Contract As Empowerment Author(s) : Robin Kar Source: The University of Chicago Law Review, Spring 2016, Vol. 83, No. 2 (Spring 2016), Pp. 759-834 Published By: The University of Chicago Law Review
Contract As Empowerment Author(s) : Robin Kar Source: The University of Chicago Law Review, Spring 2016, Vol. 83, No. 2 (Spring 2016), Pp. 759-834 Published By: The University of Chicago Law Review
Contract As Empowerment Author(s) : Robin Kar Source: The University of Chicago Law Review, Spring 2016, Vol. 83, No. 2 (Spring 2016), Pp. 759-834 Published By: The University of Chicago Law Review
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The University of Chicago Law Review is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The University of Chicago Law Review
This Article offers a novel interpretation of contract law , which I call "con-
tract as empowerment. " On this view , contract law is neither a mere mechanism to
promote efficiency , as many economists suggest , nor a mere reflection of any famil-
iar moral norm - such as norms of promise keeping , property , or corrective justice.
Contract law is instead a mechanism of empowerment* it empowers people to use
legally enforceable promises as tools to influence other people's actions and thereby
to meet a broad range of human needs and interests. It also empowers people in a
special way , which reflects a moral ideal of equal respect for persons. This fact ex-
plains why contract law can produce genuine legal obligations and is not just a
system of coercion.
This Article introduces contract as empowerment and argues that it offers a
theory of contract with distinctive advantages over the alternatives. Contract as
empowerment is an interpretive theory : it is simultaneously descriptive , explaining
what contract law is, and normative , explaining what contract law should be. To
establish the theory's interpretive credentials , this Article identifies a core set of
doctrines and puzzles that are particularly well suited to testing competing inter-
pretations of contract law. It argues that contract as empowerment is uniquely ca-
pable of harmonizing this entire constellation of doctrines while explaining the le-
gally obligating force of contracts. Along the way , contract as empowerment offers
(l)a more penetrating account of the expectation damages remedy than exists in
the current literature , (2) a more compelling account of the consideration require-
ment , and (3) a concrete framework to determine the appropriate role of certain
doctrines - like unconscionability - that appear to limit freedom of contract.
The whole of this explanation is greater than the sum of its parts. Because of its
harmonizing power , contract as empowerment demonstrates how a broad range of
seemingly incompatible surface values in modern contract law can work together -
each serving its own distinctive but partial role - to serve a more fundamental
t Special thanks to the following people, who have each contributed to the develop-
ment of my thinking on these topics over the years, sometimes through formal readings of
drafts and sometimes through informal discussions: Elizabeth Anderson, Amitai Aviram,
Ian Ayres, Aditi Bagchi, Douglas Baird, Randy Barnett, Peter Benson, Kenworthey Bilz,
Brian Bix, Curtis Bridgeman, Richard Brooks, Marshall Cohen, Jules Coleman, Stephen
Darwall, Dhammika Dharmapala, Zev Eigen, Stephen Findlay, Claire Finkelstein, Nuno
Garoupa, Margaret Gilbert, Andrew Gold, Mark Greenberg, Jeffrey Helmreich, Barbara
Herman, Robert Hillman, Heidi Hurd, Aaron James, A. J. Julius, Avery Katz, Gregory
Keating, Gregory Klass, Russell Korobkin, Jody Kraus, John Lindo, Jeffrey Lipshaw, Daniel
Markovits, John Mikhail, Michael Moore, Liam Murphy, Nathan Oman, Michael Perry,
Margaret Jane Radin, Peter Railton, Donald Regan, Jennifer Rothman, Alan Schwartz,
Seana Shiffrin, Stephen Smith, Jason Solomon, Lawrence Solum, Suzanne Switzer, Thomas
Ulen, Lauren Willis, Gideon Yaffe, and Ekow Yankah. I would also like to thank Alexis
Dyschkant and Diedre Peters for their invaluable research assistance.
759
Introduction
2. Empowermen
breach
Conclusion
Introduction
1 Alan Schwartz and Robert E. Scott, Contract Theory and the Limits of Contract
Law , 113 Yale L J 541, 543 (2003).
22 Although the term "obligation" can be used in different ways, I believe this re-
quirement is a defining feature of its core meaning. I thus agree with Professor Stephen
Darwall that "[t]here can be no such thing as moral obligation and wrongdoing" - at least
in one core, familiar sense - "without the normative standing to demand and hold agents
accountable for compliance." Stephen Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality,
Respect , and Accountability 99 (Harvard 2006). Although people sometimes use the
terms "moral wrong" and "moral obligation" to refer to a wider class of phenomena, the
term "legal obligation" is almost never used so widely. When I ask whether contract laws
can produce "genuine legal obligations," I am therefore asking whether they can give
contracting parties the genuine authority to demand compliance with a contract that is
backed by the coercive power of the state.
23 This point has been made variously, and sometimes with different terminology,
by many theorists. See, for example, id at 91-118; Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and
Norms 80-84 (Oxford 1999) (describing legal obligations as generating exclusionary rea-
sons and exclusionary reasons as having a mandatory or required aspect); David O.
Brink, Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy , in Garrett Cullity
and Berys Gaut, eds, Ethics and Practical Reason 255, 259-61 (Clarendon 1997); H.L.A.
Hart, Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons , in H.L.A. Hart, Essays on Bentham:
Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory 243, 253 (Clarendon 1982) (describing le-
gal obligations as "peremptory" and tying this to Professor Joseph Raz's conception of an
exclusionary reason).
24 As Darwall correctly explains, the overriding or exclusionary features of obliga-
tion are only part of their authority, "since there can be requirements on us that no one
has any standing to require of us." Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint at 13 (cited
in note 22). Darwall explains that:
We are under a requirement of reason, for example, not to believe propositions
that contradict the logical consequences of known premises. But it is only in
certain contexts, say, when you and I are trying to work out what to believe to-
gether, that we have any standing to demand that we each reason logically,
and even here that authority apparently derives from a moral or quasi- moral
aspect: our having undertaken a common aim.
Id at 13-14.
It is this fact that leads Raz to propose that law's authority to generate exclusionary rea-
sons depends on its epistemic capacity to help people identify what they ought to do bet-
ter than they could on their own. Joseph Raz, Authority, Law, and Morality , in Joseph
Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics 210, 214
(Clarendon rev ed 1994):
The first two theses articulate what I shall call the service conception of au-
thority. They regard authorities as mediating between people and the right
reasons which apply to them, so that the authority judges and pronounces
what they ought to do according to right reason. The people on their part take
their cue from the authority whose pronouncements replace for them the force
of the dependent reasons.
But I agree with Darwall that this account fails to capture the authority of interpersonal
demands and so cannot be the right account of genuine legal obligations. See Darwall,
The Second-Person Standpoint at 12 n 25 (cited in note 22) ("In my view, failure to ob-
serve this distinction [between counsel and command] infects Joseph Raz's account of
authority.").
26 Speaking at the most general level, social contract theorists seek to account for
some normative concepts in terms of "principles that are, or would be, the object of a
suitable agreement between equals." Stephen Darwall, Introduction , in Stephen
Darwall, ed, Contractarianism / Contractualism 1, 1 (Blackwell 2003). There are two ma-
jor branches of social contract theory: the "contractarian" and "contractualist" branches.
"Contractarians take[] the [relevant] principles to result from rationally self-interested
bargaining," whereas "contractualists" take "the relevant agreement [to be] governed by
a moral ideal of equal respect, one that would be inconsistent, indeed, with bargaining
over fundamental terms of association in the way contractarianism proposes." Id at 4.
Contractualist theories can, in turn, be specified in a number of different ways. Promi-
nent versions of contractualism can be found in the works of Professors Stephen
Darwall, Immanuel Kant, John Rawls, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and Thomas Scanlon.
See id at 5-7. I myself am a contractualist about genuine legal obligations. I differ from
some other contractualists, however, in that I employ contemporary developments in
evolutionary game theory and moral psychology to specify the motives and complex
forms of social life that go into responding to genuine obligations.
27 A number of contractualists have suggested that most people have moral motiva-
tions of some kind. See, for example, Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint at 151-81
(cited in note 22) (describing the psychology of what he calls the "second-person stand-
point" as a feature of human nature that motivates action and that is often responsive to
the perceived authority of principles and interpersonal demands - not just the desirabil-
ity of outcomes); John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 46 (Belknap 1971). On this type of
view, each person beyond a certain age and possessing the requisite intellectual capacity
develops a sense of justice under normal social circumstances. In the course of their de-
velopment, ordinary people acquire a skill in judging things to be just and unjust, and in
supporting these judgments by reasons. Moreover, ordinarily people have some desire to
act in accord with these pronouncements and expect a similar desire on the part of oth-
ers. Clearly this moral capacity is extraordinarily complex. See T.M. Scanlon, What We
Owe to Each Other 191-97 (Belknap 1998) (suggesting that ordinary people are motivat-
ed to act not only rationally but also in ways that they can justify to others as conform-
ing to principles for the general regulation of behavior that others, similarly motivated,
cannot reasonably reject).
28 Kar, 84 Tex L Rev at 918-19 (cited in note 12).
29 For some examples of this scientific characterization relevant to law, see general-
ly id; John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls ' Linguistic Analogy and the
Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge 2011); John Mikhail, Uni-
versal Moral Grammar: Theory, Evidence and the Future , 11 Trends in Cognitive Sci 143
(2007). See also Rawls, A Theory of Justice at 502-03 (cited in note 27):
[0]ne might ask how it is that human beings have acquired a nature described
by these psychological principles. The theory of evolution would suggest that it
is the outcome of natural selection; the capacity for a sense of justice and the
moral feelings is an adaptation of mankind to its place in nature.
As it turns out, this form of life is poorly understood as the mere result of individuals
pursuing outcomes that they take to be personally desirable - no matter how one charac-
terizes people's individual utility functions. See generally Kar, 84 Tex L Rev 877 (cited in
note 12). I have argued, instead, that the natural function of the human sense of obliga-
tion (namely, what it was naturally selected for over the course of human evolution and
prehistory, and therefore what it is particularly well suited to achieve) is to allow people
to resolve social contract problems flexibly. See id at 878. Because of this fact, the human
sense of moral and legal obligations has some (admittedly fallible) tendencies to track
principles that meet a contractualist test. See Robin Bradley Kar, The Two Faces of Mo-
rality: How Evolutionary Theory Can Both Vindicate and Debunk Morality (with a Spe-
cial Nod to the Growing Importance of Law), in James E. Fleming and Sanford Levinson,
eds, Evolution and Morality 31, 60-65 (NYU 2012) (describing these tracking features of
the human sense of obligation). But see id at 77-92 (describing some systematic ways
that these psychological capacities apparently fail to track the right properties and in-
stead generate what I call "moral illusions"). Hence, I accept on empirical grounds that
ordinary people are motivated to treat some other people as genuine sources of obliga-
tions and to interact with them in ways that exhibit noninstrumental forms of respect.
It would be nice if these psychological facts inclined people to treat all humans in
this way, but our evolutionary history appears to have generated some natural tenden-
cies toward parochialism instead. See Robin Bradley Kar, The Psychological Foundations
of Human Rights , in Dinah Shelton, ed, The Oxford Handbook of International Human
Rights Law 104, 129-34 (Oxford 2013). As is evident from both world history and the
psychological literature on in-group/out-group favoritism, many people are naturally in-
clined to limit this form of respect to perceived in- group members and deny it to some
perceived out-group members. See, for example, Naoki Masuda, Ingroup Favoritism and
Inter group Cooperation under Indirect Reciprocity Based on Group Reputation , 311 J
Theoretical Bio 8, 9 (2012). I have argued that the law (and especially the recent emer-
gence of international law) can nevertheless promote the extension of these motivations
to more human beings. See Kar, The Psychological Foundations of Human Rights at
141-42 (cited in note 29).
30 For a detailed description of how this distinctive form of human social life and
interaction is structured, see Kar, The Psychological Foundations of Human Rights at
134-40 (cited in note 29). Although that article is focused on how international law can
promote this form of social interaction among otherwise parochially inclined people, it
describes the psychology and structure of social interaction among people with a sense of
interpersonal obligation and how these psychological attitudes work to resolve problems
of cooperation in great detail.
34 I thank Professor Brian Bix for pushing me to clarify this exception in the initial
statement of the theory. Because contract as empowerment is rooted in a more general
account of obligation, it does not rule out the possibility of other grounds for the legal
enforcement of some other classes of promises. Indeed, I outline some of those other rea-
sons elsewhere. See, for example, Part III.B. Contract as empowerment does, however,
identify a distinctive class of empowerment interests, which can be cited in a special con-
tractualist explanation for why most contract-law rules look the way that they do.
35 I would like to thank Professor Dan Markovits for pressing me to clarity these
different definitions of empowerment and the relations between them.
36 This does not mean that contract-law rules must be equally empowering. Consider,
in this regard, Rawls's famous argument for the maximin principle, which endorses a prin-
ciple for the regulation of the basic structure of society that endorses certain forms of
economic inequality so long as these inequalities are part of a system of social coopera-
tion that conduces to the advantage of the least well off. Rawls, A Theory of Justice at
152-57 (cited in note 27). Rawls's argument for the maximin principle is a contractualist
argument, and it suggests that certain inequalities are in fact justifiable to each person.
In the case of contract law, it is possible that rules that are unequally empowering in
some ways are still ones that no one could reasonably reject in light of the available al-
ternatives - either because the ideal of equal empowerment is too difficult or costly to
achieve in practice or because the system of rules provides those who are subject to it
with advantages that outweigh the inequalities that persist. What is important about
the contractualist standpoint is, however, the baseline. Deviations from equal empower-
ment must be justified to each person , viewed as free and equal moral agents. On this
view, the mere fact that a system of rules conduces to the advantage of each is not
enough to outweigh unequal empowerment unless every alternative set of rules that is
more equally empowering is even worse for each subject of the inequality.
37 For the classic statement of promise-based accounts of contract, see Charles
Fried, Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation 7-27 (Harvard 1981). For
a more recent and wide-ranging discussion, see generally Symposium, Contract as Prom-
ise at 30: The Future of Contract Theory , 45 Suffolk U L Rev 601 (2012).
3® See Part III.B.
39 See Part III.B.
40 See Part III.A.
41 This is an issue because the fact that something is morally obligatory does
erally mean that it is morally permissible to use state coercion to force moral a
fact can create special problems for normative theories of contract, because co
typically allows expectation damages or specific performance that goes beyond
needed to compensate parties for any harms caused by their reliance. It can the
pear that contract remedies violate some moral limitations on the law, such as Joh
Mill's famous "harm principle" - or the principle that the law should get involved
moral wrongs that generate harms. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty , in John Stuart
Liberty and Other Writings 1, 13 (Cambridge 1989) (Stefan Collini, ed). For go
sions of these issues, see Stephen A. Smith, Contract Theory 69-78 (Oxford
dressing moral objections to promissory theories). See also generally Brian H.
ries of Contract Law and Enforcing Promissory Morality: Comments on Charles
Suffolk U L Rev 719 (2012).
A2ś For a discussion of the will-based theory of contract, see Duncan Kenne
the Will Theory to the Principle of Private Autonomy : Lon Fuller's " Conside
Form", 100 Colum L Rev 94, 115 (2000) ("The will theory of contract liability
all the rules of law that compose the law of contracts can be developed from
proposition that the law of contract protects the wills of the contracting parties.
R. Cohen, The Basis of Contract , 46 Harv L Rev 553, 554-58, 575-78 (1933)
theory was more central to nineteenth-century common-law thought tha
thought. See Max Radin, Contract Obligation and the Human Will , 43 Colum L
575-77 (1943) (discussing the centrality of the will theory to nineteenth
thought). As I explain in Part III.C.l, the importance of the will-based theory t
law is, however, still granted in some form in almost all modern theories of cont
43 See Part III (offering empowerment-based accounts of, among other thin
mandatory aspects of contract remedies, the consideration requirement, the im
of good faith and fair dealing, the various objective approaches to interpretatio
existence of some market regulations).
60 See, for example, Restatement (Third) of Property: Wills and Other Donative
Transfers §§ 3.1-3.9 (1999) (addressing the execution of wills); Restatement (Third) of
Trusts §§ 10-16 (2003) (addressing the creation of trusts).
51 For classic works that develop aspects of the view that contracts should be un-
derstood to protect promisees' reliance interests, see generally P.S. Atiyah, The Rise and
Fall of Freedom of Contract (Clarendon 1979); Grant Gilmore, The Death of Contract
(Ohio State 1974); L.L. Fuller and William R. Perdue Jr, The Reliance Interest in Con-
tract Damages: 1, 46 Yale L J 52 (1936). The idea that reliance interests are important to
contracts goes back even further, however. For example, even before publication of § 90
of the Restatement (First) of Contracts, some people - like Professor Samuel Williston -
were inclined to view reliance as a substitute for consideration, thus qualifying promises
as legally enforceable contracts. See Peter Linzer, et al, eds, A Contracts Anthology 339-
49 (Anderson 2d ed 1995) (representing Williston's comments from the American Law
Institute debates).
S2 See Part III.B.
53 In saying this, I am using the term "true contract" in a way that differs fro
how the Restatement (Second) of Contracts defines "contract." The Restatement
fines a "contract" as "a promise or a set of promises for the breach of which the
gives a remedy, or the performance of which the law in some way recognizes as a
ty." Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 1 (1981). This definition is thus broad enou
to include certain claims that I do not consider claims for true breaches of contr
for example, many claims for promissory estoppel or covenants. I use a diffe
terminology than the Restatement because I believe that the best interpretation of
these different legal claims shows them to reflect interests that are fundamentally dif-
ferent. It aids the understanding to keep these distinctions clear, rather than viewing
every legally enforceable promise as a true contract. Indeed, keeping these distinctions
clear would likely be helpful for courts as well.
54 Schwartz and Scott, 113 Yale L J at 543 (cited in note 1).
55 Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 118 (cited in note 3).
56 Id. Benson further explains:
In common law jurisdictions at least, there is at present no generally accept-
ed theory or even family of theories of contract. To the contrary, there exist
only a multiplicity of competing theoretical approaches, each of which, by its
very terms, purports to provide a comprehensive yet distinctive understanding
of contract but which, precisely for this reason, is incompatible with the
others.
Id.
57 Id at 119.
58 See, for example, Fried, Contract as Promise at 28-39, 103-09 (cited in note 37)
(suggesting that the consideration requirement and unconscionability doctrines present
special problems for the coherence of modern contract law); Seana Valentine Shiffrin,
The Divergence of Contract and Promise , 120 Harv L Rev 708, 722-24 (2007) (discussing
some puzzling features about why the standard expectation damages remedy diverges
from the morality of promise); Charles J. Goetz and Robert E. Scott, Enforcing Promises:
An Examination of the Basis of Contract , 89 Yale L J 1261, 1261-64 (1980) (discussing
the puzzling nature of the consideration requirement and standard remedial rules);
Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice , 89 Yale L J 472, 472-75
(1980) (addressing the distinctive and potentially puzzling role of substantive fairness
concerns in contract law).
59 See, for example, Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 153 (cited in note 3) ("No
doctrine of the common law of contract is more distinctive of it or longer and more con-
tinuously established than the requirement of consideration."); id at 121 ("The link be-
tween consideration and the availability of the expectation measure is taken to be the
central and distinguishing feature of contractual liability."). See also Douglas Baird, Re-
constructing Contracts 3 (Harvard 2013) (noting that "[f]or Holmes, the law of contract
revolved around three central ideas" - including the consideration requirement, the cen-
trality of the expectation measure of damages, and the various objective approaches to con-
tract formation); id at 5 (suggesting that "[t]he core principles that Holmes put forward [as
definitive of the core of contract] are still very much with us, but their logic and limits
are now much better understood," and organizing the reconstruction of contract law around
these basic principles and questions); Smith, Contract Theory at 387 (cited in note 41):
[T]he main reason contract theorists have devoted special attention to reme-
dies is that thinking about remedies raises important theoretical questions. . . .
[T]he analytic debate about whether contractual obligations are best under-
stood as promises, reliance-based obligations or something else [ ] has been
conducted, to a significant degree, as a debate about remedies. So too, what was
earlier described as the normative debate about whether contractual obligations
are justified on the basis of individual rights or social utility [ ] has frequently al-
so been conducted, particularly in recent years, as a debate about remedies.
(citation omitted). The claim that doctrines policing bargains for contractual fairness are
partly definitive of contract law is more controversial. But as I argue in Part III.C.2, his-
tory suggests that the actual rules governing contractual exchanges have typically re-
flected some blend of commitments to contractual freedom and fair exchange. It is thus
better to consider this feature of contract law as part of the relevant explanandum.
60 See Part III.B.
61 See Benson, The Unity of Contract at 153 (cited in note 3).
62 With respect to the consideration requirement, Professor Grant Gilmore pro
sized its demise. Gilmore, The Death of Contract at 76-81 (cited in note 51). Prof
Charles Fried has argued for its abolishment. Fried, Contract as Promise at 28-39 (ci
note 37). In 1981, Professor Charles L. Knapp noted that promissory estoppel, which
nates the consideration requirement and allows for reliance damages, had "become pe
the most radical and expansive development of this century in the law of promissory li
ity." Charles L. Knapp, Reliance in the Revised Restatement: The Proliferation of Prom
ry Estoppel , 81 Colum L Rev 52, 53 (1981). Yet in a review of these developments a
two decades later, Knapp suggested that a "reassessment appear[ed] to be in order
that "1980 may have been the high-water mark for promissory estoppel." Char
Knapp, Rescuing Reliance: The Perils of Promissory Estoppel , 49 Hastings L J 1191, 1192
(1998). As for the standard contractual remedies, some theorists like Professor Seana
Shiffrin have argued on moral grounds that specific performance may be a more appro-
priate remedy than expectation damages. Shiffrin, 120 Harv L Rev at 722-24 (cited in
note 58). Nonetheless, the standard remedy for breach of contract is still expectation
damages. See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 347 (1981) (defining the general
measure of damages as the loss in value caused by breach, plus any incidental and con-
sequential losses, less any costs and losses that were avoided).
63 See, for example, Kronman, 89 Yale L J at 473 (cited in note 58) ('There are, in
fact, many rules of contract law that are deliberately intended to promote a distributional
end of some sort."); Elizabeth Anderson, Toward a Post Cold-War Political Economy
(Left2Right, Jan 9, 2005), archived at http://perma.cc/F7XA-X6K8 (describing these ten-
sions as integral parts of advanced capital market economies and noting that we therefore
"tend to think that the economies of the advanced democracies in North America and
Europe are 'mixed' in some kind of combination of laissez-faire capitalism and socialism").
64 See, for example, Ian Ayres, Regulating Opt-Out: An Economic Theory of Altering
Rules , 121 Yale L J 2032, 2035 (2012) (defining mandatory and default rules).
65 See, for example, Schwartz and Scott, 113 Yale L J at 619 (cited in note 1) ( The
welfare- maximization goal that we advance . . . cannot support many of the mandatory
rules that today govern much contracting behavior between firms."); id:
A normative theory of contract law that takes party sovereignty seriously
shows that much of the expansion of contract law over the last fifty years has
been ill-advised. Contract law today is composed of a few default rules, many
default standards, and a number of mandatory rules. Most of the mandatory
rules should be repealed or reduced to defaults.
66 Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 356(1) (1981).
70 See, for example, Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938 § 6(a), 52 Stat 1060, 1062-63,
codified as amended at 29 USC § 206(a) (setting forth minimum hourly wages for em-
ployees). See also 26 USC §§ 207, 212, 215 (setting forth maximum-hour limitations,
child labor provisions, and other employment regulations).
71 US Const Amend XIII, § 1 ("Neither slavery nor involuntary servitude, except as
a punishment for crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted, shall exist
within the United States, or any place subject to their jurisdiction.").
72 UCC § l-302(b) (ALI 2012) ('The obligation! ] of good faith . . . may not be dis-
claimed by agreement."); Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 205 (1981) ("Every con-
tract imposes upon each party a duty of good faith and fair dealing in its performance
and its enforcement.").
73 Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 119 (cited in note 3).
74 See id.
75 For one such prominent criticism, see Robert E. Scott and George G. T
Embedded Options and the Case against Compensation in Contract Law , 104
Rev 1428. 1434-56 (2004).
™ See Part III.C.2.
77 See Smith, Contract Theory at 215 (cited in note 41).
78 See note 58 and accompanying text.
7y See note 56 and accompanying text.
80 See Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 118-19 (cited in note 3).
82 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 347 (1981); Benson, The Unity of Con-
tract Law at 119 (cited in note 3).
83 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 347, 359-60 (1981).
84 This is because there has not yet been any harm caused to the victim of the breach.
For a classic discussion, see Fuller and Perdue, 46 Yale L J at 57-66 (cited in note 51) (dis-
cussing the purposes behind awarding contract damages, which especially include protec-
tion of reliance interests and protection from the harms caused by reliance on breached
contracts); id at 52-53 ("Yet in this case we 'compensate' the plaintiff by giving him some-
thing he never had. This seems on the face of things a queer kind of 'compensation.'").
85 See, for example, Joshua Greene and Jonathan Baron, Intuitions about D
Marginal Utility , 14 J Behav Dec Making 243, 243-44 (2001) (describing how s
judgments about the desirability of money show that money typically has
marginal utility).
86 This may be because the millionaire is rationally responding to tne increased
liquidity and financial insurance that his other assets bring. There is now, however, a
solid and growing body of evidence that poverty causes risk aversion and time dis-
counting that cannot be attributed to the relative absence of factors like these. See
generally Johannes Haushofer and Ernst Fehr, On the Psychology of Poverty , 344 Sci-
ence 862 (2014).
87 It may, in fact, be less, because the writer was not looking for other work and did
not have any other commercial opportunities on the horizon.
88 I thank Professor Robert Hillman for pressing me on this point.
89 Fuller and Perdue, 46 Yale L J at 60 (cited in note 51) ("[If] we take into ac-
count 'gains prevented' by reliance, that is, losses involved in foregoing the opportuni-
ty to enter other contracts, the notion that the rule protecting the expectancy is adopt-
ed as the most effective means of compensating for detrimental reliance seems not at
all far-fetched.").
90 Id at 62.
9i Id at 61.
92 See Michael S. Moore, Placing Blame : A General 1 heory of the Criminal Law
186-87, 225-29 (Oxford 2010).
93 See, for example, Daniel Kahneman, A Psychological Perspective on Economics ,
93 Am Econ Rev Papers & Proceedings 162, 162-65 (2003) (reviewing experimental evi-
dence of some systematic irrationality in human psychology); id at 162:
No one ever seriously believed that all people have rational beliefs and make
rational decisions all the time. The assumption of rationality is generally un-
derstood to be an approximation, which is made in the belief (or hope) that de-
partures from rationality are rare when the stakes are significant, or that they
will disappear under the discipline of the market.
For an important discussion of some consequences of these facts for law, see generally
Korobkin and Ulen, 88 Cal L Rev 1051 (cited in note 31).
94 See, for example, J. Peter Neary, Presidential Address: Globalization and Market
Structure , 1 J Eur Econ Assn 245, 245 (2003) (reviewing the "economic aspects of globali-
zation" and arguing "that they cannot be satisfactorily addressed in perfectly or monopo-
listically competitive models").
95 For a nice discussion of such costs, see Nathan B. Uman, Markets as a Moral
Foundation for Contract Law , 98 Iowa L Rev 183, 190 & n 31 (2012):
The deeper problem with an economic defense of markets is the ubiquity of
transaction costs. . . . Market actors in the real world face ubiquitous infor-
mation costs, bargaining costs, search costs, and the like. These transaction
costs cannot be dismissed as negligible frictions. . . . Indeed, one study conclud-
ed that roughly forty percent of the entire U.S. economy consisted of private
transaction costs.
96 This point about approximation follows from two observations about microeco-
nomic theory as applied to questions of price determination and market equilibria. The
first is that "[t]he actions of buyers and sellers naturally move markets toward the equi-
librium of supply and demand." N. Gregory Mankiw, Principles of Microeconomics 77
(Cengage 7th ed 2014). To the extent that markets are dynamic and real market prices
are in flux, real market prices should therefore tend merely to approximate market equi-
librium prices. See Jean-Philippe Bouchaud, J. Doyne Farmer, and Fabrizio Lillo, How
Markets Slowly Digest Changes in Supply and Demand , in Thorsten Hens and Klaus
Reiner Schenk-Hoppe, eds, Handbook of Financial Markets: Dynamics and Evolution 57,
148 (Elsevier 2009). Second, the proposition that market prices naturally move toward
market equilibria is premised on several theoretical idealizations, which have been chal-
lenged in the main text - for example, that there is perfect market competition, rational
action, complete information, and an absence of market externalities. See Mankiw, Prin-
ciples of Microeconomics at 47-88 (cited in note 96). Deviations like these need not under-
mine the claim that prices naturally move toward the market equilibrium. See generally,
for example, Aldo Rustichini, Mark A. Satterthwaite, and Steven R. Williams, Convergence
to Efficiency in a Simple Market with Incomplete Information , 62 Econometrica 1041 (1994)
(arguing that some deviations between actual trading behavior and true preferences,
which might otherwise undermine the efficiency of a market, tend to vanish as market size
increases). Still, facts like these suggest that real market prices are better understood as
tending toward approximation than toward idealization. See, for example, Angus Deaton
and Guy Laroque, On the Behaviour of Commodity Prices , 59 Rev Econ Stud 1, 4 (1992)
("For most of the thirteen commodity prices . . . the behaviour of prices from one year to
the next conforms to the predictions of the theory about conditional expectations and
conditional variances.") (emphasis added). There is, finally, some empirical and theoreti-
cal evidence that market prices can deviate more sharply from those expected by ideal
microeconomic theory in some contexts. See, for example, Kent D. Daniel, David Hirshleifer,
and Avanidhar Subrahmanyam, Over confidence, Arbitrage, and Equilibrium Asset Pric-
ing, 56 J Fin 921, 957 (2001) (explaining that, in the context of securities markets, "mis-
valuation of industry or market-wide factors persists"); Pinelopi Koujianou Goldberg and
Michael M. Knetter, Good Prices and Exchange Rates: What Have We Learned ?, 35 J
Econ Lit 1243, 1244 (1997) ("|T|t appears that the local currency prices of foreign products
do not respond fully to exchange rates"). See also generally Ivana Kubieová and Luboš
Komárek, The Classification and Identification of Asset Price Bubbles , 61 Czech J Econ &
Fin 34 (2011) (discussing the classification of price bubbles and ways to identify them).
97 For a classic discussion of this normalizing function, see F.A. Hayek, The Use of
Knowledge in Society , 35 Am Econ Rev 519, 519 (1945):
The peculiar character of the problem of a rational economic order is deter-
mined precisely by the fact that the knowledge of the circumstances of which
we must make use never exists in concentrated or integrated form, but solely
as the dispersed bits of incomplete and frequently contradictory knowledge
which all the separate individuals possess.
See also id at 526-27 ("We must look at the price system as such a mechanism for com-
municating information if we want to understand its real function. ... In abbreviated
form, by a kind of symbol, only the most essential information is passed on, and passed
on only to those concerned.").
100 See, for example, Daryl J. Levinson, Rights Essentialism and Remedial Equili-
bration , 99 Colum L Rev 857, 859 (1999) ("[T]he centrality of efficient breach to contract
theory has led us to think of the obligation of contract as the choice between performing
and breaching at a price.").
101 See, for example, Richard Craswell, Contract Remedies, Renegotiation, and the
Theory of Efficient Breach , 61 S Cal L Rev 629, 636 & n 9 (1988); Robert L. Birmingham,
Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency , 24 Rutgers L Rev 273,
281 (1970), citing Samuel Williston, 5 A Treatise on the Law of Contracts § 1338 at 3762-
63 (Baker, Voorhis rev ed 1937).
102 Craswell, 61 S Cal L Rev at 634 (cited in note 101). To use the language of eco-
nomics, the costs of any such breaches are thereby effectively "internalized" by the
breaching parties.
103 Daniel Friedmann, The Efficient Breach Fallacy , 18 J Legal Stud 1, 3 (1989). As
Professor Jules L. Coleman has explained:
We can distinguish between Pareto optimality and Pareto superiority. ... A
state of affairs S is Pareto superior to another, A, if and only if no one prefers A
to S and at least one person prefers S to A. The notion of Pareto optimality is
then defined with respect to Pareto superiority. A state of affairs S is Pareto
optimal provided there is no state of affairs Sn that is Pareto superior to it.
Jules L. Coleman, Book Review, The Grounds of Welfare , 112 Yale L J 1511, 1516 (2003).
Kaldor- Hicks efficiency is defined in slightly different terms: "One state of affairs, S, is
Kaldor- Hicks efficient to another, A, if and only if the winners under S could compensate
the losers such that, after compensation, no one would prefer A to S and at least one per-
son would prefer S to A." Id at 1517.
104 See, for example, Richard A. Posner, Let Us Never Blame a Contract Breaker , 107
Mich L Rev 1349, 1353 (2009) ("Involuntary breaches are often inefficient: the promisor
miscalculated his ability to comply with the contractual terms to which he had agreed").
105 See, for example, Richard R.W. Brooks, The Efficient Performance Hypothesis ,
116 Yale L J 568, 578-79 (2006) (discussing how combinations of remedies other than
expectation damages can be "equally efficient and potentially more consistent with the
other normative understandings of contract enforcement"); Ian Ayres and Kristin
Madison, Threatening Inefficient Performance of Injunctions and Contracts , 148 U Pa L
Rev 45, 56 (1999) ("While it is nigh-on impossible to construct a single damage rule that
will induce efficient behavior along all possible dimensions, giving defendants the op-
tions of inalienability and additur leads toward more efficient plaintiff precaution and,
under certain conditions, more efficient defendant reliance.") (citation omitted); Ian
Ayres and Robert Gertner, Strategic Contractual Inefficiency and the Optimal Choice of
Legal Rules , 101 Yale L J 729, 760-62 (1992) (demonstrating that different damages re-
gimes would be more efficient in different circumstances). For a useful discussion, see
Smith, Contract Theory at 120 (cited in note 41).
106 Smith, Contract Theory at 120 (cited in note 41) ("As economists themselves have
pointed out, ... if performance of a particular contractual obligation is indeed inefficient,
the relevant contracting parties will have incentives to renegotiate or 'bargain arounď a
rule of specific performance so as to reach the efficient result.").
!07 Id at 120-24.
108 See Eric A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Contract Law after Three Decades: Suc-
cess or Failure ?, 112 Yale L J 829, 835 (2003) (noting that the possibility of renegotiation
prior to performance has proved problematic for efficient breach theorists because effi-
cient performance will occur regardless of the remedy when renegotiation costs are low
enough).
109 Professors Robert Scott and George Triantis have, for example, argued that the
rule disfavoring penalty liquidated damages and specific performance in favor of expecta-
tion damages is sometimes less efficient than one that threatens punishment or that allows
private parties a greater role in assessing option prices for breach. Scott and Triantis, 104
Colum L Rev at 1480-86 (cited in note 75). But as these authors have freely acknowl-
edged, their argument suggests that the standing law of contract remedies cannot be
grounded purely in efficiency concerns. Id at 1428 ("[T]his Article [ ] makes the case
against the expectation damages default rule."). Professor William S. Dodge has similar-
ly argued that efficiency considerations favor punitive damages for willful breaches. See
generally William S. Dodge, The Case for Punitive Damages in Contracts , 48 Duke L J
629 (1999). But this too is not the law. Hence, to whatever extent arguments like these
have merit, contract as empowerment offers a better , and not just an equally compelling,
118 Scanlon presents an argument that no one could reasonably reject a moral rule
that requires performance in these circumstances, but his argument is rooted in the val-
ue of assurance, not empowerment. See generally Scanlon, Promises and Contracts (cited
in note 116).
119 See Shiffrin, 120 Harv L Rev at 709 (cited in note 58) ("[TJhe legal norms regu-
lating these promises diverge in substance from the moral norms that apply to them.
This divergence raises questions about how the moral agent is to navigate both the legal
and moral systems.").
120 gee F. Andrew Hessick, Standing, Injury in Fact, and Private Rights , 93 Cornell
L Rev 275, 306-07 (2008).
by definition promises that seek nothing in return and, hence, are not being used
duce others to engage in any reciprocally advantageous exchanges. The stability o
ern markets in no way depends on enforcing these promises, and there are no oth
ous, large-scale social welfare benefits that depend on their enforcement. The or
costs of their enforcement are therefore more likely to outweigh any benefits. By p
ing at least a plausible rationale for the consideration doctrine, efficiency theori
thus claim a second important explanatory advantage over promise-based theorie
125 Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 71 (1981). The present theory also recom-
mends a further limitation to promises that reasonably require legal enforcement to in-
fluence action. This recommendation rules out the legal enforceability of most social
promises, and it is largely consistent with the state of the law. I will, however, discuss
this limitation only later. See Part III.B.
126 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 71, comment b (1981) ("[A] mere pre-
tense of bargain does not suffice, as where there is a false recital of consideration.").
There are some exceptions to this rule, for things like option contracts, but I discuss
those exceptions separately in Part III.B.3.
127 See Wessman, 29 Loyola LA L Rev at 774-75 (cited in note 68).
128 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 71 (1981).
129 17 Ind 29 (1861).
130 Id at 30.
131 Id at 32.
of the trust) can be ascertained from (a) the will itself; or (b) an existing in-
strument properly incorporated by reference into the will; or (c) facts referred
to in the will that have significance apart from their effect upon the disposition
of the property bequeathed or devised by the will.
136 This follows from the standard definition of consideration. See Restatement (Sec-
ond) of Contracts § 71 (1981).
137 See, for example, Nancy S. Kim, Wrap Contracts: Foundations and Ramifications
6-16 (Oxford 2013) (describing various theories for why contracts should be enforced).
138 See Scanlon, Promises and Contracts at 105-11 (cited in note 116).
139 See, for example, Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 131 (cited in note 3);
Katz, Book Review, 81 U Chi L Rev at 2046 (cited in note 99) ("The key feature of con-
tract law, as opposed to the other standard first-year subjects, is that it affords private
parties the power of lawmaking. Contractual obligations are primarily created by decen-
tralized nonstate actors pursuing their own goals and plans."); Elizabeth Anderson, The
Ethical Limitations of the Market , 6 Econ & Phil 179, 180 (1990) ('The most important
ideal that the modern market attempts to embody is a particular conception of free-
dom."); G.H.L. Fridman, Freedom of Contract, 2 Ottawa L Rev 1, 1 (1967) ("One of the
fundamental dogmas of the law is that everyone is free to contract as he wishes, as long
as no illegality is involved."); Friedrich Kessler, Contracts of Adhesion - Some Thoughts
about Freedom of Contract , 43 Colum L Rev 629, 630 (1943) ("[Fļreedom of contract does
not commend itself for moral reasons only; it is also an eminently practical principle. It
is the inevitable counterpart of a free enterprise system.").
140 See Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 198-99 (cited in note 3).
141 See, for example, Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 208 (1981) (stating the
unconscionability doctrine); Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 201 (1981) (presenting
the modified objective approach to interpretation); Restatement (Second) of Contracts
§ 205 (1981) ("Every contract imposes upon each party a duty of good faith and fair deal-
ing in its performance and its enforcement."); Schwartz and Scott, 113 Yale L J at 619
(cited in note 1) (discussing the growth of mandatory rules in modern contract law). See
also Kronman, 89 Yale L J at 472-511 (cited in note 58) (describing numerous limita-
tions on contracting that arise to promote public policy or substantive fairness).
142 See, for example, Cass R. Sunstein and Richard H. Thaler, Libertarian Paternal-
ism Is Not an Oxymoron , 70 U Chi L Rev 1159, 1160 (2003) ("According to the conven-
tional wisdom, libertarians cannot possibly embrace paternalism, and paternalists abhor
libertarianism."); Richard A. Epstein, Unconscionability: A Critical Reappraisal , 18 J L
& Econ 293, 293-95 (1975).
143 See, for example, Richard A. Epstein, In Defense of the Contract at Will , 51 U Chi
L Rev 947, 947 (1984) (viewing "government regulation" as in "persistent tension" with
"private ordering").
144 See, for example, id.
145 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 201-04 (1981) (providing principles for
interpreting contracts, including the principle that when parties attach different mean-
ings to an agreement, it will be interpreted in accordance with the meaning of one party
if the other party knew or had reason to know of the meaning attached by the former).
146 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 178-96 (1981).
147 See, for example, Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 208 (1981) (providing that
courts either can decline to enforce contracts that have unconscionable terms or can limit
any unconscionable terms).
148 See Part III.A-B.
149 See Part I.
150 For the classic early statement of the "revealed preferences" approach to measur-
ing utility, see generally P.A. Samuelson, A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer's Be-
haviour , 5 Economica 61 (1938). I do not believe that human flourishing is equivalent to
subjective-preference satisfaction, for reasons elaborated in, for example, Amartya Sen,
Internal Consistency of Choice , 61 Econometrica 495, 498-504 (1993). But there is no
doubt that some connection exists in many circumstances.
151 See Hayek, 35 Am Econ Rev at 524 (cited in note 97).
lb¿ See, for example, Anderson, 6 Econ & Phil at 180-81 (cited in note 139):
On this view [of freedom as embodied in modern markets], freedom is primari-
ly exercised in the choice and consumption of commodities in private life. It
consists in having a large menu of choices in the marketplace and in exclusive
power to use and dispose of things and services in the private sphere without
having to ask permission from anyone else.
See also Epstein, 18 J L & Econ at 293 (cited in note 142) ("One of the first functions of
the law is to guarantee to individuals a sphere of influence in which they will be able to
operate, without having to justify themselves to the state or to third parties.").
153 Anderson, 6 Econ & Phil at 183-84 (cited in note 139) (describing economic goods
as goods whose values are best realized through market transactions, in which "exit" ra-
ther than "voice" is the primary mechanism of influence). See also generally Albert O.
Hirschman, Exit , Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and
States (Harvard 1970).
154 See Part IILA.2.
155 See Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Ph
34-45 (Harvard 2009).
156 Fried, Contract as Promise at 1 (cited in note 37).
157 P.S. Atiyah, Promises, Morals, and Law 123-29 (Oxford rev ed 1983).
158 James Gordley, Morality and Contract: The Question of Paternalism , 4
Mary L Rev 1733, 1759 (2007).
159 Benson, The Unity of Contract Law at 131 (cited in note 3).
160 I explain this in Robin Kar, The Challenge of Boilerplate (Jotwell, Sept
archived at http://perma.cc/9QEP-TG5X.
161 See id. This point has also been emphasized in Margaret Jane Radin, Boi
The Fine Print, Vanishing Rights, and the Rule of Law 55-81 (Princeton 2013).
174 Another way to put this point is to say that the modified objective ap
interpretation is more empowering than both purely objective approaches a
subjective approaches. With respect to purely subjective approaches, it would b
cantly disempowering to require a perfect (subjective) meeting of the minds fo
formation. Agreements of this kind rarely exist in practice, and this altern
would therefore disempower people by making almost all contracts unenforceab
175 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 178 (1981).
176 Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 178 & comment a (1981).
177 See generally, for example, Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938, 52 Stat 10
fied as amended at 29 USC § 201 et sea.
178 See, for example, Title VIII of the Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer
Protection Act ("Payment, Clearing, and Settlement Supervision Act of 2010"), Pub L No
111-203, 124 Stat 1376, 1802-22, codified at 12 USC §§ 5461-72.
179 See, for example, 17 USC § 501 (establishing remedies for copyright infringement).
180 See generally, for example, Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act, 52 Stat 1040
(1938), codified as amended at 21 USC § 301 et seq.
181 See, for example, 26 USC § l(a)-(d) (setting forth a progressive individual in-
come tax).
182 See generally, for example, Social Security Act, 49 Stat 620 (1935), codified as
amended at 42 USC § 301 et seq.
183 See, for example, Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act §§ 1101-03, Pub L
No 111-148, 124 Stat 119, 141-46 (2010), codified at 42 USC §§ 18001-03.
184 See, for example, Darwall, Introduction at 4-7 (cited in note 26) (arguing that
common illegal acts are inconsistent with treating others as moral equals); Rawls, 77 J
Phil at 515 (cited in note 31). See also T.M. Scanlon and Johnathan Dancy, Intention and
Permissibility , 74 Proceedings Aristotelian Socy Supp Vol 301, 313 (2000) (suggesting
that an action like murder is inconsistent with treating another person as possessing a
form of personal authority over his or her own life that cannot be reasonably rejected).
lg5 See Part I.
186 See Scanlon and Dancy, 74 Proceedings Aristotelian Socy Supp Vol at 313 (cited
in note 184) (arguing that intentional killing is "inconsistent with the idea that each per-
son has a special claim to and authority over his or her own life and body, an idea which
[the authors] take to be itself one that no one could reasonably reject").
197 See UCC § 2-103 (ALI 2012) (defining good faith for merchants as "h
fact and the observance of reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing in
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 205, comment a (1981) ("Good faith perf
enforcement of a contract emphasizes faithfulness to an agreed common
consistency with the justified expectations of the other party; it excludes a
types of conduct characterized as involving 'bad faith' because they violate c
standards of decency, fairness or reasonableness.").
198 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 241-42 (1981) (setting forth
distinguish material breaches from partial breaches).
199 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 235-44 (1981) (setting forth f
evaluating failures to perform and allowing corresponding responses by n
parties).
200 Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 261-72 (1981).
201 Compare Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§ 261-72 (1981) (allowing the uni-
lateral discharge of duties on the grounds of impracticability or frustration), with Re-
statement (Second) of Contracts §§ 273-77 (1981) (requiring consideration or a substi-
tute to discharge duties with the assent of the obligee).
202 See generally, for example, Fair Credit Reporting Act, Pub L No 91-508, 84 Stat
1128 (1970), codified as amended at 15 USC § 1681 et seq; Fair Debt Collection Practices
Act, Pub L No 95-109, 91 Stat 874 (1977), codified as amended at 15 USC § 1692 et seq.
See also UCC § 2A-104(l)(c) (ALI 2012) (stating that leases are subject to state consumer-
protection laws).
203 See generally, for example, Truth in Lending Act, Pub L No 90-321, 82 Stat 146
(1968), codified as amended at 15 USC § 1601 et seq. See also Equal Credit Opportunity
Act § 503, Pub L No 93-495, 88 Stat 1521-22 (1974), codified as amended at 15 USC
§ 1691.
204 See, for example, Daniel Morton- Bentley, Two Guiding Trends in Contemporary
Labor and Employment Law: Technology and Fairness (The Federalist Society, Dec 9,
2011), archived at http://perma.cc/5P5K-AZTE (observing that one of the "two primary
trends guiding contemporary labor and employment law" is "increased fairness measures
at the expense of legal certainty").
205 See, for example, Epstein, 18 J L & Econ at 304 (cited in note 142) ("[CJourts
should then enforce [contractual] transactions in accordance with the general principles
of contract law, without any resort to unconscionability doctrines, and without any inde-
pendent examination of the 'fairness' of the agreement's substantive terms."V
206 I say "sometimes" because it is rare to find people who believe that contracts
should always be set aside in favor of courts' views on the substantive fairness of an ex-
change. Some on the economic left nevertheless believe that there should be more, not
less, room for doctrines like unconscionability. See, for example, Kronman, 89 Yale L J at
510 (cited in note 58) (arguing that "contractual regulation will on occasion be the least
intrusive and most efficient way of redistributing wealth to those who have a legitimate
claim to a larger share of society's resources").
207 With respect to this epistemic issue, Professor Richard Epstein has suggested,
for example, that "[i]t is difficult to know what principles identify the 'just term,' and for
the same reasons that make it so difficult to determine the 'just price.'" Epstein, 18 J L
& Econ at 306 (cited in note 142).
208 por reasons that Professor Friedrich Hayek has outlined, I believe that - absent
robust private market activity - it is often difficult to identify exchanges that would be mu-
tually beneficial, let alone fair. See generally Hayek, 35 Am Econ Rev 519 (cited in note 97).
209 For further discussion of these challenges, see generally id.
210 Although the fact that a set of rules produces unfair allocations of goods and ser-
vices can provide a reasonable ground to reject these rules, that rejection will be reason-
able only if there is an alternative set of rules that is more fair and does not create too
much additional harm to anyone.
211 This method would thus employ, rather than undermine, information produced
by private markets. Rather than failing to acknowledge Hayek's important insights in
The Use of Knowledge in Society , this method would take advantage of them. See gener-
ally Hayek, 35 Am Econ Rev 519 (cited in note 97).
212 I say a "modified objective test" rather than an "objective test" for the reasons
explained in this Section.
213 To understand this proposal, one must understand what it means to say that two
parties have entered into a contract from an "equal bargaining position." I say that two
parties have entered into a contract from a perfectly equal bargaining position if they
have negotiated with perfectly equal capacities, perfectly equal access to knowledge of
any facts relevant to the exchange, perfectly equal understandings of all of the relevant
terms, perfectly equal capacities to modify all of the relevant terms, perfectly equal time
and opportunity to deliberate, and perfectly equal access to the market. In addition, nei-
ther party can have induced the other to enter into the contract through misrepresenta-
tion, duress, undue influence, or manipulation of the other's voluntary choices in ways
that are likely to systematically disadvantage the other party. The parties must there-
fore be motivated solely by their equally reliable assessments of the expected costs, bene-
fits, and perceived market fairness (or fairness relative to other market possibilities) of
the underlying exchange.
214 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 208, comment c (1981) ("[A] contract
[may] be oppressive taken as a whole, even though there is no weakness in the bargain-
ing process and no single term which is in itself unconscionable."); Samuel Williston, 8 A
Treatise on the Law of Contracts § 18:10 at 111-14 (West 4th ed 2010) (Richard A. Lord,
ed) ("Thus, the fairness of the bargaining procedure - and hence, whether there is proce-
dural unconscionability - may be of less importance if it results in harsh or unreasonable
substantive terms, or substantive unconscionability may be sufficient in itself even
though procedural unconscionability is not.") (citation omitted); Philip L. Bruner and
Patrick J. O'Connor Jr, 8 Bruner & O'Connor on Construction Law § 21:142 at 53-54
(Thomson Reuters 2014) ("[A] number [of jurisdictions] have adopted a 'sliding scale' ap-
proach that permits a court to conclude an arbitration clause is unconscionable based on
less evidence of either one of the two types of unconscionability as long as there is
stronger than usual evidence of the other type of unconscionability.").
215 On the exceptional use of unconscionability, see, for example, Sitogum Holdings,
lne v Ropes , 800 A2d 915, 916 (NJ Super Chanc Div 2002) (noting that "[t]he common
law doctrine of unconscionability has proved difficult to define and has been rarely in-
voked undoubtedly because, other than in exceptional cases, it has largely been viewed
as grossly interfering with the freedom to contract"). On the typical need for both proce-
dural and substantive unconscionability, see, for example, Bruner and O'Connor, Bruner
& O'Connor on Construction Law at § 21:142 at 53-54 (cited in note 214) ("[M]ost juris-
dictions require a showing of both procedural and substantive unconscionability."). But
see Williston, 8 A Treatise on the Law of Contracts at § 18:10 at 115 (cited in note 214),
quoting Maxwell v Fidelity Financial Services, Ine , 907 P2d 51, 59 (Ariz 1995) ("There-
fore, we conclude that under [UCC § 2-302], a claim of unconscionability can be estab-
lished with a showing of substantive unconscionability alone, especially in cases involv-
ing either price-cost disparity or limitation of remedies.").
216 See Posner, Economic Analysis of Law at 147-48 (cited in note 188). See also
Richard Craswell, Freedom of Contract, in Eric A. Posner, ed, Chicago Lectures in Law
and Economics 81, 81 (Foundation 2000) ("Depending on one's point of view, freedom of
contract can be seen as a choice between individual liberty and heavy-handed govern-
ment control, or between communitarian consensus and the worst excesses of laissez-
faire capitalism.").
217 Some economists have made similar recommendations. See, for example, Steven
Shavell, Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 301 (Belknap 2004) ("As a general
matter, parties will want incomplete contracts to be interpreted as if they had spent the
time and effort to specify more detailed terms") . The present recommendation neverthe-
less specifies filling gaps in contracts not with the terms that the parties would have ac-
tually agreed to but with the terms they would have agreed to had they been bargaining
from a position of perfect procedural fairness.
218 See, for example, 15 USC §§ 1601-67.
219 See, for example, Uniform Consumer Credit Code § 5.108 (Prentice-Hall 1968).
220 See Charles L. Knapp, Nathan M. Crystal, and Harry G. Prince, Problems in
Contract Law 357-58 (Wolters Kluwer 2007).
¿¿1 Id at 379-80 (explaining that, under the reasonable-expectations doctrine, the
objectively reasonable expectations of policyholders will be honored even if a study of pol-
icy provisions shows that they would have negated those expectations).
222 See generally, for example, National Labor Relations Act, 49 Stat 449 (1935),
codified as amended at 29 USC § 151 et seq.
223 See, for example, Civil Rights Act of 1964 § 703, Pub L No 88-352, 78 Stat 241,
255-57, codified as amended at 42 USC § 2000e-2.
224 See Kessler, 43 Colum L Rev at 633 (cited in note 139) ("[0]ur common law of
standardized contracts is highly contradictory and confusing, and the potentialities in-
herent in the common law system for coping with contracts of adhesion have not been
fully developed.").
225 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 208 (1981); UCC § 2-302 (ALI 2012); E.
Allan Farnsworth and William F. Young, Cases and Materials on Contracts 386-454
(Foundation 5th ed 1995). See also Burch v Second Judicial District Court of the State of
Nevada , 49 P3d 647, 650 (Nev 2002) ("Generally, both procedural and substantive un-
conscionability must be present in order for a court to exercise its discretion to refuse to
enforce a contract or clause as unconscionable. . . . Because the procedural unconsciona-
bility in this case is so great, less evidence of substantive unconscionability is required to
establish unconscionability.").
bee, tor example, Umri Ben-öhahar and Carl b. bchneider, More lhán You
Wanted to Know: The Failure of Mandated Disclosure 59-93 (Princeton 2014); Radin,
Boilerplate at 197-216 (cited in note 161). See also Kar, The Challenge of Boilerplate
(cited in note 160).
227 See, for example, Radin, Boilerplate at 243-48 (cited in note 161) (suggesting
steps for NGOs, firms, regulatory agencies, courts, and lawyers).
in which true happiness requires freedom from the bondage of self. See Kar, 84 Tex L
Rev at 927 (cited in note 12).
247 See Hayek, 35 Am Econ Rev at 524 (cited in note 97); Macneil, 72 Nw U L Rev at
859 (cited in note 244) ("The combination of exchange with promise has been one of the
most powerful social tools ever developed for the production of goods and services.").
248 See, for example, Posner, Economic Analysis of Law at 123-26 (cited in note 188)
(discussing the economic functions of contracts, particularly with respect to consideration).
249 See generally, for example, Tversky and Kahneman, 211 Science 453 (cited in
note 31) (describing classical assumptions of rationality in economic theory and recom-
mending their replacement with a theory of bounded rationality); Daniel Kahneman, A
Perspective on Judgment and Choice : Mapping Bounded Rationality , 58 Am Psychologist
697 (2003) (suggesting the replacement of classical rational-choice theory with a theory
of bounded rationality in the social sciences).
250 See generally Kar, 84 Tex L Rev 877 (cited in note 12). See also Jonathan Haidt,
The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion 25-26 (Allen
Lane 2012) (supplementing the two main theories from whence "morality comes" -
innateness and childhood learning - with a third theory that "morality is self-constructed
by children on the basis of their experiences with harm"); Mikhail, Elements of Moral
Cognition at 296-97 (cited in note 29) (noting that classical natural lawyers like Cicero
and Hume believed that our "moral sense" is innate to our human nature).
251 Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other at 191 (cited in note 27) (suggesting that
ordinary people are motivated to act not only rationally but also in ways that they can
justify to others as conforming to principles for the general regulation of behavior that
others, similarly motivated, cannot reasonably reject).
255 See Kar, The Two Faces of Morality at 68-69 (cited in note 29).
256 id at 69.
257 See, for example, Kar, 84 Tex L Rev at 877 (cited in note 12); Brian bkyrms, Evo-
lution of the Social Contract 4-7 (Cambridge 1996). See also generally Kar, The Psycho-
logical Foundations of Human Rights (cited in note 29).
258 For a general account of these varied views, see generally Darwall, Contractarianism/
Contractualism (cited in note 26).
259 See generally Scanlon, Contractualism and Utilitarianism (cited in note 32).
Conclusion
265 Schwartz and Scott, 113 Yale L J at 543 (cited in note 1).
266 See Part I.
™ See Parts II, III.
268 See generally Daniel M. Hausman, Introduction , in Daniel M. Hausman, ed, The
Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology 1 (Cambridge 3d ed 2008).
Although Professor Elizabeth Anderson has thought deeply about the implications of
such a move for understanding systems of tax and transfer, the current Article engages
in an analogous exercise with respect to contract law.