistische Schriften 1837–1850: eine
Auswahl. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.
Marx, K. (1982). Obras Fundamentales-Tomo I. Mexico: Fondo de Cultura
Económica.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1968). Werke – Band 40. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1981). Werke – Band 1. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
CHAPTER 4
Roberto Fineschi
There is a relatively long list of ‘Marxian’ categories that Marx has never
used: labor theory of value, historical materialism, philosophy of praxis
and so on. ‘Realabstraktion’ is no exception. The question is then whether
this category might be useful for a better understanding (or transforma-
tion) of society, or shed more light on Marx’s theory. Further difficulties
arise from the delicate status of complex philosophical concepts such as
‘real’ or ‘abstraction’, which themselves are not easy to define and
extremely controversial. In order to avoid a generic use of those catego-
ries, I shall try to reconstruct and contextualize the specific meaning these
words have in Marx’s mature theory of Capital, and how they change in
progress. The theory of commodity circulation and the definition of
abstract labor will be the main focus of this research, and eventually the
theory of fethishism and reification. In light of this philological recon-
struction, it will be possible to answer the question about the limits within
which we can use this category.
R. Fineschi (*)
Siena School for Liberal Arts, Siena, Italy
The wording is precise and can be found again at the end of the pro-
cess, once the general equivalent is posited, with the opposition ‘thought’
versus ‘social result’: ‘This is a theoretical statement as long as the com-
modity is merely thought as a definite quantity of objectified universal
labour time. The existence [Dasein] of a particular commodity as a univer-
sal equivalent is transformed from a pure abstraction into a social result of
the exchange process, if one simply reverses the above series of equations’
(Marx 1988: 287; German: Marx 1980: 124).
The exchange process was supposed to be the ‘real’ side of the argu-
ment, in opposition to the just thought abstraction made by the actors
before they actually exchange. The exposition in A Contribution follows
and develops the same path Marx formulated for the first time in the
Grundrisse.2
This strong contrast of ‘thought’/‘abstract’ versus ‘instantiated’/‘actual’
value is, however, not so relevant in the later, more mature formulation of
Capital, vol. 1. What was supposed to be the ‘thought’ part of the analysis
becomes now the value-form section. It would be too long to deal exten-
sively with that, but it has been philologically shown how in Capital, and
in particular in the second German edition, Marx considered the entire
development of the money deduction, within the value-form, as a theo-
retical whole, where the exchange-individuals are already present in the
argument since the very beginning (Lietz 1987, 1989). In fact, also in A
Contribution, the ‘real’ interaction was nothing but what would later
become the passage to a general equivalent. In A Contribution, however,
this passage was not possible in the thought analysis, but only in the ‘real’
dynamic of the exchange process. In Capital, the value-form is already a
whole theory of money deduction that implies exchanging individuals; for
this reason, a general equivalent can be deduced within the value-form.
A consequence of this change is that also the concept of ‘real’ is to be
conceived in a theoretical sense; the ‘real’ instantiation of the ‘thought’
value abstraction happens in thought as well, within a theory. Marx is not
talking about ‘historical’ developments as in a history book. Also the ‘his-
torical excursus’ that we can find in the chapter on the Exchange process
is a sort of phenomenology of the generalization of the value-form to a
money-form, but neither a chapter of history nor a theory of a pre-
capitalist society.3
Epistemologically, the distinction is not between a non-better defined
reality and thought. Here, Marx makes a theory of individuals that think
and act: this is not about them acting in history outside of the theory, but
64 R. FINESCHI
a theory of their historical action. This doesn’t certainly mean that outside
thought no ‘reality’ exists, but that Marx’s is a theory of that reality, and
what reality means is defined within this theoretical system. Exchange pro-
cess, commodity, money of course exists before the theory that explains
them, and such a theory is possible only because they have already devel-
oped to a certain extent. However, the theory that explains them does not
simply correspond to, or mechanically reflect, their historical genesis or
form of appearance.
I believe that this is why Marx re-worded these sections and did not use
anymore the concept of thought in opposition to actual or instantiated
(not ‘real’, strictly speaking). It seems to me that a controversial point in a
few interpretations is the non-very clear status of the category ‘real’4:
sometimes it seems that they mean the non-theorized world outside the
mind; in some other cases, they mean the dynamic of the social process
that produces those abstractions, which is however already framed within
a theory. In some others, it seems that the two levels uncritically go into
each other, so that it remains unclear what the ‘reality’ of the process is.5
The meaning that the concept ‘abstract’ in Capital is therefore differ-
ent: it doesn’t follow anymore the same development as in the Grundrisse
and A Contribution; in Capital, it is not the other side of ‘real’, but ‘con-
crete’. Moreover, the adjective is used to define ‘labor’ and ‘wealth’, which
is a very limited and precise utilization.
the ‘real’ subsumption of the labor process under capital. These concepts are
connected, but in a specific sense. In general terms, labor is abstract inas-
much as it produces value, not because of its parcelization. It subsists even if
every single producer is in charge of the entire production of their good,
even if there is no internal division of labor within the production process.
The second kind of abstraction is instead explicitly connected with the partial
character of the activity that aims at the production of an object, not the
division of labor in society in its complex. In this case, production of abstract
labor refers to the further division inside the process, and the growing par-
tiality of the individual activity in the production of the product itself, until
it becomes so formalistic that can be replaced by a machine. It is loss of
complexity, concreteness that characterizes this second abstraction.
If, on the one hand, the growing partiality of the individual activity is the
most adequate form of labor in the capitalist mode of production, on the
other this is not why labor is abstract. Internal division of labor has always
existed and will exist after capitalism, but not abstract labor, which is value
producing labor; and, in fact, Marx never used ‘abstract labor’ for the par-
celed labor. The fact that he does not is significative, because several cir-
cumstances could have brought him to do it, first of all the probable source
of the phrase ‘abstract labor’. Both in the Jena’s system drafts7 and Philosophy
of right8, Hegel, the philosopher that probably invented the expression
‘abstract labor’, talks about this kind of abstraction: labor is abstract because
of its parcelization; the more parcelized, the more abstract. Making this
point, Hegel put together a theory of value and property, and the division
of labor within production and mechanization. This means that Hegel,
misled by the classics and Smith in particular, mixed together the division
of labor in commodity circulation and manufacture production.9 As regards
the individual actors determined in this theoretical framework, in Hegel we
have the same short circuit we can find later in those interpreters of Marx
that put on the same plan the phenomenal level (abstract labor as defined
in the commodity circulation, what Marx actually called abstract labor,
where subjects appears as ‘persons’, the fundament of bourgeois ideology),
and the production process (abstract labor as parcelization, what Marx
actually did not define abstract labor, where subjects are, instead, ‘classes’).
This consistently affects also the foundations of a Marxian political theory.
If we move back to Marx, he did not use the ‘parcelization’ concept to
talk about abstract labor in Capital, and he actually only randomly did
before. He did it just occasionally in few passages in the notes of ‘44.10 In
those notes, he still had an anthropological perspective, a Gattungswesen
model, according to which the capitalist mode of production alienated the
66 R. FINESCHI
philosophical reflex of the real inversion that takes place in the commodity
society; Hegel’s philosophy and the dialectical method, as top theoretical
expression of this inversion, is therefore the perfect way to give theoretical
form to this world: the inverted philosophy that comes out and gives
proper explanation of an actual inverted reality. At the same time, this
method and philosophy seems implicitly to be valid as long as this inverted
reality exists. In Colletti’s own words:
Die Wertform was added by Marx to the first edition of Capital while the
work was already in press. It is a fact that the page which we have taken from
it reproduces to the letter the arguments with which Marx first criticized
Hegel’s dialectic in his early writing, the Kritik des Hegelschen Staatsrechts.
The abstract-universal, which ought to be the predicate—i.e. a ‘property of
the concrete or the sensate’—becomes the subject, a self-subsisting entity;
‘contrariwise the concrete-sensate counts merely as the phenomenal form of
the abstract-universal’—i.e. as the predicate of its own substantified predi-
cate. This overturning, this quid pro quo, this Umkehrung, which, accord-
ing to Marx, rules Hegel’s Logic, rules also, long before the Logic, the
objective mechanisms of this society—beginning right from the relation of
‘equivalence’ and the exchange of commodities. (Colletti 1973: 282)
The inversion of abstract and concrete in the scientific method does not
match a ‘real’ inversion. This is what ideology does. The inversion of sub-
ject and object in the production process is to be conceived in regard to
previous modes of production, not essence.17
The final part of this essay regards the concept of ‘real abstraction’ as a
whole, after I have tried to show controversial interpretations that can
separately derive from a misunderstanding of the concepts of ‘real’ and
‘abstract’. In general terms, one of the most important focuses is that, in
capitalism, abstractions become real and work in the system as acting sub-
jects. It is not always very clear what these abstractions should be, since
Marx does not explicitly use the phrase ‘real abstraction’. Probably, most
of the interpreters would accept in the list money as ‘naked’ universal form
of wealth, and capital as this abstraction transformed into a subject.18
In general terms, one could wonder whether real abstractions exist only
in the capitalist mode of production, inasmuch as, as Hegel already
showed, abstractions always need to exist in particular ‘bodies’. They don’t
exist as such in their universality, but are particular universals: ‘singulars’
(Hegel 2010: 546 and ff.). An alleged separate ‘universal’ turns to be just
a particular. An actual universality can be only the one that is able to show
how universals act through particulars until a particular, in its particularity,
plays the role of a universal. Therefore, existing universals are always ‘real’,
in the sense that they are instantiated. In more specific terms, we have
already seen how abstract is a quality of concrete, and their separation is an
‘intellectual’ result, as Hegel would say. In a dialectical theory, the fact that
abstractions are real, universals are particulars and so on is no surprise.
If we come back to Marx’s theory, money is a particular commodity
that works as universal commodity. The labor that produces the money-
commodity works in its particularity as universal representative of labor
(Marx 1996: 69, 77; German: Marx 1991: 59, 68). And also the abstract
activity of the workers is a concrete activity. Abstract labor is possible only
as pure formal treatment of concrete labor, because concrete labor and
abstract labor are just two sides of the same activity. Then, the abstraction
of labor in general or value objectivity as such are real abstractions in the
sense that a specific labor and a specific commodity work as universal labor
4 REAL ABSTRACTION: PHILOLOGICAL ISSUES 71
and universal commodity. They are not purely abstract, but particular ones
that work as universal, they are singular.
Does this structure belong just the capitalist mode of production or
not? In general terms, since the instantiation of universality as such is part
of the concept of Singularity itself, this seems to be an ontologically tran-
shistorical notion. Singularities don’t belong just to the capitalist mode of
production: an emperor, the three medieval classes, State and so on are
not less existing universalities, ‘real abstractions’, than money or capital. A
king, for instance, is a really existing universal that thinks that he is the
king because of himself and not because there are people that relate as
subjects to him. Besides, these are social actors, subjects as capital or
money are. If this is also a crucial aspect in the meaning of ‘real abstrac-
tion’, it doesn’t seem then that existing universals acting as subjects are
only in the capitalist mode of production. We can talk maybe of histori-
cally specific real abstractions, if we want to keep this concept.
The fact that the capitalist mode of production produces fetish charac-
ters, such as Money or Capital itself, means that abstractions are produced
in a very specific and limited way. Actually, Marx shows that Money or
Capital are abstracts only inasmuch as they seem to own their social quali-
ties as physical properties, while this happens only because there is a social
relationship and process that posits that. They are as they appear only
inasmuch as they are a ring in a big chain, which includes the material
process of production. But the same happens in regard to ‘person’ or
‘man’: they are those universalities only abstracting from the real process.
But capitalism is a process, and produces and re-produces those universals
as things: this is its specific historical determination. To reconstruct this
process and understand how it actually works does not cancel that appear-
ance as long as the material structures that produce it are solid. Cutting
the veil, showing the essence, does not stop the objective process.
Given that, it seems that real abstractions are not just in the capitalist
mode of production; a domination of abstractions assumes different, spe-
cific forms in different times. What is specific of the capitalist mode of
production is that these abstractions are not simply ‘real’ but appear as
things. If we make the mistake to reduce the concept of reality to being a
thing, we fall in a very simple and unsophisticated form of realism and
cancel the subtitle Marxian distinction between content and form.
72 R. FINESCHI
Conclusions
Since the concept of ‘real abstraction’ is not explicitly present in Marx’s
works, I have tried to show how its use is connected with complexes issues.
The first is the definition itself of ‘real’ and ‘abstraction’: these concepts
can be easily misunderstood outside a precise philological reconstruction
of Marx’s thought. This kind of miscomprehension has bought to contro-
versial parallels with essentialist theories that are very far, in my opinion,
from Marx’s theory of the historical process. The restriction of real abstrac-
tion just to capitalism is another controversial point that can be ques-
tioned by a more general analysis of the concept of Singularity as both
historical and transhistorical categories.
These difficulties impose, in my opinion, a cautious use of this category
that is very suggestive and evocative on the one hand and potentially mis-
leading on the other.
Notes
1. Actually ‘value’. In this moment (1859), Marx still did not have a clear
distinction between value and exchange-value. Philological results have
shown that he will precisely and consistently define these categories only in
the second German edition of book 1 (1872/3). See Hecker (1987).
2. In that text as well, he distinguished between a thought and real deduction
of general equivalent/money (at the time they were defined in the same
way): ‘This third thing, distinct from the other two since it expresses a ratio,
exists initially in the head, in the imagination, just as in general ratios can
only be thought if they are to be fixed, as distinct from the subjects which are
in that ratio to each other’ (Marx 1986: 81; German: Marx 1976: 77–78).
Then, he adds: ‘For mere comparison, for the valuation of products, for the
notional determination of their value, it is enough to make this transforma-
tion in the head (a transformation in which the product exists simply as the
expression of quantitative relationships of production). For the comparison
of commodities, this abstraction is sufficient; for actual exchange, this
abstraction must again be objectified, symbolized, realized through a token’
(Marx 1986: 91; German: Marx 1976: 78). Finally, ‘Through the product
becoming a commodity and the commodity becoming exchange value, it
acquires, first in our mind, a dual existence. This mental duplication pro-
ceeds (and must proceed) to the point where the commodity appears dual
in actual exchange: as natural product on the one hand, as exchange value
on the other. I.e. its exchange value acquires an existence materially sepa-
rated from it’ (Marx 1986: 81; German: Marx 1976: 79).
4 REAL ABSTRACTION: PHILOLOGICAL ISSUES 73
others. A single man cannot operate upon Nature without calling his own
muscles into play under the control of his own brain. As in the natural
body head and hand wait upon each other, so the labour process unites the
labour of the hand with that of the head. Later on they part company and
even become deadly foes. The product ceases to be the direct product of
the individual, and becomes a social product, produced in common by a
collective labourer [Gesamtarbeiter], i.e., by a combination of workmen,
each of whom takes only a part, greater or less, in the manipulation of the
subject of their labour. As the co-operative character of the labour process
becomes more and more marked, so, as a necessary consequence, does our
notion of productive labour, and of its agent the productive labourer,
become extended. In order to labour productively, it is no longer necessary
for you to do manual work yourself; enough, if you are an organ of the
collective labourer, and perform one of its subordinate functions. The first
definition given above of productive labour, a definition deduced from the
very nature of the production of material objects, still remains correct for
the collective labourer, considered as a whole. But it no longer holds good
for each member taken individually’.
14. How a socialized production process can be controlled and rationally man-
aged by a socialized worker is, of course, a big open question; it is not even
guaranteed that it might be possible to find an answer. However, it seems
solid that this was the perspective Marx was moving to.
15. ‘Within the relationship between value and the expression of value con-
tained therein, the abstract universal does not count as a property of the
concrete in its sense-reality, but on the contrary the concrete-sensate
counts merely as the phenomenal or determinate form of the abstract uni-
versal’s realization. The labour of the tailor which one finds, e.g., in the
equivalent coat, does not incidentally have the general property of being
human labour within its value-relation as cloth. On the contrary: To be
human labour is its very essence; to be the labour of the tailor is only the
phenomenal or determinate form taken by this its essence in its realization.
This quid pro quo is inevitable, since the labour represented in the labour-
product creates value only in that it is undifferentiated human labour; such
that the labour objectified in the value of a product is not at all distinguish-
able from the labour objectified in the value of another product’. And
Marx concludes thus: ‘This total reversal and overturning, which means
that the concrete-sensate counts only as the phenomenal form of the
abstract-universal, and not contrariwise the abstract-universal as a property
of the concrete, characterizes the expression of value. This is what makes
its understanding difficult. If I say that Roman law and German law are
both forms of law, this is obvious. If, however, I say that the law, this
abstraction, translates itself into reality in Roman law and German law—
76 R. FINESCHI
References
Adorno, T. W. (1990). Zur Metakritik der Erkenntnistheorie. In Gesammelte
Schriften. Band 5. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Backhaus, H. G. (1997). Dialektik der Wertform. Untersuchungen zur marxschen
Ökonomiekritik. Freiburg: Ḉa ira.
Bellofiore, R., & Fineschi, R. (2009). Re-reading Marx. New Perspectives after the
Critical Edition. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Bonefeld, W., & Heinrich, M. (Eds.). (2011). Kapital & Kritik. Nach der “neuen”
Marx’-Lektüre. Hamburg.
Cazzaniga, G. M. (1981). Funzione e conflitto. Forme e classi nella teoria marxiana
dello sviluppo. Liguori: Napoli.
Colletti, L. (1973). Marxism and Hegel. London: NLB.
Elbe, I. (2008). Marx im Westen. Die Neue Marx-Lektüre in der Bundesrepublik
seit 1965. Berlin: Akademie.
Engster, F. (2016). Subjectivity and Its Crisis: Commodity Mediation and the
Economic Constitution of Objectivity and Subjectivity. History of the Human
Sciences, 29(2), 77–95.
Fineschi, R. (2001). Ripartire da Marx. Processo storico ed economia politica nella
teoria del “capitale”. Napoli: La città del sole.
4 REAL ABSTRACTION: PHILOLOGICAL ISSUES 77
Alfonso Maurizio Iacono
A. M. Iacono (*)
Department of Civilizations and Forms of Knowledge,
University of Pisa, Pisa, Italy
e-mail: [email protected]
had posed the problem of studying human history, starting from men
gathered in a society, and had stressed that the key factor for understand-
ing the development of different societies was the ‘means of subsistence’
(Robertson 1818: 111; Millar 1960: 175), from which customs, laws, and
forms of government could be derived. In this regard, it has been argued
that Marx was a successor of the so-called ‘Scottish School’ (Pascal 1938:
178), and that his materialistic conception of history had been anticipated
by Ferguson, Millar, and Robertson. It has been noted that in France too,
in the eighteenth century, Quesnay, Mirabeau, and Turgot had advanced
a materialistic theory of history (Meek 1973), which can be regarded as
the foundation of political economics as a standalone science. The idea
that understanding the institutions and customs of different societies
requires an investigation into the material conditions resulting in these
differences paved the way for political economics to become a separate
discipline, as it analyzed the structure of civil society. Political economics
becomes the key to understanding the whole of society. But there’s a
problem here. Having established a connection between the materialistic
conception of history and political economics in the eighteenth century,
there is however an open question with respect to Marx: do his thoughts
extend the concepts developed in the eighteenth century to definitively
reduce the explanation of capitalist society to its economic basis, or is his
way of combining the materialistic theory of history and his critique of
political economics aimed at preventing this reduction—a reduction only
present in the attempts of classical economists to construct a standalone
economic science? There is at least one aspect of Marx’s analysis that
allows us, if not exhaustively, at least to highlight from a different perspec-
tive the meaning of this very widely debated question. It is the connection
that Marx makes between his critique of the isolated man, placed at the
origin of history, and the critique of the use by classical economists of this
concept in their attempt to construct a simplified economic model capable
of explaining the complex economic mechanism of the capitalist means of
production.
The role of abstraction in Marx’s critique and method comes into play
here. Alfred Sohn-Rethel observed that Marx derives from Hegel the idea
of form as shaped by time, but he distances himself from it because, unlike
Hegel, he ‘understands the time governing the genesis and the mutation
of forms as being, from the very first, historical time—the time of natural
and human history. That is why the form processes cannot be made out in
anticipation. No prima philosophia under any guise has a place in Marxism.
5 MARX’S METHOD AND THE USE OF ABSTRACTION 81
what situation of the human race are footsteps of art unknown? In the con-
dition of the savage, as well as in that of the citizen, are many proofs of
human invention; and in either is not any permanent station, but a mere
stage through which this travelling being is destined to pass.
(Ferguson 1995: 14)
tures in historical analysis, but also the epistemological sense of these con-
jectures and of those concepts. While Ferguson’s criticism simply identifies
an erroneous historical method which establishes comparisons between
reality and an artificially constructed concept, Marx starts from the prob-
lem of the genesis of such a concept from social reality. That’s why he says
that ‘the individual and isolated hunter and fisherman’ does not represent
a reaction to excessive refinements and a return to a misunderstood natu-
ral life, but constitutes the anticipation of ‘civil society’.
Here we are faced with a new aspect of the relationship that Marx
establishes between the materialistic conception of history and the critique
of political economics: his theory of history allows him to address an epis-
temological problem that economists had to face in their investigation of
the capitalist economic system: of constructing, through an abstraction, a
simplified economic model for comparison against the real one. Marx
emphasizes the fact that man in a natural state, rather than being an
inverted mirror to negative criticism of civilization’s effects, comes across
as the image of a bourgeois economic individual transcending his society.
This image, which anticipates the ‘civil society’ (bürgerliche Gesellschaft),
does nothing more than reduce capitalist social relations to simple and
abstract economic terms. An abstraction, therefore, of social relationships
reduced to economic relationships: Marx’s critique of the isolated man as
the starting point of history and as a starting point for political economics
stands as a critique of this reductive abstraction, in an attempt to restore
the connection between economic and socio-historical relationships. Let
us now examine Marx’s second criticism, the one at the starting point of
classical economists.
For Marx, the image of the ‘the individual and isolated hunter and
fisherman’ is simultaneously a simplified abstraction and an expression of
common bourgeois thinking, or rather a simplified abstraction deriving
from common bourgeois thinking. This apparently concrete image, which
is in reality abstract, is in fact opposed to ‘civil society’ precisely because it
is constructed upon the structure of the latter. In fact, precisely because an
individual within ‘civil society’ appears to be free of natural limitations, he
is nevertheless part of nature, imbued with his own historical characteris-
tics. The individual of the eighteenth century, says Marx, ‘appears as an
idea, whose existence they project into the past. Not as a historic result but
as history’s point of departure. As the Natural Individual appropriate to
their notion of human nature, not arising historically, but posited by
nature’ (Marx 1973: 25).
5 MARX’S METHOD AND THE USE OF ABSTRACTION 85
What interests Marx is precisely the idea that economists make human
nature into the linchpin of simple abstraction with which to compare the
means of capitalist production. The problem of classical economists was to
construct a synchronic model capable of representing the economic cate-
gories of capitalist society and of explaining the value of commodities. It
was necessary to find a simple abstraction that would allow categories to
be generalized; and just as Rousseau conceived of the natural state not as
a real state, but as an abstraction with which to compare civilized society,
economists had to resort to an abstract model, but with the seemingly
concrete appearance of ‘the individual and isolated hunter and fisherman’,
able to represent all the different facets of value. And while Ferguson was
arguing that conjectures on man’s supposed original state made no sense
from a historical point of view, Adam Smith had to resort to this same
original state to explain the economic point of view.
Similarly, while Turgot, in his writings on progress, also placed the
emphasis on the development of the human species in its different stages,
rather than on the contractarian idea of originally independent and iso-
lated men, when he found himself having to formalize the theory of value,
he had to resort to the isolated man or to men who enter into relation-
ships with each other as independent (Turgot, about 1769). In the eigh-
teenth century, a conflict arose between the features of historical analysis
and the features of economic analysis. Thanks to the first attempts of com-
parative anthropology, it started to be possible in socio-historical research
to apply a procedure to understand differences between different histori-
cally known social stages as variations in the faculties of the human species,
that is as variations found in the characteristics of human nature, expressed
and developed in societies. In economic research, on the other hand, the
procedure presupposed a conception of human nature whose peculiarity,
valid for all epochs, is ideally and abstractly expressed in a hypothetical
pre-social stage.
Marx deals with this second procedure; his problem is not only to put
historical analysis back on a firm footing, but to understand the process of
simplification/generalization in the models of political economics and
therefore the method of abstraction. It is from this point of view that one
must interpret his critique of the starting point of political economics as a
function of the question of the origins of human societies; that is, from the
point of view of the construction of a theoretical model capable of offering
a general representation of the capitalist means of production.
86 A. M. IACONO
the fact that satisfying private needs takes place under the pretext of
exploitative relationships that underlie the social character of commodities.
On the contrary, the transfer of this social character from men to com-
modities ultimately implies that the domain of private life is also invested
with purely utilitarian economic relationships. Therefore, the reduction of
society to economic society is presented as the deceptive and erroneous
epistemological premise of the birth of political economics as a science:
the individual, in nature, is the economic individual of the capitalist sys-
tem. From this point of view, it is possible to explain all the determinations
of value. Marx admits this when he mentions Robinson Crusoe. In the
chapter on The Fetishism of Commodities and the Secret Thereof in Book 1
of Das Kapital, Marx describes Crusoe, who, in his isolation, clarifies the
relations between himself and his things. It is an abstraction deriving from
his isolation: in this representation, in fact, both the cooperative nature of
labor and the relationships between men, mediated by goods, are taken
away at the very start. Crusoe presents himself as one ‘having rescued a
watch, ledger, and pen and ink from the wreckage’ (Marx 1887: 50), that
is, objects needed for his survival, and which were produced by the labor
of society.
The transparency provided by the figure of Crusoe derives from the
total abstraction of the social character of private labor and therefore of
the social relationships of private labor, summarized perfectly in one per-
son. But clock, ledger, pen and inkwell ultimately point out how the ori-
gin of Crusoe’s behavior in isolation is at odds with his possibility of a
private relationship with things. However, ‘All the relations between
Robinson and the objects that form this wealth of his own creation, are
here so simple and clear as to be intelligible without exertion, even to Mr.
Sedley Taylor. And yet those relations contain all that is essential to the
determination of value’ (Marx 1887: 50).
The point that Marx criticizes about Smith and Ricardo’s ‘Crusoean’
things is not that they give no account of value determination, but that in
the idealized reintroduction of the figure of ‘the individual and isolated
hunter and fisherman’, the social aspect of economic relationship is lost.
The savage of Adam Smith, who rationally discovers the advantage of spe-
cializing in the production of objects and then bartering with others who
need them, ideally also owns a watch, ledger, pen and inkwell, but these
objects do not appear only because of the absence, in an abstract sense, of
the social aspect on which the rational utility of bartering is based. The
reduction of reason to pure economic rationality becomes the abstraction
88 A. M. IACONO
How does M. Proudhon, who assumes the division of labour as the known,
manage to explain exchange value, which for him is always the unknown? ‘A
man’ sets out to ‘propose to other men, his collaborators in various func-
tions,’ that they establish exchange, and make a distinction between ordi-
nary value and exchange value … to tell us finally how this single individual,
this Robinson, suddenly had the idea of making ‘to his collaborators’ a pro-
posal of the type known and how these collaborators accepted it without the
slightest protest. (Marx 1955: 12)
This sphere that we deserting, within whose boundaries the sale and pur-
chase of labour-power goes on, is in fact a very Eden of the innate rights of
man. There alone rule Freedom, Equality, Property and Bentham. Freedom,
because both buyer and seller of a commodity, say of labour-power, are
constrained only by their own free will. They contract as free agents, and the
5 MARX’S METHOD AND THE USE OF ABSTRACTION 91
agreement they come to, is but the form in which they give legal expression
to their common will. Equality, because each enters into relation with the
other, as with a simple owner of commodities, and they exchange equiva-
lent. Property, because each disposes only of what is his own. And Bentham,
because each looks only to himself. The only force that brings them together
and puts them in relation with each other, is the selfishness, the gain and the
private interests of each. (Marx 1887: 7)
The fact that commodities are repositories of social labor leads to two
consequences: (a) the reduction of the process of social labor, and there-
fore of production relationships, to something simple; (b) the demarca-
tion of subjectivity, of its intentional space of action, to the sphere of
circulation, where social labor, crystallized in commodities, circulates
within the orbit of economic interests. Once the workforce is treated as a
commodity, as dead labor, its subjectivity is recognized only in its circula-
tion. It is exactly the undervaluation of these two consequences that leads
Marx to criticize Bastiat and Carey. With regard to the latter, Marx
observes that he belongs to a country, the USA, in which bourgeois soci-
ety has not developed from feudal society and therefore is seen as a start-
ing point for a new movement. ‘That the relations of production within
which this enormous new world has developed so quickly, so surprisingly
and so happily should be regarded by Carey as the eternal, normal rela-
tions of social production and intercourse (…)?’ (Marx 1973: 806).
And here too, the activity of informed individuals determines social
relationships and the development of productive forces within a
harmonious vision of the economic system. Here we see clearly how Marx
considers history to be the key distinguishing factor: ‘but the unhistoric
moment in Carey is the contemporary historic principle of North America,
while the unhistoric element in Bastiat is a mere reminiscence of the
French eighteenth-century manner generalizing’ (Marx 1973: 810).
Criticizing the way Bastiat explains wages in the Harmonies Economiques,
Marx nevertheless stresses the method of explaining the relationship
between capital and wage labor as stemming from an agreement between
the capitalist and the wage earner: ‘We will not call attention here to the
genius of a procedure which begins by presupposing a capitalist on one
side and a worker on the other, so as then, afterwards, to let the relation
of capital and wage labour arise between them by their mutual agreement’
(Marx 1973: 812).
92 A. M. IACONO
ship toward a search, inspired by the classics, for the unintentional rela-
tions inherent in production relationships, allows a new discourse on the
topic of subjectivity to be opened up. The naturalization of social relation-
ships as they arise in the sphere of the commodity circulation, the Eden of
man’s innate rights (i.e. as relationships between isolated and independent
individuals), implies that social action derives only from that of abstract
homogenization among individuals who have the same interest in defend-
ing themselves against others with opposed interests. Hence the idea of
the social pact as the ‘anticipation of civil society’ and as a great metaphor
for the class behavior of the bourgeoisie, which abstractly conceives of the
intentional relationships of the sphere of circulation as the relationships of
all the spheres of mutual actions between men, ‘where every man is in it
for himself’. Thus the myth of the isolated man is nothing more than the
abstraction within this single figure of all those aspects of human action
that are seen separately in capitalist society. As a result of the socio-
historical process, it reveals its origins from the capitalist conditions of
production, the division of labor and the private appropriation of social
work. This unveiling, by destroying that myth, represents the isolation of
the individual for what it actually is when the capitalist process of expro-
priation of labor rules: the reality is having to deal only with oneself in
relationships with others, with loneliness as the only moment to search for
one’s fragmented individuality.
For this reason, Marx’s critique of ‘the individual and isolated hunter
and fisherman’ overcomes the epistemological discussion of abstraction.
The reference to production and its capitalist nature, on which the circula-
tion of commodities and the social behavior of isolated individuals is
based, also indicates the need to find a commonality between the working
class and the proletariat different from that of the bourgeoisie, the con-
quest of an organized and mass conscience that, starting from the fight
against the private appropriation of social labor, reverses the visibility
offered by the relationships between men in the sphere of commodity
circulation, and funds its unity not only in the opportunity to defend itself
against a common enemy, but also in the permanent ability to translate
that struggle into the open visibility of the social appropriation of social
labor. From this point of view, the search for sociality through commodi-
ties and for dismembered individuality among the separate spheres of
5 MARX’S METHOD AND THE USE OF ABSTRACTION 95
human action will perhaps prevent solitude from destroying the possibility
of reconstituting the social individual. Despite globalization, the great
changes in the organization and division of labor, and in the ways people
and environment are exploited, this research still deserves to be pursued.
Notes
1. I have explored the subject at length in Iacono (1994, 2016).
2. On the relation between capital and capitalist, Marx observes: ‘(…) capital
in its being-for-itself is the capitalist. Of course, socialists sometimes say, we
need capital, but not the capitalist. Then capital appears as a pure thing, not
as a relation of production which, reflected in itself, is precisely the capitalist’
(Marx 1973: 242).
3. Malinowski grossly misunderstands historical materialism as he equates it to
utilitarian economics, which he criticizes because accepts the myth of the
primitive economic man (Malinowski 1932: 276).
References
Ferguson, A. (1995). An Essay on Civil Society (1767). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Galiani, F. (1963). Della moneta (1750). Milano: Feltrinelli.
Iacono, A. (1994). The American Indians and the Ancients of 18th Century. In
W. Haase & M. Reinhold (Eds.), The Classical Tradition and the Americas
(Vol. I). Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.
Iacono, A. (2016). The History and Theory of Fetishism. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Lafitau, J. (1724). Moeurs des sauvages amaricains, comparées aux moeurs des pre-
miers temps. Paris. English Edition: W. N. Fenton & E. L. Morre (Eds.),
Customs of the American Indians Compared with the Customs of Primitive Times.
Toronto: The Champlain Society. [I Vol. : 1974; II Vol.:1977].
Luporini, C. (1974). Realtà e storicità: economia e dialettica nel marxismo. In
Dialettica e materialismo (pp. 153–211). Rome: Editori Riuniti.
Malinowski, B. (1932). Argonauts of the Western Pacific. London: Routledge.
Marx, K. (1887). Capital. A Critique of Political Economy (Vol. I). Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1955). The Poverty of Philosophy. Moscow: Institute of Marxism-Leninism.
Marx, K. (1973). Outlines of the Critique of Political Economy (M. Nicolaus,
Trans.). London: Penguin.
Marx, K. (1975). Letter to Annenkov (December 28.1846). In Marx-Engels,
Collected Works (Vol. 38). Moscow: International Publishers.
96 A. M. IACONO
Paul Blackledge
P. Blackledge (*)
Shanxi University, Taiyuan, China
e-mail: [email protected]
2004: 188, 2012: 79). However, he does not explore the debt to Engels
registered by both of these writers. This omission is unfortunate because
their common debt to Engels’s Anti-Duhring and The Origin of the
Family, Private Property and the State is a useful lens through which to
illuminate the strengths and weaknesses of their arguments.
According to Thomson, Engels’s definition of civilization is superior to
that deployed by bourgeois archaeologists, because whereas the latter
merely held to a descriptive model of civilization as ‘the culture of cities’,
the former articulated a much more analytical account that treated civiliza-
tion as the ‘culmination of an organic process of economic and social
change’ (Thomson 1955: 175). Engels argued that civilization is the
‘stage of development of society at which division of labour, the resulting
exchange between individuals, and commodity production, which com-
bines the two, reach their full development and revolutionize the whole of
hitherto existing society’ (Engels 1990a: 272; Thomson 1955: 175). This
process, according to Thomson’s gloss, emerged in the Bronze Age but
did not come into its ‘full growth’ until the Iron Age, particularly in
Greece (Thomson 1955: 178).
Engels claimed that ‘[t]he stages of commodity production, with which
civilization began, is marked economically by the introduction of (1)
metal money and, thus, of money capital, interest and usury; (2) the mer-
chants acting as mediating class between producers; (3) private ownership
of land and mortgage; (4) slave labour as the prevailing form of produc-
tion’ (Engels 1990a: 274). Interestingly, these lines are quoted with
approval both by Thomson and by Sohn-Rethel, and in both cases they
underpin their accounts of the moment when a full monetary economy
first came into being (Thomson 1955: 177; Sohn-Rethel 1978: 95–96).
More specifically, Sohn-Rethel argues that ‘Thomson confirmed and
supported’ Engels’s conclusions that ‘Greek society was the first to be
based on a monetary economy’ and that this process was significant
because of the links between ‘the rise of commodity production in Greece
with the rise of Greek philosophy’. Sohn-Rethel went on to argue that he
had distinguished between ‘primitive exchange on the one hand and pri-
vate commodity exchange on the other’. He insisted that ‘[t]he former
was contemporary with the various forms of “communal modes of pro-
duction” and evolved chiefly in the external relations between different
tribal communities’ whereas the latter emerged
100 P. BLACKLEDGE
The traditional Marxism to which Jappe refers is, of course, the inter-
pretation of Marx’s theory of value that has roots in Engels’s work on
Vols. II and III of Capital.
Amongst those who have criticized Engels for his misunderstanding of
value theory, Chris Arthur has also praised Sohn-Rethel for his work on
abstraction. According to Arthur, Sohn-Rethel explained how abstraction
in exchange ‘is not a mental operation; it is a material abstraction’. And
this process of material abstraction underpinned the subsequent emer-
gence of abstract labor: ‘Before the positing of labour as “abstract” there
is the positing of commodities themselves as bearers of their abstract iden-
tity as values’ (Arthur 2004: 80). This is an interesting argument because
though it follows Sohn-Rethel’s general approach to conceptualizing the
relationship between practice and consciousness, it departs from his rejec-
tion of the concept of abstract labor. This is an important point because it
was through his rejection of this concept as ‘a fetish concept bequeathed
by the Hegelian heritage’ (Sohn-Rethel quoted in Jappe 2013: 7) that
Sohn-Rethel effectively made explicit what was implicit for much of the
twentieth century: the fundamental difference between Marx’s and
Engels’s understanding of the labor theory of value.
Elsewhere Arthur has argued that Engels’s misunderstanding of Marx’s
theory of value illuminates deeper methodological concerns with his
thought (Arthur 1996). In 1859 Marx and Engels published outlines of
their basic methodology. According to Arthur, discrepancies between the
two essays illuminate deep divergences between two of them. The first of
these essays was Marx’s preface to A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy, followed by Engels’s two-part review of this book. Both
works are, for different reasons, somewhat opaque and difficult to inter-
pret. In the first instance, as Arthur Prinz points out that Marx’s preface
was written with an eye to the censor and thus underplayed the active,
interventionist aspect of Marxism (Prinz 1968; Blackledge 2006: 27).
Secondly, Engels’ review is incomplete. It was supposed to run to three
parts but only the first two installments were written because the journal
in which it was being serialized, Das Volk (effectively edited by Marx),
went bankrupt before Engels had time to complete the final part of
the review.
The central paragraph of Marx’s preface is an infamously dense rehash
of themes from The German Ideology (Marx 1987a: 263; Carver 1983:
72–77). This condensed summary of Marx’s theory of history has been a
source of debate since its first publication. If the 1859 preface has been
6 METHOD AND VALUE: ENGELS THROUGH SOHN-RETHEL 103
The economists of the seventeenth century, e.g., always begin with the liv-
ing whole, with population, nation, state, several states, etc.; but they always
conclude by discovering through analysis a small number of determinant,
abstract, general relations such as division of labour, money, value, etc. As
soon as these individual moments had been more or less firmly established
and abstracted, there began the economic systems, which ascended from the
simple relations, such as labour, division of labour, need, exchange value, to
the level of the state, exchange between nations and the world market. The
latter is obviously the scientifically correct method. The concrete is concrete
because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence unity of the
diverse. It appears in the process of thinking, therefore, as a process of con-
centration, as a result, not as a point of departure, even though it is the point
of departure in reality and hence also the point of departure for observation
and conception. … the method of rising from the abstract to the concrete is
only the way in which thought appropriates the concrete, reproduces it as
the concrete in the mind. (Marx 1973: 101)
The clearly dialectical but not Hegelian method suggested in this para-
graph has been subject to much interrogation (Ilyenkov 2013). As it hap-
pens Engels’s review of Marx’s Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy was written without sight of the 1857 Introduction, and Arthur
argues that it suffers by comparison (Arthur 1996: 180; Carver 1983:
96–97). In his review, Engels wrote that whereas the Germans had previ-
ously lacked a first-rate political economist, Marx had now filled this gap.
What is more, his contribution to political economy superseded those of
his predecessors because his approach was rooted in a new, scientific
approach to the study of history: ‘The materialist conception of history’
(Engels 1980: 469).
Whereas Smith and Ricardo had proved themselves incapable of grasping
the essence of capitalism because they could not see beyond its horizons,
104 P. BLACKLEDGE
truth of Engels’s argument consequently strikes at the core of both his and
much more substantially Marx’s critique of Proudhon’s reformist ‘critique
of political economy from the standpoint of political economy’. The law
of value is not 3500 years old but operates in a system of generalized com-
modity production where labor has been separated from the means of
production such that the ability to work becomes commodified as labor
power. Marx detailed the emergence of this system in his famous discus-
sion of the primitive accumulation of capital (Marx 1976: 873–876). The
fact that this argument and Marx’s earlier critique of Proudhon built on
insights from Engels’s Umrisse makes Engels’s misunderstanding of value
theory all the more unfortunate. In fact, his error implicitly opened the
door to the sort of utopian and reformist politics he had explicitly fought
against since the 1840s.
Simply put, in his preface and supplement to Vol. III of Capital, Engels
evidenced that he had ‘completely misconstrued Marx’s value theory’; and
he did so because he confused ‘concrete and abstract labour’ (Weeks 1981:
8, 55). In fact, in his introduction to Marx’s original draft of Vol. III, Fred
Moseley has lamented that the questions Engels asked of Marx about this
volume evidence that ‘when Engels started this very difficult project, he
appears to have had very little knowledge and overall understanding of
Marx’s Book III’ (Moseley 2016: 3). It is difficult to overstate the impor-
tance of Engels’s misunderstanding of the theoretical architecture of
Capital. The distinction between the concepts of abstract and concrete
labor sits at the core of Marx’s mature critique of political economy—
indeed, he wrote to Engels that it was one of the ‘the best points in my
book’ (Marx 1987b: 407). This distinction is important because it is
through the concept of abstract labor that Marx overcomes fundamental
problems with the variants of the labor theory of value as conceived by
Adam Smith and David Ricardo (Rubin 1979: 248–255). Whereas neither
Smith nor Ricardo fully grasped how distinct types of concrete labor could
be compared, Marx solved this problem through the argument that labor
has a dual character. It is both ‘concrete labour’—the specific act of work-
ing to produce useful things—and ‘abstract labour’—the process of value
creation through the equalization of concrete acts of labor under the dis-
cipline of competition (Saad-Filho 2002: 26–29; Rubin 1973: 131–158;
Colletti 1972: 82–92). Whereas Smith’s and Ricardo’s studies in political
economy ultimately failed in their attempts to conceptualize capitalism
because they were unable to extricate their accounts of the labor theory of
value from the superficial materiality of labor as a multiplicity of distinct
6 METHOD AND VALUE: ENGELS THROUGH SOHN-RETHEL 107
References
Albritton, R. (1999). Dialectics and the Deconstruction of Political Economy.
London: Palgrave.
Arthur, C. (1996). Engels as an Interpreter of Marx’s Economics. In C. Arthur
(Ed.), Engels Today. London: Macmillan.
Arthur, C. (2004). The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Blackledge, P. (2004). Perry Anderson, Marxism and the New Left. London:
Merlin Press
Blackledge, P. (2006). Reflections on the Marxist Theory of History. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Blackledge, P. (2010). Marxism, Nihilism and the Problem of Ethical Politics
Today. Socialism and Democracy, 24(2), 101–123.
Blackledge, P. (2012). Marxism and Ethics: Freedom, Desire and Revolution. New
York: SUNY Press.
Blackledge, P. (2017). Practical Materialism: Engels’s Anti-Dühring as Marxist
Philosophy. Critique, 45(4), 483–499.
110 P. BLACKLEDGE
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1976). The German Ideology. In Marx and Engels
Collected Works (Vol. 5). London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Meikle, S. (1985). Essentialism in the Thought of Karl Marx. La Salle: Open Court.
Moseley, F. (2016). Introduction. In F. Moseley (Ed.), Marx’s Economic
Manuscripts 1864–1865. Leiden: Brill.
Ollman, B. (1976). Alienation. Cambridge: Cambridge University.
Ollman, B. (2003). Dance of the Dialectic. Illinois University Press.
Postone, M. (1993). Time, Labour and Social Domination. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Prinz, A. (1968). The Background and Ulterior Motive of Marx’s ‘Preface’ of
1859. Journal of the History of Ideas, 30, 437–450.
Rowthorn, B. (1980). Capitalism, Conflict and Inflation. London: Lawrence
and Wishart.
Rubin, I. I. (1973). Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value. Montreal: Black Rose.
Rubin, I. I. (1979). A History of Economic Thought. London: Ink Links.
Saad-Filho, A. (2002). The Value of Marx. London: Routledge.
Seaford, R. (2004). Money and the Early Greek Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Seaford, R. (2012). Monetization and the Genesis of the Western Subject.
Historical Materialism, 20(1), 78–102.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1978). Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of
Epistemology. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.
Steedman, I. (1977). Marx after Sraffa. London: Verso.
Thomson, G. (1955). The First Philosophers. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Weeks, J. (1981). Capital and Exploitation. Princeton University Press.
Žižek, S. (1989). The Sublime Object of Ideology. London: Verso.
CHAPTER 7
Mario Duayer
Introduction
This chapter deals with the so-called question of the method in Marx. The
debate around the methodological issues in the Marxist tradition are
mainly based on the famous text entitled ‘The Method in Political
Economy’, which appears in the introduction of the Grundrisse (Marx
2011a). Though unfinished and not published by the author, it consti-
tutes the only work in which Marx deals explicitly with the issues relative
to the method. It is then natural that it is the obligatory reference for the
theoretical arguments on the Marxist method.
As the chapter consists in a critical contribution inside the Marxist tra-
dition, it is worth warning, and not just for convention, that other dimen-
sions of the work of the authors here mentioned are not being questioned:
the critical commentaries concentrate only in their interpretations of the
‘Method…’, It is even important to recognize the value of these works in
the divulgation of the Marxist text, as well as being of importance to
enlarge and enrich important aspects which surge from it.
M. Duayer (*)
Universidade Federal Fluminense, Rio de Janeiro, Brazil
The critique realized in the chapter seeks to show, in the first place, that
it is a serious misunderstanding to suggest that Marx settles the general
lines of his method in this writing; second, and even more relevant, that,
with Lukács1 as an exception, the most influential interpretations cannot
account for the ontological orientation of the Marxist text, precisely the
fundamental dimension of his critique. With this purpose, the chapter
starts transcribing the passages of the work of Marx of interest for our
discussion. Then, it examines what some authors have elaborated to illus-
trate the most characteristic elements of what could be considered the
standard interpretation. Finally, it suggests that Marx describes the proce-
dures of science in general and not of his method, reason why it can be
inferred that the resolution of the matter is not properly of a method,
either gnoseological or epistemological, but ontological.
Marx’s Method?
The critique cannot be elaborated without quoting the large initial pas-
sage of ‘The Method of Political Economy’, which synthesizes the ideas of
Marx (2011a). To facilitate the exposition, it was decided to use italics for
the most commented passages by the literature on the matter:
As we shall see now, in general, those two paragraphs have been used to
affirm or suggest that Marx considers his own the second method—the
retracing phase—the scientifically correct method. Callinicos, for example,
after quoting the passage, concludes that ‘This, then, is Marx’s method of
analysis. (…) So we move first from concrete to abstract, breaking down
the concrete into its “simplest determinations”, and then from abstract to
concrete, using these to reconstruct the whole. We shall see this method at
work when Marx analyses capitalist society in Capital’ (Callinicos 2004: 74).
Carchedi seems to support an identical interpretation. Quoting Marx’s
passage in which he suggests that it is necessary that ‘From there the jour-
ney would have to be retraced until I had finally arrived at the population
again, but this time not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich
totality of many determinations and relations’, he highlights that ‘This is
what Marx calls the “concrete in thought”. The “retracing” phase is the
dialectical deduction, the unfolding (reconstruction in thought) of more-
and-more concrete, detailed, and articulated notions of reality derived
from their potential state. Each step in the unfolding is a (temporary)
conclusion, but also the premise for the following step in the chain of
deductions’ (Carchedi 2011: 46).
The author describes the process of knowledge explained by Marx in
terms of dialectical induction and deduction, different from their equiva-
116 M. DUAYER
lents in formal logics. We are not trying to discuss, here, Carchedi’s prop-
ositions, but if it is said that ‘Marx’s starting point of induction is indeed
empirical reality’; it is clear that for him, Marx, in fact, is talking about his
own method.
Foley certainly shares a similar interpretation when he affirms that ‘This
double motion is pervasive in Marx’s writing’. He thinks that Capital can
be seen as ‘a movement to reconstruct in thought the whole complex of
capitalist social relations beginning from the simplest abstractions - com-
modity, value, and money - and eventually arriving at the most complex and
distorted forms, for example, the stock market and crisis’ (Foley 1986: 4).
Basu, in a working paper for the Economics Department of the
University of Massachusetts (Amherst), famous for its Marxist tradition, is
convinced that, from the Grundrisse till the redaction of Capital, Marx
puts into practice his understanding of ‘the correct method of political
economy’, which had been detailed in the ‘Introduction’. According to
the author, Marx explains that ‘“ascending from the abstract to the con-
crete” is the only scientific way to understand a concrete reality like a capi-
talist society’ (Basu 2017: 6). Such a movement ends ‘With a structured
synthesis of determinations, which is how Marx visualized the reproduc-
tion in thought of the concrete reality he was studying’ (Basu 2017: 6).
In his analysis of ‘The Method of Political Economy’, Netto observes
that ‘the method in Marx’ is not the product of a sudden and fantastic
insight, but of a long process of investigation. In his opinion, in the
‘Introduction’, after 15 years of studies, ‘the central elements’ of Marx’s
method are ‘precisely’ formulated. According to the author, the few pages
of the work present synthetically ‘the bases of the method which made
viable the analysis in Das Kapital and the foundation of Marx’s social
theory’ (Netto 2011: 19).
The author remembers that, in the process of knowledge, of theoretical
production and of theoretical appropriation of the object suggested by
Marx ‘it starts “with the real and with the concrete”, which appear as
given; through the analysis, elements are abstracted and, progressively,
with its advance, some concepts and abstractions are reached which refer
to the simplest determinations’ (Originally highlighted, Netto 2011: 42).
And he adds, based on the Marxist text, that this was the method
adopted by economics in its origins. However, in the sequence of his anal-
ysis, Netto dismisses a crucial element of Marx’s argument. In fact, accord-
ing to him, Marx claims that ‘the analytical procedure was a necessary
element for the emergence of the political economy’, and, nonetheless, it
7 MARX: THE METHOD OF POLITICAL ECONOMY AS AN ONTOLOGICAL… 117
The theoretical knowledge is, (…) according to Marx, the knowledge of the
concrete, which constitutes reality, but it is not directly offered to thought:
it must be reproduced by it and only ‘the retraced journey’ allows this repro-
duction. We already pointed out that, (…) the concrete to which thought is
capable to arrive through the method that Marx considers as ‘scientifically
correct’ (the ‘concrete in thought’) is a product of thought which realizes a
‘retraced journey’. Marx does not hesitate in qualifying this method as the
one which consists in ‘rising from the abstract to the concrete’, it is ‘the only
way’ by which ‘thought appropriates the concrete’. (Netto 2011: 44–45)
(Althusser) should also explain that before being the raw material of theo-
retical production, the intuitions and representations constitute the lexical
heritage of each language, and it results from the social practice. (…) They
crystallize the social thought built up in each historical moment and they
provide knowledge with the heritage of ideas which constitute the materials
on which the theoretical work operates. (Quartim de Moraes 2015: 79/80)
In that sense, it can be asserted that Marx refers, when saying that it
always starts in population, not to a mere noun, but to a representation of
the population which, lacking an economic science, was the necessary con-
dition for the agents in the real economic life. There is no doubt that is
what Marx has in mind when he notices that
The economic science, therefore, at its beginning stage, starts with the
representation of population of the real agents of social production.
Quartim is more emphatic when he highlights that for the economists of
the seventeenth century ‘there was no other way of moving on in the eco-
nomic analysis’, so that Marx was wrong to qualify that way as false.
(Quartim de Moraes 2017: 45). Fact that Marx, according to him, admits
tacitly in the sequence of his arguments:
As soon as these individual moments had been more or less firmly estab-
lished and abstracted, there began the economic systems, which ascended
from the simple relations, such as labour, division of labour, need, exchange
value, to the level of the state, exchange between nations and the world
market. The latter is obviously the scientifically correct method. The con-
crete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations,
hence unity of the diverse. It appears in the process of thinking, therefore,
as a process of concentration, as a result, not as a point of departure, even
though it is the point of departure in reality and hence also the point of
departure for observation [Anschauung] and conception. Along the first
path the full conception was evaporated to yield an abstract determination;
along the second, the abstract determinations lead towards a reproduction
of the concrete by way of thought. (Marx 2011a: 54)
7 MARX: THE METHOD OF POLITICAL ECONOMY AS AN ONTOLOGICAL… 121
Ontological Critique
The first matter to be observed for an adequate interpretation of Marx’s
thought is his categorical declaration on the instauration of the economic
systems. As we saw above he stated that: ‘As soon as these individual
moments had been more or less firmly established and abstracted, there
began the economic systems, which ascended from the simple relations,
such as labour, division of labour, need, exchange value, to the level of the
state, exchange between nations and the world market. The latter is obvi-
ously the scientifically correct method’ (Marx 2011a: 54. Emphasis added).
7 MARX: THE METHOD OF POLITICAL ECONOMY AS AN ONTOLOGICAL… 123
Man’s reflections on the forms of social life, and consequently, also, his sci-
entific analysis of those forms, take a course directly opposite to that of their
actual historical development. He begins, post festum, with the results of
the process of development ready to hand before him. The characters that
stamp products as commodities, and whose establishment is a necessary pre-
liminary to the circulation of commodities, have already acquired the stabil-
ity of natural, self-understood forms of social life, before man seeks to
decipher, not their historical character, for in his eyes they are immutable,
but their meaning. Consequently, it was the analysis of the prices of com-
modities that alone led to the determination of the magnitude of value, and
it was the common expression of all commodities in money that alone led to
the establishment of their characters as values. It is, however, just this ulti-
mate money form of the world of commodities that actually conceals,
124 M. DUAYER
instead of disclosing, the social character of private labour, and the social
relations between the individual producers.
The categories of bourgeois economy consist of such like forms. They are
forms of thought expressing with social validity the conditions and relations
of a definite, historically determined mode of production, viz., the produc-
tion of commodities. (Marx 2011b: 210–211)
The bourgeois political economy, argues Marx, is the socially valid form
of the thought, objective for those productive relations, whose content he
tries to investigate. What he means is that it consists in a totalization, in a
figuration, in a scientific ontology of the capitalist society. It departs from
the representation, as all of them, takes distance and differentiates from it,
but, in the process, it hypostatizes that form of life, and, in consequence,
it is a-historical. But certainly, it investigates its structure and its dynam-
ics—in a logical time, without history, that is, without substantial changes.7
It departs from the finished totality, fully developed, ignores its historical
character; it proceeds analytically and produces a richly articulated synthe-
sis, without history.
Marx makes a completely different analysis with what he calls the vulgar
economy, precursor of the neoclassicism. In chapter 48 from the 3rd vol-
ume of Capital, entitled ‘The Trinity Formula’, he analyzes the term
as follows:
order, should see precisely in this trinity, which is devoid of all inner connec-
tion, the natural and indubitable lofty basis for its shallow pompousness.
(Marx 2017: 1056–1057)
Here, Marx emphasises that the vulgar economy departs from the rep-
resentation of the captive agents of the capitalist economy relations, and,
instead of turning progressively different from it, it does completely the
opposite: it keeps the ontology (figuration/totalization) immediately gen-
erated and needed for those relations, and it systematizes them by means
of a scientific apparatus and, this done, it goes back to the agents as a form
of more efficient thought in the immediate practice.8 This is done with the
seal of science.
As it was indicated in this chapter, I tried to demonstrate, first, that the
usual interpretations of ‘The Method of Political Economy’ are directly
contrary to Marx’s text. On the other hand, as the title of the section
points out, it concerns The Method of Political Economy and not The Method
of the Critique of the Political Economy. Secondly, it was argued every sci-
ence totalizes. The vulgar economy totalizes (synthesizes); the political
economy totalizes; and the critique of the political economy, that is, Marx,
also totalizes. Those totalizations constitute ontologies with a social force.9
They offer the image to the subjects, backed by the prestige of science, by
means of which they position themselves in their reciprocal relations and
in their relation with the natural world.
If every science totalizes, signifies the world for the subjects, and,
besides, provides a scientific apparatus to administer it, manage it, it fol-
lows that it is efficient in practice. Thus, the decisive theoretical battle
between the theoretical systems can only take place at an ontological
level—that is to say, ontologies in dispute, radically different ways of
understanding the world. In other words, an effective critique is an onto-
logical critique. If, as we saw in Marx, the political economy is a form of
thought valid and objective for the social life under capital; if it is eco-
nomic science at the service of the management of that society; if it
expresses and reinforces the ontological notions spontaneously generated;
if, with its prestige, it not only elevates the common ideas to the exclusive
figuration of society, but it also provides the techniques to reproduce it,
then the critique of the political economy, as a substantial critique, creates
a radically different intelligibility of the structure and the dynamics of the
society ruled by capital, in the first place by restoring its historicity and, in
consequence, by opening to the human practice the possibility of its trans-
126 M. DUAYER
Notes
1. See Lukács (2012), chapter IV, section 2, for a detailed analysis of the matter
elaborated by the author.
2. Without the proper permission of the author, from now on we will only use
‘Quartim’ in the references, since the Marxist theorist is widely known in
that way.
3. See below Marx’s passage on the vulgar economy from the chapter about
the Trinity formula.
4. As Lukács defends (2013): ‘We have already seen how the teleological posi-
tion consciously realized produces some distance in the reflection of reality
and how, with this distance, the subject-object relation arises in the proper
sense of the term. These two moments imply simultaneously the emergence
of conceptual comprehension of the phenomena of reality and their ade-
quate expression in language… In fact, word and concept, language and
conceptual thought are linked elements of the complex called the social
being, which means that they can only be understood in their true essence
when related to the ontological analysis of the social being and recognizing
the real functions which they exert within the complex’. (Lukács 2013:
84–85. Personal translation).
5. As Lukács observes: ‘the totality of nature can be inferred in many ways,
however strict the analysis be; in the social field on the contrary, the totality
is always given in an immediate way’ (Lukács 2012: 304. Personal transla-
tion). It is on this totality always immediately given where the subjects act
and, consequently, they always refigure it in some way. On this matter, cf.
also Duayer (2006, 2015).
6. Lukács remembers that what Marx follows from the abstract to the concrete
‘cannot start at an ordinary abstraction. […] because, considered in isola-
tion, any phenomenon could be taken, once it is transformed in an ‘ele-
ment’ by means of the abstraction, as a starting point; only such a path
would never lead to the comprehension of totality’ (Lukács 2012: 312.
Personal translation).
7. On the characteristic temporalities of capitalism—abstract time and histori-
cal time—see Postone, in particular, chapter 8. According to the author, ‘the
7 MARX: THE METHOD OF POLITICAL ECONOMY AS AN ONTOLOGICAL… 127
References
Basu, D. (2017). The Structure and Content of Das Kapital. Working Paper, −12,
Dept. of Economics of Massachusetts (Amherst).
Bhaskar, R. (1989). Reclaiming Reality. London: Verso.
Callinicos, A. (2004). The Revolutionary Ideas of Karl Marx. London: Bookmarks.
Carchedi, G. (2011). Behind the Crisis: Marx’s Dialectics of Value and Knowledge.
Leiden: Brill.
Duayer, M. (2006). Anti-Realismo e Absolutas Crenças Relativas. Margem
Esquerda, 8, 109–130.
Duayer, M. (2015). Jorge Luis Borges, filosofia da ciência e crítica ontológica:
verdade e emancipação. Margem Esquerda, 24, 87–110.
Foley, D. (1986). Understanding Capital: Marx’s Economic Theory. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Kuruma, S. (1969). Discussion of Marx’s Method. Part 1. Resource Document.
Retrieved November 15, 2017, from https://www.marxists.org/archive/
kuruma/method-discussion1.htm.
Lukács, G. (2012). Para uma Ontologia do Ser Social I. São Paulo: Boitempo.
Lukács, G. (2013). Para uma Ontologia do Ser Social II. São Paulo: Boitempo.
Marx, K. (2011a). Grundrisse. Boitempo, São Paulo (in English). Retrieved from
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1857/grundrisse/
ch01.htm.
Marx, K. (2011b). O Capital, LI. Boitempo, São Paulo (in English). Retrieved
from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/download/pdf/
Capital-Volume-I.pdf.
Marx, K. (2017). O Capital, LIII. Boitempo, São Paulo (in English). Retrieved
from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/ch48.htm.
Netto, J. P. (2011). Introdução ao Estudo do Método de Marx. São Paulo:
Expressão Popular.
128 M. DUAYER
Patrick Murray
Karl Marx and Bishop George Berkeley may seem like strange bedfellows,
given Marx’s reference to Berkeley as ‘the advocate of mystical idealism in
English philosophy’ (Marx 1970a: 78).1 However, both Marx and Berkeley
were educated in philosophy; both took an interest in the new science of
political economy and each brought his philosophy to bear on political
economy.2 Each combines phenomenological inquiry with identifying how
abstraction can go wrong, creating bad abstractions. Marx goes beyond
Berkeley, with the phenomenological breakthrough of historical material-
ism and by introducing, with his theory of value, the idea of social practices
of real abstraction—practices integral to the circulation of capital—that
result in capitalist society being ruled by bad abstractions of its own making.
A second historical through line runs from Berkeley through Samuel
Bailey (1791–1870) to Marx.3 Berkeley, like Bailey, whose thinking he
influenced, offers a critique of intrinsic value as a bad abstraction. Unlike
Marx, who sees intrinsic value—which makes fetishes of commodities,
money and capital—to be an unavoidable consequence of the social prac-
tices of real abstraction involved in capital’s circuits, Berkeley and Bailey
see intrinsic value as a theoretical gaffe. Marx quotes Bailey as saying that
P. Murray (*)
Philosophy Department, Creighton University, Omaha, NE, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
for instance, a black line of an inch in length; this, which in itself is a par-
ticular line, is nevertheless with regard to its signification general, since as
it is there used, it represents all particular lines whatsoever; for that which
is demonstrated of all lines or, in other words, of a line in general’ (Berkeley
1957: 12). Generality is all about how particulars are handled; a line
becomes general when it serves as an example of something general.
General ideas, for Berkeley, are ideas that are attended to in the right way;
there are no abstract ideas.
This is mixed praise. Hegel treats nature and humanity the way that
capital does, reducing them to bad abstractions produced by abstract
thought or abstract labor: ‘The human character of nature and of the
nature created by history—man’s products—appears in the form that they
are products of abstract mind and as such, therefore, phases of mind—
thought entities’ (Marx 1964: 176). Marx precociously interprets Hegel
through the lens of the critique of value and the real abstractions involved
in the circulation of capital that had begun to emerge from his reading of
political economy.7 Just as Marx insists that the truth of the thing-like
ghostly objectivity of value is capital, which is a process, the circuit of self-
valorizing value, he says here, ‘what Hegel does is to put in place of these
fixed abstractions the act of abstraction which revolves in its own circle’
(Marx 1964: 191 note). Marx appears to be reading the course of con-
sciousness as Hegel presents it the Phenomenology along the lines of capi-
tal’s ‘abstraction in action’.
Returning to his reference to those ‘fixed’ abstractions, Marx pays
Hegel another left-handed compliment: ‘Hegel’s positive achievement
here, in his speculative logic, is that the definite concepts, the universal
fixed thought-forms in their independence vis-à-vis nature and mind are a
necessary result of the general estrangement of the human essence and
therefore also of human thought, and Hegel has therefore brought these
together and presented them as moments of the abstraction-process’
(Marx 1964: 189).
Because Hegel reduces human consciousness to sheer thought, he nec-
essarily generates ‘fixed thought-forms’ set against nature and spirit. This
bonds Marx’s criticism of Hegel’s Phenomenology with his criticisms of his
Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences and the Philosophy of Right.
Anticipating his view that value necessarily is expressed in money, Marx
says of Hegel: ‘Logic (mind’s coin of the realm, the speculative or thought-
value of man and nature—their essence grown totally indifferent to all real
determinateness, and hence their unreal essence) is alienated thinking,
and therefore thinking which abstracts from nature and from real man:
abstract thinking’ (Marx 1964: 174).
So, Marx imagines Hegel’s Logic as a bank, a treasury of bad abstrac-
tions produced by the abstract thinker: ‘His thoughts are therefore fixed
mental shapes or ghosts dwelling outside nature and man. Hegel has
locked up all these fixed mental forms together in his Logic’ (Marx 1964:
190). In his Encyclopedia, Hegel puts logic before nature and spirit, so
that ‘the whole of nature only repeats for him the logical abstractions in a
8 MARX, BERKELEY AND BAD ABSTRACTIONS 139
sensuous, external form’ (Marx 1964: 91). Just as useful things in the
commodity form count as ‘carriers of value’, Hegel treats the wealth of
nature and society as mere carriers of logical (bad) abstractions.8
We can see this remarkable reading of Hegel through Berkeley’s eyes as
a tale of abstraction gone wrong. Hegel’s logical categories are bad
abstractions: ‘As a result there are general, abstract forms of abstraction
pertaining to every content and on that account indifferent to, and, con-
sequently, valid for, all content—the thought-forms or logical categories
torn from real mind and from real nature’ (Marx 1964: 189). Marx draws
the conclusion regarding these ‘general, abstract forms of abstraction’ that
Berkeley drew regarding abstract general ideas: ‘Thus, the entire Logic is
the demonstration that abstract thought is nothing in itself’ (Marx
1964: 189).
from every social sort: ‘The fact that the production of use-values, or
goods, is carried on under the control of a capitalist and on his behalf does
not alter the general character of that production. We shall therefore, in
the first place, have to consider the labour process independently of any
specific social formation’ (Marx 1976: 283).
Marx’s general concept of the labor process abstracts, precisely because
it is general, from the tools or materials required, and from the social form
and purpose of the labor process. That has led to the mistaken notion that
Marx’s general concept of labor abstracts from these complexities alto-
gether. ‘Considering something independently’ is just what Hume, fol-
lowing Berkeley, called making a distinction of reason. To consider the
labor process apart from social form and purpose is not to claim that it can
exist as a labor process-in-general. The phenomenological breakthrough
of historical materialism is to show that there can be no such thing.
Considering the labor process in abstraction from social form, Marx
identifies three general features of the labor process: ‘The simple elements
of the labour process are (1) purposeful activity, that is work itself, (2) the
object on which that work is performed, and (3) the instruments of that
work’ (Marx 1976: 284). With these general features of the labor process,
Marx sets up his critique in Chapter 48 of Capital 3, ‘The Trinity Formula’,
of the fetishizing of the three revenue forms: interest, rent and wages.11
There Marx relies on two key phenomenological points: (1) the three fac-
tors of production always have a determinate social form and (2) produc-
tion requires that all three factors be involved.
(1) The formulation of the Trinity Formula produced means of produc-
tion—interest, land—rent, labor—wages presents the three factors of the
labor process-in-general as mysteriously invested by nature with the social
powers of yielding revenues in the forms of interest, rent and wages. In
this formula, we have the consistent conflation of the general categories
produced means of production, land and labor with the socially specific
revenue forms interest, rent and wages (and, correlatively, with three social
classes: capitalists, landowners and wage laborers). Revenues in these spe-
cific social forms: ‘appear to grow out of the roles that the earth, the pro-
duced means of production and labour play in the simple labour process,
considering this labour process simply as proceeding between man and
nature and ignoring any historical specificity’ (Marx 1981: 964).
This mismatch is the outcome of twisting the general abstraction, the
labor process, into the bad abstraction that posits a labor process-in-
general and conflates it with the capitalist valorization process.
8 MARX, BERKELEY AND BAD ABSTRACTIONS 141
(2) The fact that three factors of production in the production of wealth
are distinguishable can lead to the fallacious reasoning of the Trinity
Formula, which, taking its lead from the forms of revenue: wages, interest
and rent, isolates the contributions of the three factors: ‘In the formula
capital-interest, earth-ground-rent, labour-wages, capital, earth and labour
appear respectively as sources of interest (instead of profit), ground-rent
and wages as their products or fruits—one the basis, the other the result,
one the cause, the other the effect—and moreover in such a way that each
individual source is related to its product as something extruded from it
and produced by it’ (Marx 1981: 955).
Marx expands on the image of fruit, saying of the three forms of reve-
nue: ‘They appear as fruits of a perennial tree for annual consumption, or
rather fruits of three trees’ (Marx 1981: 960). Marx’s image of three fruit
trees, each producing its own fruit, recalls his earlier use of ‘the Fruit’ as a
bad abstraction (Marx and Engels 1975: 60). The image represents general
concepts that have been twisted into bad abstractions. The notion of three
independent sources of revenue, the three perennial fruit trees, betrays a
phenomenology of the labor process that separates distinguishable factors
into three independent sources. Marx’s phenomenological point is that all
three factors of production are required to produce fruit from any tree.
No orchard has a ‘land trees’ row, a ‘means of production trees’ row and
a ‘labor trees’ row—that is a phenomenological joke.
When Marx takes up labor as an isolated member of the ‘Trinity’, he
writes, ‘“die” Arbeit’ to mimic, I believe, ‘“the” Fruit’. This gets lost in
David Fernbach’s translation of ‘“die” Arbeit’ simply as ‘labour’ (Marx
1981: 954). Marx calls ‘“the” labour’ ‘a mere spectre … nothing but an
abstraction and taken by itself cannot exist at all’ (Marx 1981: 954). Taken
in abstraction—a bad abstraction—from the two other necessary factors in
the labor process, produced means of production and raw materials,
human labor is not the source of any wealth.
concrete labor; they owe their value to ‘human labor in the abstract’. Marx
identifies ‘human labor in the abstract’ with human physiological expendi-
ture of energy: ‘however varied the useful kinds of labour, or productive
activities, it is a physiological fact that they are functions of the human
organism, and that each such function, whatever may be its nature or its
form, is essentially the expenditure of human brain, nerves, muscles and
sense organs’ (Marx 1976: 164).
If congealed ‘human labor in the abstract’ is the substance of value,
then how are we to think about abstract labor and its relation to value?
Here is a thorny problem.
Isaak I. Rubin rightly insists that, for Marx, value is not something tran-
shistorical but rather is specific to the capitalist mode of production. There
are countless passages in Marx that support Rubin. For example, ‘It is only
by being exchanged that the products of labour acquire a socially uniform
objectivity as values’ (Marx 1976: 166). Value exists only where there is an
extensive and well-established sphere of simple commodity circulation,
that is, only where wealth is generally produced in the commodity form.
Marx states that this is true only where capitalist production predominates
(Marx 1976: 272). But this generates a conundrum that I call ‘Rubin’s
dilemma’ (Murray 2016: 124ff). The problem is that if value is historically
specific, and if congealed abstract labor is the substance of value, then
abstract labor must be socially specific. Rubin puts it this way:
I agree, but, since Rubin has only one concept of abstract labor in play,
he is forced to say that abstract labor is socially specific to capitalism.13 But
this conflicts with passages in Capital such as ‘all labour is an expenditure
of human labour-power, in the physiological sense’ (Marx 1976: 137). Is
there a way out?
Moishe Postone comments that passages such as these ‘are very prob-
lematic. They seem to indicate that it [value] is a biological residue, that it
is to be interpreted as the expenditure of human physiological energy’
144 P. MURRAY
(Postone 1993: 144). Like Rubin, Postone insists: ‘If, however, the cate-
gory of abstract human labor is a social determination, it cannot be a
physiological category’ (Postone 1993: 145). Postone concludes: ‘The
problem, then is to move beyond the physiological definition of abstract
human labor provided by Marx and analyze its underlying social and his-
torical meaning’ (Postone 1993: 145). Yes, we must ‘move beyond the
physiological definition of abstract human labor’, but not by eliminating
it. There is no need to correct Marx; he provides what is needed. The
dilemma arises not because Marx’s definitions of abstract human labor are
problematic. No, the problem lies in thinking that Marx puts only one
concept of abstract labor in play and, consequently, that he identifies
abstract labor as value-producing labor. Labor is value-producing, Marx
says, insofar as it is abstract: ‘it is in this quality of being equal, or abstract,
human labour that it forms the value of commodities’ (Marx 1976: 137,
my emphasis). It is fallacious to reason: since labor is value-producing only
insofar as it is abstract, and since all labor can be analyzed as abstract,
physiological labor, therefore all labor is value-producing. Abstract labor is
not value-producing labor; in fact, abstract labor is not a kind of labor. It is
not a candidate to be the cause of value.
The way out of the dilemma is to recognize that Marx has three con-
cepts in play in the first chapter of Capital; two pertain to abstract labor.
Marx has a general concept of human labor, which is his concept of con-
crete labor (Marx 1976: 128). All labor is concrete labor, labor that is
technically specific, oriented to the accomplishment of specific purposes
such as hammering nails to attach one board to another to construct a
bookcase. The lesson of historical materialism is that all labor is socially
specific as well. Marx highlights these two features of his general phenom-
enology of human labor: ‘If there is no production in general [Marx is
summarizing the point that production always has a specific social form
and purpose.], then there is also no general production. Production is
always a particular branch of production—e.g. agriculture, cattle-raising,
manufactures etc.—or it is a totality’ (Marx 1973: 86).
According to Marx’s general phenomenology of human labor, human
labor is always socially and technically specific; there is no human labor in
the abstract. Sound familiar?
The first concept relating to abstract labor is that of physiological exer-
tion. Like the general concept of human labor, this concept is generally
applicable; it cuts across human history: ‘all labour is an expenditure of
human labour-power, in the physiological sense’ (Marx 1976: 137). This
8 MARX, BERKELEY AND BAD ABSTRACTIONS 145
concept abstracts from both social and technical particularity, which are
inseparable from human labor. That phenomenological fact means that
abstract labor in this physiological sense cannot stand on its own. Abstract
labor is not a kind of labor, much less the kind of labor that could give rise
to value. Rather, the concept of abstract labor as physiological exertion
isolates and identifies a feature common to all human labor. The substance
of value, congealed (socially necessary) abstract labor, is a bad abstraction.
Dominated by the law of value, capitalist society is ruled by bad abstrac-
tions—a nightmare scenario for Berkeley. Since value results from practical
abstraction—not a theoretical mistake—it can be overcome only by social
action that replaces real abstraction as the dominant form of social
mediation.
In view of the practical abstractions that characterize the capitalist mode
of production, we can call value-producing labor, ‘practically abstract’.
Postone rightly insists that we must ‘investigate the historically specific
social relations that underlie value in order to explain why those relations
appear and, therefore, are presented by Marx, as being physiological—as
transhistorical, natural, and thus historically empty’ (Postone 1993: 145).
Yes, but the answer lies in the concept of ‘practically abstract’ labor as
labor that is socially validated in its most abstract characteristic, as physi-
ological labor. Martha Campbell observes that it is social labor of this type
that generates the ‘phantom-like objectivity’ of value: ‘The objectivity of
value stems from the indirectly social (in other words, simultaneously pri-
vate and social) character of production. The entire significance of money
as universal equivalent is that it mediates (allows the existence of) this
contradiction but does not remove it’ (Campbell 2004: 224).
This ‘indirectly social’ character of commodity-producing labor is what
requires the money-mediated processes of ‘real abstraction’ in the circula-
tion of wealth as capital; that is why the circulation of capital is ‘abstraction
in action’. What distinguishes it and makes it ‘practically abstract’ is that
labor in capitalist society is socially validated as abstract, physiological labor,
with indifference toward its useful features.14
Marx needs to introduce the concept of abstract, physiological labor to
explain the sense in which ‘practically abstract’ labor is abstract. From the
opening sentence of Capital, Marx tells us that he is writing about those
societies where wealth is generally produced in the commodity form.
From the start, he is writing about the social sort of labor that produces
commodities. How is commodity-producing labor socially validated? It is
validated through the sale of its products. But that sale transforms prod-
146 P. MURRAY
Notes
1. One aim of the present chapter is to argue that taking an interpretive per-
spective ‘from Berkeley to Marx’ provides a valuable vantage point on
modern philosophy and political economy. In his Interpreting Modern
Philosophy, James Collins discusses the significance of ‘reforming the from-
to perspectives’ on modern philosophers (Collins 1972: 212–231).
2. Marx comments on the match between Berkeley’s philosophy and his
nominalist theory of money: ‘Very fittingly it was Bishop Berkeley, the
advocate of mystical idealism in English philosophy, who gave the doctrine
of the nominal standard of money a theoretical twist’ (Marx 1970a:
78–79).
3. On Marx’s relationship to Bailey, see Chapters 6 and 17 of Murray (2016).
4. See Chapter 18 of Murray (1988).
5. We may wonder if Berkeley, with his talk of observing that certain colors,
tastes, smells and so on ‘go together’, leading us to ‘account’ such a ‘col-
lection’ as ‘one distinct thing’, may remain closer to Locke’s account of
experience than he might like. On Hegel’s critique of Locke for putting
simple ideas ahead of objects, see Schuler (2014).
6. See Chapter 11 of Murray (1988) and Chapters 8 and 9 of Murray (2016).
7. We may wonder if Marx is too clever. Is Marx imposing on Hegel by view-
ing him through the lens of his incipient critique of the practical bad
abstractions of value and capital?
8. On these topics, see Murray (1988: 45–51).
9. Marx attributes Ricardo’s ‘inability to grasp the specific form of bourgeois
production’ to his ‘obsession that bourgeois production is production as
such’ (Marx 1968: 529).
10. Jürgen Habermas misreads Chapter 7 in this way. Consequently, he
wrongly attributes to Marx a conception of labor (conceived of as instru-
mental or purposive-rational action) as ‘in principle solitary’ (Habermas
1971: 137). This misstep led Habermas away from Marx’s critical theory
of value and capital toward a neo-Weberian critique of instrumental action.
11. See Chapter 14 of Murray (2016). Martha Campbell, in correspondence,
points out that the phrase ‘fetishism of the factors of production’ should be
corrected to ‘fetishism of the capitalist revenue forms, interest, rent, and
wages’.
12. See Chapter 4 of Murray (2016).
148 P. MURRAY
13. Postone (1993) and Murray (1988), among others, follow Rubin in this
reasoning.
14. ‘Practically abstract’ labor must produce useful things for which there is
demand in order to produce value, but how it is useful is a matter of
indifference.
15. Real abstraction in capitalism is not restricted to the circulation of money
and commodities: it pervades the capitalist mode of production. One of
the first interpreters to introduce the idea of real abstraction as a descrip-
tion of processes in capitalist society, Alfred Sohn-Rethel, did limit it to
exchange (Sohn-Rethel 1978: 77–78). For a criticism, see Postone (1993:
178).
References
Berkeley, G. (1957). A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge.
Indianapolis, IN: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc.
Campbell, M. (1993). Marx’s Concept of Economic Relations and the Method of
Capital. In Marx’s Method in “Capital” (F. Moseley, Ed.). Atlantic Highlands,
NJ: Humanities Press.
Campbell, M. (2004). Value Objectivity and Habit. In R. Bellofiore & N. Taylor
(Eds.), The Constitution of Capital: Essays on Volume I of Marx’s “Capital”.
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Collins, J. (1972). Interpreting Modern Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Descartes, R. (1970). Meditations on First Philosophy. In The Philosophical Works of
Descartes (E. Haldane & G. R. T. Ross, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Habermas, J. (1971). Knowledge and the Human Interests (J. J. Shapiro, Trans.).
Boston: Beacon Press.
Marx, K. (1964). Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (D. J. Struick, Ed.;
M. Milligan, Trans.). New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K. (1968). Theories of Surplus-Value, Part II (S. W. Ryazanskaya, Ed.;
R. Simpson, Trans.). London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K. (1970a). A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (M. Dobb,
Ed.; S. W. Ryazanskaya, Trans.). New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K. (1970b). Critique of Hegel’s “Philosophy of Right” (J. O’Malley, Ed.;
A. Jolin & J. O’Malley, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Marx, K. (1971). Theories of Surplus-Value, Part III. (S. W. Ryazanskaya and
Richard Dixon, Eds.; Jack Cohen and S. W. Ryazanskaya, Trans.). London:
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse (M. Nicolaus, Trans.). Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
8 MARX, BERKELEY AND BAD ABSTRACTIONS 149
Marx, K. (1975). Notes (1879–80) on Adolph Wagner. In T. Carver (Ed. &
Trans.), Karl Marx: Texts on Method. New York: Harper and Row.
Marx, K. (1976). Capital: Volume 1 (B. Fowkes, Trans.). Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Marx, K. (1978). Capital: Volume 2 (D. Fernbach, Trans.). Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Marx, K. (1981). Capital: Volume 3 (D. Fernbach, Trans.). Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Marx, K. (1988). Economic Manuscript of 1861–1863 (L. Miskievich, Ed.;
B. Fowkes & E. Burns, Trans.). In Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works
(Vol. 30). New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1975). The Holy Family (R. Dixon & C. Dutt, Trans.). In
Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works (Vol. 4: Marx and Engels:
1845–47). New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1976). The German Ideology (C. Dutt, W. Lough, et al.,
Trans.). In Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works (Vol. 5: Marx and
Engels: 1845–47). New York: International Publishers.
Murray, P. (1988). Marx’s Theory of Scientific Knowledge. Atlantic Highlands:
Humanities Press International.
Murray, P. (2016). The Mismeasure of Wealth: Essays on Marx and Social Form.
Leiden: Brill.
Postone, M. (1993). Time, Labour, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of
Marx’s Critical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rubin, I. I. (1972). Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value (M. Samardzija & F. Perlman,
Trans.). Detroit: Black & Red.
Schuler, J. (2014). Empiricism without the Dogmas: Hegel’s Critique of Locke’s
Simple Ideas. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 31(4), 347–368.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1978). Intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Epistemology
(M. Sohn-Rethel, Trans.). London: Macmillan.
PART II
Werner Bonefeld
W. Bonefeld (*)
Department of Politics, University of York, York, UK
e-mail: [email protected]
It is, in reality, much easier to discover by analysis the earthly kernel of the
misty creations of religions than to do the opposite, i.e., to develop from the
actual, given relations of life the forms in which they have become apotheo-
sized. The latter method is the only materialist, and therefore the only sci-
entific one. The weakness of the abstract materialism of natural science, a
materialism which excludes the historical process, are immediately evident
from the abstract and ideological conceptions expressed by its spokesmen
whenever they venture beyond the bounds of their own speciality. (Marx
1990: 494, note 4)10
between things and coins, and in this relationship, the actual social rela-
tions subsist but as coined factors of production. In capitalism, individuals
are really governed by the movement of coins. Although coins tend to
inflate or become depressed, coins are not subjects. Yet, they impose
themselves on, and also in and through, the person to the point of mad-
ness and disaster, from the socially necessary consciousness of cash and
product, money and profit, to abject misery and bloodshed. Capitalist
wealth is money as more money, and the necessity of more money objecti-
fies itself in the persons as mere ‘agents of value’ who depend for their life
on the manner in which the logic of things unfolds. What a monstrosity!
An economic thing, this coin, that really is nothing more than a piece of
metal manifests itself as an economic quantity in fateful movement, asserts
a power by which ‘the life of all men hangs by’. That is, the mythological
idea of fate becomes no less mythical when it is demythologized ‘into a
secular “logic of things”’ that akin to an abstract system-logic structures
the economic behaviors of the actual individuals by means of competing
price signals (Adorno 1990: 311, 320, 319).
The secular logic of things entails the bourgeois concept of social equal-
ity as a real abstraction. That is, equality of every member of society before
money and before the rule of law is entirely formal in character. It recog-
nizes individuals as abstract citizens, each endowed with standardized
rights, regardless of the inequality in property. Furthermore, their formal
equality as abstract citizens endowed with equal rights to trade at liberty
from direct coercion, bound only by the rule of law, is governed by the
money fetish. That is, the ‘power which each individual exercises over the
activity of others or over social wealth exists in him as the owner of
exchange value, of money. The individual carries his social power, as well
as his bond with society, in his pocket’ (Marx 1973: 156–157). Marx
writes of the money fetish that ‘a social relation, a definite relation between
individuals … appears as a metal, a stone, as a purely physical external
thing which can be found, as such, in nature, and which is indistinguish-
able in form from its natural existence’ (1973: 239). Economic objectivity
is a socially constituted objectivity—the social relations vanish in their
appearance as a metal or a stone, and this appearance is real as power over,
and in and through, them. What appears, in the appearance of society as
an economic object, is a definite social relationship between individuals
subsisting as relationship between economic things. The movement of
economic things governs the class-divided individuals as formally equal
citizens who, in and through their struggle for social reproduction, endow
160 W. BONEFELD
pieces of metal with a consciousness and a will. This will asserts itself in the
form of a seemingly natural force and regulation by invisible principles.
Society appears as some transcendental thing that governs the social indi-
viduals by means of an ‘invisible hand’, which takes ‘care of both the beg-
gar and the king’ (Adorno 1990: 251).
Marx grasps rule by economic abstractions with the category of capital.
Capital is fundamentally just a name of a definite form of social relations.12
Capital is society as economic thing, and this thing is fundamentally the
value thing. Value is invisible, like a ghost (Bellofiore 2009). The ghost of
value appears in the form of money as more money. To the point of
‘momentary barbarism’ (Marx and Engels 1997: 18) the class tied to work
hangs by the profitable exploitation of her labor power. She maintains her
employability, and therewith wage-based access to subsistence, only as an
effective producer of surplus value. The buyer of labor power and the pro-
ducers of surplus value contract on the labor market as formally equal citi-
zens. The buyer contracts labor power as resource of profit. The worker
sells to make a living. Labor-time that does not produce profit counts for
nothing. It is either expended for profit or redundant. For the sake of
profit, there is no time to lose. Unprofitable employers go bankrupt, lead-
ing to loss of employment. The notion that capitalist society is ruled by
abstractions says therefore more than it first appeared. Life-time is labor-
time. The struggle for life-time is constant, and so is the struggle to sus-
tain access to the means of life by making a profit for the buyer of labor
power. Economic objectivity hides what is important. Hidden within the
appearance of society as a movement of economic quantities, vanished
from view, is the sheer unrest of life to make ends meet—for the laborer,
working for the profit of another class of Man is the necessary condition
of making a living. That is, the laborer makes a living on the condition that
the consumption of her labor power produces a surplus value for its buyer.
What can the seller of redundant labor power trade in its stead—body and
body substances: how many for pornography, how many for prostitution,
how many for drug mules, how many for kidney sales?
The macro-economic calculation of the unemployed as economic zeros
is not untrue. It makes clear that the life of the sellers of labor power really
depend for their life on the profitability extraction of surplus value from
their labor. Laboring for the sake of a surplus in value is innate to the con-
cept of the worker. She belongs to a system of wealth in which her labor
has utility only as a means of profit. Sensuous activity not only vanishes in
the supersensible world of economic things, of cash, price and profit. It
9 ON CAPITAL AS REAL ABSTRACTION 161
also appears in it—as working class struggle to sustain access to the means
of subsistence and as conflict on competitive labor markets to avoid the
risk of redundancy. It also appears as competition between the employers
of labor power to avoid bankruptcy as each tries in competition with all
others to validate their private appropriation of social labor in the form of
value, that is, money as general equivalent of the socially necessary expen-
diture of labor-time. The economic argument that profit is a means of
avoiding bankruptcy is not untrue. It articulates the truth of society as
economic abstraction. Each individual capitalist has constantly to expand
‘his capital, so as to preserve it, but he can only extend by means of pro-
gressive accumulation’ (Marx 1990: 739). Thus, each individual capitalist
is spurred into action to maintain his connection to abstract wealth by
means of greater surplus value extraction, on the pain of avoiding com-
petitive erosion and liquidation of existing values. Each individual capital-
ist is therefore compelled to compress necessary labor-time of social
reproduction so as to increase the surplus labor-time of surplus value pro-
duction, expanding wealth in the form of profit by multiplying the pro-
ductive power of labor.
The fact that the rule of economic abstractions benefits the owners of
great wealth does not entail that they are in control. The personalized
critique of capitalism does not touch capitalism by thought. Rather, it
both rejects the capitalist as corrupting capitalist development for its own
self-interest and identifies capital as an economic instrument that can be
employed for the benefit of the property-less producers of surplus value.
In this manner, the critique of the capitalist transforms into an argument
for the further development of capitalism, ostensibly for the benefit of the
class that works. For the sake of making capitalism work for the workers,
it argues for the full-employment of social labor and envisages the trans-
formation of society into a centrally planned factory.13
Conclusion
Neither the capitalist nor the banker, nor, indeed, the worker can extricate
themselves from the reality in which they live and which asserts itself not
only over them but also through them, and by means of them. Society as
economic subject prevails through the individuals. Money does not only
make the world go round, its possession establishes the connection to the
means of life. The struggle for access to the means of life is a struggle for
money—it governs the mentality of bourgeois society. What a misery! In
9 ON CAPITAL AS REAL ABSTRACTION 165
the face of great social wealth, the producers of surplus value sustain them-
selves from one day to the next as the readily available human material for
capitalist wealth. Indeed, making ends meet is the real life-activity of living
labor. Nothing is what it seems. The struggle for money (as more money)
governs the mentality of bourgeois society as, seemingly, a thing in-itself.
The ‘movement of society’ is not only ‘antagonistic from the outset’
(Adorno 1990: 304). It also ‘maintains itself only through antagonism’
(311). That is, class struggle is the objective necessity of the false society.
It belongs to its concept. Hidden within ∆K rages the struggle to make
ends meet and achieve social reproduction.16 The working class does not
struggle for socialism. It struggles to satisfy its needs. The struggle of the
dispossessed sellers of labor power is ‘dictated by hunger’ (Adorno
2005: 102).
In distinction to traditional Marxist conceptions, to be a productive
laborer is not an ontologically privileged position. Rather, ‘it is a great
misfortune’ (Marx 1990: 644). In Capital, Marx develops the capitalist
class relations from the sale of the commodity labor power. However, the
trade in labor power presupposes the divorce of dependent labor from the
means of subsistence, creating the property-less laborer as the indepen-
dent seller of labor power. Coercion as the foundation of the sale of labor
and economic compulsion is the condition of the free and equal trade in
labor power (see Bonefeld 2011). On the one hand, the labor market is
the institution of the buying and selling of labor power on the basis of
contract between formally equal traders—the one buying for the sake of
making a profit, the other selling for the sake of making a living. On the
other it comprises labor market competition between individualized sellers
of labor power, each seeking to maintain themselves in gendered and
racialized, and also nationalized labor markets where the term cutthroat
competition is experienced in various forms, from arson attack to class
solidarity, and from destitution to collective bargaining, from gangland
thuggery to communal forms of organizing subsistence-support, from
strike-breaking to collective action.
Innate to the existence of a class of dispossessed sellers of labor power
is the struggle, collectively or against each other, or both, for access to the
means of subsistence. The struggle of the working class is one for wages
and conditions; it is a struggle for access to the means of life and for life.
It is a struggle against the buyer’s ‘were-wolf’s hunger for surplus labour’
and appropriation of additional atoms of unpaid labor-time, and thus
166 W. BONEFELD
against the reduction of their life to a mere time’s carcase. They struggle
against a life constituting solely of labor-time and thus against a reduction
of human life to a mere economic resource, and they struggle for employ-
ment to establish access to the means of life. They thus struggle for human
significance and, above all, for food, shelter, clothing, warmth, love, affec-
tion, knowledge, time for enjoyment and dignity. Their struggle as a class
‘in-itself’ really is a struggle ‘for-itself’: for life, human distinction, life-
time and, above all, satisfaction of basic human needs. The working class
struggles for making ends meet, for subsistence and comfort. It does all of
this in conditions, in which the increase in material wealth that it has pro-
duced pushes beyond the limits of its capitalist form. And then, repeating
an earlier quotation, society ‘suddenly finds itself put back into a state of
momentary barbarism; it appears as if famine, a universal war of devasta-
tion had cut off the supply of every means of subsistence’ (Marx and
Engels 1997: 18).
The dictum that ‘capital is class struggle’ (Holloway 1991: 170) does
not express something positive or desirable. Rather, it amounts to a judg-
ment on the capitalistically organized social relations of production, in
which ‘the needs of human beings, the satisfaction of human beings, is
never more than a sideshow’ (Adorno 2008: 51). The class struggle is the
dynamic force of the society as the thing of real economic abstraction, of
wealth as a value abstraction.
In conclusion, the critique of class society does not find its positive
resolution in the achievement of fair and just exchange relations between
the buyers of labor power and the producers of surplus value. Redistribution
of wealth in favor of property-less workers ‘who chew word to fill their
bellies’ (Adorno 2005: 102) is absolutely necessary to sustain them in
greater comfort. For this reason, redistribution is also the convenient fic-
tion of a socialist critique, which envisages capitalist transformation in the
form of a labor economy that is comfortable for the wage slaves. The cri-
tique of class society finds its positive resolution only in the classless soci-
ety, in which the social individuals no longer objectify themselves in the
form of a movement of real economic abstractions that are fed by a depen-
dent class of surplus value producers. Rather, this society objectifies itself
as a society of communist individuals.
9 ON CAPITAL AS REAL ABSTRACTION 167
Notes
1. On the points raised here, see Gunn (1992), Murray (2016), Postone
(1993) and Bonefeld (2014). On social nature, see Schmidt (1971).
2. Economics deals with economic quantities without being able to tell us
what they are. For the sake of establishing itself as a science of economy
matters, it seeks to make economic things intelligible. For this reason, it
rejects the inclusion of the human social relations into economic argument
as a metaphysical distraction. Economics is, however, quite unable to estab-
lish itself as social science in distinction to society. As Joan Robinson put it
in exasperation about the seeming inability of economics to establish itself
as a science of economic matter: ‘K is capital, ∆K is investment. Then what
is K? Why, capital of course. It must mean something, so let us get on with
the analysis, and do not bother about these officious prigs who ask us to say
what it means’ (1962: 68). On the difficulty of economics to establish itself
as a discipline without subject matter, see Bonefeld (2014 chap. 2).
3. On ghost-walking, see Marx (1966, chap. 48).
4. On abstract labor, see Bonefeld (2010).
5. On Sohn-Rethel conception of real abstraction, see Engster and Schlaudt
(2018).
6. The German original says Historischer Materialismus ist Anamnesis der
Genese.
7. Traditional social theory divides society into system-logic and social action
and considers this divide as a dialectic of structure and struggle or structure
and agency, which is the premise of hegemonic social theory (see Bonefeld
1993, 2016b). Economics conceives of it as a relationship between spon-
taneous market structure and rational individual behavior.
8. In distinction, Habermas’ social theory accords to acting subjects the
power to prevent the total colonization of their life-world by the forces of
the system, keeping a space for non-instrumental properties, such as empa-
thy and human warmth. On Habermas as a traditional thinker of system-
logic and social action, see Reichelt (2000) and Henning (2018).
9. Emphasis added, and translation altered, based on the German original.
10. See Postone (1993) for a critique of Marxian economics as a series of pro-
grammatic statements about the rational planning of essentially capitalist
labor relations. Contemporary notions of anti-austerity as a politics of eco-
nomic planning present the same misconceived idea. See, for example,
Panitch et al. (2011) and Varoufakis (2013). For critique, see Bonefeld
(2012) and Grollios (2016).
11. As the tradition of dialectical materialism argues wrongly. On this point,
see also footnote 1.
12. On this, see Bonefeld (2014).
168 W. BONEFELD
13. Leninism is not an alternative to capitalism, nor are its reformist competi-
tors or radical off-springs.
14. On this, see Bonefeld (2010).
15. M…P…M’ (or M…M’, for short) is the classical expressions for the trans-
formation of Money into the Production of essentially surplus value that is
realized in exchange in the form of greater amount of Money that expresses
the extracted surplus value in the form of profit. See Bonefeld (1996) for a
fuller account.
16. On ∆K, see footnote 2.
References
Adorno, Th. (1976). Sociology and Empirical Research. In T. Adorno, H. Albert,
R. Dahrendorf, J. Habermas, J. Pilot, & K. Popper (Eds.), The Positivist Dispute
in German Sociology (pp. 68–86, G. Adey & D. Frisby, Trans.). London:
Heinemann.
Adorno, T. (1990). Negative Dialectics. London: Verso.
Adorno, T. (1997a). Seminar Mitschrift of 1962. Appendix. In H.-G. Backhaus
(Ed.), Dialektik der Wertform (pp. 501–512). Freiburg: Ḉa ira.
Adorno, T. (1997b). Seminar Mitschrift of (2000). In Introduction to Sociology.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Adorno, T. (2003). Graeculus. Notizen zu Philosophie und Gesellschaft. In
R. Tiedemann (Ed.), Frankfurter Adorno Blaetter (Vol. VIII, pp. 9–41).
Frankfurt: Edition Text und Kritik.
Adorno, T. (2005). Minima Moralia. London: Verso.
Adorno, T. (2008). Lectures on History and Freedom. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Arthur, C. (2004). The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Backhaus, H. G. (1992). Between Philosophy and Science: Marxian Social
Economy as Critical Theory. In W. Bonefeld, R. Gunn, & K. Psychopedis
(Eds.), Open Marxism (Vol. I, pp. 93–132). London: Pluto.
Backhaus, H. G. (1997). Dialektik der Wertform. Freiburg: Ḉa ira.
Backhaus, H. G. (2005). Some Aspects of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the
Context of His Economic-Philosophical Theory. In W. Bonefeld &
K. Psychopedis (Eds.), Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of
Capitalism (pp. 13–29). London: Routledge.
Bellofiore, R. (2009). A Ghost Turning into a Vampire. In R. Bellofiore &
R. Fenischi (Eds.), Re-reading Marx (pp. 178–194). London: Palgrave.
Bonefeld, W. (1993). Crisis of Theory. Capital & Class, 17(2), 25–47.
Bonefeld, W. (1996). Money, Equality and Exploitation. In W. Bonefeld &
J. Holloway (Eds.), Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money
(pp. 178–209). London: Palgrave.
9 ON CAPITAL AS REAL ABSTRACTION 169
Bonefeld, W. (2010). Abstract Labour: Against Its Nature and on Its Time.
Capital & Class, 34(2), 257–276.
Bonefeld, W. (2011). Primitive Accumulation and Capitalist Accumulation. Science
& Society, 75(3), 379–399.
Bonefeld, W. (2012). From Humanity to Nationality to Bestiality. Ephemera,
12(4), 445–553.
Bonefeld, W. (2014). Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy.
London: Bloomsbury.
Bonefeld, W. (2016a). Negative Dialectics and the Critique of Economic
Objectivity. History of the Human Sciences, 29(2), 60–76.
Bonefeld, W. (2016b). Bringing Critical Theory Back in at a Time of Misery.
Capital & Class, 40(2), 233–244.
Engster, F., & Schlaudt, O. (2018). Alfred Sohn-Rethel: Real Abstraction and the
Unity of Commodity-Form and Thought Form. In B. Best, W. Bonefeld, &
C. O’Kane (Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Frankfurt School Critical Theory
(Vol. I, pp. 284–301). London: Sage.
Grollios, V. (2016). Syriza’s Delusions and the Nihilism of Bourgeois Culture.
Constellations, 23(3), 404–412.
Gunn, R. (1992). Against Historical Materialism. In W. Bonefeld, R. Gunn, &
K. Psychopedis (Eds.), Open Marxism (Vol. II, pp. 1–45). London: Pluto.
Henning, C. (2018). Jürgen Habermas: Against Obstacles to Public Debates. In
B. Best, W. Bonefeld, & C. O’Kane (Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Frankfurt
School Critical Theory (Vol. I). London: Sage, forthcoming.
Holloway, J. (1991). Capital Is Class Struggle. In W. Bonefeld & J. Holloway
(Eds.), Post-Fordism and Social Form (pp. 170–175). London: Palgrave.
Lotz, C. (2014). The Capitalist Schema. Lanham: Lexington Books.
Marx, K. (1966). Capital (Vol. III). Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1971). A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. London:
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse. London: Penguin.
Marx, K. (1975). The Poverty of Philosophy. In Marx/Engels Collected Works
(MECW) (Vol. 6). London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K. (1976). Theories of Surplus Value (Vol. III). London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K. (1990). Capital (Vol. I). London: Penguin.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1997). The Communist Manifesto. London: Pluto.
Murray, P. (2016). The Mismeasure of Wealth: Essays on Marx and Social Form.
Leiden: Brill.
Panitch, L., Albo, G., & Chibber, V. (2011). Preface, Socialist Register 2012 (pp.
IX–XII). London: Merlin Press.
Postone, M. (1993). Time, Labour and Social Domination. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
170 W. BONEFELD
Jacques Bidet
The author thanks Gao Jingyu for her careful linguistic revision of the text.
J. Bidet (*)
Paris X University, Nanterre, France
abstraction’ results not from commodity exchange, but from capitalist pro-
duction, which they think is to be based on abstract labor. Yet, this abstrac-
tion itself is supposed to be produced by the market relations inherent to
the capitalist mode of production. In my opinion, this thesis confuses the
notions of abstraction, abstract labor and real abstraction. This confusion
muddles up the set of the structural, historical and political analyses it
inspires. Its most extreme formulation can be found in Postone’s (1993)
work. It is also prevalent in what I call the ‘esoteric school’—in reference
to an esoterism attributed to Marx by Hans Georg Backhaus (1978) and
assumed as such by these authors1—which tends to read Capital on the
base of its drafts and preliminary versions and, therefore, on formulations
that Marx eventually discarded when they proved unsuited to his project.
Its main focus is the current known as Neue Wertkritik2 that certainly
shares affinities with other currents, particularly those emerging from situ-
ationism, in the cultural and environmental critique of capitalism. In my
view, however, its core political content does not really exceed this mixture
of protest and resignation defined by Marx as that of religion. I argue
against these authors not on their conclusions, but their presuppositions,
which are also present in various contemporary philosophical commentar-
ies of Capital and approaches of Marxism. That is why I formulate my
critique only by putting forward my own approach of this problem.
Market labor (L2). Marx does not begin his exposition at L1, but
directly at L2. And what makes it somehow difficult to read is that he deals
with L1 within his exposition of L2. L2 actually implies level L1. In par-
ticular, it implies the pair constituted by concrete labor/abstract labor. But
Marx relates it to another pair, that of use value/exchange value or (equiv-
alently in this regard) use value/value. The problem he is facing here in
the initial moment of his exposition is that of the passage not from L1 to
L2, but within L2 from the concept of ‘exchange value’, which corre-
sponds to the common evidence of market relation, to the concept of
‘value’ that will take its place in his theory as that of ‘production relation’
(Produktionverhältnis), a recurring term at L2. In other words, Marx is
building the concept of value. To account for it, we need a term that is not
part of his terminology but belongs, nonetheless, to his conceptual regis-
ter: ‘market labor’. Indeed, labor as analyzed at the beginning of chapter
1 is labor under the conditions of market production: those of competi-
tion among independent productions. This context determines both a
‘value’ by the socially-necessary labor time and a ‘market price’ (term
which belongs to this same rational conceptual configuration of L2) by
the conditions of supply and demand. The ‘socially-necessary time’ relates
simultaneously to the concrete labor (the technique used) and the abstract
labor (the intensity of the expenditure) in a market context. In short, the
pair (L1) of concrete labor/abstract labor is analyzed here in the context
of market production, that is to say, of the relation between use value/value
which belongs to L2. And Marx builds the concept of ‘value’ in the spe-
cific sense in which it will function in his theory. Meaningfully, the exam-
ples he chooses, not for pedagogic simplification, but for their conceptual
scope (the carpenter, the mason) belong to the L2 of abstraction in which,
as he states in a small but extremely significant note, he still leaves aside the
question of whether or not this labor is included in a waged capitalist rela-
tion (MEW 23 1962: 59 note 15).
Capitalist labor: waged labor in the capitalist mode of production (L3).
Such a labor is, first, ‘labor in general’; therefore, it cannot be said more
or less abstract than any other kind of labor. It is also ‘market labor’, sub-
ject to the conditions of productivity and intensity of market relations
which provide abstract labor with its specific characteristics (see the com-
plex relations between intensity, productivity and value). It is, finally, spe-
cifically capitalist labor because, in its concrete and in its abstract aspects,
it displays characteristics which are not simply those of market production
as such. Thus, again, I propose a term which does not belong to Marx’s
10 THE LOST ROADS AND THE STEEP PATHS OF ‘REAL ABSTRACTION’ 175
Let us first consider value. It means we go back to L2. The true object
of the first chapter of Capital is not ‘the commodity’ as a particular item,
an element of a set, but the social relation that defines it: the market rela-
tions of production-circulation. You simply cannot understand the ques-
tion if you suppose that the object of the beginning of Marx’s exposition
is ‘circulation’ or market exchange as the esoteric current does6 for value is
properly defined by the socially-necessary time under market relations of
production. This is the starting point for understanding how it is ‘trans-
formed’ immediately into ‘market price’ and, subsequently, into price of
production’. What is described here is the set of the rational conditions
required for market production (whose counterpart is market circulation).
Market practice, that is, production for exchange, implies an abstraction:
the partners leave aside the use value of the commodity. Money, which
ensures universal exchange by making it possible to ‘abstract’ the concrete
nature of the exchanged object, is the keystone of this rational edifice. In
reality, this abstraction is never absolute: the concrete aspect of the use
value appears in different ways. In the process of market circulation, it is
somehow ‘on hold’, waiting for its moment, that of consumption. In the
process of market production, on the contrary, the abstract is immediately
connected to the concrete. The market, as a relation of production,
Produktionsverhältnis, is a kind of defined articulation, historically specific,
between concrete labor and abstract labor, which makes it possible for dif-
ferent productions to be linked with coherence. It is one form of coordi-
nation among others: from the beginning, Marx mentions by contrast
other possibilities—from (slightly imaginary, no doubt) the Indian com-
munity to the large rural patriarchal family and the systematic (and quite
real) division of labor in factories (MEW 23 1962: 56–57; 92.). Here, that
enables us to apprehend adequately the social rationality of value, that of
the market, as a real abstraction. To grasp the concrete aspect, it includes,
one must start not from circulation, but from the logic of (market) pro-
duction. This is what the esoteric school does not seem to understand.
As for surplus value, it belongs to the logic of capitalist production as
such: that of market production when labor force itself functions as a com-
modity. Thus, we must distinguish between the abstraction of value and
the abstraction of surplus value. In the process of capitalist exploitation, a
worker produces an object (good or service) of a higher value than the
goods that he receives as salary—this is, at least, a minimal formulation of
the question. It is important here to observe that Marx makes a minimal
use of the expression ‘producing value’. He essentially uses it in the
10 THE LOST ROADS AND THE STEEP PATHS OF ‘REAL ABSTRACTION’ 177
and it is forgotten that, behind those things that are granted a value, what
is ultimately exchanged is human labor: it is forgotten that the market is a
relation of production. All this is well known and easily understood. What
remains more problematic is the following of the (conceptual) story. In
chapter 2, Marx actually proceeds from commodity fetishism to market
fetishism, that is, from a phenomenology to an ontology. This chapter begins
with a sentence seemingly trivial, but actually rather enigmatic: ‘It is plain
that commodities cannot go to market and make exchanges of their own
account’. Still, there must exist a market. In other words, the market is not
a fact naturally given in a society, a natural order which commodities
themselves would belong to. According to Marx, for the market to exist in
this way in this seemingly natural form, a social act is actually needed: an
inaugural act (‘In the beginning was the deed’ Im Anfang war die Tat), a
‘social act’ (die Gesellschaftliche Tat), a ‘social action’ (die Gesellschaftliche
Aktion) or even a decisive ‘normal social act’ (English version). This act is
a both ‘social and general’ (allgemein gesellschaftlich) and, at the same
time, an ‘individual’ act (individuell), and therefore it is incessantly
repeated by social actors. It consists of positioning ourselves under the law
of the market, of freely deciding that the market should reign as our mas-
ter. This is what Marx expresses in an apocalyptic formula which is also a
remake of Hobbes. ‘These have one mind and shall give their power and
strength onto the beast’. The ‘beast’ to which they thus make themselves
subject is not capital, but money, as an arbiter of the market. When they
convert the market into a law, they subject themselves to the law of the
market. This is a contradiction in terms, analogous to the contract of ser-
vitude mentioned by Rousseau, which is a real social contradiction. This
original act of the market introduced in chapter 2 is the presupposition of
capitalism: a presupposition that capitalism poses as a universal law because
it tends to convert labor force itself and every available use value into com-
modities. In this sense, fetishism is actually the fact of capitalism, making
an absolute of a market logic. It must be observed here that Marx con-
ceives the matter in terms of a social ontology in which the being is an act.
To be is to act. This is a metastructural act of L2, but only possible and
posed as such in the structural conditions of L3, that of capitalism, when
the market really becomes the universal order.
This is what can be said about capitalism when it has not yet been intro-
duced as such, that is, as a class structure founded in exploitation, but only
from the viewpoint of the market logic that governs it (that of its meta-
structure), that is, when nothing is known about it, except that it is
10 THE LOST ROADS AND THE STEEP PATHS OF ‘REAL ABSTRACTION’ 179
working day and the struggle for its limitation through national legisla-
tions. For Marx, writing Capital was the first stage of a larger investigation
into the world as a whole. Such a comprehensive project that exceeded his
strength was later resumed in the theories of the World-system which
emphasize its immanent ‘coloniality’. Now, in the nation-state form of
modern society that Marx takes as a reference, the organization is as ‘meta-
structuring’ and ‘structuring’ as the market. If this is the case, for the
exposition to be in accordance with its object, it should be stated in the
first section: within the metastructural ‘prologue’ L2 of the structural
exposition L3. In fact, why would not these modern producers, consid-
ered at the market L2 where they are supposed to relate to each other as
free, equal and rational humans (according to the modern ‘popular preju-
dice’, Volksvorurteil, of an equality that, as Marx highlights, was unimagi-
nable for Aristotle in the times of slavery) (MEW 23 1962: 74), be able to
decide to limit the reign of the market by commonly decided regulations?
Therefore, what is missing in the ‘logical’ development of the exposition
is a correct start based on the initial coexistence of market and organiza-
tion in the metastructure itself and consequently in the structure of this
form of society. That is the point we have now to consider. As we will see,
such is the ontological context of the real abstractions, of the contradic-
tions and struggles they arouse.
the rest of the population (whose vital interests does not interest capital).
In addition to an economic contradiction (any reduction of salary result-
ing in an increase in surplus value), there is a vital contradiction that leads
to the maximum possible consumption of the labor force and to the deg-
radation of all economic, social, cultural and political conditions of human
life. On the other hand, this contradiction has a positive side as a produc-
tive contradiction. Capitalists, who are only interested in abstract wealth,
that of surplus value, can only accumulate it through producing some
concrete commodity that must have a use value, at least for some people,
even if for a nefarious social use, such as in the production of weapons of
mass destruction. Anyway, as such, the requirement of a use value paves
the way for a political contradiction. Actually, for producing commodities,
coercion is not enough: a certain consent of the producer-consumer is
required. More precisely, people, as collective producer-consumer, have
some social power and show historically the ability, particularly in the con-
text of nation-states, to determine the nature of material and cultural
objects to be produced, such as schools, hospitals, housing, public trans-
port and so on. One cannot, indeed, derive all these concreteness of use
values from ‘capital’ as such, that is, from projects or mechanisms that
would belong to it. When capital has an opportunity in colonies, it imposes
slavery, keeping native or imported workers in the state of foreigners. On
the contrary, in the context of nation-states, the people from below make
the ‘real abstraction’ recede as they unite in class struggles. Class struggles
produce ‘real concreteness’ in opposition to real abstraction. The speculative
focus of the esoteric theorists on the thematic of ‘real abstraction’ corre-
sponds to a pathetic rhetoric by which the philosopher, abandoning the
hope of being recognized as a king, disguises himself as a prophet. Such a
posture means nothing else but the reversal of historicism into resignation.
Thus, for Moishe Postone, the mobilizations of unions, feminism and
other movements are nothing more than ‘expressions of the system’. The
same condescendence can be found in Anselm Jappe.11 Yet we should not
ignore, among other things, the fact that the only social forces, which have
proved historically committed against productivism, are those of the
worker’s movements that fought incessantly for the 8-hour workday, the
40-hour week, the 35-hour week, now 32, retirement at the age of
60 years and so on. With the motto, ‘We work too much! Enough! Life is
not for producing, but for living!’. Limiting production is saving the planet.
To better understand this class confrontation, we have to go back to the
theoretical abstraction of L2, that of mediations and the ‘immediacy’ they
184 J. BIDET
rganization, the bottom class, which I call the ‘fundamental class’ or the
o
‘popular class’, is composed of those who do not have any property or
competency privilege. This does not mean that they do not have knowl-
edge (their knowledge can be as ample as or more than the knowledge of
those called ‘competent’, but they are not included in a competent author-
ity) or power. They have a collective social potency, a potential to hold on
a power that simply aims to accumulate and govern, regardless of the inter-
ests of concrete life. We saw above how this pair of ‘productive’/‘political’
contradictions open the way for the rise of the fundamental class. We must
now show that, in this regard, the fundamental class has a different relation
to these two dominations.12
Notes
1. See Anselm Jappe: ‘It is necessary to assume the difference between the
‘exoteric’ and the ‘esoteric’ Marx, between the conceptual core and the
historical development, between the essence and the phenomenon’ (Jappe
2017a: Kindle position 5589). Here, I also refer to his main book (Jappe
2017b).
2. This current has affinities with the New Dialectic, whose interpretation
about Hegel’s Logic is still better connected with the main Marxist tradi-
tions. See the critique I formulated some time ago in Bidet (2005) of
Christopher Arthur (2004).
3. In a decisive text at the end of Chapter 5, Marx mentions, respectively, the
‘production process’ (L1), the ‘commodity production process’ (L2) and
the ‘capitalist production process’ (L3): ‘Als Einheit von Arbeitsprozess
und Wertbildung ist der Produktionsprozess von Waren, als Einheit von
Arbeitsprozess und Verwertungsprozess ist er kapitalistischer
Produktionsprozess, kapitalistische Form von Warenptoduktion’ (MEW
23 1962: 211).
4. He only addresses this point marginally; for instance, in the paragraph
entitled Arbeitsprozess (MEW 23 1962: 192–199). See also the passage
about Robinson, taken as the producer in general.
188 J. BIDET
References
Arthur, C. (2004). The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Backhaus, H.-G. (1978). Materialien zur Rekonstruktion der Marxschen
Werttheorie. In Gesellschaft. Beiträge zur Marxschen Theorie (Vol. 11,
pp. 16–177). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Bidet, J. (1985). Que faire du Capital? Materiaux pour une refundation. Paris:
Klincksieck.
Bidet, J. (2004). Explication et reconstruction du Capital. Paris: Collection Actuel
Marx Confrontation, PUF.
190 J. BIDET
Maurício Vieira Martins
What holds up the bird is the branch and not the laws of elasticity. If we
reduce the branch to the laws of elasticity, we must no longer speak of a
bird but of colloidal solutions. At such a level of analytical abstraction, it is
no longer a question of environment for a living being, nor of health nor
of disease. Similarly, what the fox eats is the hen’s egg and not the chem-
istry of albuminoids or the laws of embryology (Canguilhem 1978: 159).
In his controversy with the biologists who divested the phenomenon of
life of its sensuous characteristics, philosopher Georges Canguilhem saw
himself forced to evoke, in quite visual terms, how important a phenom-
enology of the real world is. Our take is, at least at first, in agreement with
Canguilhem: What the fox eats is in fact a hen’s egg, and not the chemis-
try of albuminoids, and what holds the birds up is, glaringly, the tree
branch. And yet the question remains: Is there in the history of thought a
supplementary way to approach this thematic field, a way that preserves
the integrity of the sensuous world but also manages to demonstrate the
strength of the underlying relations that organize it?
We believe there is. Marx’s career illustrates particularly clearly the path
of a thinker who, in his first works, aimed to deal exclusively with the
M. V. Martins (*)
Universidade Federal Fluminense, Niterói, Brazil
cal tradition. In the case here illustrated, the operation of abstraction done
by thought is the counterpart of a real process. Therefore, there is a modi-
fication in the antinomy opposing the so-called real object to the object of
knowledge (the former understood as an empirical thing only, the latter as
a thing of thought only). This is an intertwining of the so-called cognitive
process with the most basilar determinations of commercial production,
responsible for the emergence of the real abstraction.2
Once the real basis of this abstraction is acknowledged (it can be called
an ontological basis), there is a qualification of the greatest importance to
be made. It is the truth or falsehood tenor that a research manages to
attain. As regards scientific activity, and Marx not being a relativist, he
continuously wonders at the criterion that allows to determine the truth
value of a group of theoretical propositions. Getting to the point: There is
a true, productive scientific abstraction, as well as there is a wrong one,
that wanders away from what it sought to explain. While the former man-
ages to shed light on the causal mechanisms underlying the phenomenon
in focus, the latter is content with its most partial and peripheral aspects.
A very clear distinction is found in a passage of Theories of Surplus Value,
in which Marx disagrees with a recurrent critique to David Ricardo, as the
British economist was accused of being too abstract. In response, Marx
inverts the terms of the matter in one of his most antiempiricist statements:
* * *
* * *
that behind these singular historical figures, there are connections that
repeat periodically: their direct or indirect links to big international capi-
tal; the successive plans of fiscal conservatism; the most vulnerable social
groups as their preferred target; and so on. Needless to say, such structural
marks repeat throughout the world: even countries previously preserved
from the voracity of the capital find themselves involved in the diktat of
the capitalist mercantile logic, concrete commands that flesh out what
Marx called the value law, an abstraction in actu that generates devastating
effects in our lives.
On the other hand, it is necessary to realize that what is called the
Marxist school has sometimes had difficulty in maintaining the dialectic
unit of its founder. In the reception of his work, it is frequently verified that
there is a rift between the different but interconnected approaches mentioned
before. To be more explicit: what for Marx was a taut articulation between
the systematic plan of analysis (at the highest level of abstraction) and the
historical approach (that points to the unavoidable presence of the social
classes and their conflict) became an antinomy in some of his followers. So
we find on the one hand a Marx for the economists and philosophers, who
barely concerned with the lineament of the most general structures: when
this happens, the validity of the value law becomes a fantasy almost, alien-
ated from historicity and the growing social violence (a risk that, because
of what was presented above, must, of course, be avoided at all costs). On
the other hand, there are researchers more talented in historical research,
who reconstruct with precision the different temporal and spatial facets in
which the concrete processes develop, but sometimes giving less impor-
tance to those more abstracts recursions, entwined in the richness of the
historical experience.
Having acknowledged this, we should immediately add that, while at
the level of concepts it is necessary to be clear as to the causal power of the
value law, of course the concrete political struggle focuses on a very real
group. One doesn’t struggle against imperialism in the abstract, for
instance, but against its most direct representatives and, above all, against
the policies of expropriation that they put forward, knowing also that, if
eventually one of these representatives disappear, almost immediately
another arises in an equivalent place, due to the reasons mentioned. This
taut articulation between the core category determinations is what must
be faced in each concrete junction.
In a wider philosophical level, we would say that the topic of abstrac-
tion in actu in Marx leads to a much more complex understanding of real-
200 M. V. MARTINS
ity, which rejects its identification with the merely sensuous order. In his
own field of research during his maturity—political economy—Marx man-
aged to overcome the dichotomy that opposed real to metaphysical
objects, a dichotomy that goes back to Plato. The relevance of this proce-
dure is evident: it discerns progressively stratified levels of a real that it is
not exhausted in its appearance. This procedure allows the connection of
Marxism and other fields of knowledge, even the so-called natural sciences
(such as physics, chemistry, etc.), which have long freed themselves from
the prison of the empiricist vision of the world. Against the proud praise
of the fragment as an end in itself (praise to be found in some postmodern
authors is the clearest example), there is a progress toward a more complex
vision of the world in which we live in, to be found in the assumption of
the real abstraction and the abstraction in actu. In the level of political
action, some projects are left in check: those projects that imply it is pos-
sible to transform the capitalist society by altering its most immediate
effects, such as the concentration of income, for example, through pro-
grams of wealth distribution—praiseworthy in themselves, but with evi-
dent limitations. What truly begs transforming, through organized
political action, is the inherent logic of the value law and its deleterious
effects; otherwise, we will forever be dealing with consequences, without
reaching the underlying mechanisms that produce them.
Notes
1. Specialists argue whether it is possible to locate in Marx’s lengthy work
(which hasn’t been published in full) the term real abstraction. It seems it is
not the case. Having said that, throughout this chapter, we quote passages
from the author that show that this category is coherent with Marx’s
thought. To historically reconstruct the debate—A. Sohn-Rethel’s impor-
tance, the subsequent repercussion, and so on—the following papers can be
consulted: A. Toscano (2008) and H. Reichelt (2007). We chose to also
include in this chapter the category of abstraction in actu—with emphasis in
its dynamic aspect—to be found in the second volume of The Capital.
2. However, it is not affirmed that all abstractions made by human thinking are
analogous to the one here examined. That would be an overgeneralization,
11 ON REAL OBJECTS THAT ARE NOT SENSUOUS: MARX AND ABSTRACTION… 201
References
Amorim, H. (2014). Dossiê – O trabalho imaterial em discussão, Caderno CRH,
Salvador, 70, V. 27, jan./abr. Retrieved from http://www.scielo.br/scielo.
php?script=sci_issuetoc&pid=0103-497920140001&lng=pt&nrm=iso.
Archer, M., Collier, A., Bashkar, R., et al. (1998). Critical Realism: Essential
Readings. London: Routledge.
Canguilhem, G. (1978). O normal e o patológico. Rio de Janeiro:
Forense-Universitária.
Kliman, A. (2000/2001). The Crisis, the Debt and the Law of Value. The
Hobgoblin, 3 (Winter). Retrieved from http://www.thehobgoblin.co.uk/jour-
nal/h32002_AK_Debt.htm.
Lukács, G. (2012). Para uma ontologia do ser social (Vol. I). São Paulo: Boitempo.
Maar, W. L. (2016). O novo objeto do mundo: Marx, Adorno e a forma valor.
Doispontos, 13(1), 29–40. Curitiba: São Carlos.
Martins, M. Vieira. (2017). Espinosa e Marx: pensadores da imanência. Verinotio –
Revista on-line de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. XII. Retrieved from http://
www.verinotio.org/conteudo/0.8939226622636641.pdf.
Marx, K. (1968). Theories of Surplus Value. Volume IV of Capital. Part II. Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1975). Capítulo inédito d’O capital: resultados do processo de produção
imediato. Porto: Publicações Escorpião. English: https://www.marxists.org/
archive/marx/works/1864/economic/ch01.htm.
Marx, K. (1983). O capital: crítica da economia política (Vol. 2). São Paulo:
Abril Cultural.
Marx, K. (1996). O capital: crítica da economia política (Vol. 1). São Paulo: Nova
Cultural. English: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/down-
load/pdf/Capital-Volume-I.pdf.
202 M. V. MARTINS
Alberto Bonnet
In this chapter we will try to precise the meaning that holds the concept
of form within the Marxian critique of political economy and, so far as real
abstraction is an attribute of the form, contribute in that way to the task
that summons us in this volume. Given the fact that every contemporary
reading of classical texts, like Marx’s critique of political economy, is medi-
ated by some subsequent reading, we will avoid the naive presumption of
recovering a supposedly original and authentic meaning in these texts.
Therefore, we confess beforehand that we read Marx’s critique of political
economy from the Critical Theory perspective and, more specifically, in
the way it was assimilated within the so called Open Marxism. The concept
of form is, from this perspective, a key concept to the critique of capitalist
social relations. But it is also a very complex concept. The efforts trying to
precise its meaning in these few pages will force us, in consequence, to
adopt an epigrammatic style.
A. Bonnet (*)
Buenos Aires National University (UBA), Buenos Aires, Argentina
Quilmes National University (UNQ), Bernal, Argentina
Social relations are, then, the matter of the forms. However, it suffices
taking in consideration this reference from Adorno to the adaptation of
the one who works on heterogeneous material to see that this statement is
insufficient. Actually, wealth adopts the commodity-form from social and
historical determinations in ‘those societies in which the capitalist mode of
production prevails’, as we said, but its matter does not subdue to social
relations, given that the products of labor are commodities ‘only because
they are something two-fold, both objects of utility, and, at the same time,
depositories of value’. The form use value is, certainly, a form of social
relations. It is a social form inasmuch as (a) the usefulness of commodities
can only be so to its consumers, and it is always socially and historically
determined (by the so-called norms of consumption, etc.). It is also social
inasmuch as (b) the way the process of (concrete) labor in-form the use
value of commodities always presuppose social and historical conditions
that are determined (a certain degree of development of social labor pro-
ductive forces, etc.). And, finally, it is a social form inasmuch as (c) in com-
modities that use value acts as a mere material support of its value (let us
recall the phenomena of obsolescence, planned by companies, of com-
modities usefulness).
However, it is still true that, that use value is a ‘natural form’. Nature
also, in summary, integrates the matter of its form. Even more, if we
assume that the matter of the form are social relations, we must acknowl-
edge that in every case nature integrates that matter inasmuch as it medi-
ates both poles of labor: as nature in the object of labor and as nature in
the very subject that performs the labor. It is true that both the external
nature and the internal nature exist only in that terrain as realities socially
mediated by labor (as forms) and by thought (as concepts). But this does
not imply that nature can be subdued to society just like that. As Schmidt
(2014: 70) points out, ‘in Marx nature is not merely a social category’.8
And this is not without consequences: the very dialectic of the form com-
modity is unconceivable if we do not keep in mind use value as its ‘natural
form’. The ultimate matters of forms, in summary, are social relations and
the socially mediated nature.
It is necessary to remark, before moving on, that we refer to these social
relations and to that socially mediated nature as ‘ultimate’ matter of forms
because the relationship between form and matter should be understood
in relative terms. Actually, the mentioned Marxian definition of exchange
value as a ‘necessary way of expression or form of manifestation of value’,
or the very definition of this value as ‘abstract human labour’ objectified
12 THE CONCEPT OF FORM IN THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY 209
of dialectic finally entitles the mind not only to primacy over manual work
but endows it with omnipotence. Marx, on the other hand, understands
the time governing the genesis and the mutation of forms as being, from
the very first, historical time—the time of natural and of human history’
(Sohn-Rethel 1978: 18–19).
However, through the introduction of the concept of process-form,
Holloway actually radicalizes Sohn-Rethel’s point.11 Indeed, it is not
enough to just claim the procedural character of capitalist forms in their
origin and historical transformations; it is also necessary to add that its
everyday reproduction possesses that procedural feature. The latter state-
ment is, actually, a corollary of the former, as it would ridicule the opposite
claim, that the foundation of the existence of form, of its origin and trans-
formations, is radically different to the foundation of its everyday repro-
duction. That foundation is the contradictory character of capitalist forms
as the way of existence of antagonistic social relations. And, in conse-
quence, forms are not given forms, constituted-forms, but process-forms,
forms in process of being constituted. They are not forms that have already
in-formed their matter, but permanent processes of in-formation of that
matter. The money and commodity-forms we have already mentioned are,
therefore, everyday processes of commodification and monetization of
social relations.12 This has enormous consequences that will be recovered
in what follows.
6. Now, in capitalist society, these relations between form and matter
adopt a specific characteristic that we have not yet mentioned: fetishism.
Indeed, fetishism is an attribute of capitalist forms. ‘Whence, then, arises
the enigmatical character of the product of labour, so soon as it assumes
the form of a commodity? Clearly, it arises from this form itself13’ (Marx
1982 I: 164). This is also of enormous significance in this context.
Forms, as we have already said, are ways of existence of a given mat-
ter. But this statement is still too general and does not precise the spe-
cific way in which social relations exist as matter of capitalist forms.
Indeed, social relations, as matter of capitalist forms, specifically exist ‘in
the mode of being denied’ (according to Gunn’s precise expression).
‘That is, one term [social relations] may exist in and through another
which contradicts it [commodity, in our case]. This, I take it, is the key
to Marx’s notion of commodity fetishism. When we learn that social
relations which appear as “material relations between persons and social
relations between things” appear, thus, as “what they are” […], we are
being informed of a circumstance that is unintelligible unless the
214 A. BONNET
point, the concept of form has helped us precise the objectives of this cri-
tique, but it does not tell us anything about the possibility of such critique.
It may even appear that the concept of form closed that possibility inas-
much as, on the one hand, we claim that forms in fact in-form social rela-
tions in a fetishist way and, on the other hand, we assume that such critique
can only be immanent to them.21 However, even when it is true that the
concept of form also helps us to understand the difficulties the anti-
capitalist critique faces, it does not close its possibility. Indeed, as we have
already pointed out, capitalist forms are ways of existence of antagonist
social relations and, therefore, are contradictory forms. Let us add now
that, in this contradiction of capitalist forms, we found its aperture.
Capitalist forms, inasmuch as they are contradictory, are not closed forms
but process-forms. And, also, the fetishism of these forms, as process-
forms, is not a closed one, but a process of fetishization. In the end, the
reproduction or not of capitalist forms, that is to say, of the irrational way
social relations exist under capitalism, depends of class struggle.
Notes
1. This does not mean, however, that Marx’s argument starts with the form
commodity. As Holloway correctly pointed out already (Holloway 2015),
his starting point is wealth (der Reichtum) in its diversity, wealth that
appears enclosed in the commodity-form, in those societies in which the
capitalist way of production prevails (see, to extend his argument, Holloway
2018). The importance of this nuance will be clear further.
2. Because of this Marxian use of the concept, Rubin tends to assimilate the
concepts of form and function (Rubin 1990: 31 and subsequent). Although
there actually is a relation between both concepts, which we cannot exam-
ine here, it is not convenient to reduce the analysis of form to one function.
3. If we accept that the Marxian exposition of the categories follows a logical
order instead of a historical one (as it should, since Rosdolsky 1977: 109
and subsequent), some moments of that exposition do not have to be
referred to forms in the sense of effective ways of existence of social rela-
tionships—although naturally, in such cases, Marx would be employing the
concept of form in a different way.
4. Surely Marx kept in mind Aristotelian thinking when employing the con-
cept of form in his critique of political economy. Already, young Marx
knew about the Aristotelian employment of the concept (as it is evident in
his reading notes of De Anima in 1839–1840) and, in particular, the
12 THE CONCEPT OF FORM IN THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY 221
11. Radicalization that results from the very ‘opening of Marxist categories’
proposed by open marxism. ‘This openness appears in, for instance, a dia-
lectic of subject and object, of form and content, of theory and practice, of
the constitution and reconstitution of categories in and through the devel-
opment, always crisis-ridden, of a social world’ (Bonefeld et al. 1992: 11).
12. The elementary forms of commodity and money are enough to develop
our argument because in the in-formation of human activity as abstract
labor and of the product of that activity as value objectified in the com-
modity and represented in money, we find the expression of the antagonis-
tic character of social relations in capitalism. But we cannot forget at this
point that the same considerations are valid for the capital form. The con-
tradictory character of capital as a way of existence of antagonistic social
relations, which is expressed in an aggravated way in its big crisis and its
corresponding process of reorganization—or, eventually, in its overcoming
as an irrational way of organizing society—is also characteristic in its every-
day reproduction.
13. Needless to say that this fetishism Marx attributes here to the elementary
commodity-form is, even more, still an attribute of the more complex
forms that social relations assume in capitalist society: it is money fetishism
(Marx 1982 I: 187), capital fetishism (1982 II: 303) and money-capital
fetishism (1982 III: 515).
14. Bonefeld (2001) notices that this expression from Marx (‘verrückte Form’,
translated in English as ‘absurd form’) actually has two meanings, both
relevant: ‘absurd form’ (verrückte) certainly refers to the irrationality of
money as a way of organizing social relationships; ‘displaced form’ (ver-
rückte), on the other hand, acknowledges the reification of social labor as
a whole in a specific commodity (translating ‘perverted form’, in that case,
would be even more appropriate).
15. The conversion of human labor into abstract labor is manifested in
exchange but, inasmuch capitalist production is commodity production,
such conversion is a process that actually starts in the sphere of produc-
tion—and it is consummated in the sphere of circulation. Labor as an activ-
ity and its product are already in-form as abstract labor and value in the
process of production.
16. This idea of a process of abstraction that operates in reality itself is distinc-
tively Marxian—although unthinkable without the development of
German idealism in general and Hegelian in particular. It does not find any
place, in consequence, in Althusser’s (1969) distinction between the con-
crete (‘real object’) and the abstract (‘object of thought’) that, malgré lui,
is barely a sophisticated version of the Diamat’s crude objectivism (see
Sohn-Rethel 1978: 20).
12 THE CONCEPT OF FORM IN THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY 223
17. To further precise the features of this idea of real abstraction, in contrast
with mental abstraction, it is convenient to go back at the way Marx distin-
guishes between labour in general and abstract labour in 1857 Einleitung—
given that the abstraction of the forms commodity and money has its roots
in the abstraction of labour as activity in capitalist society (Marx 1973: 103
and subsequent).
18. It is worth noting here that not all concepts may aspire to have such forms
as counterparts. Marx usually employs the term ‘categories’ (Kategorien)
to refer to the concepts of commodity, money, that is to say, precisely those
concepts that manifest the fundamental ways of existence of social relations
in capitalism. But this does not imply that Marx only employs these kinds
of concepts (see the distinction between the concepts of labor in general
and abstract labor indicated in the previous endnote).
19. Due to the limitations of space, we cannot stop here to consider bolder
interpretations of these relationships between subjective and objective
forms, such as the relationship established by Sohn-Rethel 1978) between
form and abstract thought or the analogy drawn by (Žižek 1989) between
form and unconscious.
20. It is known that Marx—although he thought of doing so—never got to
systematically derive the state-form within his critique of political econ-
omy. The so called State derivation debate, however, showed definitively
that Marxian critique of capitalist forms could be extended to the state-
form (Holloway and Picciotto 1978; Bonnet and Piva 2017 in Spanish).
21. To assume criticism as immanent is equivalent, in political terms, to assume
emancipation as self-emancipation, i. e., the first thesis of the International
Association of Workers: ‘The emancipation of the working class must be
the work of the working class itself’.
References
Adorno, T. (1973). Negative Dialectics. London; New York: Routledge.
Adorno, T. (1976). Introduction to Th. W. Adorno, et al: The Positivist Dispute in
German Sociology. London: Heinemann.
Adorno, T. (1983). Terminología filosófica I. Madrid: Taurus.
Adorno, T. (1989). Society. In S. E. Bronner & D. Mackey Kellner (Eds.), Critical
Theory and Society: a Reader. New York; London: Routledge.
Althusser, L. (1969). For Marx. London: Penguin Press.
Aristóteles. (1978). Acerca del alma. Madrid: Gredos.
Aristóteles. (1994). Metafísica. Madrid: Gredos.
Aristóteles. (1995). Física. Madrid: Gredos.
224 A. BONNET
Cristián Sucksdorf
Contradiction and Reality
The concrete task in these pages is to establish some interpretative guide-
lines for Marx’s understanding of the relationship between bodies and
representations, but limiting the analysis to its most evident manifestation:
the real existence of contradictions.
We still need to establish which can be the common thread to make
explicit how Marx analyzes, from the perspective of the praxis, the specific
relationship between contradictions and reality in capitalism. Firstly we
should be aware of something evident: a contradiction (counter-dictio) is
something of the order of discourse, that is, of the order of representation
or abstraction, but not of the bodies. There is no contradiction (nor nega-
tion) whatsoever between bodies.1 What is more: contradiction in the
strong sense (logic contradiction) shows the limit of language, the point
in which language cannot even point to something in the world. An
unbreachable barrier that therefore becomes the ultimate criterion of
falsehood: if it is possible to demonstrate that a discourse is contradictory,
C. Sucksdorf (*)
Buenos Aires National University (UBA), Buenos Aires, Argentina
Real Abstractions
Although Sohn-Rethel intended to broaden the general understanding of
Marx’s thought—as, in his view, ‘the unproclaimed theme of Capital and
of the commodity analysis is in fact the real abstraction’ (Sohn-Rethel
1980: 28)—his concept seeks mainly to account for the possibility condi-
tions of pure thought, separated from the world and experience.8 That is
to say, the conditions for the ‘thought-form’ (Denkform) which is the
basis for the Western world. His intent is to establish a genealogy of the
abstract quality of thought, and this genealogy will find its unproclaimed
origin in commodities. But how is it possible for commodities to account
for the raise of pure thought? The starting point of Sohn-Rethel is the
assumption of a ‘the secret identity of commodity form and thought form’
(idem: 9). Such identity (or, strictly speaking, isomorphism) of thought
and commodity is not a given, a mere fact; understanding it presupposes
tracking down its material genesis. In other words, its historical inscription
as a determination of practical life is precisely what will allow linking the
13 THE REAL CONTRADICTIONS (COMMODITIES AS COHERENCE… 231
Differences with Sohn-Rethel
At this point, we separate from the original determinations of Sohn-
Rethel’s concept because our concern is not the formation of pure con-
sciousness or abstract thinking, but the particular mode of construction
and functioning of real abstractions (or real contradictions) in Mark’s
work. We leave aside then any reference to Kant’s epistemology and the
formation of consciousness. But before redirecting the analysis of Marx’s
232 C. SUCKSDORF
objective forms of bourgeois society together with all the subjective forms
corresponding to them’ (Lukács 1969: 89).
The matter is that in capitalism, all social relations refer to commodi-
ties. This is why the via regia to understand capitalist societies is to analyze
commodities; however, it is for the same reason the specificity of com-
modities makes it impossible for it to be a universal category through
which to analyze any society at any historical time. A category that we
endeavor to use for the analysis of reality cannot be central to any histori-
cal time or any society. A concept that encompasses a universal reality is
incapable of having a hold in the world; it belongs to theology or meta-
physics in the most ethereal sense. For each historical moment, there can
only be a group of simple categories (which in turn must consist of ever-
more concrete forms, following the method indicated by Marx in his
famous 1857 Einleitung) to explain that reality and not ‘reality in gen-
eral’, which is nothing but the negation of reality, that is, ideality.
But what are those specific determinations of commodities in capital-
ism? Marx states it in the first sentence of The Capital (descendent from
that of contribution to the Critique): ‘The wealth of those societies in
which the capitalist mode of production prevails, presents itself as “an
immense arsenal of commodities”, its unit being a single commodity’
(Marx 1973: 3, our italics).11 What defines the capitalist commodity then
is that it is the way in which wealth presents itself and not just one of its
many manifestations. But there is more: the commodity is the unit of
wealth, so, in capitalism, wealth comes in the form of commodities. If we
take into account that for Marx wealth is considered in itself (i.e. ‘beyond
its limited bourgeois form’), it is ‘the universality of individual needs,
capacities, pleasures, productive forces etc., created through universal
exchange’ (Marx 2007: 447; MEW 42 1983: 396), we can infer then that
the commodity-form is, in capitalism, the form of social relationships.
Briefly put, all social relationships in capitalism are ruled by the trade
grammar, that is, its form. Consequently, commodities in capitalist societ-
ies are not ‘things’ or mere objects or surplus products, they are the objec-
tive form of subjective Bonds; in other words, the interrelations in which
individuals exist have become things, an ‘immense accumulation of com-
modities’. Because of these determinations, exclusive to capitalism, Lukács
asserts that the commodity is the ‘the model of all the objective forms of
bourgeois society, together with all the subjective forms corresponding to
them’ (Lukács 1969: 89).
234 C. SUCKSDORF
The commodity becomes then pure value: the currency form abstracted
from its dealing with the things. If we stick to the definition of commodity
as a bearer (Träger) of use value, there would not be an exchange of com-
modities, given that the trading circulation, C-M-C (‘selling for buying’),
as well as the circulation of money, M-C-M (‘buying for selling’), entails
the metamorphosis of commodities into money, and therefore imply that
the use value is something ultimately inseparable from value. If exchange
disregarded use value and limited itself to exchange values, there would be
the motionless and impossible form: Money-Money-Money. That is,
nonsense.14 Such abstraction of use value would mean, in turn, that in the
236 C. SUCKSDORF
active life. The social relations that make up wealth in its total form, that
is to say, the active life and its possibility conditions (accumulated and pos-
sible relations of individuals among themselves and with nature) present
themselves now projected or re-presented on things. In other words, the
meaning of commodities in capitalism makes the products of labor insepa-
rable from the fact that social relations are represented in them: commodi-
ties are that impossible unity of value and use value. These two
determinations of commodities—value and use value—can be expressed in
different contradictory pairs, depending on which aspect we stress: as
physical-metaphysical or sensuous-suprasensuous, as individual-universal
or private-social and so on, but its most important expression is the one
that points to its genesis in contradiction, that is, the fact that it is at the
same time a result of concrete labor (use value) and abstract labor (value).
The real and the idea coexist in the commodity as contradiction.
At this junction, we can better understand the consequences or the shift
that Sohn-Rethel proponed to give basis to the real abstraction. Firstly,
such passage is done through an unspoken operation: it equiparates the
determinations of commodities’ (exchange) value and use value, with the
actions of exchanging and using, and so this equiparation hides precisely
the difference between these moments. Which is that difference hidden by
the equiparation? The contradiction. Use and exchange are unrelated activ-
ities; they could not be linked at all. If they are related, it is accidentally,
externally, in their borders and limits. They can only exist together as
alternation: when exchanging takes place, using disappears from the real
scene and accrues to the possible, and vice versa. In the determinations of
commodities, on the contrary, the relation between use value and value
implies contradiction, but also identity. Each instance is negating the
other, while at the same time it is asserting it as a necessary correlation.
With use value only, it is not a commodity, but a mere object or good; on
the other hand, value as such always points back to its material dimension,
that is, to some use value. Without that material dimension, value is noth-
ing. For the products of labor to be commodities, then their existence
must be subjected to the double quality of being at the same time value
and use value. This is the meaning hidden in the oxymoron with which
Marx defines the commodity: ‘sensuously suprasensuous thing’ (sinnlich
übersinnliches Ding) or ‘physical-metaphysical’. In the passage from the
determinations of commodities to the actions of using and exchanging,
there is also a passage from a contradictory unit (the commodity) to an
alternative relation (exchanging and using) that is not underlined by any
238 C. SUCKSDORF
(a) The equiparation of any historical period and the subsequent obscur-
ing of the specific role of commodities in capitalist societies (and
only in them), that is, wealth presents itself as an ‘immense accu-
mulation of commodities’. Such equiparation obscures the fact
that commodities in capitalism are not mere surplus products, but
a representation in objects of the social relations.
(b) Explaining the commodity-abstraction only in terms of exchange and
denying the importance of production and the mode of labor at its
formation. This shift from production to exchange reduces the
contradiction between concrete labor and abstract labor to a pro-
jection of the abstraction of use value, and therefore what disap-
pears is the abstract quality of the real activity, what Marx called in
his early work alienated labor (entfremdete Arbeit). We can add,
then, that the real abstraction embodied in commodities happened
before in the lives and bodies of concrete individuals, that is, in
their active life and their vital activity.
(c) Changing the double form of commodities (value and use value) for
pure value, or, in other terms, hiding the trade contradiction in the
money form. Not only is the materiality of commodities lost when
ascribing the basis of real abstraction to the separation and abstrac-
tion of use value during exchange, the real quality of the contradic-
tion between value and use value is reconverted into the
juxtaposition of the reality of exchanging (‘the social action’) and
the ideality of using (‘the private minds’) hidden in the circula-
tion of money.
What we can notice now is that these three points in which Sohn-Rethel
grows apart from Marx’s thought are not casual. They are fundamental
aspects in which Marx himself addresses the contradictory quality of real-
ity under the hegemony of the commodity-form, that is, the trade gram-
13 THE REAL CONTRADICTIONS (COMMODITIES AS COHERENCE… 239
mar. We also find that these three points constitute a unit. Commodities
cannot only be understood as pure value, that is, as non-contradictory
forms (reduction on subsumption of commodities to money) unless they
are reduced to the moment of exchange, unless their contradictory form—
private and social at once—of labor that produced them is hidden.
Additionally, the moment of exchange cannot be considered fundamental
unless commodities are regarded as mere surplus products, and so liable to
be equated supra-historically to any other mode of production. If, in con-
trast to that, we consider that commodities are a representation of wealth,
it is no longer possible to reduce it to the moment of exchange, it must
include the historical form of labor that produced it. What has been
pushed away from the understanding of real abstraction is contradiction.
The movement underlying real contradiction has been substituted for the
still picture of an idealized valorization, that is, for the reduction of com-
modities to exchange, money and value; but, more importantly, the
wholeness of its grid, of the representation of wealth, has been dissolved.
It is still left for us to analyze the consequences of halting so the move-
ment of contradiction into a picture of real abstraction. To do so, we shall
review some aspects of how Marx’s thought develops these problems of
real contradiction.
tation of pure value). But because of the same reason, this transit presup-
poses asserting the point of departure as well as the arrival.
Of commodities, Marx says, ‘Its property of being a value not only can
but must achieve an existence different from its natural one’. From the
start, we are facing two orders of the existence of commodities. However,
it is not merely different, complementary aspects, profiles that coexist in
succession, but, on the contrary, it is a contradiction: ‘each commodity
must be qualitatively different from its own value [this is use value]. Its
value must therefore have an existence which is qualitatively distinguish-
able from it [money], and in actual exchange this separability must become
a real separation [real abstraction], because the natural distinctness of
commodities must come into contradiction with their economic equiva-
lence’ (MEW 42: 76; Marx 2007: 66).
The double existence of commodities ‘must become a real separation’,
that is, the contradiction between use value and value culminates in the
annihilation of the self-same relation: the terms must separate. This sepa-
ration, however, is not possible in the commodity closed in itself. How is
it possible, then? In the relation that each commodity supposes with the
others. That relation is expressed in an ideal mode in the exchange value
as a price, that is, a sum of money and, in a real mode, in the conversion
of commodities into money. So, the contradiction between use value and
value is transferred to the mediation of money. What takes place in this
shift is that the contradiction inherent to any commodity finds resolution
in its relation to the rest of the commodities through money (which is,
really, particular money, but at the same time, it is ideally the universal
representation17 of all commodities). The contradiction then moves from
an individual commodity to money in general as the general form of con-
tradiction. Finally, the abstraction of use value occurs, as Sohn-Rethel says,
but now we understand that exchange is only a moment, and so is real
abstraction. Marx says:
tion and consumption as well as use value (during the exchange). To sum
up, Sohn-Rethel’s approach does not allow relating the real abstraction
with the process of valorization. Precisely, this is so because that process is
not a simple abstraction, but a real contradiction, which is only possible
due to the vertiginous, repeating escape from itself (metamorphosis) that
the commodity—or its total form, the capital—undergoes.
Notes
1. This is a traditional Western topic. Among its most famous expressions,
there is the Aristotle’s founding classic (Aristotle 1982) Organon and
Kant’s approaches with Kant (2003) in which contradiction has been rel-
egated to the ideal and also to the limit of its decomposition. As the impos-
sibility of the real. In a manner radically different from tradition, Freud
states that negation does not exist in the unconscious, but that it arises
from an action from which the conscious and the ego emerge (Freud 1992:
249–250), Sartre (1993) claims in Being and Nothingness that negation
depends on nothingness, which is only possible because of the human atti-
tude of interrogation, in other words, a nihilization of the being-in-itself
produced by the being-for-itself.
2. That is, the Basic forms of the logic principles, as those of identity, non-
contradiction, excluded middle and so on.
3. Evidently, this does not mean that for Marx there is no logical contradic-
tion; on the contrary, as Hegel does, Marx conceives the existence of
another kind of contradiction, which allows broadening knowledge.
4. As there is in Foucault, a paradoxical follower of Marx’s position with
regard to idealism and nominalism, Deleuze and Guattari develop in a
similar way to Marx the relationship between bodies and meanings. See
Deleuze and Guattari (2002).
5. It may be that the explicative power of Foucault’s concept over Marx’s is
due to the former is a developed form of what in the latter is merely an
intuition.
6. This broadened reality has been attempted in several ways, among them
surrealism and psychoanalysis have been very fruitful. Walter Benjamin
envisaged their possibilities as he suggested that revolutionary art would be
that which managed to ‘win the energies of drunkenness for the revolu-
tion’ (Benjamin 2007: 313).
246 C. SUCKSDORF
References
Aristotle. (1982). Tratados de lógica (Organon) (Miguel Candel Sanmartin,
Trans.). Madrid: Gredos.
Benjamin, W. (2004). Libro de los pasajes. Madrid: Akal.
Benjamin, W. (2007). El surrealismo. In Walter Benjamin Obras, II., Vol. 2
(pp. 301–316). Madrid: Abada. Editores.
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2002). Postulaciones de la lingüística. In Mil mesetas.
Capitalismo y esquizofrenia (pp. 81–116). Valencia: Pre-textos.
Derrida, J. (1998). Espectros de Marx (3rd ed.). Madrid: Trotta.
Foucault, M. (2008). El nacimiento de la biopolítica Curso en el College de France
(1978–1979). Buenos Aires: FCE.
Freud, S. (1992). La Negación [1925] in Sigmund Freud, Obras completas, Vol.
19 (1923–1925) (pp. 249–250) (José Etcheverry, Trans.), fourth reprint.
Buenos Aires: Amorrortu.
Henry, M. (1976). Marx. Une philosophie de la réalité. Une philosophie de l’économie.
Gallimard, París [Spanish edition of the first part: (2011): Marx, Buenos Aire:
La cebra].
Kant, I. (2003). Attempt to introduce the concept of negative magnitudes into
philosophy [1763]. In Immanuel Kant: Theoretical philosophy 1775–1770
(pp. 165–204), (David Walford, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lukács, G. (1969). Historia y conciencia de clase. Mexico: Grijalbo.
248 C. SUCKSDORF
Ingo Elbe
This text is the revised version of an article that will appear shortly in Garofalo
and Quante (2017): Attualitá di Marx in Italian.
I. Elbe (*)
Carl von Ossitzky University of Oldenburg, Oldenburg, Germany
Already in the year 1844, Marx diagnosed the ‘society of private property’
as ‘the complete domination of the estranged thing’ (Marx and Engels
2010a: 221). Without yet being able to explain this domination, recurring
motifs of the real objectification of the relations of production and their
socio-psychological and ethical consequences are thematized—in the late
work as well—primarily under the concept of alienation:
none is for itself value objectivity as such […] outside of their relationship to
each other—the relationship in which they are equal—neither the coat nor
the linen possess value objectivity or their objectivity as mere congelations of
human labor as such. They only possess this social objectivity as a social
relationship
keines für sich solche Werthgegenständlichkeit [...]. Ausserhalb ihrer
Beziehung auf einander—der Beziehung, worin sie gleichgelten—besitzen
weder der Rock noch die Leinwand Werthgegenständlichkeit oder ihre
Gegenständlichkeit als blosse Gallerten menschlicher Arbeit schlechthin.
Diese gesellschaftliche Gegenständlichkeit besitzen sie [...] nur als gesell-
schaftliche Beziehung. (MEGA II/6 1987: 30)
(1) Concrete acts of labor/use value are thus first non-relational attri-
butes and bearers of relational attributes. Use value (and the con-
crete labor that constitutes it) is also a relation—the usefulness of
objects for human beings or as concrete labor, the socially medi-
ated reshaping of nature in order to make natural objects appropri-
ate to human ends. But first, this usefulness cannot be thought
without objective attributes, which is why Marx speaks of ‘natural
material’ (with regard to concrete labor: not without concrete
forms of activity, e.g. tailoring, and a real relation to natural objects,
e.g. cloth), and secondly, it is not dependent upon specific social
relations that use value as such (or the relation of concrete labor)
exists—it exists in all human societies. Of course, use values and
14 REIFICATION AND REAL ABSTRACTION IN MARX’S CRITIQUE… 255
their manners of use also have their history, but one can sit on a
chair whether it was created under feudalism or capitalism.
According to Marx, ‘not an atom of matter’ (Marx 1976: 138)
enters into the attribute of value or the substance of value, and it
constitutes a historically specific social relationship—under feudal
relations of production, for example, it is not the equality of acts of
labor that constitutes the nexus of material reproduction.
(2) Abstract labor, as a general attribute ascertained by means of nomi-
nal abstraction, is secondly the bearer of abstract labor as the sub-
stance of value, because, in order to be related to each other in the
process of exchange as products of human labor as such (i.e. to
have value), products of labor must also, independently of this rela-
tion, be products of labor. Abstract labor as a nominal abstraction
is therefore in this sense non-relational.
Since the value of the individual commodity cannot appear in any medium
distinct from its use value (the commodity is a dead object that has no ges-
tures, no language, etc.), its value cannot appear at all in its own body. The
commodity cannot be grasped as the social distinct from its use value, but
rather solely as use value. If the commodity must appear as value, and if it
cannot do so in any medium other than that of use value, then the commod-
ity can only appear in a use value that is distinct from its own. (Wolf
1985: 118)
Notes
1. See Honneth (2005), Wallat (2009), Deutsche Zeitschriftfür Philosophie
(2011), Bitterolf and Maier (2012), Friesen and Lotz (2012).
2. See Sohn-Rethel (1973: 38). For a critique of Sohn-Rethel, see Reichardt
(2008).
14 REIFICATION AND REAL ABSTRACTION IN MARX’S CRITIQUE… 261
3. I cannot deal further here with the considerable problems caused by this
thought in Marx’s theoretical frame of reference, in particular with regard
to the mediation of the quality and the quantity of the determination of
value. See Elbe (2010: 261–263) as well as Ellmers (2016).
4. ‘As use values or goods, commodities are corporeally distinct things. Their
existence as value, in contrast, constitutes their unity. This unity does not
originate in nature, but rather in society’ (MEGA II/5: 19). Things are
similar with regard to the ‘substance’ of value: ‘As useful activity directed
to the appropriation of natural factors in one form or another, labour is a
natural condition of human existence, a condition of material interchange
between man and nature, quite independent of the form of society. On the
other hand, the labour which posits exchange value is a specific social form
of labour. For example, tailoring if one considers its physical aspect as a
distinct productive activity produces a coat, but not the exchange value of
the coat. The exchange value is produced by it not as tailoring as such but
as abstract universal labour, and this belongs to a social framework not
devised by the tailor’ (Marx and Engels 2010b: 278).
5. See: ‘by equating their different products to each other in exchange as
values, they equate their different kinds of labour as human labour’ (Marx
1976: 166).
6. ‘Tailoring and weaving’ both ‘therefore possess the general property of
being human labour, and they therefore have to be considered in certain
cases, such as the production of value, solely from this point of view’ (Marx
1976: 150). ‘In every social form of labor, individual acts of labor of dif-
ferent individuals are also related to each other as human labor, but here,
this relationship itself counts as the specific social form of the acts of labor’
(MEGA II/5 1983: 41).
7. See: ‘The validation of concern here is neither one agreed upon by those
engaging in exchange, nor imposed by the state. Rather, it is a relation
structurally given in an economy based upon exchange’ (Heinrich 2008:
119).
8. This state of affairs arises from a passage in Capital that is usually not
understood, in which Marx on the one hand emphasizes that it’s only a
specific social relationship between people ‘which assumes here, for them,
the fantastic form of a relation between things’ (Marx 1976: 165) and on
the other hand writes that ‘to the producers, therefore, the social relations
between their private labours appear as what they are, i.e. they do not
appear as direct social relations between persons in their work, but rather
as material [dinglich] relations between persons and social relations
between things’ (ibid.: 166). On this, see Wolf (1985: 217).
9. What ‘vanishes’ in the empirical forms of wealth is not the fact that labor is
necessary to create its material bearers, but rather that the form itself is the
262 I. ELBE
References
Bitterolf, M., & Maier, D. (Eds.). (2012). Verdinglichung, Marxismus, Geschichte.
Von der Niederlage der Novemberrevolutionzurkritischen Theorie. Freiburg i.
Br.: Ca Ira.
Brentel, H. (1989). Soziale Form und ökonomisches Objekt. Studienzum Gegenstands-
und Methodenverständnis der Kritik der politischen Ökonomie. Opladen:
Westdeutscher Verlag.
Colletti, L. (1977). Marxismus und Dialektik. Frankfurt M.; Berlin; Wien: Ullstein.
Dannemann, R. (1987). Das Prinzip Verdinglichung. Studiezur Philosophie Georg
Lukács. Frankfurt/M: Sendler.
Deutsche Zeitschriftfür Philosophie. (2011). Schwerpunkt Verdinglichung, 59 (5).
Elbe, I. (2008). Marxismus-Mystizismus – oder: Die Verwandlung der Marxschen
Theorie in deutsche Ideologie. In Wissenschaftliche Mitteilungen des Berliner
Vereinszur Förderung der MEGA-Edition, Heft 6: Gesellschaftliche Praxis und
ihrewissenschaftliche Darstellung. Beiträgezur ‘Kapital’-Diskussion (pp. 187–209).
Berlin: Argument.
Elbe, I. (2010). Marx im Westen. Die neue Marx-Lektüre in der Bundesrepublik,
zweitekorr. Aufl. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
14 REIFICATION AND REAL ABSTRACTION IN MARX’S CRITIQUE… 263
Chris O’Kane
C. O’Kane (*)
St John’s University, Jamaica, NY, USA
society and then on the basis of the New Reading of Marx’s theory of
value that provides a systematic reconstruction and expansion of the accu-
mulation and reproduction of capital.
Sohn-Rethel
Alfred Sohn-Rethel was the first to use the term ‘real abstraction’ in
Marxian theory. Simmel (2004) first used the term in 1900. In part, a
rejoinder to what he saw as the insufficiencies of the ‘objective’ status of
Marx’s theory of value, Simmel’s work promulgated a neo-Kantian ‘sub-
jective’ theory of value that investigated the effects of money in the con-
text of what he saw as the inextricable separation of subject from object in
modern society.6 For Simmel, the real abstraction of value exemplified
this: ‘Exchange, i.e. the economy, is the source of economic values because
exchange is the representative of the distance between subject and object
which transforms subjective feelings into objective valuation’ (Simmel
quoted in Reichelt 2007: 15).
In contrast to Marx, for Simmel, the real abstraction of value was thus
established by individuals using the Kantian faculties of the mind embed-
ded in market exchange; an inevitable consequence of the complex divi-
sion of labor of modern society that separated subjects from the objects
they create. Instead of a historically-specific-form of social domination
constituent of the capitalist mode of production, real abstraction was thus
the hallmark of the tragedy of modern culture.
As his use of the term implies, Sohn-Rethel’s critique of real abstraction
consisted in an immanent criticism of the neo-Kantian tragedy of culture
on a Marxian basis. Such a critical theory was established by drawing on
the critique of political economy. For Sohn-Rethel, critical Marxism was
premised on the notion that ‘Marxian thinking is undogmatic and critical
to the core’ (Sohn-Rethel 1978: 192). Accordingly, Sohn-Rethel held that
Marx’s methodology entailed ‘an approach to reality, but by way of the
‘critique’ of the historically given consciousness’ (idem: 194–195), which
consisted in ‘tracing the genetical origin of any current ideas and concepts,
on the very standards of the social existence determining ideas and
concepts’ (idem: 195). In Marx’s case, such a method was employed to
critique the ‘particular mode of consciousness of political economy’ as the
‘necessary false consciousness’ of capitalist society, by unveiling ‘the
270 C. O’KANE
the abstraction comes about by force of the action of exchange … out of the
exchanging agents practising their solipsism against each other. The abstrac-
tion belongs to the interrelationship of the exchanging agents and not to the
agents themselves. For it is not the individuals who cause the social synthesis
but their actions in exchange, the action is social, the minds are private.
(Idem: 44)
Adorno
As their correspondence shows, Adorno was an enthusiastic supporter of
Sohn-Rethelian real abstraction, even if Adorno’s parallel project differen-
tiated itself in important, if often neglected, ways. This can be seen in
Adorno’s famous statement that ‘Alfred Sohn-Rethel was the first to point
out that … in the general and necessary activity of the Spirit, inalienably
social labor lies hidden’ (Adorno 2001a: Redirection of the Subjective
Reduction).7 For, as I shall now show, this passage points to the similari-
ties and differences between Sohn-Rethel and Adorno’s critical theory of
real abstraction.
Like Sohn-Rethel, Adorno also characterized his critical theory of soci-
ety as an attempt to adapt Marx’s critique of political economy to the cur-
rent epoch through his own interpretation of Marx’s theory of ‘exchange’.
However, unlike Sohn-Rethel, as the quotation indicates, such a critique
entailed an account of the social formation of epistemology via the fetish-
istic exchange abstraction that brought together Marx, Kant and Hegel.
Moreover, this notion of abstraction was also tied to Adorno’s theory of
272 C. O’KANE
Lefebvre
Henri Lefebvre is often portrayed as the ‘leading prophet of alienation’
(Merrifield 2006: XXXII). Yet his lifelong project of critiquing the repro-
duction of capitalist society, via his elaboration of the domination of lived
experience in his critique of everyday life, cities and space, was likewise
centered on a critical Marxist critique of fetishistic concrete abstraction
that paralleled Sohn-Rethel and Adorno’s work.11
Like Sohn-Rethel and Adorno, for Lefebvre, Marx’s theory was ‘not a
system or dogma’, but a ‘starting point that is indispensable for under-
standing the present-day world’ (Lefebvre 1968: 77). Like these thinkers,
Lefebvre held that Marx’s ‘basic concepts’ had ‘to be elaborated, refined,
and complemented by other concepts where necessary’ (idem: 188).
Consequently, mirroring these figures, Lefebvre’s critique of real abstrac-
tion, was thus developed as part of his elaboration of the relationship
between his interpretation of fetishistic concrete abstraction in the critique
of political economy and a critique of the domination of lived experience
in the objective-subjective entities of everyday life, cities and space in capi-
talist society.
Lefebvre’s interpretation of fetishistic concrete abstraction entailed
‘social reality, i.e., interacting human individuals and groups’, creating
‘appearances which are something more and else than mere illusions’ for
these ‘appearances are the modes in which human activities manifest
themselves within the whole they constitute at any given moment’. What
Lefebvre called ‘concrete abstractions’ are thus real abstractions; these
appearances are ‘abstract’ social forms which are nonetheless ‘concrete’
since they are constituted by social labor (Lefebvre 2009: 76). Like Sohn-
Rethel and Adorno, Lefebvre also stressed that concrete abstractions are
not created by the mind, but possess a ‘practical power’. They ‘have a
concrete, objective reality: historically (as moments of the social reality)
and actually (as elements of the social objectivity)’ (idem: 76–77). For
‘The starting-point for this abstraction is not in the mind, but in the prac-
tical activity … Abstraction is a practical power’ (idem: 109).
Moreover, mirroring Adorno, Lefebvre emphasized that the extent of
form-determinate domination is limited. ‘For the logic of commodities …
does not succeed in forming a permanent closed system’. The ‘complex
determinations’ of ‘human labour’ are ‘not entirely taken over by this
form’ (Lefebvre 1968: 100). Rather, the reification of persons is prevented
by the internal opposition of the qualitative content of these forms.
15 THE CRITIQUE OF REAL ABSTRACTION: FROM THE CRITICAL THEORY… 275
Social relations, which are concrete abstractions, have no real existence save
in and through space. Their underpinning is spatial … the connection
between this underpinning and the relations it supports calls for analysis.
Such an analysis must … explain a genesis and constitute a critique of those
institutions …. and so forth, that have transformed the space under consid-
eration. (Idem: 404)
Postone
Moishe Postone’s seminal work, Time, Labor and Social Domination,
undertakes a critical-theoretical reconstruction of Marx’s critique of polit-
ical economy that systematizes Marx’s ambiguous theorization of abstract
labor. For Postone, it is ultimately the historically-specific reciprocal deter-
mination of concrete and abstract labor in conjunction with abstract time
that compulsively mediates the ‘treadmill’ dynamic of capitalist accumula-
tion and reproduction. The cornerstone of this interpretation is Postone’s
argument that ‘in Marx’s analysis, the category of abstract labor expresses
this real social process of abstraction; it is not simply based on a conceptual
process of abstraction’ (Postone 1996: 152). This means that for Postone,
the critique of real abstraction is tantamount to the critique of political
economy as a historically-specific critique of labor.
On this basis, Postone puts forward pertinent and trenchant criticisms
of Sohn-Rethel’s notion of real abstraction as ‘not a labor abstraction but
an exchange abstraction’. For, as Postone rightly notes ‘Sohn-Rethel …
does not relate the notion of labor abstraction’ but that of exchange ‘to
the creation of alienated social structures’.13 This means that Sohn-Rethel
treats classless society as tantamount to abolishing exchange, not the capi-
talist division of labor.
Moreover, as Postone intriguingly argues Sohn-Rethel’s notion of real
abstraction undermines his corresponding critique of epistemology. In this
first place, it ‘weakens his sophisticated attempt at an epistemological read-
ing of Marx’s categories’. In the second, his ‘emphasis on exchange, which
excludes any examination of the implications of the commodity form for
labor, restricts his social epistemology to a consideration of forms of static,
abstract mechanical thought necessarily excludes many forms of modern
thought from the purview of his critical social epistemology’, thus pre-
venting Sohn-Rethel from ‘dealing with nineteenth- and twentieth-
century forms of thought in which the form of capital-determined
production itself takes on a fetishized form’ (idem: 178).
278 C. O’KANE
Reichelt
Helmut Reichelt argues that ‘The “principle of exchange” and, connected
to this, the “exchange abstraction” as “real abstraction” form a central
component of Adorno’s concept of society’ (Reichelt 2007: 3). This is
because ‘Adorno’s critical theory … understands the capitalist economy as
an inverted reality in which individuals no longer “interact with one
another” on the market as rationally acting subjects, as the idea of the
exchange economy suggests’ (idem: 5). Yet, as Reichelt perceptively points
out, despite its programmatic status in Adorno’s critical theory, Adorno
only ‘assumes’ that the whole economy is to be developed out of the
exchange principle, meaning that ‘How this process of autonomisation is
to be conceptualised in detail is not explained by Adorno’ leaving ‘the
central concepts—objective abstraction, inversion, autonomisation, total-
ity, power of the universal over the particular’ as ‘postulates with regard to
their concretisation as far as the critique of economics is concerned’
(idem: 6).
From this vantage point, Reichelt has developed a notion of real
abstraction with regard to his elaboration of Marx’s monetary theory of
value. Such a theory holds that the atomized capitalist process of produc-
tion for exchange constitutes a sensible supersensible inverted world, in
which sensuousness in its widest sense—as use value, labor, exchange with
nature—is demoted to a means of the self-perpetuation of an abstract pro-
cess that underlies the whole objective world of constant change… the
whole sensuous world of human beings who reproduce themselves
through the satisfaction of needs and labor is step-by-step sucked into this
process, in which all activities ‘are themselves inverted’ (Reichelt
2005: 46–47).
This is because the sensible productive activity of individuals within the
class relation of the capitalist social division of labor are necessarily realized
15 THE CRITIQUE OF REAL ABSTRACTION: FROM THE CRITICAL THEORY… 279
Kerr
Finally, Derek Kerr points out that Lefebvre’s theory of abstract space
refrains from properly integrating Marx’s theory of accumulation. By ‘sep-
arating out contradictions of space from those in space and by reducing
class struggle and history to the latter, it is not clear what constitutes the
contradictions of space’. In ‘abandoning the Marx of Capital’, Lefebvre’s
theory of ‘the relation between the mode of production and its space is
never specified’ (Kerr 1994: 25). Drawing on the early work of Bonefeld,
Kerr argues that Marx’s critique uncovers ‘the contradictory constitution
of the capital relation as it attempts to transform and express itself through
the spatial and temporal modalities of existence’ (idem: 32). While making
the incisive point that it is the time of surplus production that is realized
in the relation between time and abstract space, Kerr has not explored the
relationship between these forms of real abstraction, abstract space and the
domination of lived experience as proposed by Lefebvre.
In sum, the New Reading of Marx is undoubtedly correct at pointing
to the systematic shortcomings in the value-theoretical bases of Sohn-
Rethel, Adorno and Lefebvre’s critical social theories of real abstraction.
Postone and Reichelt’s systematizations of the ambiguous aspects of
Marx’s theory of value that elaborate the constitution and reproduction of
capital via the social objectivity of abstract labor and the forms of value are
likewise important conceptions of real abstraction. Yet the unintended
consequences of the new reading has been to diminish the status of the
critical theory of real abstraction, reducing it to an errant ersatz reading of
the critique of political economy.
280 C. O’KANE
In the next section, I argue that this approach has served as the basis for
a number of new theories of real abstraction. I then contrast this approach
with work that has brought together the new reading of Marx and the
critical theory of society. I close by arguing that the second approach
should be further developed to articulate what I call the New Reading of
the Critical Theory of Real Abstraction.
Conclusion
Bonefeld and Lotz’s work point toward how I contend that the critical
theory of real abstraction might be further developed, not merely as a
reconstruction or systematic elaboration of Marx’s theory of value, but
through the integration of critical theories and new readings of real
abstraction.
My own recent work (O’Kane 2018c) has sought to further develop
such a new reading of the critical theory of real abstraction, arguing how
Adorno’s idea of society as subject and object, qua exchange, can be refor-
mulated to critique ‘neoliberalism’, the 2007 crisis and the ensuring
embrace of authoritarianism. My forthcoming work seeks to extend it to a
conception of the negative totality of capitalist society that includes house-
hold production and the domination of nature.
15 THE CRITIQUE OF REAL ABSTRACTION: FROM THE CRITICAL THEORY… 283
Notes
1. As I argue below Marx’s notion of accumulation entails the reproduction
of social relations in the sphere of production and circulation in the capital-
ist mode of production. Capitalist society refers to the objective and sub-
jective domains of the capitalist economy as well as the state and private
sphere, which are implicated in, yet distinct from, the process of capital
accumulation.
2. See Elena Louisa Lange (forthcoming), for a discussion of the develop-
ment or real abstraction from a value-theoretical perspective.
3. Marx’s trans-historical definition of abstract labor holds that ‘all labour is
an expenditure of human labour, in the physiological sense, and it is this
quality of being equal, or abstract, human labour, that it forms the value of
commodities’ (Marx n.d.: 137). This is contrasted with his historically-
specific definitions which states that ‘not an atom of matter’ enters into this
process of abstraction in which ‘value is realized only in exchange, i.e. in a
social process’ (idem: 105). For a recent debate on these two definitions of
abstract labor, see Bonefeld (2010) and Kicillof and Starosta (2011).
284 C. O’KANE
4. For an example of the former, see Marx’s statement that ‘The different
proportions, in which different sorts of labour are reduced to simple labour
as their standard, are established by a social process that goes on behind the
back of the producers and, consequently, seems to be fixed by custom. In
the values coat and linen, abstraction is made from the difference of their
use-values; now we have seen that also in the labour that represents itself in
these values, abstraction is made from the difference of its useful forms of
tailoring and weaving’ (Marx n.d.: 134–135). For the latter, see the French
edition of Capital where Marx added the following sentence: ‘it is evident
that one abstracts from the use-value of the commodities when one
exchanges them and that every exchange relation is itself characterized by
this abstraction’ (Marx quoted in Ehrbar 2010: 439). As I show below,
these interpretations are represented by Sohn-Rethel and Postone.
5. Although this is mentioned in Chapter 3.3 of Volume I.
6. See David Frisby’s introduction to Simmel (2004), Winder (n.d.).
7. The Redmond translation does not include page numbers, so I will include
the name of the section when quoting from Negative Dialectics.
8. Adorno’s most cohesive exposition of this process of abstraction can be
found in Adorno (2018). For shorter variations, see also ‘Sociology and
Empirical Research’ in Adorno et al. (1981), as well as Adorno (2002:
31–32). For a detailed reconstruction of Adorno’s account of this process,
see O’Kane (2018b).
9. Hence ‘transcendental universality is no mere narcissistic self-exaltation of
the I …but has its reality in the domination which ends up prevailing and
perpetuating itself through the exchange-principle’ (Adorno 2001a: On
the interpretation of the transcendental 180–182).
10. For a discussion of Adorno’s periodization of late capitalism, see O’Kane
(2018c).
11. This section draws on O’Kane (2018a).
12. The critical-theoretical lineage refers to thinkers who develop their new
reading of Marx within the tradition of critical theory and includes not
only students of Adorno but thinkers in other critical Marxist traditions,
such as Open Marxism. This distinguishes them from others who work
within this theoretical discourse, such as Michael Heinrich and Chris
Arthur, who are influenced by the work of Backhaus, Reichelt and others
but do not see their attempts to reconstruct the critique of political econ-
omy as part of the critical-theoretical tradition.
13. For an elaboration of this critique of Sohn-Rethel’s notion of real abstrac-
tion, see Jappe (2013).
14. This is because while here and elsewhere Postone points to the relations
between the treadmill dynamic, the state, crises and mass psychology, it is
unfortunately the case that he has yet to systematically elaborate them.
15 THE CRITIQUE OF REAL ABSTRACTION: FROM THE CRITICAL THEORY… 285
References
Adorno, T. W. (2001a). Negative Dialectics (Dennis Redmond, Trans.). Retrieved
June 15, 2018, from http://members.efn.org/~dredmond/ND2Trans.txt.
Adorno, T. W. (2001b). Late Capitalism Or Industrial Society? (Dennis Redmond,
Trans.). Retrieved June 15, 2018, from https://www.marxists.org/reference/
archive/adorno/1968/late-capitalism.htm.Last.
Adorno, T. W. (2002). Introduction to Sociology. London: Polity Press.
Adorno, T. W. (2018). On Marx and the Basic Concepts of Sociology. Historical
Materialism, 26(1), 1–11.
Adorno, T. W., et al. (1981). The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology. London:
Ashgate Pub Co.
Arthur, C. (2004). The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Arthur, C. (2013). The Practical Truth of Abstract Labour. In R. Bellofiore
et al. (Eds.), In Marx’s Laboratory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse
(pp. 101–120). Leiden: Brill.
Bellofiore, R. (2016). Marx After Hegel: Capital as Totality and the Centrality of
Production. Crisis and Critique, 3(3), 31–64.
Bonefeld, W. (2010). Abstract Labour: Against Its Nature and on Its Time.
Capital and Class, 34(2), 257–276.
Bonefeld, W. (2014). Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy: On
Subversion and Negative Reason. London: Bloomsbury.
Charnock, G. (2014). ‘Lost in Space’ Lefebvre, Harvey and the Spatiality of
Negative. South Atlantic Quarterly, 113(2), 313–325.
Charnock, G. (2018). Space, Form and Urbanity. In B. Best et al. (Eds.), The Sage
Handbook of Frankfurt School Critical Theory. London: Sage.
Charnock, G., Purcell, T. F., & Ribera-Fumaz, R. (2014). The Limits to Capital in
Spain. London: Palgrave.
Ehrbar, H. (2010). Annotations to Marx’s Capital. Register. Retrieved from
http://content.csbs.utah.edu/~ehrbar/akmc.pdf.
Endnotes. (2013). The Logic of Gender, in Endnotes. Gender, Race, Class and
Other Misfortunes, 3. Endnotes Register. Retrieved June 15, 2018, from
https://endnotes.org.uk/issues/3/en/endnotes-the-logic-of-gender.
Jappe, A. (2013). Sohn-Rethel and the Origin of Real Abstraction. Historical
Materialism, 21(1), 3–14.
286 C. O’KANE
Wolfgang Fritz Haug
Words can become a ‘label by which the true believers recognize one
another’; thus Marx angrily judged one of the phrases in the founding
program of the Socialist Workers Party of Germany of 1875 (Marx and
Engels 24 2010a: 91; MEW 19 1987: 25).1 His own concepts were some-
times also not immune to similar misuse, such as his notion of ‘value
abstraction’, indispensable for the analysis of the value-form, the gateway
to understanding Capital. Such was also the case for the concept of ‘real
abstraction’, with the help of which Alfred Sohn-Rethel claims to expose
the conditions of possible potential and range of this Marxian conception.
For the criterion for concepts is their contribution to understanding con-
crete reality. This is also the case for Sohn-Rethel’s abstract-general, meta-
theoretical concept of real abstraction. Initially, it confronts us as a
W. F. Haug (*)
Freie Universität Berlin, Berlin, Germany
e-mail: [email protected]
I
Our first word was ‘words’. What do we mean, when in contrast to that we
say concept in a theoretical context? Now, every theoretical concept also
initially confronts us as a word. But then it is the name for a piece of the-
ory. We can speak of a theorem. When we go through it to say what a
concept means, we in turn use other concepts, whose network is always
traceable, referring to a theory in the sense of a theoretically permeated
real problem field.
Are concepts accordingly the categories of a theory? They are often
regarded as such, and in Soviet Marxism–Leninism they were ‘officially’
declared to be so. But then Marx spits in this conceptual soup with the
fundamental statement of his critique: ‘Classical political economy bor-
rowed the category “price of labour” from everyday life without further
criticism, and then simply asked the question, how is this price deter-
mined?’ (Marx 1976: 677f.). If we additionally consider how he himself
worked this field, we recognize the transition to a positive-theoretical con-
ception: labor as such cannot be sold at all; only products of labor can
(which includes services). Under the wage relation, what is sold is labor-
power, measured in terms of the duration of time of its expenditure. The
value of labor-power, in turn, is measured in terms of the labor necessary
for its reproduction. Here is where the axiomatic statements apply: labor
does not have value; it creates value. Where there were once categories,
there are now concepts, which constitute a theorem. The category—in
our example, the wage as the ‘price of labor’—can however now be grasped
in its own positivity. It is not simply false, but rather, as the everyday form
of praxis of wage workers, saturated with empirical evidence. Marx gener-
ally determines that categories of this sort ‘express the forms of being, the
characteristics of existence, and often only individual sides of this specific
society, this subject’ (Marx 1973: 106). Marx knew Ancient Greek very
well and know that the category of kategoreuo, ‘to publicly accuse s omeone
16 REAL ABSTRACTION IN LIGHT OF THE ‘PRACTICAL REVOLUTION… 291
II
In his critique of Hegel from 1843, the young Marx criticized—at this
time, still close to Feuerbach—the operation with ‘abstractly logical cate-
gories’ as well as their subjectification, which causes the real d
eterminations
292 W. F. HAUG
familiar with the elements on which they rest. E.g. wage labour, capital,
etc.’, which in turn are empty abstractions without the division of labor,
exchange, value, money, price, etc., not to forget labor, ‘ever thinner
abstractions until I had arrived at the simplest determinations’ (idem).
From here, ‘the journey would have to be retraced until I had finally
arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic conception
of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and relations’.
This is ‘is obviously the scientifically correct method’ (idem: 101). In
these passages, Hegel’s formula of ascending from the abstract to the con-
crete begins its career as the Marxist understanding of method. One was
not disturbed by the fact that Marx thus described the act of theoretical
construction begun by Smith and classically carried out by Ricardo; that of
‘retracing the journey’: ‘As soon as these individual moments had been
more or less firmly established and abstracted, there began the economic
systems, which ascended from the simple relations, such as labour, division
of labour, need, exchange value, to the level of the state, exchange between
nations and the world market’. (idem: 100) May we conclude from this
that he did not yet have his own path in view? After all, the Grundrisse
(Outlines) Of the Critique of Political Economy, where he still had to strug-
gle to present his object, were still ahead of him. Still hidden in the future
for him, however, were the first volume of Capital—the only one com-
pleted by him in the two editions he had shaped and the French transla-
tion with its progressive layers of revision—in which he practiced his
dialectical method as well as further developing (Haug 2006b) it and con-
ceptualizing it. The manuscripts for the third volume quoted above also
still largely don’t ‘know’ anything of it.
But theoretically educated Marxists could know—at least since the
beginning of the project of the first MEGA in the early Soviet Union and
at the latest since the publication of the MEW. For Capital does not and
could not begin—Althusser, who asked his readers to ‘abstract’ from the
beginning of Capital, may forgive me—with abstract labor, but rather
with the ‘simplest concrete element of economics’ in the form of ‘the sim-
plest social form in which the product of labour presents itself in contem-
porary society’, the commodity form (Marx and Engels 24: 2010a:
544–545). This structure alone, obvious at first glance in the table of
contents, should actually suffice for this commonplace to lose credibility.
294 W. F. HAUG
III
A key question is in fact the one initially only dealt with in a rudimentary
manner by Marx, that of how the ‘relationship between scientific presenta-
tion and the real movement’ (see above) is to be processed in a historical
materialist manner. It is made concrete in the question concerning the
beginning, then of how transitions from one level of reality to a more
complex one are to be achieved. A priori constructions, also those in the
name of Hegelian dialectic, are inadmissible. ‘Inquiry’, Marx writes in the
Postface to the Second Edition, ‘has to appropriate the material in detail,
to analyse its different forms of development and to track down their inner
connection. Only after this work has been done can the real movement be
appropriately presented’ (Marx 1976: 102). But that only describes, it
does not explain, how Marx is to accomplish and epistemologically con-
ceptualize this presentation. The task that Marx poses in the quoted
Postface from 1873, and the solution to which he calls ‘my dialectical
method’, sounds more concrete: grasping ‘every historically developed
form as being in a fluid state’ and presenting it out of this rhythm of
becoming and passing away (idem: 103). He returns to the ‘how’ of solv-
ing this task halfway, at the beginning of the chapter on machinery and
large-scale industry, in a footnote where, 16 years after the introduction to
the Grundrisse, he casually—as if in a protocol of reflection upon his theo-
retical mode of production—returns to the question of the scientifically
correct method, but now looking back on what has already been achieved
and looking forward with a clearer view to what has yet to be achieved. In
context, it is a critical history of technology. Surprisingly, Marx refers back
to his fourth thesis on Feuerbach from 1845, where he confronts
Feuerbach’s analytical reduction of the ‘religious world’ to its ‘secular
basis’ with the insight that the genesis of the religious world ‘can only be
explained by the inner strife and intrinsic contradictoriness of this secular
basis’ (Marx and Engels 5 2010d: 4). Now, in Capital, with regard to
technology, he returns to this: ‘It is, in reality, much easier to discover by
analysis the earthly kernel of the misty creations of religion than to do the
opposite, i.e. to develop from the actual, given relations of life the forms
in which these have been apotheosized. The latter method is the only
materialist, and therefore the only scientific one’ (Marx 1976: 493, ff. 4).
Within the context of the history of technology, Marx attributes the key
role to the ‘active relation of man to nature’. In the social, especially
16 REAL ABSTRACTION IN LIGHT OF THE ‘PRACTICAL REVOLUTION… 295
IV
Marx approaches bourgeois economics and its science with this question.
He begins with the ‘immense collection of commodities’ as which the
wealth of societies in which the capitalist mode of production predomi-
nates first confronts the superficial view of the passerby in the shop win-
dow, reduces it to the abstraction of the ‘individual commodity’ in general,
and begins with the emergence of its dual character. The analysis leads him
to the finding that the dominant determination of ‘value’, which initially
emerges as the exchange relation between two commodities, does ‘not
contain an atom’ of the use value that interests the potential buyer (idem:
128). This equation of two unequal commodities abstracts from it.
Analysis follows this abstraction, and in the search for the equal element in
the unequal hits upon the abstraction of the product of labor as such. It
follows it into the sphere of production and initially follows the dual char-
acter of the commodity in commodity-producing labor. He then demon-
strates the condition of its possibility, indeed necessity in the relations of
private (non-social) production that is at the same time characterized by a
division of labor (social). With that, he has found the entity (Instanz) that
stamps the forms and above all form-relations (the reign of the real-
abstract category of value over that of use value) encountered thus far on
the commodities and their production. In it, and in its form-imprint he
recognizes the ‘point […] crucial to an under-standing of political econ-
omy’ (idem: 132).
296 W. F. HAUG
do not yet appear, however. To abstract from this and the realized exchange
is decisive in order to trace the ‘genesis’ of the ‘money form’. I will not
repeat the details here. They are, so to speak, depicted in slow motion and
by means of the force of abstraction that replaces the microscope that
Marx announces in the foreword, in my Vorlesungen, supplemented by a
few bridges to practical, everyday consciousness. Here only so much: the
genetic reconstruction of the transitions from the simple to the expanded
form of value and from this to the general form of value and finally to the
money form, only presuppose (in the laboratory-like exclusion of (abstrac-
tion from) foreign—that is external to the exchange relationship being
initiated—influences (which is why the reconstruction is genetic and not
historical) one thing: that namely the driving force of interest in exchange
as well as its objects continues to operate. Under this condition, the value
form transitions into a more complex one ‘on its own’.
V
Marx had already discovered in his Introduction of 1857 that genesis and
history diverge, and how this plays into the use of methodical abstraction
in relation to objective moments or aspects. Namely where, as with the
category of production, he raises the question as to universal concepts
valid for all historical forms of production. The category ‘labor’, ‘labor as
such’, ‘labor sans phrase’ offers itself, that is the abstraction of the category
‘labor’; not to be confused with the concept of ‘abstract labor’! (Marx
1973: 105). And it becomes clear to him how epistemological capacity
and historical fact drift apart in such cases. As with other such abstractions,
labor also ‘by no means begins only at the point where one can speak of it
as such’, but rather ‘possess a truth for all other forms of society’ (idem).
Only, in capitalism, effective-practical truth comes along: in the USA, ‘the
most modern form of existence of bourgeois society’ of his time, Marx saw
‘the abstraction of the category “labour”, “labour as such”, labour pure
and simple, becomes true in practice’ (idem). The truth of the abstraction
here stands for the fact that—as Adorno says in the appropriate context—it
clings (schmigt sich an) to a practical reality. In both cases, it is a question
of opening up reality by means of a genetic reconstruction.
With that, we have again arrived at the question of real abstraction. It
has consistently accompanied us as a dynamic moment of praxis in
conditions of private production with a division of labor. For Marx, the
value abstraction is a transitional point to its complementary opposite, a
298 W. F. HAUG
VI
Belonging to the reality that can be conceived of as real abstraction is the
great para-ideological power of capitalist mass culture, to wit commodity
aesthetics. Here, real abstraction means tangible autonomization in rela-
tion to the production of use value. This goes hand in hand with the real
concretion of a particular economic sector, accompanied by the emer-
gence of special art schools, where one learns to design imaginary use
values independently of the real use value in the mode of aesthetic abstrac-
tion. These institutions act according to the ‘basic law of commodity aes-
thetics […]: It is not real use value that triggers the purchase, but rather
the promise of use value’ (Haug 1980: 41, 44; 1986). Additionally, there
is the pseudo-concretion according to the ‘operational law of commodity
aesthetics’. The potential buyers have to promise the use value of the com-
modity to themselves, and this, their self-activity, must be able to rely on
the appearance of the product produced in the abstract for itself. Therefore,
the Archimedean point from which the mistrust of these addressees can be
aesthetically unhinged, and the desire that motivates them to buy as an
‘inner means of coercion’(Sombart) can be triggered, lies ‘within’ the
potential buyers (52). The aesthetic abstraction of use value clings to this
interior. This is our next real abstraction in the shape of a simulated
concretion.
What is to be grasped here is the dialectic of opposites: the striving for
abstract wealth becomes the spring from which modern semblance flows.
Indifference cries out difference. It is precisely the indifference of capital
toward its transitory use value that is expressed in its most fantastic stag-
ing. The abstraction from use value manifests as the aesthetic promise of
use value and leads to the formation of aesthetic monopolies of use value.
In short: real abstraction appears here as illusory concreteness for the pur-
16 REAL ABSTRACTION IN LIGHT OF THE ‘PRACTICAL REVOLUTION… 299
chasing masses. It is precisely the abstraction from these masses that the
real-ideological abstraction by distraction of their direct or mediated pro-
ducer existence what expects these masses to convert them in consumers.
In a certain way, all the aesthetics that have been specifically differenti-
ated are indebted to an aesthetic abstraction. The bourgeois institutional-
ization of ‘aesthetics’ as a discipline and socially recognized form of
practice has lent aesthetic abstraction the significance of a projection
screen of the imaginary. ‘Autonomous art’, thus constituted, could act as
a sphere that reconciles a society torn apart and reified in the economic
sphere in a ‘beautiful illusion’ (Haug 1994: 675). The ‘reconciliation’
turns into mass deception, where, as Walter Benjamin observed in the
fascist mass rallies, the masses are helped to their ‘expression’ in a way that
deprives them of their ‘right’ (Benjamin 1989: 382).
VII
The use that Sohn-Rethel made of his concept is a dual one. For one
thing, he derives from the mercantile capitalist abstraction of value the
upsurge of abstract thought in the Hellenic seaport cities of the sixth
century BC; for another thing, the acute status of the problem of social
synthesis. These assumptions cannot be dismissed. Only, their analytical-
reductive or, as Sohn-Rethel repeatedly states, implementation as ‘deriva-
tion’ is poorly compatible with the principles of historical materialism.
Also an unsecured change is the ‘derivation’, without further ado, ‘of
purely theoretical thought from the commodity economy’ (Sohn-Rethel
1972: 90). As Klaus-Dieter Eichler has shown, the emergence of the
ancient philosophical impetus toward abstraction cannot be explained by
this alone, since ‘the world market […] is not a cult community of univer-
sal extent’ (Eichler 2006: 35). In other words: it does not require abstrac-
tion from each individual cult community—an essential condition for the
‘pure’ mode of rationality that is meant.
The mistake rests upon the logical totalization of the value abstraction.
This can be seen in the example of the real abstraction of abstract labour.
In that its real abstraction is derived from the totality, it turns into an ideal
abstraction. This is so because the logical totality is beyond any real whole.
Marx thus mocks logicism in the light of reality at every opportunity. He
also bridges the gap between the speculative totality and the relative, ever
more renewed and decaying wholeness to be analyzed in reality with con-
cepts of mediation and transition. What they have in common with the
300 W. F. HAUG
VIII
Finally, I return to the question of the reality character of real abstraction
or, from the opposite side, of the abstract character of reality. Even if,
according to Pablo Nocera, the reality of real abstraction has nothing in
common with the ‘nivel de la Wirklichkeit, de las propiedades efectivas de
un objeto’ (Nocera 2005) it would, according to him, be wrong to con-
ceive of it as an abstraction of thought. ‘On the contrary, the abstraction
that belongs to the scope of the exchange is external’, actually happens
outside, in the social world. But what is this level of reality of this world?
That which Nocera approvingly quotes from Sohn-Rethel sounds like a
riddle of the sphinx: ‘no es pensamiento, pero guarda la forma de pensam-
iento’ (Sohn-Rethel 1978: 59). But what should a form of thinking be
without thinking?
Nocera’s criticism of Althusser is that his tearing apart of ‘real object’
and ‘knowledge object’ makes insoluble the fundamental problem of any
historical-materialist epistemology of measuring concepts against the real
determinations. What is at stake, then, is the specific position of Marxist
thought toward reality. So far, so good. But how can we imagine the ‘third
element’ postulated by Nocera, ‘que revoluciona el campo mismo’ of
Althusser’s distinction? Nocera calls it, following Sohn-Rethel, ‘The way
of thinking before and outside of thought’ (idem) and locates this form of
thinking preceding thinking in the ‘orden simbólico’. What speaks against
this is the fact that a historical-materialistic reflection of this Lacanian con-
cept of the ‘symbolic order’ would come up against the fact that the real
character of the social order is nothing symbolic. In this view, social cate-
gories are not signs for anything at all, but practically self-interpreting
determinations of existence. Anyone who says mother to mother is with
her, is not using a symbol. Language is not a collection of signposts.
Another way suggests itself, where Sohn-Rethel says of the ‘abstract’
form of socialization of money-mediated commodity production: ‘it is not
the people who accomplish this, not they who cause this connection, but
rather their actions’ (Sohn-Rethel 1972: 52). That’s reminiscent of the
murderer’s saying that he did not commit the murder; rather, his knife
did. No, the key is given by the sentence quoted by Sohn-Rethel and
many of those who spoke in the discussion initiated by him, with which
Marx reduced the ‘Father, forgive them, for they know not what they do’
(Luke, 25:34) to its worldly content: ‘They don’t know it, but they do it’
16 REAL ABSTRACTION IN LIGHT OF THE ‘PRACTICAL REVOLUTION… 303
(Marx 1976: 166); ‘Sie wissen es nicht, aber sie tun es’ (MEW 23 1962: 88).
And further: ‘for the characteristic which objects of utility have of being
values is as much men’s social product as is their language’ (idem). But
unlike language, the value form is a ‘a relation concealed beneath a veil of
things’ (unter dinglicher Hülle; MEW 23 1962: 88, ff. 27), as Marx adds
in a comment on the 2nd edition of the first volume of Capital to the
Italian economist Ferdinando Galiano, who in the eighteenth century
understood the value of goods as a ‘relation [ragione] between persons’
(idem: 167, ff. 29; transl. corr. WFH; Haug 2017b). What people do can
be researched and then known. But in this case, knowledge does not
change action, the real-abstract value form of its product ‘appears to those
caught up in the relations of commodity production (and this is true both
before and after the above-mentioned scientific discovery) to be just as
ultimately valid’ (ibid.), for it is the form of movement of the contradic-
tion of private production based upon social division of labor, in which
every producing actor ‘produces for society represented by the “market”,
but always only lines his own pocket’ (Haug 2005: I, XI.1).3
In order to further clarify the questions raised here, it is essential to
proceed from the ‘capovolgimento pratico della teorica della conoscenza’.
Antonio Labriola, the historical founder of Marxist philosophizing,
emphatically points out that this ‘practical revolution of epistemology’
(Labriola 1973: 206), or ‘la inversione pratica del problema della conosci-
bilità’ (idem: 224) is contained in historical materialism. The relatively
few to whom the name Labriola means something still know him as a
provider of keywords to Antonio Gramsci, without accounting for the fact
that Gramsci in his Prison Notebooks he became the philosophical executor
of Labriola’s project of a Marxist Philosophy of Praxis. Labriola’s thesis
that this philosophy is immanent in the things about which it philoso-
phizes, indeed that the critique of political economy follows the ‘self-crit-
icism’ of the social relations, leads him to conceive of it as the source or
‘marrow’ of historical materialism. In practice, he argues with primary
attention on material work, active thinking or thinking action is with the
things themselves, albeit not yet in scientific form. Experimental scientific
research he understands as a special form of material work aiming at such
knowledge. It is only in this being with the things themselves that the path
to the reconstruction of the concrete in thought is found. Their peculiar
way of being originates in the interweavements and dynamic autonomiza-
tions resulting from their social massiveness and from their criss-crossing
304 W. F. HAUG
Notes
1. In view of the Lassallian formula, Marx speaks of the ‘iron law of wages’ in
the Gotha Programme of the young German social democracy. The adjec-
tive ‘iron’—he himself used it in the Preface to the first edition of Capital
(Marx and Engels 35 2010b: 9; MEW 23 1962: 12)—suggests precise
knowledge of the ‘objective laws of social development’ and phrases the
place where further analysis is needed. So recently the word ‘logical’ as sup-
posed key to the method of the Marxian main work.
2. In the French edition: ‘l’expression de valeur’ (Marx 1969) [1872]: 17).
3. Marx’s talk of the ‘semblance of objectivity’ (Marx 1976: 167) of the fetish
character of the commodity (MEW 23 1862: 88) is therefore unfortunate,
because ‘semblance’ [Schein] suggests that one can scare it away by enlight-
enment. Pablo Nocera rightly adheres to Marx’s realization that the fetish
character of the commodity, the other face of value abstraction in motu, ‘has
an autonomous existence that does not depend on the knowledge that the
subjects have of it’ (Nocera 2005). But this is contradicted by the sentence
that it is about ‘A type of reality that is only possible on condition that the
individuals who are immersed in it are not aware of their own logic’ (idem).
However, the relations of production as one with the relations of property
are not a question of consciousness, even if many people are under the spell
of bourgeois ideology and reinforced by the power of facts, are either
unaware of it or push aside the thought of it in the certainty that they cannot
change anything.
16 REAL ABSTRACTION IN LIGHT OF THE ‘PRACTICAL REVOLUTION… 305
References
Benjamin, W. (1989). Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII (R. Tiedemann and
H. Schweppenhäuser, Eds.). Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.
Eichler, K. D. (2006). Zum Gründungsmythos der europäischen Philosophie. In
K. Broese et al. (Eds.), Vernunft der Aufklärung – Aufklärung der Vernunft
(pp. 25–36). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
Enlace Zapatista. (2017). ¡Oximoron! (La derecha intelectual y el fascismo lib-
eral). Retrieved March 25, 2018, from https://enlacezapatista.ezln.org.
mx/2000/04/01/oximoron-la-derecha-intelectual-y-el-fascismo-liberal/.
Haug, W. F. (1980). Crítica de la estética de mercancías (Guillermo Hirata,
Trans.). Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
Haug, W. F. (1986). Critique of Commodity Aesthetics. Appearance, Sexuality and
Advertising in Capitalist Society, intrd. Stuart Hall. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Haug, W. F. (1987). Commodity Aesthetics, Ideology & Culture. New York &
Bagnolet (France): International General.
Haug, W. F. (1994). Ästhetische Abstraktion. In Historisch-kritisches Wörterbuch
des Marxismus (Vol. 1, pp. 673–675). Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, W. F. (2005). Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital’. Revised version.
Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, W. F. (2006a). Neue Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital’.
Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, W. F. (2006b). Marx’s Learning Process: Against Correcting Marx with
Hegel. Rethinking Marxism, 18(4), 572–584.
Haug, W. F. (2013). Das ‘Kapital’ lesen – aber wie? Zur Philosophie und Epistemologie
der marxschen Kapitalismuskritik. Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, W. F. (2015). Marktwert II. In Historisch-kritisches Wörterbuch des
Marxismus (Vol. 8/II, pp. 1816–1824). Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, W. F. (2016). Lecciones de introducción a la lectura de El Capital, New
revised and expanded version, transl. W. F. Haug and S. Vollmer. Barcelona:
Laertes Trebol Negro.
Haug, W. F. (2017a). En la cueva del león. ¿Se puede leer El Capital de Karl Marx
a partir de sus Tesis sobre Feuerbach? In Memoria (pp. 28–34), 261, México.
Haug, W. F. (2017b). On the Need for a New English Translation of Marx’s
Capital. Socialism and Democracy, 31(1), 60–86.
Labriola, A. (1912). Socialism and Philosophy (Ernest Untermann, Trans.).
Chicago: Charles H. Keer & Company.
Labriola, A. (1973). Discorrendo di socialismo e di filosofía. Turín: Einaudi.
Marx, K. (1969) [1872]. Le Capital. Critique de l’économie politique, French
translation of Joseph Roy completely reviewed by Karl Marx. Paris:
Éditions sociales.
306 W. F. HAUG
Peter McLaughlin and Oliver Schlaudt
Technology and Science
What is the relation of science and technology? A common view is that
technology applies science—the view is sometimes even radicalized as:
Science is pursued for the sake of technology. Francis Bacon is often cited
in this connection: ‘Nature to be conquered must be obeyed’.1 The natu-
ral interpretation of this slogan is that, if you want to dominate nature,
you should pursue science, learn nature’s laws, and then obey them in
their application to technology. But we can also read the relation in the
other direction and say that since we do in fact regularly conquer nature in
technology, we must having been implicitly obeying her laws all the time;
and thus our technology already embodies natural laws. If we study what
is done in technology, we can learn about the laws of nature. Furthermore,
this view allows us to avoid speculations about the noble—or ignoble—
motives of individual scientists and to concentrate on the structural deter-
minants of social action (cf. Merton 1939). The interpretation of nature
Galileo visited the Arsenal in Venice, not to build better ships but to ‘phi-
losophize’, that is, to use his training in Aristotelian natural philosophy
and Archimedean mathematics to study technology and thereby learn
about nature.
This Galilean perspective on the relation of science and technology was
at the core of Marxist historiography of science in the first half of the
twentieth century as represented by Boris Hessen and Henryk Grossmann.2
Early historiography of science had made it clear that in spite of all the
proclamations in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries on the utility of
science for the improvement of production and the wealth of society, it
was only in the nineteenth century that science actually became useful for
production. Whereas traditional historians concluded that technology
was, therefore, irrelevant to an explanation of the Scientific Revolution of
the early modern age,3 Hessen and Grossmann viewed technology not as
the final cause of science but as the material basis of an experimental explo-
ration of nature. They saw in the development of (especially mechanical)
technology the basis and determining factor for the subsequent emer-
gence of a science of mechanics. To give an example, the production norm
of a transmission mechanism such as a clockwork expresses an abstract
notion of friction-free motion. This abstract notion is in a sense already
embodied in the technology as such.
What we are interested in here is the extent to which science can be
viewed as the analysis of technique/technology and the extent to which
the analysis of technology can be seen as the articulation or conceptualiza-
tion of the ‘real’ abstractions performed by technology. When we ask what
can be learned about nature or the study of nature from various human
practices, the concept of real abstraction might be useful, even if used in a
17 REAL ABSTRACTION IN THE HISTORY OF THE NATURAL SCIENCES 309
different way than it has been used in sociology. We shall propose a notion
of real abstraction for the study of the nature and history of the natural
sciences, especially with regard to their relation to technological practice.
Real Abstraction
The term ‘real abstraction’ was brought to currency by Alfred Sohn-Rethel
in Intellectual and Manual Labour (1978) to describe the fact that in the
exchange of goods people actually, but in general not consciously, abstract
from the use value of the commodity which they trade away. This means
that in the exchange itself, a commodity is used only as a means for obtain-
ing a different commodity, not as a means to the end that defines its own
use value or utility. The commodity is so to speak ‘frozen’ into pure quan-
tity and immutable substance. Even if the people involved in the exchange
of goods are not conscious of the abstraction from the commodity’s use
value, the abstraction still constitutes an objective feature of their actions.
In this sense the abstraction is real as opposed to being effected merely in
thought. This phenomenon is of philosophical importance according to
Sohn-Rethel because he holds the real abstraction, once the exchange of
goods becomes a widespread practice in a society, to impose a certain view
of the world on the members of this society. Real abstraction is thus similar
to the Kantian categories that structure experience or like a looking-glass
which shows us an image of the world in terms of numbers and general laws.
The mechanism by which the real abstraction that takes place in
exchange is translated into categories of thought, however, remains mys-
terious, as has been noted by many critics (e.g. Falk 1977: 393–394). We
think, nonetheless, that the notion of real abstraction can be made useful
for understanding the history of the natural sciences, and we will offer a
reading that permits us to use this concept without having to rely on such
obscurities. The basic idea is to view the exchange of commodities, from
which Sohn-Rethel derived the real abstraction, as just one special case of
a more general process of real abstraction. Thus any abstraction that is car-
ried out so to speak by hand rather than merely in thought may be called
a real abstraction.
Marx himself provides an instructive example. In the first chapter of
Capital Marx explains how in exchange one commodity, which in itself is
simply one particular use value among others, becomes the expression of
the economic value of another commodity: ‘use value becomes the form
of manifestation, the phenomenal form of its opposite, value. The bodily
310 P. MCLAUGHLIN AND O. SCHLAUDT
form of the commodity becomes its value form’. Marx illustrates this point
by comparing the exchange of goods of equal value to establishing an
equilibrium on the balance between objects of the same weight. He then
goes on saying (Marx and Engels 1975: 35, 66–67):
A sugar-loaf being a body, is heavy, and therefore has weight: but we can
neither see nor touch this weight. We then take various pieces of iron, whose
weight has been determined beforehand. The iron, as iron, is no more the
form of manifestation of weight, than is the sugar-loaf. Nevertheless, in
order to express the sugar-loaf as so much weight, we put it into a weight-
relation with the iron. In this relation, the iron officiates as a body represent-
ing nothing but weight. A certain quantity of iron therefore serves as the
measure of the weight of the sugar, and represents, in relation to the sugar-
loaf, weight embodied, the form of manifestation of weight. This part is
played by the iron only within this relation, into which the sugar or any
other body, whose weight has to be determined, enters with the iron. Were
they not both heavy, they could not enter into this relation, and the one
could therefore not serve as the expression of the weight of the other. When
we throw both into the scales, we see in reality, that as weight they are both
the same, and that, therefore, when taken in proper proportions, they have
the same weight. Just as the substance iron, as a measure of weight, repre-
sents in relation to the sugar-loaf weight alone, so, in our expression of
value, the material object, coat, in relation to the linen, represents value alone.
the sciences. The view which we want to put forward in this paper is that
things happened in the opposite way as usually conceived. That is, from an
historical perspective, the device, embodying a real abstraction, often
comes first and only afterwards is the concept of the quality it instanti-
ates derived.
fulcrum and force. What the author does is to develop general abstract
concepts in the study of technical devices which embody these abstrac-
tions. Theoretical analysis (science) arises here in a particular kind of study
of technique.
A special role in the construction of the Mechanical Problems is played
by the balance with unequal arms. This asymmetric balance, which became
common in Greece after the mid-fifth century, had a fixed counter-weight
and a moveable suspension point, which could be adjusted until the beam
reached equilibrium—unlike later Roman devices with a moveable coun-
terweight. This device is characterized as at once a balance and a lever. As
a balance, it establishes equilibrium or equality in which counteracting
forces mutually cancel out each other’s effects. And as a lever, it allows a
smaller weight (on the longer arm) to balance or overcome a greater
weight. In the Mechanical Problems, the asymmetric balance provides the
point of departure and the model for the cognitive development realized
in the treatise.
There are many technical devices embodying some form compensation
of weight by length or length by weight. The shadoof, a long pole with a
bucket on one end and a counterweight on the other, had long been in
use in Mesopotamia and Egypt in irrigation to lift water from a river or a
basin. The Macedonian army under Aristotle’s employer Phillip, by put-
ting counterweights on its long spear (sarissa), was able to increase the
effective length of the spear without reducing the maneuverability of the
phalanx. All such devices embody a ‘complementarity’ of weight and dis-
tance and make the experience possible that weights are balanced not only
by other weights (as in the symmetric balance) but also by lengths. The
abstraction from the dimensional difference between length and weight is
made by the device itself. The subsequent question will then be: When
and how is this real abstraction intellectually recognized and appropriated
in thought.
The answer to our first question as to how a technical device can ‘be
there’ without first being intended to serve the specific purpose that gives
it its name, hence simply, is that the device first served a different purpose,
as is exemplified by the shadoof and the sarissa. This answer probably holds
in general. Any material device can be used for various ends, including
ends they were not originally intended. A similar phenomenon is known
in evolutionary biology as exaptation. Biologists Gould and Vrba (1982)
introduced this term to account for traits that evolved for one function
and were later adapted for another. The French archaeologist, Sophie de
314 P. MCLAUGHLIN AND O. SCHLAUDT
Conclusion
The use of the concept of real abstraction in the history of science presup-
poses that technical devices can be studied to recognize such real abstrac-
tions and thus that the development of technology has a role in determining
the direction of scientific development—not as the final cause but as the
material basis or subject matter of science. Boris Hessen pointed to the
striking fact that the development of physics in the nineteenth century
from mechanics to thermodynamics to electrodynamics did not follow any
a priori immanent logic of physics but rather followed the actual develop-
ment of technology.5
It is worth mentioning that Sohn-Rethel is one of the few critics of
Hessen or Grossmann to correctly describe their view of the relation of
science and technology. In fact he criticized them specifically for believing
that science arises out of technology not for the sake of technology: ‘The
argumentation therefore leads involuntarily to the strange view that
machines generate natural sciences rather than the reverse’. And in another
paper he sharpens the critique: ‘After all, it is science that helps to build
machines, rather than the machines hatching out science, even mechanis-
tic science’.6 Sohn Rethel was one of the few to understand the thrust of
316 P. MCLAUGHLIN AND O. SCHLAUDT
the analyses of Hessen and Grossmann, but he failed to see the fruitfulness
of their position because he restricted real abstraction to the distribution
sphere. If there is a real abstraction in technique, then of course the
machines (with our help) can ‘hatch out’ science. This disregard for the
production sphere reflects a more general disdain of instrumental reason,
common in the Frankfurt School, which hinders any serious analysis of the
intellectual opportunities offered by the second reading of Bacon’s dic-
tum, which hints at a general dialectics of means and ends. Instrumental
reason need not be restricted to searching for appropriate means for given
ends, as Horkheimer would have it (1947: 3–4), but can also discover new
ends contained in given means as real abstractions.
Notes
1. ‘Natura enim non nisi parendo vincitur’ (Bacon [1620] 1858, Bk. I, §3).
2. Hessen (Social and Economic Roots) cites the opening lines of the Discorsi as
his first appendix. On the historical work of Hessen and Grossmann see
Freudenthal and McLaughlin (2009).
3. See especially Koyré (1943, 1948).
4. For a detailed account of this work and of the role Greek balances see Renn
and McLaughlin (2018).
5. See Hessen in Freudenthal and McLaughlin (2009: 78–82).
6. Sohn-Rethel (1973a: 85, 1973b: 37). A long footnote on Hessen and
Grossmann was not included in the English version of the book (1978).
References
Aristotle. (1936). Mechanical Problems. In W. S. Hett (Ed.), Aristotle: Minor
Works (pp. 329–411). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bacon, F. ([1620] 1858). Novum Organum. In J. Spedding, R. Ellis, & D. D.
Heath (Eds.), The Works of Francis Bacon (Vol. 1). London: Longmans.
De Beaune, S. A. (2008). L’homme et l’outil. L’invention technique durant la
préhistoire. Paris: CNRS Editions.
Falk, P. (1977). Review of R. W. Müller, Geld und Geist. Acta Sociologica,
20(4), 393–396.
Freudenthal, G., & McLaughlin, P. (Eds.). (2009). The Social and Economic Roots
of the Scientific Revolution: Texts by Boris Hessen and Henryk Grossmann. Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 278. New York: Springer.
17 REAL ABSTRACTION IN THE HISTORY OF THE NATURAL SCIENCES 317
Galilei, G. (1974). Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity and Force of
Gravity and Force of Percussion. Trans. with introduction and notes, by Stillman
Drake. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
Gould, S. J., & Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation – A Missing Term in the Science of
Form. Paleobiology, 8(1), 4–15.
Horkheimer, M. (1947). The Eclipse of Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
Koyré, A. (1943). Galileo and Plato. Journal of the History of Ideas, 4, 400–428.
Koyré, A. (1948). Les philosophes et la machine. I: L’appréciation du machinisme.
Critique (pp. 324–333), 3. [Reprint in (1961). Etudes de la pensee philosophique
(pp. 279–309). Paris: Armand Colin].
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1975). Collected Works (MECW) (Vol. 35). London:
Lawrence & Wishart.
Merton, R. K. (1939). Science and the Economy of Seventeenth Century England.
Science & Society, 3, 3–27.
Renn, J. and McLaughlin, P., (2018): The Balance, the Lever and the Aristotelian
Origins of Mechanics, in: R. Feldhay/J. Renn/M. Schemmel/M. Valleriani,
Emergence and Expansion of Pre-Classical Mechanics, New York: Springer,
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1973a). Geistige und körperliche Arbeit. Zur Theorie der gesell-
schaftlichen Synthesis. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1973b). Intellectual and Manual Labour. An Attempt at a
Materialistic Theory. Radical Philosophy, 6, 30–73.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1976). Das Geld, die bare Münze des Apriori. In P. Mattick,
A. Sohn-Rethel, & H. G. Haasis (Eds.), Beiträge zur Kritik des Geldes
(pp. 35–117). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1978). Intellectual and Manual Labour. A Critique of
Epistemology. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.
CHAPTER 18
Sergio Tischler
Introduction
Time in capitalism is a secularized and reified category. It is the expression
of a praxis determined by the power of general labor or abstract labor over
concrete labor, that is, a praxis whose synthesis is produced with Money as
a means (Sohn Rethel 2001. Tr.1). As a part of the form of value, time is
made of an objective abstraction, a real one, and it is also an alienated
category for domination. It is in no way neutral or detached from class
antagonism.
The revolutions which evolved from the so-called real socialism were
incapable of changing time in a radical manner, of generating a time eman-
cipated from that abstract and objective form, which would be an expres-
sion of collective self-determination of society. Those revolutions failed as
projects of human emancipation, and a central part of that failure concerns
that matter.2
Zapatismo was able to relocate the matter of anti-capitalist revolution
as the central human concern. It is not done from evocation of a
S. Tischler (*)
Autonomous University of Puebla, Puebla, Mexico
Mass support existed for the October events, but it was not of a single mind.
Millennialists, avant-gardists, and utopian dreamers of every sort were eager
to interpret the revolutionary future as their own. Bolshevism needed to
speak for all of these people, structuring their desires inside a historical con-
tinuum that, at the same time, contained their force. In the process of being
inserted into the temporal narrative of revolutionary history, the utopian
dimension of a wide variety of discourses was constrained and reduced.
(Buck-Morss 2004: 62)
carried along with its debris the idea of revolution. Maybe the great
achievement of zapatismo was rescuing the idea of revolution and of hope
from that ruined condition. It created an imaginary space for thinking the
change of the world in a different and fresh fashion, fed by an image of
revolution against the model that made its vertical and state-centered
manner hegemonic.
However, this idea of radical change does not imply the establishment
of a new model of revolution, neither the projection of a fixed image of
the future which must be achieved, unfolding some kind of sustained
truth in a series of partial assertions. On the contrary, it’s a commitment
to open and expand the category of revolution with the perspective that
revolution is a contradictory process exposed to the traps of the demise of
history in the different syntheses of power, and that the constitutive sub-
jectivity of those syntheses for the left if found in the idea of an avant-
garde, which presents the future as a fight for hegemony and the historical
totaling of time. The Zapatista expressions ‘A world where many worlds
fit’ and ‘Asking we walk’ are telling us about a different fighting experi-
ence, an experience where the image of the time does not refer to a social
relationship of domination/subjugation as a result of the process of total-
ing and subsumption of the concrete under the abstract.
Zapatismo rejects the image of time as hegemony, that is to say, the
image of time as a universal idea that is the denial of human self-
determination, just as it is presented by the social experience determined
by the power of money in capitalism, or by vertical and coercive organiza-
tion of social labor from state bureaucracy in the experiences of ‘real social-
ism’.5 In that sense, the Zapatista experience is a radical criticism of the
universal as an abstraction and as a form of power which arises and breeds
from the denial of social self-determination and from the assertion of the
world as social and class antagonism. However, it is a paradoxical criticism.
The paradox is presented by the image of a revolutionary army which rose
up to deny itself, whose aspiration is to disappear and not planting firmly
as an expression of power. The struggle of the EZLN is a struggle to create
a political time-space where the armed organization is no longer necessary
in the fight for emancipation. It considers itself as a moment—not the
main moment—of this process.
This idea can be extended to the initiatives related to other anti-capitalist
movements of the country. The Sixth Declaration of the Lacandon Jungle
of June 2005 can be an example. In these initiatives, it is intended that the
struggles are not only reduced to participate with specific requests in a
324 S. TISCHLER
The notation of time which arises in such contexts has been described as
task-orientation. It is perhaps the most effective orientation in peasant soci-
eties, and it remains important in village and domestic industries. (…) Three
points may be proposed about task-orientation. First, there is a sense in
which it is more humanly comprehensible than timed labour. The peasant or
labourer appears to attend upon what is an observed necessity. Second, a
community in which task-orientation is common appears to show least
demarcation between “labour” and “life”. Social intercourse and labour are
intermingled—the working-day lengthens or contracts according to the
task—and there is no great sense of conflict between labour and “passing the
time of day”. Third, to men accustomed to labour timed by the clock, this
attitude to labour appears to be wasteful and lacking in urgency. (Thompson
1979: 245)
And he continues:
time and space is part of this process.12 And the image which most pre-
cisely portraits this in terms of violence and social destruction is exposed
in the well-known Walter Benjamin’s Thesis IX on the Angel of History.
Against the idea of progress that represents time and history as a ‘chain of
events’, the Angel of History sees a ‘storm’ which throws ‘debris after
debris’ to his feet, writes Benjamin (2007: 29).
In any case, what we tried to explain in this section is the topic of the
homogeneous and abstract time of the form of value of social relations in
capitalism, in terms of antithesis and denial of time understood as an
expression of emancipated praxis. This is, that time as an abstract objectiv-
ity is the negation of the subject. The revolutions that led to ‘real social-
ism’ did not eliminate abstraction as a dominio relation or time as the
antithesis of social self-determination.
As stated previously, the theoretical novelty of the topic of time and eman-
cipation has a political character and is closely related to the historical
failure of the so-called real socialism; this fact brings with itself the ques-
tioning of the revolutionary theory which guided those revolutions and
states the question of why that concept of revolution failed as a project for
emancipation when realized as a political praxis.
A key aspect of this failure, speaking in general terms, is that political
abstraction and time as a part of such an abstraction/domination, far from
disappearing, were reconfigured in a new power constellation: domination
by means of market and law, whose central figure, the laborer as owner
and seller of working force and citizen, was replaced by the figure of the
state as a place of immediate identity between economics and politics,
expressed in the bureaucratic administration of world of work.
In capitalism, real abstraction and objective domination—which is pre-
sented as a dominion applied by the object, by things, and not in a direct
relation—negate the subject in the mercantile form of social relations, that
is, in labor as a dual category subsumed to the dominion of abstract labor.
Simultaneously, in the experience of ‘real socialism’, the subject is denied
in the category of labor organized by the socialist state as a vertical totality,
and the state unifies economics and politics in a bureaucratic and repres-
330 S. TISCHLER
sive manner, suppressing in the facts the individual and collective self-
determination of laborers.
This process of concentration of power was defined as necessary by the
revolutionary avant-garde in a route of human emancipation, being the
condition for the rationalization of labor and the development of the pro-
ductive force of society, which are the keys for building an emancipated
society. From this process emerged an identity which asserted the relation
state-party-labor as an expression of the abolition of social domination and
the realization of the revolutionary subject, but in reality it was the nega-
tion of the self-determination of such subject and the assertion of abstrac-
tion as a dominio relation in the fetished figures of the state bureaucracy
and the party.
In both historical experiences (capitalism and real socialism), alienated
praxis is determined by social relations which presuppose abstraction as a
social process that separates the subject from the object, and the latter, the
object, acquires autonomy in the form of a system or a totality which is the
negation of the former, the subject.
In capitalism, the identity of the subject with the object is something
similar to a dream of a full and free society which in fact presupposes the
tyranny of homogeneity as a dominio category.13 It appears as the phantas-
magoric result of a material ideology which is settled in the kingdom of
commodities. On the other hand, in ‘real socialism’, the identity appears
in the fetishism which accompanies the reversion of the subject into the
image of the state machinery which secures labor as an organic totality,
that is, a bureaucratic rationalization of the praxis. Both are ways which
deny creative and self-determinative activity of the society.
On the other hand, in capitalism, the form of value implies a totality
and a systematic totaling of the social relations which occur in an uncon-
scious manner, that is, in the reproduction of the object in itself, and it
acquires the form of an autonomous rationality. On the contrary, in the
state-centered project of ‘real socialism’, totality is pursued in a conscious
manner, and the state/party is presented as the central subject of this
process.14
Nonetheless, pursuing totality implied the maintenance of a power
constellation based on a ‘high and a low’—as said in Zapatista language—
and the prolongation of a vertical temporality inscribed within the abstract
form of the state, that is, within a temporality that was the result of a new
way of separation and tearing of the subject from the object—to say in
18 ZAPATISTA AUTONOMY: THE INVENTION OF TIME AS A DISCONTINUITY… 331
Walter Benjamin was the revolutionary thinker who unveiled with great
theoretical audacity the profound class secret from the idea of progress
and the traps which that idée-force supposed for an authentic revolutionary
transformation. In his Theses on the concept of history,15 he pointed out that
the idea of progress has as a basic structure on a homogeneous, empty
time, and that such a time is a dominio relation which through a mystified
form is presented in the idea of progress as something neutral. We may say
that, in some way, in this criticism Benjamin moves Marx’s analysis of time
as a part of the form of value of the social relations, to the criticism of the
idea progress and the idea universal history that it carries. The mystifica-
tion which occurs in the form of commodity and the form of value of the
social relations is moved to the mystification of universal history in the
idea of homogeneous and lineal time.
Against the image of revolution as the ‘train engine’ of progress, both
in the reformist version and in Leninism, Benjamin explains that revolu-
tion understood in those terms brings a historical ruin.16 Revolution, on
the other hand, must cut the continuum of history and it must not be its
realization, since this continuum is the prolongation of the dominio rela-
tions, something that leads us to the antagonist images of time of the
avant-garde and the avant-gardes at the beginning of the Russian
Revolution exposed by Buck-Morss. With the perspective of skipping the
historical continuum, Benjamin suggests the idea of a ‘now time’ as an
antithesis of homogenous and empty time. This would be the authentic
time of emancipation, the time of human self-determination which skips
the historical continuum.
With the idea of revolution as a ‘hand brake’ of the train engine of
progress, Benjamin updates Marx’s criticism to capitalism and presents an
332 S. TISCHLER
Afterword
The classic figure of the Latin American guerrilla fighter can be under-
stood as an image of the coexistence of two souls, of two times: the rebel-
lious time and the vertical time of the organization, which is represented
as the seed of a new state, a new historical synthesis.
In relation to this, it can be suggested that in the guerrilla revolutionary
experience, there developed a subjectivity linked to the hegemony of that
time over the rebellious time.
In a different way, in zapatismo, we can see a history against that his-
tory. A classic one is the political manifestation of power dialectics, of
revolutionary power understood in classical terms; the other, the Zapatista
one, implies the dialectics of emancipation, a dialectics that is not sus-
pended in another form of power while making a fetish of it, but it goes
further instead, to the bottom of the criticism of dominio relations.
And that is a process to reinvent time and revolution.
This article was translated by Anahí Prucca.
Notes
1. This case, and the ones specified in the document, is a personal translation
from Spanish into English (T.N.).
2. The Cuban case deserves a special consideration which, to some extent,
leaves it out of the generalization we just made.
3. Regarding the state as a form of the social relations of capitalism, see
Holloway (2002).
4. The centrality of the political organization of the struggles is emphatically
explained by Subcomandante Insurgente Moisés. Regarding this, see
EZLN (2015).
5. In fact, time as a time of collective self-determination was never a key mat-
ter for the revolutionary avant-gardes: the classic model which supposed
that the identity of the state with the people gained by the takeover of
power would allow a time managed rationally, where the antagonistic con-
tradictions would not continue to be of importance in the social
dynamics.
6. In that sense, it can be said that our experience in social change is limited,
though there certainly were some moments of splendor. From this comes
the idea that the criticism of what already exists must not be restricted by
those limits, fetishizing them as if they were the ultimate historical direc-
tion, but it must open the horizon of a greater change instead.
7. On the category of form as a fixation of the social flow, see Holloway
(2002).
336 S. TISCHLER
References
Adorno, T. (1975). Dialéctica negativa. Madrid: Taurus. In English. Retrieved
from https://rosswolfe.files.wordpress.com/2015/03/theodor-adorno-neg-
ative-dialectics.pdf.
Baronnet, B., Mora Bayo, M., & Stanhler-Sholk, R. (2011). Luchas “muy otras”.
Zapatismo y autonomía en las comunidades indígenas de Chiapas, Universidad
Autónoma Metropolitana, Universidad Autónoma de Chiapas, México, Centro
de Investigaciones y Estudios Superioresen Antropología Social (CIESAS).
Baschet, J. (2015). Adiós al capitalismo. Autonomía, sociedad del buen vivir y mul-
tiplicidad de mundos. Madrid: Ned Ediciones.
Benjamin, W. (2007). Sobre el concepto de historia. Tesis y fragmentos. Buenos Aires:
Piedras de Papel. In English. Retrieved from http://www.afoiceeomartelo.
com.br/posfsa/Autores/Benjamin,%20Walter/BENJAMIN,%20Walter%20
-%20On%20the%20Concept%20of%20History.pdf.
Bonefeld, W. (2013). El Estado y el capital: sobre la crítica de lo político. In
W. Bonefeld (Ed.), La razón corrosiva. Una crítica al Estado y al capital.
Herramienta Ediciones: Buenos Aires.
Buck-Morss, S. (2004). Mundo soñado y catástrofe. La desaparición de la utopía de
masas en el Este y el Oeste. Madrid: La Balsa de la Medusa. In English. Retrieved
from https://monoskop.org/images/a/ae/BuckMorss_Susan_Dreamworld_
and_Catastrophe_The_Passing_of_Mass_Utopia_in_East_and_West.pdf.
EZLN. (2015). El pensamiento crítico frente a la hidra capitalista I. Participación
de la Comisión Sexta del EZLN, México.
Gunn, R. (2005). En contra del materialismo histórico: el marxismo como un
discurso de primer orden. In A. Bonnet, J. Holloway, & S. Tischler (Eds.),
Marxismo abierto. Una versión europea y latinoamericana V. 1. Buenos Aires:
Ediciones Herramienta/Universidad Autónoma de Puebla. In English.
Retrieved from https://libcom.org/files/Bonefeld,%20Gunn%20and%20
Psychopedis%20-%20Open%20Marxism%20-%20Volume%202%20-%20
Theory%20and%20Practice.pdf.
Gunn, R. (2015). Lo que usted siempre quiso saber sobre Hegel y no se atrevió a pre-
guntar. Buenos Aires: Ediciones Herramienta/Benemérita Universidad
Autónoma de Puebla (BUAP).
Harvey, D. (1998). La condición de la posmodernidad. Investigación sobre los orí-
genes del cambio cultural. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu Editores.
Holloway, J. (2002). Cambiar el mundo sin tomar el poder. El significado de la revo-
lución hoy. Buenos Aires: Ediciones Herramienta/Universidad Autónoma de
338 S. TISCHLER