Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
It Ain't Necessarily So
Author(s): Hilary Putnam
Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 59, No. 22, American Philosophical Association
Eastern Division: Symposium Papers to be Presented at the Fifty-Ninth Annual Meeting,
New York City, December 27-29, 1962 (Oct. 25, 1962), pp. 658-671
Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2023596
Accessed: 03-02-2020 19:58 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Journal of Philosophy
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
658 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO *
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 659
I. ANALYTIC TRUTHS
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
660 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 661
Later I shall make a few remarks about the truths of logic and
mathematics. For the moment, let me turn to statements of quite
a different kind, for example, the statement that if one did X and
then Y, X must have been done at an earlier time than Y, or the
statement that space has three dimensions, or the statement that
the relation earlier than is transitive. All of these statements are
still classified as necessary by philosophers today. Those who feel
that the first statement is "conceptually necessary" reject time
travel as a "conceptual impossibility."
Once again I will beg your pardon for engaging in philosophical
science fiction. I want to imagine that something has happened
(which is in fact a possibility) namely, that modern physics has
definitely come to the conclusion that space is Riemannian. Now,
with this assumption in force, let us discuss the status of the
statement that one cannot reach the place from which one came
by traveling away from it in a straight line and continuing to move
in a constant sense. This is a geometrical statement. I want to
understand it, however, not as a statement of pure geometry, not
as a statement about space "in the abstract," but as a statement
about physical space, about the space in which we live and move
and have our being. It may be claimed that in that space, in the
space of actual physical experience, the notion of a "straight line"
has no application, because straight lines are supposed to have no
thickness at all and not the slightest variation in curvature, and
we ca.nnot identify by any physical means paths in space with
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
662 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 663
have two meanings, one for laymen and one for scienitists. Paths
that are straight in the layman's sense may not be straight in the
scientist's sense, and paths that are straight in the scientist's sense
may not be straight in the layman's sense. Onie caanInot come back
to one's starting point by proceeding indefinitely on a path that
is straight in the old Euclidean sense; when the scientist says that
one can come back to one 's starting point by continuing long
enough on a straight line, there is no paradox and no contradiction
with common sense. What he means by a straight line may be
a curved line in the layman's sense, and we all know you can come
back to your starting point by continiuilng' long enough on a closed
curve.
This account is not tenable, however. To see that it isn't, let
us shift to the second statement. Here we are in immediate diffi-
culties because there seems to be no difference, even today, between
the layman's senise of 'path' and the scientist's sense of 'path'.
Anything that the layman could trace out if we gave him but
world enough and time, the scientists would accept as a "path,"
and anything that the scientist would trace out as a "path," the
layman would accept as a "path." (Here I do not count micro-
scopic "paths" as paths.) Similarly with 'place'. To put it an-
other way: if Euclidean geometry is only apparently false owing
to a change in the meaning of words, then if we keep the meanings
of the words unchanged, if we use the words in the old way,
Euclidean geometry must still be true. In that case, in addition
to the N "places" to which one can get by following the various
paths in our Riemannian space, there must be infinitely many ad-
ditional "places" to which one can get by following other paths
that somehow the scientist has ov-erlooked. Where are these
places? Where are these other paths? Tn fact, they don't exist.
If someone believes that they exist, then he must invent special
physical laws to explain why, try as we may, we never sncceed in
seeing one of these other places or in sticking to one of these other
paths. If someone did accept such laws and insisted on holding
on to Euclidean geometry in the face of all present scientific
experience, it is clear that he would not have simply "made a
decision to keep the meanings of words unehanged'"; he would
have adopted a metaphysical theory.
The statement that there are onily finitely miany disjoint
"places" to get to, travel as yoit )may expre.,ses a downirio-ht "con1-
ceptual impossibility" within the framework of Euclidean geom-
etry. And one cannot say that all that has happened is that we
have changed the meaning of the word 'path', because in that
case one would be committecl to the metaphysical hypothesis that,
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
664 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
in addition to the "paths" that are still so ealled, there exist others
which are somehow physically inaccessible and additional "places"
which are somehow physically inaccessible and which, together with
what the physicists presently recognize as places and paths, fill out
a Euclidean space.
Insofar as the terms 'place', 'path', and 'straioght line' have any
application at all in physical space, they still have the application
they always had; something that was literally inconceivable has
turned out to be true.
Incidentally, although modern physics does not yet say that
space is Riemannian, it does say that our space has variable
curvature. This means that if two light rays stay a constant
distance apart for a long time and then come closer together after
passing the sun, we do not say that these two light rays are follow-
ing curved paths through space, but we say rather that they follow
straight paths and that two straight paths may have a constant
distance from each other for a long time and then later have a
decreasing distance from each other. Once again, if anyone wishes
to say, "Well, those paths aren't straight in the old sense of
'straight'," then I invite him to tell me vhich paths in the space
near the sun are "really straight." And I guarantee that, first,
no matter which paths he chooses as the straight ones, I will be
able to embarrass him acutely. I will be able to show, for example,
not only that light rays refuse to travel along the paths he claims
to be really straight, but that they are not the shortest paths by
any method of measurement he may elect; one cannot even travel
along those paths in a rocket ship without accelerations, decelera-
tions, twists, turns, etc. In short, the paths he claims are "really
straight" will look crooked, act crooked, and feel crooked. More-
over, if anyone does say that certain nongeodesics are the really
straight paths in the space near the sun, then his decision will have
to be a quite arbitrary one; and the theory that more or less
arbitrarily selected curved paths near the sun are "really straight"
(because they obey the laws of Euclidean geometry and the
geodesics do not) would again be a metaphysical theory, and the
decision to accept it would certainly not be a mere decision to "keep
the meaning of words unchanged."
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 665
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
666 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
KEY
t2
ti
to _4
A B
S PAC E
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 667
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
668 THIE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
V. CONCLUSIONS
In the last few years I have been amused and irritated by the
spate of articles proving that time travel is a "conceptual im-
possibility." All these articles make the same mistake. They
take it to be enough to show that, if we start talking about time
travel, things go wrong with ordinary language in countless places
and in countless ways. For example, it makes no sense to prevent
an occurrence that is in the past, yet a time traveler about to
visit the Ice Age in his time machine may well take an overcoat
to keep from freezing to death several million years ago. Exactly
similar objections could have been raised against the notion of
there being only finitely many "places" prior to the development
of Riemannian geometry. It is precisely the existence of the
world-line language that makes us sure that all these apparently
insurmountable difficulties about "preventing," "expecting," etc.,
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IT AIN'T NECESSARILY SO 669
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
670 TIIE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
other way of speaking does not link up with any coherent con-
ceptual system.
The causality case is analogous to the geometry case in that
the decision to preserve the older way of speaking-that is, to say,
whenever an event A appears to produce either of two different
events B and B', that there must be some hidden difference in the
attendant circumstances-involves postulating ghost entities. The
ghost entities in question are called "hidden variables" in the
literature of quantum mechanics.
I am inclined to think that the situation is not substantially
different in logic and mathematics. I believe that if I had the
time I could describe for you a case in which we would have a
choice between accepting a physical theory based upon a non-
standard logic, on the one hand, and retaininlg standard logic and
postulating hidden variables on the other. In this case, too, the
decision to retain the old logic is not merely the decision to keep
the meaning of certain words unchanged, for it has physical and
perhaps metaphysical consequences. In quantum mechanics, for
example, the customary interpretation says that an electron does
not have a definite position prior to a position measurement; the
position measurement causes the electron to take on suddenily the
property that we call its "position" (this is the so-called "quan-
tum jump"). Attempts to work out a theory of quantum jumps
and of measurement in quantum mechanics have beeni notorioulsy
unsuccessful to date. Recently it has been pointed out 4 that it is
entirely unnecessary to postulate the absence of sharp values prior
to measurement and the occurrence of quantum jumps, if we are
willing to regard quantum mechanics as a theory formalized
within a certain nonstandard logic, the modular logic proposed in
1935 by Birkhoff and von Neumanni, for precisely the purpose of
formalizing quantum mechanics.
There seems to be only one conclusion to come to, and I here-
with come to it. The distinction between statements niecessary
relative to a body of knowledge and statements contingent relative
to that body of knowledge is an important methodological dis-
tinction and should not be jettisoned. But the traditional philo-
sophical distinction between statements necessary in some eternal
sense and statements contingent in some eternal sense is not
workable. The rescuing move which consists in saying that if a
statement which appears to be necessary relative to a body of
4 This was pointed out by David Finkelstein in his lecture to the informal
subgroup on Measurement in Quantum Mechanics at the Boulder Symposilim
on Mathematical Physics, sponsored by the American Mathematical Society in
the summer of 1960.
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
APA ABSTRACTS 671
ETHICS
BY JOHN SWEIGART
This content downloaded from 62.204.213.86 on Mon, 03 Feb 2020 19:58:28 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms