Esssay To Critically Evaluate Two Competing Theories of The State
Esssay To Critically Evaluate Two Competing Theories of The State
Esssay To Critically Evaluate Two Competing Theories of The State
I Marxism
How do Marxists define the state? Traditionally Marxists prefer an interpretative
approach to the state which owes much to Marx’s critique of capitalism as an
unviable model of economic relationships. For Marx economic structure determine
the nature of social economic and cultural relationships formed in society. The state
was consequently seen as a vehicle to reinforce capitalist modes of production.
Although Marx’s writings permit for some interpretation here (Dunleavy 203), there
can be no doubt that Marxists would emphasise the repressive character of any
state apparatus in society. The state was marked by its functional relationship with
the bourgeoisie whose dominant position within society it was charged to uphold.
Dunleavy distinguishes between three models of the Marxist theory of the state. The
instrumental model runs fairly accurately along the general notion of the state as a
executing agency of the will of the bourgeoisie as mentioned above. The arbiter
model permits theorists to accommodate a more autonomous role for the state
within society. Marx highlighted here the role of the state bureaucracy in particular
as a group where autonomous actions could possibly originate.
However even so, the overall effect even of these attempts at formulating a set of
interests that are specific to the bureaucrats of the state apparatus is still one of
reinforcing the power of the bourgeoisie in society. (Dunleavy 210). The third model
views the state in functional terms and stresses that it is best understood as a
‘means of co-ordinating the social organisation of the complex division of labour’
(Dunleavy 210). Given that the division of labour is a prerequisite for the
maintenance of bourgeois dominance in capitalist society and economy, even this
functional model retains it reference to Marx’s fundamental notion of the state as a
repressive instrument in the ensuing class struggle between the antagonistic forces:
the proletariat and the bourgeoisie.
The variety of approaches that found their expressions in Marxist thought over the
decades leaves one with the impression that Marx failed to develop a ‘unitary theory
of the state’ at all (Vincent 147). Any attempt to identify a consistent definition of
statehood must fail since Marx uses an interpretative perspective which allows for
no independent notions of what a state is. He frames the discussion about the
essence of the state with the help of his theory of class struggle, subordinating any
definitional attempt to his theory of historical development (Vincent 157). Although
he does hint at the broad location of state within his conceptional framework and
identifies it as a component of the superstructure, he at the same time,
incongruently, asserts that there is no mediation between state and society (Vincent
158).
Marx’s theory of the state may have spawned a whole range of more elaborate
versions, but Western scholars often dismiss the work of Communist historians and
political scientists as ideologically motivated propaganda. Vincent opines:
‘The subsequent history of Marxist theorizing on the state resembles a form of late
medieval scholasticism and appears to be a singularly unfruitful area of study…’
(Vincent 175)
There are few advantages of Marx’s theory of the state. Clearly since Marx tied the
notion of the state so closely to his analysis of capitalist economy, little room for
interpretative manoeuvre was left for theorists to develop his theory of statehood in
more promising directions. Perhaps, the critical approach of Marx’s interpretation
may be counted as a unique advantage: states very often exhibit a repressive
attitude to societal conflict and are anything but neutral arbiters between the
various social groups in society.
IIPluralism
The pluralist concept of the state enjoys a long pedigree going back to liberal
thinkers such as John Locke and his opponent in kind Thomas Hobbes. Locke argued
that Hobbes’s notion of the state would necessarily lead to a unitary, absolutist form
of regime and he attacked what he believed the monistic tendencies in Hobbes.
Consequently Dunleavy remarks that
‘The rejection of absolute, unified and uncontrolled state power remains the hallmark
of pluralism’ (Dunleavy 13)
In his book Two Treatises of Government Locke contrasted his theory of consent
with that of Hobbes and disputed that there could be one singular origin of power in
society and hence in the state apparatus. Locke, as a quintessential pluralist,
therefore vehemently rejected the notion of sovereignty residing in a unified body or
individual (Dunleavy 14).
Montesquieu developed this idea further and argued that a dissipation of power in
society would produce the best conditions for social and political peace. He put
forward the idea that a separation of the various branches of power, the legislative,
judicial and executive, would guarantee a societal balance from which the public
good would benefit. This idea found its most elaborate expression in the writings of
the Federalists in the United States. Madison, concerned to reconcile the fact that
any society contains social groups pursuing their own interest with the public
interest, writes:
‘The inference to which we are brought, is, that the causes of faction cannot be
removed; and that relief is only to be sought in the means of controlling its effects.’
(Federalists 45)
This combination of horizontal with vertical checks and balances has prompted
some political theorists to speak of a tension that exists between the institutional
version of pluralism and the non-institutional one (Dunleavy 14). In Madison it is the
diversity of social groups that proves beneficial to the successful search of the
public good; consequently it is the extension of the republic, that is to say the
extension of civil and participatory rights, that is seen as instrumental in bringing
about an effective government and a vibrant society (Dunleavy 14).
The advantages of pluralism are more numerous than those of Marxism. Pluralism,
again, can be viewed as a descriptive or as a normative theory and, in its normative
version it articulates good reasons why political, social and economic power should
not be converge in one particular social group of individuals. Pluralism links the
enjoyment of civil and political rights and freedoms to the structure of the state
institutions, and claims that the state as a set of discrete institutions tied into a
framework of mutual checks and balances is the best guarantee for rights and
liberties in modern society. However, in its rejection of monism and its emphasis on
polyarchy, pluralism fails to see the state as anything but ‘discrete organisations’
(Dunleavy 42).