The Failed Feminist Challenge To Fundamental Epistemology'
The Failed Feminist Challenge To Fundamental Epistemology'
The Failed Feminist Challenge To Fundamental Epistemology'
CASSANDRA L. PINNICK
Philosophy Department, Western Kentucky University, Bowling Green, KY 42101, USA
(E-mail: [email protected])
Abstract. Despite volumes written in the name of the new and fundamental feminist project in
philosophy of science, and conclusions drawn on the strength of the hypothesis that the
feminist project will boost progress toward cognitive aims associated with science and ratio-
nality (and, one might add, policy decisions enacted in the name of these aims), the whole
rationale for the project remains (after 20 years, plus) wholly unsubstantiated. We must
remain agnostic about its evidentiary merits or demerits. This is because we are without
evidence to test the hypothesis: certainly, we have no data that would test the strength of the
hypothesis as asserting a causal relationship between women and cognitive ends. Thus, any
self-respecting epistemologist who places a premium on evidence-driven belief and justification
ought not to accept the hypothesis. By extension, there is no reasoned basis to draw any
definitive conclusion about the project itself. No matter how self-evidently correct.
A more fundamental project now confronts us. We must root out sexist distortions and
perversions in epistemology, metaphysics, methodology and the philosophy of science –
in the ‘hard core’ of abstract reasoning thought most immune to infiltration by social
values. (Discovering Reality, Harding & Hintikka 1983)
Until roughly the mid-20th century, liberal feminist politics had little
apparent impact on American universities. But thereafter the transformation
was swift. Throughout the second half of the 20th century, student demo-
graphics shifted, women’s studies flourished, and remarkable reforms to the
liberal arts curriculum became entrenched. There was no surprise when
feminist theory moved into the humanities or the ‘soft’ sciences. And, these
days, the radical edge is worn off the idea of departments and faculty lines
devoted to women’s studies. Indeed, the curricular shifts in academe that are
associated with the rise in the feminist profile are by now hardly more radical
than our expectation that women shall enjoy equal protection under law.
But all is not entirely well with feminist theory and the academy, as can be
seen with the curricular reforms at the intersection of feminist theory and the
‘hard’ sciences. For some of us, it is a surprise to be told that science,
?
This article originated as a lecture for the Fifth International Conference of the German
Society for Analytic Philosophy and is published by MENTIS in the GAP.5 Volume (2004).
104 CASSANDRA L. PINNICK
(1) Arguments which are well-formulated. (This rules out a certain swathe
of the feminist critique, namely feminist contributions that self-con-
sciously eschew argumentative form.)
(2) Arguments that present a serious or a radical challenge to the epistemic
foundations of knowledge. (After all, if not a serious challenge, i.e., if
not genuinely different and demonstrably better, then why bother?)
Promise (1): The feminist project will provide a comparatively better the-
ory for the justification of scientific belief. Thus, we ought to expect the
feminist project to have a distinctive and demonstrably improved means
for warranting sentences that purport to reflect features of the world.
Promise (2): The feminist project will provide a distinctive and demon-
strably better methodology aimed to guide future inquiry toward its epi-
stemic aims. Thus, we ought to expect the feminist project to retain and
satisfy the epistemic and methodological value placed on a normative role
for any theory of knowledge.
descriptive accounts surely are necessary, but they are not sufficient to fill out
the epistemology of science.
With this backdrop of epistemic desiderata, here are important points for
consideration, that are made in Harding’s 1998 book:
Women and men in the same culture have different ‘geographical’ locations in
heterogeneous nature, and different interests, discursive resources, and ways of
organizing the production of knowledge from their brothers. Here [in this book] the
focus is on gender differences, on the reasons why it is more accurate and useful to
understand women and men in any culture as having a different relationship to the world
around them. (p. 90)
The issue is. . .about the resources that starting off research from women’s lives can
provide for increasing human knowledge of nature’s regularities and the underlying
causal tendencies anywhere and everywhere that gender relations occur. (p. 90)
In many ways they [women and men; or perhaps I should say, persons of different
gender] are exposed to different regularities of nature that offer them different possible
resources and probable dangers and that can make some theories appear more or less
plausible than they do to those who interact only with other environments. (p. 96)
When science is defined in terms of these linked meanings of objectivity and
masculinity,…science itself is distorted. (p. 139)
Standpoint approaches can show us how to detect values and interests that constitute
scientific projects…Standpoint approaches provide a map, a method, for maximizing a
‘strong Objectivity’ in the natural and social sciences. (p. 163)
claim to provide such support when, in fact, purely descriptive narratives are
all that are provided. Given the time frame, some argue that the complete
lack of normative support for the thesis is sufficient to reject it. At any rate, I
prefer to maintain the moderate, agnostic stance toward the thesis and
toward Harding’s hypothesis.)
3. Special Cases
So far, my reservations concerning the feminist project may appear to be
selective, based on a too narrow range of feminist argumentation. Or, my
reservations may appear too broad, in that I have not taken into consider-
ation what is said to be a rich, widely ranging spectrum of particular argu-
ments that either individually or as a programmatic group prove the
hypothesis that underlies the fundamental project and, doing even more,
trace the new, and improved, epistemology that the fundamental project
makes possible.
I surely have no intention to give short shrift to the argumentative
strength of the full range of feminist critique of science, in so far as arguments
are provided. And it is argument that we need, not either anecdotal report or
historical narrative (which is not to deny that in the long run anecdote and
history are important elements of a philosophy of science; but these elements
must not substitute for the usual apparatus of epistemology that supports
methodological advice and a means to justify belief). So to forestall the
charge that I fail to do justice to the feminist critique, let me now cite noted
feminist contributions other than Harding’s.
that is near and dear to the heart of epistemologists, does not duly respond to
the implicit challenge Code makes as against traditional epistemological
categories. So, let us now look with seriousness.
If Code’s reasoning intends to support the conclusion that the episte-
mology of science ought to be based on feminist categories (for now, let us
leave this to be defined as the negation of whatever belongs to white male
categories), then Code’s reasoning commits a patent non sequitur. This is
because, even if epistemology is exactly as Code says it is, it does not follow
that feminist epistemology must or can replace it; perhaps astrology ought to
replace it. But Code has more to say:
I contend that mainstream epistemology, in its very neutrality, masks the fact of its
derivation from and embeddedness in a specific set of interests: the interests of a
privileged group of white men. (pp. ix, x)
There is no arguing against the claim that men, in general, are guilty of
oppressive practices as against women, in general. But from this truism, how
are we to demarcate a ‘white male point of view’ regarding either women or
epistemological principles? We can state facts about white men as a group,
but where is the evidence to warrant assertions about white men and epi-
stemic categories, or about white men, epistemology and women? We would
be better off looking to link members of identifiable economic groups with
corresponding ideologies, although even success in this kind of project
notoriously falls short of showing causal connections. Still, overall, socio-
economic categories are better predictive factors than gender.
A point in Code’s favor is that she rejects any turn to essentialism, because
to do so, she writes, ‘would risk replicating the exclusionary, hegemonic
structures of the masculinist epistemology…’(p. 316). However, here too,
Code’s reasoning moves to an irrelevant conclusion. For where is the evi-
dence to show that a single theory of knowledge, even hegemonic male
epistemology, does always and will always exclude real alternatives to it?
Instead, science or its history seems to be punctuated by white males as
agents of scientific change, if not progress.
Perhaps Code’s remarks are intended to be a call for sensitivity to various
kinds of knowers (what Harding, for example, calls a multicultural stand-
point). Perhaps women have distinctive capacities (such as, as some have
suggested, a generalized, special sensitivity to distress calls), unique devel-
opmental circumstances that we are able to show are not shared by males.
(These developmental circumstances would map nicely onto Sandra
Harding’s concept of ‘different geographical locations’ as between genders.)
Gender differences may be a significant mark in human knowing: (some)
women may exemplify a distinctive mode of knowledge. But how distinctive?
Is this what it says it is, women’s way of knowing, or may men aspire to it? Is
its presence, or non-presence, uniform across gender categories? The
FUNDAMENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY 111
difficulty is this: how do we know? which is to ask: how can we test, one way
or the other? One looks in vain for an answer.
Returning to the blurb. In the second instance, we have the assertion that
Longino develops a new account of scientific knowledge. Just as before (when
we considered Harding), we want to know how the new epistemology does a
better job of justifying science and its practice. This is to ask questions such
as, what old problems does the new epistemology resolve? what compara-
tively better predictive force does the new epistemology have? and so forth
through the familiar range of questions about science and its practice.
However, in this book, it appears that Longino continues to work with a
communitarian epistemology, or what she calls an intersubjective basis for
the methodology of belief justification. This is to say that, in her view, the
ultimate justifier for any claim to know is the community of believers. The
difference to remark upon is that Longino’s epistemology of science is one
where consensus is community-driven, whereas the epistemology that
Longino’s arguments aim to replace is one where consensus is evidence-
based. This ought to bring into sharp contrast the difference. For, regardless
of how a communitarian style epistemology may be dressed up, in the end,
the community is the final arbiter of belief. There is, even in the long run, no
objectively compelling ground for belief, only grounds for a particular
community. In her own words: [ justification is] ‘dependent on rules and
procedures immanent in the context of inquiry’ (p. 92). This stance evades a
pernicious relativism (if, in fact, it does) not by appeal to normative episte-
mology, but by appeal to normative sociology.
In any case, does Longino show that social interaction assists us in securing
knowledge? To say, merely, that social interaction contributes to the success
of science is an idea that is neither new, nor the special provenance of persons
outside philosophy (cf. Laudan 1984; Hull 1988). David Hull, and others, all
have worried about the ways in which sometimes grubby motives produce
scientifically noble ends. This is to say that over and over again, philosophers
of science such as Hull, Laudan, Lakatos, and even Feyerabend, all worry the
question of how historical and cultural contexts have contributed to the
development, evaluation, and acceptance of theories. (Indeed, in 1984, only
one year apart from the ‘fundamental project’ manifesto, Richard Boyd
dubbed this kind of philosophy ‘social constructivism’ (Boyd 1984)).
But if we want to understand ‘contributes to’ in the sense of providing an
epistemic boost, then we need to show that we do (or can do) better science
by means of this intersubjective deliberation. And we would show this on the
basis of isolated and tested-for social factors. In other words, we have to once
and for all place this idea, that there is some new epistemological category,
into our epistemic cross-hairs, and then see what the testing process reveals.
It has not been done.
Let me mention briefly a recent effort to argue that social interaction
contributes in a positive way to science. This is K. Brad Wray’s essay, ‘The
Epistemic Significance of Collaborative Research’ (Wray 2002). Here Wray
FUNDAMENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY 113
attempts to test the causal role that collaboration plays in science, by testing
the epistemic effect that collaboration has in accessing the scarce resources
that are needed to carry out research. Wray’s test thesis is that collaboration
ought to demonstrably boost realizing epistemic goals over scientists or
teams that do not collaborate. (This is, in addition, a nice take on a com-
munitarian thesis.) Wray intends to show that by collaborating as research
teams, scientists have greater success in accessing scarce resources needed to
carry out research and this success in turn enables them to realize the epi-
stemic goals of science more effectively than scientists who do not
collaborate.
Wray’s arguments bring together a vast array of research. To summarize
the aim of his project, he writes:
Ideally, it would be useful to have information on specific research groups, showing
increased productivity after collaboration, followed by greater funding, which in turn
would be followed by continued collaboration. Unfortunately, at present, such data are
not available. (Wray 2002, pp.158–159)
So, in the end, Wray is able to trace a social trend in the practice of science,
but not able to show an epistemological effect based on the trend. He admits
that he finds no evidence for boost due to collaboration. Indeed, despite
valuable insights brought together in this essay, Wray’s conclusions float
completely free of the epistemology of science. While Wray makes a fairly
interesting case that there is an identifiable, and even well-tracked, causal
connection between a rise in collaborative research and funding success, this
conclusion does not run to the epistemic import of collaboration and
scientific aims.
Let me recapture now the focus on Helen Longino’s arguments. Longino
provides a pretty good case study for feminist epistemology of science. And
here I do not want to be misunderstood: for on one hand, we have Longino
qua philosopher of science, on the other hand we have Longino’s philo-
sophical arguments qua feminist. Considered in the latter guise only, how, if
at all, do Longino’s arguments boost the epistemic success of science?
Longino’s focus is on evidence and the concept of objectivity. She rela-
tivizes evidence to background beliefs and on this basis says that she shows
both the opportunity and need for a feminist critique of evidence. In other
words, Longino argues (1) that background beliefs are tainted with bias, but
(2) if we were to use better background beliefs, then we will likely have better
science.
But, how is it peculiarly feminist to decry (distorting) bias in background
belief? Everyone allows that our beliefs are warranted against a back-
ground, and everyone aims for this background to be unbiased to the
extent possible (or, of course, if the bias boosts, then to maximize its
presence and impact).
114 CASSANDRA L. PINNICK
But, so what? Why ought this to be of any great concern? The reason is
this: Science is not so much a particular subject matter as it is a kind of
methodology for obtaining reliable knowledge. And it is when we are con-
cerned with methodology: ‘what methods ought we adopt to achieve our
aims?’ that the fundamental feminist project is so unimpressive.
On its face, there is a whole lot of common sense to the notion that more
women doing science will make science better. But intellectual history is
riddled with commonsensical notions that careful scrutiny reveals to be
misguided. And, even worse, intellectual history includes an encyclopedia of
public policy decisions, taken on the basis of misguided common sense or
skewed evidence, most often to the detriment, the peril even, of society.
For myself, I have the usual level of self-interest: I delight at the prospect
that public policy be rewritten to encourage and to privilege women in hard
core disciplines. However, my self-interest is tempered by a sense of epistemic
value, namely the value of evidence-based public policy. So, before endorsing
public policy that would flow logically from the feminist fundamental pro-
ject, the evidence base that would undergird the fundamental project must be
available to be assessed. Yet, it is not.
And so, we are back to our starting point. If it is correct to view science as
a methodology, then it follows that this fundamental project is a dismal
failure, for the reasons that there are no results unique to it (which is to say
that there are no new facts) and that there surely is no new, even different,
methodology that is correctly said to be uniquely feminist.
References
Boyd, R. N.: 1984, ‘The Current Status of Scientific Realism’. in J. Leplin (ed.), Scientific
Realism, University of California Press, Berkeley, pp. 41–82.
Code, L.: 1991, What Can She Know?, Cornell University Press, Ithaca.
Harding, S. G. & Hintikka, M. (eds): 1983, Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on
Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Reidel, Dordrecht.
Harding, S. G.: 1998, Is Science Multicultural? Postcolonialisms, Feminisms, and Epistemolo-
gies, Indiana University Press, Bloomington IN.
Hull, D. L.: 1988, Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual
Development of Sciencei, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Laudan, L.: 1984, Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate,
University of California Press, Berkeley.
Longino, H. E.: 2001, The Fate of Knowledge, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Pinnick, C. L.: 1994, ‘Feminist Epistemology: Implications for Philosophy of Science’, Phi-
losophy of Science 61, 646–657.
Pinnick, C. L.: 2000a, ‘Alvin Goldman’s Veritistic Epistemology and Feminist Epistemology:
A-Rational Epistemics?’ Social Epistemology 14, 281–291.
Pinnick, C. L.: 2000b, ‘Feminist Philosophy of Science: High Hopes’, Metascience 9(2), 257–
266.
116 CASSANDRA L. PINNICK
Pinnick, C. L., Koertge, N. & Almeder, R. F. (eds): 2003, Scrutinizing Feminist Epistemology:
An Examination of Gender in Science, Rutgers University Press.
Wray, K. B.: 2002, ‘The Epistemic Significance of Collaborative Research’, Philosophy of
Science 69(1), 150–168.