Modern Western Philosophy PDF
Modern Western Philosophy PDF
Modern Western Philosophy PDF
philosophy
VI SEMESTER
CORE COURSE
BA PHILOSOPHY
UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT
UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT
STUDY MATERIAL
Core Course
BA PHILOSOPHY
VI Semester
©
Reserved
The modern era in western philosophy spans the sixteenth through the eighteenth
centuries. Modern era spurred mainly by advances in science, but also by criticisms of
revealed theology, philosophers attempted to accommodate new learning with a broad view
of human abilities, and to construct systematic understandings of the world that leads to the
enlightenment in the west. The medieval philosophy had close nexus to theology, but the
modern philosophy developed the philosophical method, formation of philosophical
systems and humanism. The modern western philosophy flourished with philosophical
traditions of Rationalism of Descartes, Leibniz and Spinoza, and Empiricism of Locke,
Berkeley and Hume. The modern western philosophy has further carried by
transcendentalism of Immanuel Kant and of Hegel’s Absolute.
Modern philosophers are scientific in their usual attitude, in contrast to the more
frequently aesthetic tendencies of ancient philosophers and the dominatingly theological
interests of the scholastics of the middle Ages. Ceasing to be the handmaiden of theology,
philosophy has instead become the interpreter of rapidly advancing sciences. Yet the
modern philosopher is not afraid to speculate more boldly than scientists do, and he seeks to
3reciognise the results of thevarious natural and social sciences in a picture of the world as
a whole in which room will be found for such of the values of art, morality, and religion as
can be shown to be consonant with the established results of scientific investigation. But it
is necessary to disclose facts as they may be, and to learn to live as well as possible in the
light of this knowledge. So an uncompromising search for truth is the chief characteristic
trait of the modern philosopher. He loves beauty and he esteems personal virtue and social
justice. But he cannot take a universe friendly to these values simply for granted. The first
necessity is to know things as they are.
The spirit of modern philosophy is individualistic, while those of both ancient and
medieval philosophy were, in different ways, inclined to be institutional. A modern thinker
is an individualist in the sense that he makes experiments for himself, verifies hypotheses
with his own eyes, and tests the logic of arguments with his own thinking. He looks to
authorities for suggestion, but he accepts nothing for truth simply because it is asserted by
some authority, no matter how venerable or widely esteemed. Thinkers developed a keen
critical faculty refusing to accept traditions and scriptures without critical examination.
People began to prefer democratic forms of government to the monarchical or aristocratic
forms that existed. There was more vehement demand for social justice and equal rights.
This tendency towards freedom, characteristic of the modern period, is best expressed by
the opposition to state interference in the private lives of citizens. The widespread desire for
freedom found its expression in the field of thought in the form of idealism. Reason and
logic were accepted as the final criteria both in the field of science and of philosophy. The
desire for independence found expression in the freedom of enquiry and thinking and the
opposition to all forms of tyrannical domination. Objective knowledge in every sphere was
demanded and produced.
The epoch of modern philosophy which began in 1453 is called the Renaissance. It is
subdivided into two periods. During the first of these, the Humanistic period (1453-1600
Bruno), the leadership in philosophy was in Italy, and inspiration was drawn from the study
of the Greek and Latin classical philosophers, although there was also much interest in what
little modern science then existed. The second period of the Renaissance is known as
Natural Science Period (1600-1690). All the philosophers of this period consciously imitate
and adapt the methods and points of view of the natural scientists contemporary with them,
and themselves in some case make contributions to mathematics and the natural sciences.
All are confident of the ultimate success of philosophy in disclosing the nature of reality,
and most of them do not hesitate to develop systems. Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes in
England, and Descartes, Spinoza and of Leibnitz on the continent of Europe are the thinkers
of this period. The Enlightenment (1690-1781) was inaugurated with the publication of
Locke’s Essay on the Human Understanding in 1690. Among the great thinkers in this
period are Locke, Berkeley, and Hume in Great Britain and Voltaire and Rousseau in
France. These philosophers are not elaborate system builders like those of the preceding
period; they believe that the proper study of mankind is man rather than the universe; they
are vigorous demolishers of superstition and upholders of individual liberty and the rights
of man. Their thought was stimulated by the English Revolution of 1688, and their
influence was a partial cause of the American Revolution in 1776 and the French
Revolution. The Idealistic Period is usually dated from 1781 when Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason appeared to the death of Hegel in 1831. Germans then led the world in the
originality and depth of their philosophical thought. In some form or other, each of the
German philosophers of this period believed that the world is spiritual in nature-the
expression of a universal Mind or Spirit. Such a point of view was inspiring to poetry and
religion. This was the great Romantic age in German literature (Goethe, Schiller etc-).
English poets like Wordsworth, Shelley, Coleridge, Tennyson and Browning as well as he
American Emerson express thoughts strikingly similar to the German idealistic
philosophers.
Modern means something which is not traditional, to break with the endless
reiteration of classical themes, topics and myths; to offer a critique of existing feudal super
structure (political, moral, religious and legal systems), to defend and develop scientific
explanation of every phenomenon, and to explain reality not only objectively but also as
experienced by the subject.
Modernist was a shift from faith to reason. Enlightenment is held to be the source of
critical ideas, such as the centrality of freedom, democracy and reason as being the primary
values of a society. In this view, the tendency of the philosophers in particular to apply
rationality to every problem is considered to be the essential change. From this point on,
thinkers and writers were held to be free to pursue the truth in whatever form, without the
threat of sanction for violating established ideas.
Bibliography
William Kelley Wright, A History of Modern Philosophy, the Macmillan Company, New
York, 1996
Singh, R.P., Philosophy: Modern and Postmodern 2nd Edition: Om Publications, New Delhi,
2002.
UNIT II RATIONALISM
INTRODUCTION
The main objective of this unit is to introduce rationalism especially Descartes’
rationalistic thinking. It helps the students to know the method of abstraction as well. In
this unit we shall try to understand how Descartes thinking deviate from classical
philosophy. Finally we see how Spinoza and Leibnitz developed rationalism which was
developed by Descartes in M
odern Western Philosophy.
The rationalists maintain that there are certain fundamental principles of reality,
which are innate and recognized as true by reason or intuition. Intuition is immediate
apprehension by reason. All other truths are deduced from them. With the help of
mathematical method we must reject the vague and obscure light of the senses and
imagination, and select the simple, clear, self-evident, and innate ideas of reason, and
deduce other truths from them.
Rene Descartes (1596-1650)
In the history of Western Philosophy, it is Rene Descartes (1596-1650) who ushers
in such new lines of thought as would clearly mark the beginning of the modern era and
earn him the title ‘Father and originator of Modern Western Philosophy’ and France’s
greatest philosopher. He emphasise the role of the individual and his reasoning power
against the background of church domination. He pronounces that it is within the power of
every individual to know the truth. He highly influence on mathematics and scientific
method. Francis Bacon (1561-1626) in England looked at scientific method and claimed it
for empiricism-a triumph of the method of observation and experimentation over reason,
theories, and systems. Descartes, however, looked at scientific method and claimed it for
rationalism-a triumph of mathematics, of geometry, and of reasoning by axioms and
deduction; it is these which make science into knowledge into certain. His vision was of a
plan for a single, unified science in which philosophy and all the sciences would be
interconnected in one systematic totality. All qualitative differences of things would be
treated as quantitative differences, and mathematics would be the key to all problems of the
universe. By contrast with Plato, who saw the unity of all sciences in the mystical Idea of
the Good, for Descartes the unity of science was a rationalistic and mathematical unity
based upon mathematical axioms. By contrast with medieval Aristotelianism, explaining
change teleologically as the movement of matter toward the actualization of forms, for
Descartes all change is explained mechanically, as the movement of bodies according to the
laws of physics. Descartes was a philosopher, a mathematician, and a man of science. He
used the analytic method, which supposes a problem solved, and examines the
consequences of the supposition. Modern western philosophy has very largely accepted the
formulation of its problems from Descartes, while not accepting his solutions.
INTUITION AND DEDUCTION
According to Descartes, knowledge must be certain and indubitable. In his Rules for
the Direction of the Mind (Regulae), he states, “All knowledge is certain and evident
cognition” which is “incapable of being doubted”. Such indubitable knowledge, he holds,
can be had only
through intellect or reason. He specifies two actions of the intellect through which we arrive
at certain knowledge, viz. Intuition and deduction. Intuition, according to him, is “the
indubitable conception of a clear and attentive mind, which proceeds solely from the light
of reason”. Hence by intuition; he means the rational power of the mind to perceive clearly
and distinctly. Such knowledge, according to him, is self-evident, standing in no need of
proof. Intuition is undoubted, immediate apprehension of a self-evident truth by reason.
God imprints certain innate ideas on the mind at the time of birth. The ideas of causality,
infinity, eternity, perfect Being of God and the like are innate ideas. In his view, we can
also acquire certainty when the facts are “inferred from true and known principles through a
continuous and uninterrupted movement of thought in which each individual proposition is
clearly intuited”. This is what he calls Deduction, which attains it’s certainty from the
intuitive certainty of the first principles and the intermediate steps. Thus Descartes applies
the mathematical method to philosophy. His mathematical method consists in intuition and
deduction. First principles are given by intuition. The remote conclusions are deduced from
them. Intuition is prior to deduction. Deduction is necessary inference from truths known
with certainty. Intuition is necessary in deduction. Though he subordinates deduction to
intuition, he speaks of these as two mental operations.
According to Descartes, it is through intuition i.e. the natural light of reason, that we
come to know the existence of the self or mental substance and then we gradually deduce
the existence of God and the external material world. Descartes accepts the existence of all
these three substances-mind, matter and God. In accordance with his definition of substance
as “a thing which so exists that it needs no other thing in order to exist,” he declares God as
the absolute substance. However, in the restricted sense of the term ‘substance’, he claims
that both mind and matter come under it because they do not depend on anything else but
“concurrence of God in order to exist.” Descartes recognises Mind and Matter as relative
substances, dependent upon the absolute substance, i.e., God. Mind and Matter have been
created by God. But the term substance is not applicable to Mind and Matter in the same
sense in which it is applicable to God. In this context, Spinoza points out that if substance
stands for complete independence, then it is contradictory to regard matter and mind as
substances because they depend on God for their being.
distinct and implanted in the mind by God at the time of birth; they are self-evident. He
distinguishes sense perception from reason on the ground that the former is liable to
illusion, and hence needs to be judged by reason before being accepted as true. His only
point of warning is that we should not accept reports of sense perception “without having
(carefully and maturely) mentally examined them beforehand.” With the help of his
mathematical method we must reject the vague and obscure light of the senses and
imagination, and select the simple, clear, self-evident, and innate ideas of reason, and
deduce other truths from them.
Descartes starts with the certainty of the self which is known intuitively. He deduces
the existence of God from the innate idea of God. The idea of God is the idea of an infinite
Being. It cannot be produced by myself, because I am a finite being. The finite things
cannot produce the idea of an infinite Being. The cause must contain at least as much reality
as is contained in the effect. So God or the infinite Being is the cause of the innate idea of
God. Therefore, God exists. He is perfect and truthful. We have a conviction that external
things exist; so they must exist. Thus Descartes deduces the existence of God and the world
from the innate ideas in the self, which are distinct, clear and self-evident.
exist as a thinking being to be deceived. Descartes starts with universal doubt. To doubt is
to think. To think is to exist. “Cogito ergo sum.” “I think, therefore I exist.” is the one
certain truth which may be taken as the foundation of philosophy. If I ceased to think, there
would be no evidence of my existence. I am a thing that thinks, a substance of which the
whole nature or essence consists in thinking and which needs no place or material thing for
its existence.
The doubt of Descartes should not be confused with psychological doubt. Descartes’
doubt is not a thing of direct feeling and experience but is a deliberate and dispassionate
attitude towards human experience in general. It is not directly determined by the nature of
objects. The doubt of Descartes should not be confused with scepticism. Descartes is not
asserting that whatever can be doubted is false, but he is only supposing it to be false.
Again, the scepticism is the finished conclusion about knowledge which professes the
denial of any certain knowledge whatsoever. However, the Cartesian doubt is only a
starting point to find out that which cannot be further doubted.
In Descartes’ theory of knowledge, the one truth that is unshakable, safe and secure
from any doubt, is that of my own existence as a conscious subject. Thus the Cartesian
Cogito introduces subjectivism into modern western philosophy. Subjectivism is the view
that I can know certainty only myself as conscious subject and my thoughts. It is the view
that I can know with certainty only my own mind and its content. Subjectivism carries the
implication that the knowledge of other minds and of material objects can be proved, if at
all, only by inference from what I know with certainty, the existence of my own subjective
consciousness and my thoughts or ideas. Therefore for subjectivism the knowledge of the
existence of everything other than my own mind becomes questionable, problematic.
The existence of the self, according to Descartes, is a self-evident truth, because the
very attempt to doubt its existence implies its existence. “For it is a contradiction to suppose
that what thinks does not at the very time when it is thinking, exists.”Hence Descartes
discovers that “I think, therefore I exist” (Cogito ergo sum) is an indubitable truth. Further,
he also realises that it is nothing but the clearness and distinctness of the fact ‘I think’ which
makes it an indubitable truth. So, he establishes the criterion of truth as ‘all things which I
perceive very clearly and very distinctly are true.” From this criterion of truth, Descartes
deduces our knowledge of the existence of God. According to him, we have within us the
idea of God who is a supremely perfect being and we clearly and distinctly perceive that
such an idea can be implanted in us “only by something which possesses the sum of all
perfections, that is, by a God who really
exists.”As an all-perfect Being cannot be lacking in existence, he claims, God must exist. In
his ‘Meditations’ and ‘Principles’, he goes to the length of arguing that the existence of
material
things follows from the existence of God, who being an All-Perfect Being, cannot be a
deceiver. Consequently, in his view, there must be things existing in the external world
corresponding to our clear and distinct ideas of them.
If the two substances are opposite to each other, how can there be interaction
between them? My arm moves when I will that it shall move, but my will is a mental
phenomenon and the motion of my arm a physical phenomenon. Why then, if mind and
matter cannot interact, does my body behave as if my mind controlled it? To solve this
problem Descartes introduces the Psycho-physical Interactionism. According to this theory,
body and mind act upon each other in the ‘Pineal gland’ of the brain which is the seat of the
mind. The body acts upon the mind in sensations and the mind causes movements to take
placed in the body through the will. So the body at sometimes affects the mind, at other
times the mind directs the body. Having separated mind from matter, and assigning them
two distinct domains, Descartes prepares the ground for advocating mechanical explanation
of the material world. All occurrences, in his view, are due to the transference of motion
from one part to another. He holds that even the functions of the human body follow from
the mechanical arrangements of its various organs. Even in the absence of mind, he
contends, “it would still perform all the same movements as it now does in those cases
where movement is not under the control of the will, or, consequently, of the mind.” The
relation of the soul to the body is of the nature of the pilot to his machine. But
Interactionism is objectionable. Interactionism holds that cerebral processes affect mental
processes and that mental processes affect cerebral processes. But two quite heterogeneous
substances cannot act and react upon each other. Action and reaction presuppose a certain
similarity in nature among the things which act and react upon one another. Qualitative
likeness is the invariable precondition of causal connection. Dualism contradicts the law of
Conservation of Energy. According to this law, the total amount of physical energy in the
universe is constant, and one kind of physical energy can be transformed into another kind
of physical energy without any loss of quantity, but no physical energy can be transformed
into non-physical or mental energy and vice versa as dualism supposes. For, in that case, the
total amount of physical energy in the universe would not he constant but it would be
constantly increased and decreased.
The Cartesian dualism appeared to have two features. The first was that it made the
soul wholly independent of the body, since it was never acted on by the body. The second
was that it allowed the general principle: “one substance cannot act on another.” There were
two substances, mind and matter and they were so dissimilar that an interaction seemed
inconceivable. It explained the appearance of interaction while denying its reality.
Benedict De Spinoza (1532-1677)
Followed by Descartes mathematical method Benedict De Spinoza (1532-1677)
starts with the innate idea of God or substance which is self-existent and conceived by
itself, and deduces the finite minds and the finite physical objects from it. Spinoza had the
vision of the unity of all things. Descartes ‘dependent substance’ is contradiction in terms.
A substance cannot depend on anything else. As such there can be only one substance. If
there were more than one substance then they would limit each other and thus would take
away their self-sufficiency. This one substance, he also calls God whom he defines as a
“Being absolutely infinite; that is, substance consisting in infinite attributes each of which
expresses eternal and infinite essence”. He calls it causasuior self-creative. By describing
substance as causasui, Spinoza means that the reality is a self-explanatory, all-inclusive,
inter-related whole, outside which nothing can lie. Therefore there is one substance which is
infinite. He calls the single substances as God. Nature conceived as a whole is identical
with God.Nature is known as NaturaNaturata, i.e., sum-total of all that exist. Nature is
governed by eternal laws. God and Nature are one. “All determination is negation”. There
can be only one Being who is wholly positive, and He must be absolutely infinite. This is
known as pantheism, according to which the reality of a single impersonal God permeates
and in dwells all things.
Spinoza rejected Cartesian dualism and rejected the substantiality of mind and body.
The attribute of Mind and Matter, i.e., thought and extension cannot interact are two parallel
attributes of the same absolute substance God. God has also an infinite number of other
attributes, since He must be in every respect infinite number of other attributes, since He
must be in every respect infinite; but these others are unknown to us. Spinoza believes that
Mind is the expression of the infinite consciousness of God and Matter is the appearance of
God’s unlimited extension. God is extended as well as thinking. Substance thinking and
substance extended are one and the same substance. Every mode of extension correspond a
mode of thought, in the same order or series. This parallelism excludes materialism as well
as idealism, for matter cannot explain mind, nor can mind explain matter. By admitting only
one substance God, Spinoza fails to explain the plurality, diversity, motion and change of
the objects of the world.
ABSTRACT MONISM
Mental order and physical order are parallel to each other. Wherever there is an idea,
there is a bodily change. Wherever there is a physical motion, there is an idea
corresponding to it Spinoza says, “just as thoughts and mental processes are connected in
the mind, so in the body its modifications, and the modifications of things are arranged
according to their order.” To avoid the difficulties of Dualism and Interactionism, Spinoza
God is the causal chain or process, the law and structure of the world, the underlying
condition of all things. He is the chain of natural events, the universal laws of nature.
Spinoza says, “God is the immanent, and not the extraneous cause of all things. All is God;
all lives and moves in God”. He conceives nature as natura naturans and, natura naturata.
The former is nature-producing, while the latter is nature produced. He affirms the identity
of God and nature in the sense of natura naturans: he denies the identity of God with nature
as natura naturata. Spinoza’s monism is abstract, because he lays stress on the eternal
nature of one substance or God and regards the phenomena of nature and human volitions
as unsubstantial modes having no reality of their own and following necessarily from it, and
because he regards the human minds as devoid of freedom of the will, and therefore, of
moral responsibility. He is an advocate of pantheism (pan-all; theos-God; all is God).
Pantheism leads to a cosmism and illusionism, denies human freedom and saps the very
foundation of morality. It regards God as an eternal substance, devoid of intelligence and
will, freedom and purpose, love and grace. It reduces religion to a myth, which believes in
personal God of love and grace, who responds to human prayer and makes communion
between Him and man possible. Its conception of God as an eternal impersonal substance
does not satisfy our religious aspirations. Its conception of man as a finite mode of God, its
core and essence, devoid of freedom and purpose, does not satisfy our moral aspirations. Its
denial of beauty and ugliness does not satisfy our aesthetic aspirations. Its denial of
morality and religion, in the strict sense of the term, forfeits its right to be regarded as
rational metaphysical hypothesis. It is right in so far as it recognizes the reality of one
substance or God. It is wrong in so far as it denies the reality of many objects and minds.
Leibniz (1646-1716)
Like Descartes and Spinoza, Leibniz (1646-1716) based his philosophy on the
notion of substance, but he differed radically from them as regards the relation of mind and
matter, and as regards the number of substances. Descartes allowed three substances, God,
Modern Western Philosophy 13
School of Distance Education
mind and matter; Spinoza admitted God alone. For Descartes, extension is the essence of
matter; for Spinoza, both extension and thought are attributes of God. Leibniz held that
extension cannot be an attribute of a substance. His reason was that extension involves
plurality, and can therefore only belong to an aggregate of substances; each single substance
must be unextended. He believed, consequently, in an infinite number of substances, which
he called “monads”. Each of these would have some of the properties of a physical point,
but only when viewed abstractly; in fact, each monad is a soul. This follows naturally from
the rejection of extension as an attribute of substance; the only remaining possible essential
attribute seemed to be thought. Thus Leibniz was led to deny the reality of matter, and to
substitute an infinite family of souls.
Leibnitz rejects matter and the reality of extension and defines substance as
indivisible, self-active and spiritual units. Therefore, according to Leibnitz the real elements
must be spiritual. He calls these indivisible, self-active and spiritual units as monads. They
are the true metaphysical points which though indivisible are non-existent. They are, again,
different from atoms which though existent are not indivisible. Only a spiritual unit is
indivisible like our own self-conscious existence, and yet in real. Hence the monads alone
are real.
Every monad is a mirror of the universe, but a living mirror which generates the
images of things by its own activity or develops them from inner germs, without
experiencing influences from without. The monad has no windows through which anything
could pass in or out, but in its action is dependent only on God and on itself. All monads
represent the same universe, but each one represents it differently, their difference consists
only in the energy or degree of clearness. The clearer the representations of a monad the
more active it is. Leibnitz suggests that to have clear and distinct perceptions only is the
prerogative of God. He alone is pure activity; all finite beings are passive as well, that is, so
far as their perceptions are not clear and distinct. No two monads can ever have any causal
relation to each other; when it seems as if they had, appearances are deceptive. Leibniz held
that every monad mirrors the universe, not because the universe affects it, but because God
has given it a nature which spontaneously produces this result. There is a “pre-established
harmony” between the changes in one monad and those in another, which produces the
semblance of interaction. This is an extension of the two clocks, which strike at the same
moment because each keeps perfect time.
Monads are real and infinite in number. They are eternal and cannot be destroyed.
They are indivisible self-contained and exclusive of everything else. Being a real unit, each
monad contains the whole infinity of existence. It has no windows through which anything
might come in or go out. The infinite number of monads is qualitatively unlike, so that no
two monads are alike. They are found in a hierarchical order of existence. Each monad
imperceptibly leads to others. There is no abrupt change anywhere in the connexion
granule. Only with the help of the absolute continuity between the monads we can explain
every variety of experience. Besides with the help of the law of continuous series we bridge
the gulf between mind and matter, men and animals, conscious and unconscious states.
Monads being spiritual have two important characteristics of perception and appetition. By
virtue of its perception each monad mirrors the whole infinity of existence. The more
developed monad in the series has clear perception and the less developed monad has
confused perception. The infinite gradations in the monads correspond to their stages of
development; there are different degrees of perception. Because each monad is a force,
therefore, it has appetition by virtue of which it tends to become the whole. Again, by virtue
of its appetition each monad tends to pass from obscure to clear perception. If an action is
done from very obscure perception then it is known as impulse and if it is done from clear
perception, then it is known as will. Thus the activity of the low monads is prompted by
will and desire. The distinction between impulse and desire is one of degree and not kind.
The monads are found in a continuous series, one imperceptibly passing into the other.
However, in this series we can note the main types of monads. The lowest or bare monads
are those in which the perception is most obscure. They go to make the inorganic bodies.
They are scarcely more than centres of forces and they express themselves in the form of
motion which appears to us purely mechanical. They may be said to be in profound stupor
or deep sleep. Then there are conscious monads endowed with memory. This may be called
souls. They go to make the plant and animal world. However, the highest monads called
spirits having reason and universal necessary knowledge. They are raised to the knowledge
of the self as well as of God.
Leibnitz tried to explain the relation between body and mind by his theory of Pre-
established Harmony. According to this theory, God at the time of creation established such
a harmony between mind and body-pre adjusted them to each other in such a way, that they
always correspond to each other without calling for his constant intervention as
occasionalism supposes. Body and mind thus may be regarded as two clocks which once
constructed and set to the same time go on keeping the same time without either of them
acting upon the other. Leibnitz says, “Each living body has a dominant entelechy, which in
the case of animal is the soul”, “The soul follows its own laws, and the body its own
likewise, and they accord by virtue of the harmony pre-established among all substances,
since they are all representations of one and the same universe. There is a perfect harmony
between the perceptions of the monad and the motions of the bodies, pre-established at the
outset between the system of efficient causes (bodies) and the system of final causes
(minds). Here inconsists the concord and the physical union of the soul and the body, which
exists without the one being able to change the laws of the other.
Leibnitz spiritualises body and mind and considers them to be composed of monads.
Monads are spiritual atoms or active perceiving forces. They are self-centred, self-
contained, self-active, substances of different degrees of complexity. The body is a cluster
of lower unconscious monads. The mind is a self-conscious higher monad. It is a dominant
Modern Western Philosophy 15
School of Distance Education
monad-a queen monad. The body and the mind correspond to each other, because God
established a harmony between them, adjusted them to each other after creation. Their
correspondence is due to pre-established harmony.
Leibnitz does not go to the root of the matter, and cannot explain how even God
could establish harmony between two entirely heterogeneous substances like body and
mind. Besides, body and mind both are composed of monads. Monads are self-contained
entities. They cannot act upon each other. So God, the Monad of monads cannot, act upon
other monads, and adjust them to one another; and establish harmony among them.
Causation is interaction. Leibnitz denies it in the monads. So he cannot admit it in God. In
order to solve the difficulty of interaction between body and mind, he makes the hypothesis
of the interaction of God upon monads. This is pushing the difficulty further back but not
solving it.
CONCLUSION
Rene Descartes (1596-1650), who is the father of modern western philosophy and
rationalist philosopher, follows a method of abstraction which is evident from his
fundamental contention that ‘reason’ is the source of clear and distinct knowledge, and
‘sensibility’ is a faculty of confused knowledge. Descartes rationalism goes from concrete
things to something highly abstract and he rejects the objects given by means of senses.
Descartes sees that one firm and immovable truth, cogito ergo sum, ‘I think, therefore, I
am’ that even the most extravagant skepticism cannot touch. This is the highest possible
abstraction. Following the method of abstraction, Descartes proceeds to analyse the nature
of material substance by separating it from mental substance. So there is no meeting ground
between mind and matter, both are diametrically opposed to each other. This is generally
known as Cartesian dualism which constitutes the basis for the development of European
philosophical thought in terms of two opposed trends-idealism and materialism. Descartes
himself could not furnish any satisfactory solution to this problem. We have to go beyond
dualism and search for its solution. Spinoza’s (1532-1677) attempt to solve Cartesian
dualism by admitting only one substance God by abstraction fails to explain the plurality,
diversity, motion and change of the objects of the world. Leibnitz (1646-1716) was a
pluralist, for according to him, each monad meets the requirement of substance. But once it
has been established that there are numerous substances- windowless monads- in the
universe, it becomes impossible to establish, the unity of the world.
What are the major limitations of rationalistic thinking? Rationalism rejects all
knowledge derived from the senses of experience (posteriori), and condemns it as illusory.
But we actually perceive the things around us clearly and distinctly, and so they cannot be
treated as unreal. Our life presupposes the existence of external things which produce clear
and distinct ideas, and to which we react successfully. We cannot spin out philosophy by
mere reason without experience. Philosophical knowledge is not like mathematical
knowledge. Mathematical knowledge is abstract; it deals with abstractions and deduction
Modern Western Philosophy 16
School of Distance Education
from them. The knowledge that is deduced from them is not concrete. But philosophy does
not deal with abstractions or imaginary entities: it ideals with real entities. It seeks to give a
rational concept of the realities as whole by rational reflection of the facts of experience. So
it cannot condemn experience as illusory. The facts are given by experience, organized by
sciences and finally harmonized with one another, and reduced to a system by philosophy
by rational reflection. Philosophy cannot do without reason; nor can it do without
experience. It is criticism of life and experience. The doctrine of innate ideas advocated by
Descartes is not tenable. Locke severely criticized Descartes’ doctrine of innate ideas.
Hume opposed Descartes’ rationalism with a more powerful empiricism. Hume rejected the
Descartes’ Cogito proof, proofs of God and metaphysical dualism.
KEY WORDS
Metaphysics: The philosophical inquiry into the nature of ultimate reality. In contemporary
usage, the term includes the analysis of fundamental philosophical principles.
Epistemology: (theory of knowledge): The branch of philosophy which studies the sources,
validity, and limits of knowledge, it inquires into perception, meaning, and truth.
Deduction: Orderly, logical reasoning from one or more statements (premises) which are
assumed, to a conclusion which follows necessarily.
Intuition: Direct and immediate knowledge, as in the case of our comprehension of self-
evident truths, such as the axioms of geometry.
Idealism: Any metaphysical theory which holds that reality is mental, spiritual, or has the
nature of mind, thought, or consciousness.
Materialism: Any monistic metaphysical theory which holds that ultimate reality is matter
and that all seemingly nonmaterial things such as minds and thoughts are reducible to the
motions of particles of matter.
A priori: Refers to knowledge that is derived solely from reason independently of the senses
(neither derived from sense nor alterable by it). The truth of apriori knowledge is claimed
to be both necessary and universal.
Rationalism: The view that appeals to reason, not the senses, as the source of knowledge. In
its most extreme form, rationalism insists that all knowledge is derived from reason.
Empiricism: The view that all human knowledge derived from the sense.
Dualism: Any view which holds that two equal but opposed ultimate, irreducible principles
are required for the explanation of reality. Good and evil, mind and matter are dualism.
Part C
(Each answer not to exceed 150 words each question carries 2 weightages)
1. The Causal Proof: The causal proof of the existence of God is based on two
assumptions, namely (i) individual consciousness knows itself to be finite, and, (ii)
This consciousness of ‘God’ is derived only from the conception of an absolutely
perfect being. Of course, some may object that the infinite being may be a negative
idea, i.e., that which is not finite. Now Descartes points out that the idea of the
Modern Western Philosophy 18
School of Distance Education
infinite being is the most positive idea for in comparison which the fullness of the
Perfect Being we realise our finitude.
2. Argument from clear and distinct idea: Descartes believes that a concept which is
absolutely clear and distinct among other concepts should be accepted as true. The
concept of God stands this test fairly. Hence, God does exist.
3. Cosmological Proof: There must be some creator of all objects and living beings in
the universe and man obviously cannot even create himself. He asks, what can be the
cause of myself, my parents and all other finite beings? This he concludes, can be
proved only with the help of the idea of a Perfect Being who has created everything
else in the world.
4. Ontological Proof: According to this, the existence of God follows from the very
idea of the perfect being. The most perfect being cannot be thought without thinking
of Him as actually existing. Of course, the idea and the actual finite thing are not
inseparable. One can think of a winged horse though there may be none in reality.
But this idea of a perfect being, according to Descartes, cannot be thought apart from
His existence.
There can be no substance without attributes. However, they may be either essential or
accidental. The essential attributes define a substance, i.e., without which the substance
would cease to be substance. The accidental attributes are those variable characters which
can lose without ceasing to be what it is. As substance is self-contained and is infinite, so it
has an infinite number of attributes. Hence, the substance of Spinoza has an infinite number
of attributes, each of which expresses the essence of the substance infinitely. Spinoza holds
that out of an infinite number of attributes, human intellect can perceive only two, namely
extension and thought. There is possibility of an infinite number of attributes, coexisting
together which neither limit one another nor the substance.
Modes can never exist without the substance though the substance can exist without
them. Every mode is in God for nothing can exist without God. The modes are individual
things of finite experience. Modes are said to be actual in so far as they exist at a certain
time and space. Spinoza sometimes regards the modes to be real affections actually existing
in God and sometimes looks upon them as mere illusions created by abstract imagination
which views things as separated and unrelated.
Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., and Murdoch, D., (Tr. And Ed.), The Philosophical Writings
of Descartes, Volumes I and II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Frederick Mayer, A History of Modern Philosophy, Eurasia Publishing House, New Delhi,
1987.
Haldane, E.S. and Ross, G.R. (Tr and Ed.) The Philosophical Works of Descartes,
JadunathSinha. Introduction to Philosophy, New Central Book Agency (p) Ltd., Calcutta,
1995.
Lavine, T.Z. From Socrates to Sartre: The Philosophic Quest. London: Bantam Books,
1989.
William Kelley Wright, A History of Modern Philosophy, The Macmillan Company, New
York, 1966.
INTRODUCTION
are quite unconscious of the so-called innate ideas such as causality, infinity, eternity, God
and the like. If there are innate ideas in the mind, they must be the same in all minds. But
the so-called innate ideas of God, morality and the like differ in different societies, in
different countries, and in different ages. They differ in different persons even at the same
time in the same society. Even if there were the same idea in all minds, it would not prove
their innateness. All persons have the same idea of fire. But it is not an innate idea; it is
derived by all from experience. Universality of an idea does not prove its innateness. The
so-called innate principles are general truths, which are induction from particular facts of
experience. They are not the primary facts of knowledge, but generalisations from particular
facts, which are acquired from perception. Perception is experience. The so-called innate
principles are derived from experience; they are empirical truths, and not innate and
intuitive. They are not a priori or prior to all experience. Thus Locke disproves Descartes’
doctrine of innate ideas.
Locke maintains that the mind is a tabula rasa in the beginning. It is like a clean
slate, blank white paper, on which experience writes, and this writing by experience is all
the mind can know. Mind has no innate ideas. It receives ideas from experience. Experience
is twofold; sensation and reflection. Sensation is external perception. Reflection is internal
perception. Sensation is the source of our knowledge of external objects. Reflection is the
source of our knowledge of the internal states of mind. There is not a single idea in the
mind, which is not derived from sensation or reflection. The child gets his first ideas from
sensation; then at an advanced age he reflects upon them. He cannot think before his mind
is stocked with sensations. Descartes maintains that the mind always thinks even before it is
furnished with sensations and that it can think independently of sensations. But Locke
maintains that the mind cannot think before it has sensations. Sensations are the materials
on which the mind thinks. The mind is passive in receiving sensations. But it is active in
comparing them with one another, combining them into complex ideas, and forming general
ideas out of particular ideas. It can form complex ideas out of simple ideas. “There is
nothing in the intellect which was not previously in the sense.” This is the dictum of Locke.
All knowledge is derived from experience; it is posterior to or after experience. Knowledge
is inductive in procedure and not deductive as Descartes and Spinoza think. Knowledge
starts with particular facts of experience, and makes generalizations from them. It does not
start with some self-evident innate ideas or principles, and deduce other truths from them.
This theory is called a posteriori theory of knowledge. It is called empiricism because
experience is the only reliable source of knowledge and testing all claims to knowledge.
Empiricism is thus basing knowledge upon the senses, upon the flux of the sensible world,
which rationalism rejected as an inferior way of knowing.
Locke also takes over the subjectivism of Descartes, the view that what I know best
is my own mind and its ideas. Thus there enters into empiricism the problem inherent in
subjectivism which we found in Descartes: the chasm or gap between my own mind with its
ideas and the physical objects and human beings to which my ideas refer, and which are
external to me, in the physical and social world. How can I know them since I am confined
to knowing with certainty only my own ideas?
George Berkeley (1685-1753) pushes ahead with the argument of empiricism and
demolishes Locke’s acceptance of the belief held by Descartes that physical substances
exist. We can never have sensory experiences of material substances, says Berkeley. We
can experience only sensory qualities. What is my actual experience of substance? It is only
the experience of qualities. I perceive a tree as a certain size and shape, I perceive the
diameter of its trunk, the length of its branches, the brown colour of its trunk and branches,
and the green colour of its leaves; I touch its rough textures and smell its woody aroma- but
I can never perceive its substance itself. All that I have perceived of the tree are its qualities.
I have no perception of a substance. The existence of physical substances, Berkeley
concludes, is only in their being perceived. According to Berkeley, esseestpercipi, the
existence of a thing consists in its being perceived; a substance, in order to be real, must be
perceived by the mind. So Locke’s unknown and unknowable substratum is a meaningless
abstraction. A substance, so far as matter is concerned, is nothing but a cluster of
sensations. Physical substances cannot be known to have any other existence than in the
qualities we perceive. For Berkeleian empiricism matter -physical substance, the physical
universe- do not exist. But he believed that mental substances exist, in the form of finite
minds and also in the form of God as infinite mind. The laws of nature for Berkeley are
only the regularities of our own perceptions or ideas. Berkeley assured us that with the help
of God our perceptions are reliable and orderly and that we can therefore trust in the
uniformity of experience and in the dependability of scientific laws. But Hume gleefully
asks how does Berkeley know that mental substance exists? Under this attack we will see
collapse the idea that there are mental substances.
are not created by our own minds, but communicated to us by God who is the cause of
oursensations. He produces sensations in the finite minds according to fixed laws. He
admits the existence of minds alone, of the finite minds and of God or the infinite Mind. He
denies the existence of the external world. Hence his doctrine is called subjective idealism.
Berkeley offers the following arguments for the subjectivity of the primary qualities.
First, the primary qualities extension, solidity, number, rest and motion are perceived by the
mind. Therefore, they are ideas of the mind. They are sensible qualities. They are sensible
because they are perceived. Apart from their relation to our sensibility, they have no
existence. They have no existence apart from our sight and touch. They are perceived by the
mind; and whatever is perceived are ideas of the mind. They have no existence apart from
the mind that knows them; they have mind dependent existence. In this sense, they are
ideas. Berkeley says, “It is evident that extension, figure and motion are only ideas existing
in the mind, and that consequently neither they nor their archetypes can exist in an
unperceiving substance.” Locke wrongly maintains that they are the original, primary
qualities of matter which imprint their ideas on our minds. Secondly, the primary qualities
and the secondary qualities cannot be perceived apart from each other. Colour cannot be
perceived apart from extension, and extension cannot be perceived apart from colour by
sight. Heat and cold cannot be perceived apart from extension, and extension cannot be
perceived apart from heat and cold by touch. So if colour and temperature are ideas of the
mind, then extension also must be an idea of the mind. If the secondary qualities are ideas,
then the primary qualities also must be ideas. Berkeley says, “if it be certain that those
original qualities are inseparably united with the other sensible qualities, and, not even in
thought, capable of being abstracted from them, it plainly follows that they exist only in the
mind. Extension, figure and motion, abstracted from all other qualities, are inconceivable.
Thirdly, the same temperature appears different to different persons or to the same person at
different times under different conditions. Dip your hand into hot water; it appears hot to
you. Dip the same hand into warm water; it will appear cool to you. But the same water
cannot be hot and cool at the same time. So Locke argues that temperature is not a real
quality of matter but only an idea of the mind. Berkeley likewise argues that extension,
weight, motion and number appear different to different persons or to the same person
under different conditions. A person, who appears tall at a short distance, appears short at a
great distance. A stone that appears heavy to one appears light to another. A motion that
appears swift to one, appears slow to another. The same thing is one, three, or thirty six
according as it is measured by a yard, a foot, or an inch. So extension, weight, motion and
number are ideas of the mind.
Solidity cannot be perceived apart from extension, which is an idea. So solidity also
is an idea; all primary qualities are ideas.
Berkeley says, “great and small, swift and slow, are allowed to exist nowhere
without the mind, being entirely relative, and changing as the frame or position of the
organs or sense varies. The extension, therefore, which exists without the mind is neither
great nor small, the motion which exists without the mind is neither swift nor slow; that is,
they are nothing at all. That number is entirely the creature of the mind will be evident to
whoever considers that the same thing bears a different denomination of number as the
mind views it with different respects. Thus, the same extension is one, three or thirty-six- as
the mind considers it with reference to a yard, a foot, or an inch.
Then Berkeley refuses the existence of matter. He offers the following arguments
for the non-existence of matter. First, Locke regards matter as the unknown and
unknowable substratum of the primary qualities. The primary qualities are real, and so they
must abide in matter. It is their substratum and support. Berkeley argues, “esse est percipi”
Existence consists in being perceived. Locke himself admits that matter cannot be
perceived. It is unknown and unknowable. So it does not exist. Secondly, matter is said to
be the support of the primary qualities. But does it support them as the pillars support a
building? They are perceived to support it. But matter is not perceived to support the
primary qualities. It cannot be said to support them in an unknown manner. Thirdly, matter
is regarded by Locke as the substratum of the primary qualities. But there are not external
primary qualities. They are ideas of the mind only. So there is no need of assuming the
existence of matter to support them. Fourthly, if matter exists, it is known either by the
senses or by reason. If it is known through the senses, it is nothing but an idea. Whatever is
perceived is an idea. Nor can it be known through reason or inference. We are not
compelled to infer the existence of matter to account for our sensations, because dreams are
ideas of the mind, which are not excited by external objects. So sensations also may be
produced in our minds without external material things. There is no necessary connection
between sensations and material things. Sensations are produced by God in our mind.
Fifthly an object can never be perceived apart from its sensation. Berkeley says, “It is
impossible for me to see or feel anything without an actual sensation of that thing, so it is
impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible thing or object distinct from the
sensation or perception of it. In truth, the object and sensation are the same thing and cannot
therefore be abstracted from each other”. An object can never be perceived apart from its
sensation. Therefore, a perceived object is identical with a sensation. It has no existence
outside of mind. Sixthly, Locke advocates representative theory of perception, and
maintains that ideas are copies of representations of external objects. Berkeley argues,if
ideas are like objects the objects must be ideas. Berkeley says, “An idea can be nothing but
an idea; a colour or figure can be like nothing but another idea. If there is likeness between
ideas and their objects, they must be identical in their nature, and the objects must be
nothing but ideas.
Sensations are independent of our will; they are not created by our own minds. Nor
can they be created by other finite minds. The sun, the moon, mountains, rivers, oceans are
sensations, which cannot be produced by the finite minds. Nature is a system of sensations
or ideas produced in the finite minds by God according to fixed laws. The laws of nature are
the uniform ways according to which sensations are produced by God in the finite minds.
There is neither matter nor physical causation. There is only spiritual causation or will-
Modern Western Philosophy 25
School of Distance Education
causality. God is the cause of sensations. This is the doctrine of subjective idealism,
immaterialism, or spiritualism. Berkeley denies the reality of material substance. He
reduces the material world to appearances presented to the senses or subjective ideas
perceived by the finite minds. He admits the reality of the finite spirits and the Infinite
Spirit or God and their ideas. The conception of God saves Berkeley’s philosophy from
lapsing into solipsism. According to Solipsism, I and my ideas are real; I am certain of my
own existence and of my ideas. I do not know anything beyond myself and my ideas.
Berkeley is not really solipsist, for he explicitly holds (a) that the world contains, in
addition to me and my ideas, other finite spirits with their ideas, and (b) that I am not the
source of my presentations, but I am dependent for them on God, who cause them to occur
in a fixed and regular order”
Is there no difference, then, between real things and imaginary things? Berkeley
replies that real things are sensations produced in the finite minds by God according to
fixed laws but that imaginary things are the ideas of imagination, creations of the finite
minds. Sensations are stronger, livelier, more regular, and independent of the finite minds,
while images are weaker, fainter, less lively, and irregular. Berkeley says, the ideas
imprinted on the senses by the Author of Nature are called real things; and those excited in
the imagination, being less regular, vivid, and constant, are mere properly termed ideas or
images of things which they copy or represent. Both sensations and ideas are mind
dependent and subjective, and have no existence independently of the finite mind. Berkeley
says, the ideas of sense are more strong, lively and distinct than those of imagination; they
have likewise a steadiness, order, and coherence, and are not excited at random, as those
which are the effect of human wills often are, but in a regular train or series”. But our
sensations are never so vivid and distinct, are nevertheless ideas; that is, they exist in the
mind, or are perceived by it, as truly as the ideas of its own framing. Thus according to
Berkeley, real thing are different from unreal things because sensations are different from
images, but still they both exist in the finite minds which have them.
At the very outset of his book A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume holds, “All the
perceptions of the human mind divide themselves into two different kinds, which I shall call
Impressions and Ideas.” It follows from the above citation that Hume accepts two basic
premises of Locke. First, sense-perception is the only source of knowledge. Secondly, what
we apprehend through sense-perception are impressions and ideas. Here, we may point out
that what Hume calls ‘impressions’ are nothing other than the ‘simple ideas’ of Locke and
‘ideas’ of Berkeley. ‘Ideas’, for Hume, refer to the copies of impressions. It shows that all
three of them-Locke, Berkeley and Hume, accept the Cartesian assumption, namely, the
mind knows only its own ideas. Even with ideas as the immediate data of sense-perception,
Locke attempts to establish materialism. Though Hume agrees with Locke that what the
mind directly knows through sense-experience are ideas, yet as to Locke’s materialism, he
takes the side of Berkeley. Following Berkeley, Hume rejects Locke’s abstract general ideas
signifying material substances. On the ground that we cannot assert the existence of
anything which is not ‘given’ through our sense-perception, Hume rejects not only the
material substance of Locke, but also Berkeley’s spirit or mental substance. He advocates
the reality of impressions and ideas, alone. To quote him, “Now since nothing is ever
present to the mind but perceptions, it follows that it is impossible for us to so much as
conceive or form an idea of anything specifically different from ideas and impressions.”His
implication is that as our concepts of matter and mind as enduring substances are
specifically different from impressions and ideas, we cannot assert their existence.
Hume defines impressions and ideas in the following term, “Those perceptions,
which enter with the most force and violence, we may call impressions, and under this
name I comprehend all our sensations, passions and emotions as they make their first
appearance in the soul. By Ideas I mean the faint images of these in thinking and
reasoning.” In this definition, Hume makes it clear that both ‘impressions’ and ‘ideas’ are
‘perceptions’ of our mind, and the difference between them lies not in kind but only in the
‘degrees of force and liveliness, with which they strike upon the mind”.‘Impressions’, in his
view, are the lively perceptions. When we reflect on these lively perceptions, we receive
‘ideas’, which are less lively copies of these ‘impressions’. In order to emphasise the mental
character of ‘impressions’ and ‘ideas’, Hume maintains that the difference between them is
a difference of feeling and ‘thinking’. Thereby, he means that impressions are directly felt,
strong and vivid perceptions, whereas ‘ideas’ are comparatively feeble perceptions acquired
through recollection or imagination. Thus, putting all the stress on the degree of vivacity
with which ‘impressions and ideas’ are received by the mind, he says, “Everyone of himself
will readily perceive the difference betwixt feeling and thinking.” Here we notice the
difference between Locke and Hume. According to Locke, the strength and vivacity of the
simple ideas of sensation assure us of the presence of external material objects as the causes
of these ideas. It is this fact of being caused by extra-mental reality which, in Locke’s view,
distinguishes the ideas of sensation from the ideas of memory and imagination. Hume
however does not refer to any substantial reality, material or mental as the cause of our
‘impressions’. By ‘impressions’, he simply means those mental awareness or ‘perceptions’
which are distinguished from ‘ideas’ in respect of the degrees of ‘force and liveliness’ with
which they are felt. He does not distinguish between impressions and ideas by the manner
of their production. To quote him “By the term impression I would not be understood to
express the manner, in which our lively perceptions are produced in the soul, but merely the
perceptions themselves”.
Hume attempts to exhibit the priority of impressions through different examples. For
instance, he argues that if we lack any one of our sense-organs, then in the absence of
specific impressions, we cannot have the corresponding ideas also. “A blind man can form
no notions of colours, a deaf man of sounds.”To mention another example cited by Hume
where he says, “We cannot form to ourselves a just idea of the taste of a pineapple, without
having actually tasted it.”He means that we cannot form the accurate idea of anything
without the previous impressions of it. In these examples, we observe Hume’s attempt to
give a realistic interpretation of his epistemology and ontology. However, all these
examples, in the process of showing the temporal priority of impressions, prove the
existence of material objects also. Hence, it follows from Hume’s own examples that the
distinguishing feature of impressions is not vivacity or temporal priority but the fact that
they are caused by objective reality which is lacking in the case of ideas. Whereas Locke
emphasises the objective ground of the simple ideas of sensation, Hume puts all the stress
on the subjective characteristics of ‘impressions’.
Just like Locke’s division of simple ideas into those of sensation and reflection,
Hume draws a similar distinction within impressions: namely, impressions of sensations
and impressions of reflection. An impression of sensation, in Hume’s view, “arises in the
soul originally from unknown causes”. This view implies that there are existents other than
impressions and ideas but because they are not given in our sense-perception, they are
‘unknown’ to us. This statement contradicts his view that “we never....can conceive any
kinds of existence, but those perceptions...” Hence, it seems to us that two different
interpretations of Hume’s ontological position are possible. On the one hand, we cannot
conceive any other existences than ‘perceptions’ i.e., impressions and ideas; on the other
hand, his view implies that there are existences other than ‘perceptions’ but they are
‘unknown’ to us. Herein lays agnosticism in Hume. As according to Hume, we do not know
either external material substances or identical mental substance, the origin of the
impressions of sensation is unknown for us. Impression of reflection, in Hume’s view, “is
derived in a great measure from our ideas...” An impression leaves its copy i.e., idea in the
mind, and reflecting on this idea, the mind may again receive a new impression like desire
or aversion. Hume calls it the impression of reflection. As this kind of impression is directly
derived from an idea, we observe that neither of Hume’s two criteria, namely ‘liveliness’ or
‘priority’ is properly applicable to it.
THE PSYCHOLOGICAL LAWS OF ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS
Impressions and ideas, which constitute the matter of knowledge, are disconnected
from one another. They are connected with one another by the laws of association. The laws
Modern Western Philosophy 28
School of Distance Education
of association are purely subjective. Discrete impressions and ideas are automatically
combined with one another according to these laws. They do not require any innate ideas or
a priori forms of reason to connect them with one another. Hume advocates through-going
empiricism. Impressions or sensations are the first units of knowledge; ideas or images are
their faint copies. They are combined with one another according to the laws of association
to form complex ideas. Knowledge is composed of sensations and ideas combined by the
laws of association.
Hume has said that our atomic (distinct and separable) ideas, which correspond to
our impressions, are connected or associated by three laws of association, which are a
gentle force or impulse leading us to associate one idea with another. The association of our
ideas is based upon three qualities of our ideas, which tend to lead the mind from one idea
to another, to connect or associate one idea with another. The first law is that ideas are
associated or connected by the resemblance between ideas. The second law by which we
associate or connect one idea with another is by contiguity, one idea being close to, or
adjacent to, another in space or time. The third law of the association of ideas is by cause
and effect. These three laws pertain to all our thinking, thus also to our scientific thinking.
All our reasoning about matters of fact, says Hume, is causal reasoning. And our most
important reasoning about matters of fact is scientific reasoning, with its causal laws of
nature.
Hume claims that the relation of cause and effect is the crucial concept in all our
thinking about factual matters. By necessary connection is meant the relation between cause
and effect in which the cause necessarily produces the effect. Hume now asks the powerful
question: From what impression, if any, does the idea of cause arise? The principle, that
everything must have a cause that nothing is uncaused, that something cannot come from
nothing was regarded by Descartes and by the scholastic philosophers before him and the
rationalistic philosophers after him, as a self-evident truth that proves itself directly to
reason. Hume concludes that there is no rational proof whatsoever of the causal principle.
He says flatly: “Every demonstration which has been produced for the necessity of a cause
is fallacious.” If we believe in the causal principle, he says, it is only through habit or
custom that we do so, there is no rational basis for it. Here in this astonishing conclusion we
see the outcome of Hume’s early breakthrough: his notion of combining empiricism with
Hutcheson’s view of morality as coming only from sentiment or feeling. This had led Hume
to the startling thought that what is true of morality is also true of science: that our scientific
laws have their source only in feelings.
Why do we think that a particular cause must necessarily have a particular effect?
We cannot know this by reason. Hume comes up with the answer. We have the idea of a
necessary connection between a particular cause and effect after we experience their
conjunction repeatedly. He calls this constant conjunction. If repeatedly we have sensory
impressions of fire as spatially contiguous to my fingers and temporally prior to my fingers’
having a sensation of burning, “without any further ceremony,” says Hume, “we call the
one cause and the other effect.”Impressions of the constant conjunction, spatially and
temporally, of the flaming match and the burning sensation in the fingers still do not
provide an impression of necessary connection. If the idea of necessary connection has no
corresponding impression, then on Hume’s empiricist principle: no impression, no idea- the
idea of a necessary connection between cause and effects is worthless as knowledge and is
meaningless, a fraud, nonsense. Thus Hume’s empiricist rule is not only a test of the worth
of our ideas as knowledge (where there is no impression, the idea is worthless) but is also a
test of the meaning of our ideas (where there is no impression, the idea is meaningless).
Since necessary causal relation does not come from sensory impressions, it must be
subjective; it must come from the mind, and specifically from the psychological laws of
association of ideas. The idea of necessary connection between causes and effects is not in
the objects we observe, but only in the mind, he concludes. Thus the idea of necessary
connection between particular causes and effects is derived not from rational self-evidence
and not from any empirical sense impression, but only from the psychological association
of our ideas. Hume has shown that causal necessity is not an objective relationship between
things which scientists can observe, but is only a subjective compulsion to relate things by
the psychological laws of association. There is no necessary connection between objects.
There is only the psychological necessity of our associating ideas with one another. Hume
says: “Objects have no discoverable connection together, nor is it from any other principle
but custom...that we draw any inference from one...to the other.” Hume’s point is that the
idea of necessary connection between cause and effect is something that experience can
never give us. Each impression is a separate experience. Experience cannot guarantee that
this effect is necessary. Thus Hume redefines the idea of the cause-effect relation. A cause
is an object in constant spatial and temporal conjunction with another such that the
experience of the one compels the mind to expect the other. This is all that we can mean by
the cause –effect relationship.
For Hume all the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be divided into
two kinds of propositions, to wit, Matters of Fact and Relations of Ideas and they are
mutually exclusive.
Relations of ideas have certainty but no factual content, and matters of fact which
have empirical content but no certainty.
Even though Hume has conceded that logical certainty can be attained through
demonstrative reasoning in the field of the relations of ideas, he has implied in the
Enquiries, that such knowledge is only verbal, or tautologous. As the ‘relations’ are already
contained in the ideas, they do not provide any new information. In the Treatise, he has
brought the faculty of reason into question. As human beings are not infallible, he argues
that there is a possibility of error even with regard to rational knowledge. Hume has thus
resolved both empirical and rational knowledge into mere probability.
With regard to the idea of substance, when we ask, from what impressions does it
arise, the answer cannot claim to be from an impression of substance, but only from
impressions of qualities we experience, such qualities as size, shape, colour. Then the idea
of substance is nothing but these qualities which we experience. We cannot, therefore, say
that substances exist. We can know that something exists only if we have an impression of
it, only if we have sensory experience of it. And so Hume destroys the claim that substance
exist by showing that we have no impressions of physical substances. As far as our
knowledge of the world of facts is concerned, we are limited to our atomistic impressions
and their corresponding ideas. These impressions and ideas appear repeatedly in our
experience. We have no way of knowing what causes them. We have no knowledge that an
external world exists, that physical substances exist, that a God exists. There is no God.
There is no valid proof for the existence of God. We have no impression of God. We do not
perceive Him, nor can we infer His existence. We wish to believe in God to fulfil our
aspirations. So we believe in God. The idea of God is man-made. This is also the case for
the idea of mental substance, and specifically for Descartes’ claim that I am a thinking
substance. There is no sensory impression to which the idea of thinking substance
corresponds. On empiricist principles we cannot claim to have any knowledge of the self as
a unity, as permanent and continuous, but only as a series of perceptions. Hume says “the
rest of mankind.... are nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which
succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and
movement.” This is Hume’s famous “bundle of perceptions” theory of the self. Hume
cannot claim that the flux of our perceptions have even the unity of a bundle. Hume is here
getting close to the view of self as a stream of consciousness. Hume himself says, “The
mind is a kind of theatre, where perceptions successively make their appearance, pass and
re-pass, glide away and mingle in an infinite variety of postures and situations.” There is no
continuity, no permanence, and no identity, in these appearances in the theatre of the mind.
But suddenly Hume catches himself and says that, strictly speaking, there is not even a
theatre that we can know anything about through a sense impression. And thus the outcome
of Hume’s driving, consistent empiricism, which requires that the basis for our knowledge
be solely in sensory impressions, leads to the conclusion that we have no knowledge. Not
only is metaphysics impossible, science is also impossible. The causal laws of science have
been reduced by Hume to the psychological laws of association of ideas. Through animal
instinct we have animal faith in the world of the senses, and thus we are able to function in
the world, says Hume. Animal faith, not philosophy, governs our lives.
In the Treatise, Hume not only brings the certainty of geometry to question, but also
expresses doubt with regard to the very capacity of reason. Hume argues that it is never
possible to claim certainty about a chain of reasoning as a rational proof. First of all, our
judgement about the proof is probable and not completely certain. Then, our assessment of
this judgment about the proof is also probable. Further, the evaluation of our ability to judge
our judgment is also probable. Thus, the process leads to an infinite regress. There is no
guarantee of certainty even in the field of ‘Relations of Ideas’ and in the realm of ‘Matters
of Fact.’ Thus for Hume, “all knowledge degenerates into probability” In Hume’s view,
probability is all that we can aspire for in our life.
CONCLUSION
KEY WORDS
Ontology: Ontology is the metaphysical inquiry into the nature of being in general.
Enlightenment: A movement in Europe from about 1650 until 1800 that advocated the use
of reason and individualism instead tradition and established doctrines.
Causal Laws: Descriptive laws asserting a necessary connection between events of two
kinds, of which one is the cause and the other the effect.
Causal Reasoning: Inductive reasoning in which some effect is inferred from what is
assumed to be its cause, or some cause is inferred from what is assumed to be its effect.
Cause: Either the necessary condition for the occurrence of an effect or the sufficient
condition for the occurrence of an effect, understood as the conjunction of its necessary
conditions. The latter meaning is more common, and is the sense of cause used when we
wish to produce something or event.
Necessary conditions: Necessary conditions for something are those factors without which
that thing cannot exist, as breathing is a necessary condition for human life.
Substance: (1) An individual thing, a unity of matter and form; (2) by contrast with
properties, qualities, attributes, a substance is that which possesses or has properties,
qualities; (3) by contrast with properties, qualities, a substance is that which requires no
other thing in order to exist.
Monism:Any view which holds that one principle is sufficient to explain reality.
Part C-(Each answer not to exceed 150 words each question carries 2 weightages)
Empiricist philosopher John Locke has maintained that all reality is individual, and that
universals exist only in the abstract understanding. George Berkeley advances a step further
by bringing into question the possibility even of abstract ideas. We have no faculty for
framing abstract ideas. As all beings are particular things so all ideas are particular ideas,
Berkeley suggests. He points out two fundamental mistakes-the assumption of general ideas
in the mind, and the belief in the existence of a material world outside it. Berkeley claims,
in reality there are only particulars, and in our minds there are only images, not concepts. In
considering the individual ‘Paul’ I can attend exclusively to those characteristics which he
has in common with all men or with all living beings. But it is impossible for me to
represent this complex of common qualities apart from his individual peculiarities. Self-
observation shows that we have no general concepts. Ideas are the only object of the
understanding.
The real aim in the refutation of abstract ideas was to establish immaterialism. Matter is
an abstract idea for it means something which is moving and stationary, hard and soft etc.,
all and yet none of these. Besides, it means something existing apart from its being
perceived. But this is a vicious abstraction for what right have we to maintain that there can
be something independent of our perception when everything in our actual experience is
always in our perception? Thus matter is an abstract ideas but an abstract idea does not
exist. Hence matter does not exist. This is the general refutation of matter.
According to Locke and Descartes, there are six original or primary qualities of
extension, figure, solidity, motion, rest and number are supposed to be really in things and
the secondary qualities of colour, sound, taste, heat, cold etc- are supposed to be in the
perceiver and not in the things. Primary qualities are utterly inseparable from material
bodies, in all their different sizes and various changes. They are constantly found in the
bodies. Locke points out that primary quality are found in their objective right. They are
really existent whether there be any person to perceive them or not. But secondary qualities
are totally dependent on human subjects and their various sense-organs. Without eyes, there
are no colours, without ears there are not sounds. Besides, secondary qualities are relative
for the same bucket of water may be cold or hot, according to different arrangement.
Finally, secondary qualities are produced bythe primary qualities of bulk, solidity etc.
According to Berkeley the so-called primary qualities are also ideas. Ideas are mental.
Therefore, even the primary qualities are mental. And, hence there is no matter.
Hume. A Treatise of Human Nature, L.A. Selby-Bigge (Ed). Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1965.
--- An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1955.
Jagunath, Singha. Introduction to Philosophy, Calcutta: New Central Book Agency, 1995.
Locke, J., An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, P.H. (Ed.) Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1975.
Taylor, A.E. David Hume and the Miraculous. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1927.
T.Z. Lavine. From Socrates to Sartre: The Philosophic Quest. New York: Bantam Books,
1989.
INTRODUCTION
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is the most influential thinker because he gave a new
direction to modern philosophy and of European Enlightenment. Kant have made great stir
in the fields of epistemology, metaphysics, morality and aesthetics. Today philosophers
may disagree with Kant on many points, but no one can ignore him. By and large,
contemporary philosophers, whatever their disagreements with Kant might be, would tend
to accept his understanding of the role of metaphysics. In Kant’s time, as in the days of
Greek philosophy, the term metaphysics referred to the inquiry concerning the nature of
ultimate reality. Kant’s Copernican revolution, however, resulted in the internalisation of
these questions and showed that questions of metaphysics and epistemology are
interrelated. In his writing Kant had not merely a theoretical purpose but also a practical
impulse. Philosophy was to answer the problems of our intellect and the demands of our
moral nature. Kant attempted to answer Hume’s scepticism and to find a foundation for
knowledge.
The main objective of this unit is to introduce Immanuel Kant’s critical philosophy,
an attempt to reconcile Continental rationalism and British empiricism. It helps the students
to know the method of transcendentalism as well. We shall show Kant’s epistemology,
metaphysics, ethics and enlightenment rationality. By the end of this Unit one should be
able to read his famous works Critique of Pure Reason,Foundations of the Metaphysics of
Morals and his famous pamphlet known as “An Answer to the Question: ‘What is
Enlightenment?”(1784)
Who is right in the epistemological debate: the empiricists, with their emphasis on the
senses as the exclusive source of our knowledge of the world, or the rationalists, who insists
on reason alone as the final arbiter of truth? Kant, who was familiar with the philosophy of
Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, was steeped in a form of rationalistic philosophy stemming
from Descartes but was more immediately influenced by the German philosopher Leibniz.
Are we to face only the dogmatism (Kant’s term for rationalism) or the scepticism (Kant’s
term for empiricism)? Scepticism and rationalism appeared to Kant to pose twin threats to
philosophy.
predicate,” so that “God exists” cannot be analytically derived from “God is the most
perfect being.” In contrast, Kant endorses Descartes’ claim that the statement “I exist” is
contained in the statement “I think”. Kant most definitely disagrees with Descartes’
statement that my existence as a mind is more immediately known than the existence of
bodies outside me, including my own. He criticizes Descartes for ignoring the fact that my
consciousness of the existence of bodies outside me is just as immediate as my
consciousness of the existence of my own mental states, at least insofar as I am conscious
of this existence as determined in time.
The empiricists had shown a proper concern with understanding the origin of
knowledge, but they were guilty of several unexamined assumptions about the knowing
process. The first of these assumptions was that the mind of the knower is purely passive, a
receptacle for impressions (Hume’s term) or sensations (Locke’s term). John Locke had
explicitly described the knowing mind as a blank tablet, a tabula rasa on which the senses
write, or as an empty cabinet filled with ideas which are but copies of sensations. The
second unexamined assumption was that the mind is incapable of generating anything out
of its own internal operations necessary for the knowing process. Kant challenges both of
these assumptions. Even though “there can be no doubt that all our knowledge begins with
experience,” Kant observes, “it does not follow that it all arises out of experience”. The
empiricist were right in thinking that all our knowledge is based on our experience of the
world; they were wrong in assuming that the mind has a purely passive role and contributes
nothing to the knowing process. Kant referred to his views as a (second) Copernican
revolution because they reversed the prevailing views in epistemology by emphasizing the
active role of the mind in generating knowledge, in contrast to the mind’s passive role in the
empirical philosophies of Locke and Hume. Prior to the time of Copernicus it was believed
that the Earth was the centre of the universe and that the heavenly bodies revolved around
it. Now we know that the sun is the centre of our solar system, and the Earth one of the
planets orbiting it. Similarly, prior to Kant’s time the empiricists thought that ideas were
only copies of objects perceived by the senses. Kant’s revolution reversed prevailing
epistemological theories by presenting the view that we know things as objects only
because the mind itself contributes important organizing principles which make knowledge
of objects possible. The emphasis has shifted from the mind as passive to its playing an
active role in shaping the “world” that can be known.
In simple terms Kant wants to show how objective knowledge, that is knowledge about
the world, which is independent of our own subjective perception, is possible. This question
can be resolved into a question about the presuppositions of experience, or what it is that
must be true for us to be able to have experience, as we know it. In this way Kant will bring
together both the empiricism of Hume and the nascent rationalism of Descartes and, in so
doing, produce a complete epistemology and an explanation of the process of relation
between the conscious individual, the world and time. Kant will demonstrate, in the
Critique of Pure Reason, not only the areas in which knowledge is available to us, but also
areas in which the search for knowledge is fruitless, misguided and even dangerous, areas
in which belief, or even faith, are all that we can expect.
There are two sorts of knowledge: knowledge completely independent of the senses (a
priori knowledge) and knowledge wholly empirical (a posteriori knowledge). In defining a
priori knowledge, Kant stresses its utter and complete independence from experience. The
best example of completely a priori knowledge, Kant thinks, is found in mathematics, for in
mathematics the concepts used are not derived from experience in any way but are
generated entirely by the human mind. Sometimes Kant refers to that which is a priori as
“pure,” meaning by that term simply that it has no admixture of the senses. For example ‘A
senator is a member of the Senate’. A posteriori knowledge, or empirical knowledge as
Kant usually calls it, is derived from our sense experience. For example ‘The Senator is
corrupt’. There is really nothing much new in the distinction between a priori and
posteriori knowledge; it is similar to Hume’s distinction between “matters of fact” and
“relations of ideas”. But Kant takes this distinction one step further in relating it to the
distinction between analytic and synthetic judgements. In synthetic judgement predicate
adds something and is not contained in the subject. In analytic judgement predicate adds
nothing and is contained in the subject. Posteriori statements are synthetic and that a priori
statements are analytic. It is clear that a statement cannot be both a posteriori and analytic,
since a posteriori refers to that which is derived from the senses, and analytic means that
which is independent of the senses- a manifest contradiction. There is, however, one class
of judgment left-judgments that are both synthetic and a priori. Are there any such
judgments or concepts? Kant answers that not only are there concepts which are both
synthetic and a priori (we find many of them in natural science and mathematics, Kant
argues), but that they are the important ingredient in knowledge that the empiricists
Modern Western Philosophy 38
School of Distance Education
overlooked. Synthetic apriori knowledge would be that ideal knowledge, knowledge both
certain and informative.
Kant offers to the most important synthetic a priori concepts involved in the process
of achieving knowledge as categories and he is convinced that there are just twelve such
concepts. The most important one in the light of Hume’s attack was the principle of
causality. Hume was correct in thinking that causality is not a principle we can derive from
experience, but he was wrong in thinking that there is no legitimacy to this concept. Kant
argues that causality was one of the categories (i.e., a synthetic a priori concept) that we
bring to experience and which makes experience possible. In an extended and detailed
argument, Kant argues that without such categories as cause and effect, substance, and
others, there would be no way of transforming sensuous intuition (Kant’s term for
sensations) into judgments which can be dignified by the term knowledge. We need the data
supplied by the senses if we are to have knowledge, but these data need to be processed by
the concepts (such as cause and effect) that the mind supplies out of its own operations.
Both sensing and thinking are important. Without either, knowledge is impossible.
“Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind”.
Kant uses the concept of ‘limit’ in two separate but related contexts. On the one
hand, knowledge vis-à-vis faith has to be restricted and on the other hand, given the
peculiar ontological distinction that Kant makes between noumenon and phenomenon, it is
necessary to restrict phenomenon (i.e. sensible intuition) from being extended to noumenon
(i.e. thing in itself). The concept of phenomenon constitutes the sphere of actual and
possible scientific knowledge. In Kant’s analysis human cognition is confined to the extent
a thing can be given in sensible intuition and is determined by the categories. But human
cognition can never penetrate into the noumenon and the thing-it-itself because they cannot
be recognized by sensible intuitions. Kant thus prepares a border of cognition between what
is cognizable in principle and what is incognizable. On the basis of what is cognizable in
principle and what is incognizable, the epistemological problems in Kant arise. He
expresses those problems in terms of possibility, validity and limit of human cognition. To
understand the Kantian conception of ‘limit’, one needs to examine Kant’s separation
between noumenon and phenomenon on the basis of threefold distinction between ‘reason’,
‘understanding’ and ‘sensibility. Sensibility, says Kant, is the faculty of intuition and
understanding is the faculty of concepts. Through intuitions objects are given, through
concepts they are thought. Sensibility furnishes the manifold materials, which are
absolutely chaotic and unintelligible, while understanding gives them a unifying form and
renders them intelligible. Therefore, in Kant’s epistemology, sensibility and understanding
are the two factors, which constitute knowledge. Kant says, “All our knowledge starts with
the senses, proceeds from thence to understanding, and ends with reason, beyond which
there is no higher faculty to be found in us for elaborating the matter of intuition and
bringing it under the highest unity of thought.” The understanding throughout the use of
Modern Western Philosophy 39
School of Distance Education
categories and principles unifies the manifolds supplied by the sensibility. Reason seeks to
unify the concepts and judgments of understanding. Whereas understanding is directly
related to sensibility, reason relates itself to sensibility only indirectly through
understanding. Whereas sensation or sense-perception represents things only as they appear
to us, reason-by means of rational-discursive apperception-provides us with insight into the
real structure and essence of things. Kant realizes that our knowledge cannot be limited to
mere empirical knowledge, for there are certain ordering principles presupposed by this
very knowledge. These principles are known by reason. We learn by experience, for
example, that fire causes heat-reason does not tell us this. But we do not learn by experience
that every event has a cause. Rather we know it because the particular experiences we do
have would be incoherent without it. So we may postulate rational knowledge in addition to
empirical knowledge.
Kant’s analysis of epistemology is based on his concepts of space and time, and the
categories which constitute the sources of human cognition. Human cognition, according to
him, is synthetic a priori. The concepts and categories are “Original pure concepts of
synthesis that the understanding contains within itself a priori”. In Kant’s Transcendental
Aesthetic, “there are two pure forms of sensible intuition, serving as principle of a priori
knowledge, namely space and time”. Space and time, the basic source of the unity of
experience, derive from mind, not from the perceptual world. For Kant, though the thing in
itself exists independent of the mind, space and time are mind dependent and cannot be
applied to thing in itself. Space and time are logically prior to sensible intuition through
which a material object is given to us. Time and space are not absolute because they are
mind dependent and cannot be derived from sensible intuition, but every sensible intuition
has to be posited and ordered in a priori forms of space and time. The sensible intuitions,
synthesized in the forms of space and time, become the object of knowledge for Kant.
Without space and time no objects would be perceived, and therefore space and time are
precondition of our experiencing anything. Space and time are empirically real and
transcendentally ideal. They are empirically real because they are universally present in our
experience; they are transcendentally ideal because they do not arise from experience but
are a product of the mind. Kant used the word aesthetic in its original Greek sense of having
to do with the senses. All that has to do with the senses is in space and time.
Just as space and time are invariable categories of perception, there are also
invariable categories of thought that set the mould in which we must think. These categories
of thought are examined in the Transcendental Analytic, what Kant calls understanding.
The transcendental aesthetic provides man with the structure with which to perceive sense
objects, and the transcendental analytic provides him with the structure with which to think
about the world of experience. Human cognition/ synthetic a priori is possible through the
transcendental unity of apperception, which perceives all things and events in space and
time, comprehend them under the categories of quantity, quality, substantiality, causality,
reciprocity etc. These pure concepts (categories) of the understanding Kant considers to be
a priori, independent of experience, universal: they form the structure of any mind, of any
consciousness and necessary: they are a necessary condition of experience; without them,
there is no knowledge, there is not even any experience. Categories are not structures of
reality; they are only structures of our consciousness, our minds. They are significant only
epistemologically, that is, in relation to our knowing: they have no significance
metaphysically, or ontologically, that is, in relation to reality. And so we can know that the
laws of nature will continue to hold true, because the universal and necessary concepts of
our own minds structure them.
Kant has limited human cognition to the world of phenomena by giving room for faith. He
regards the sphere of faith, where scientific knowledge cannot penetrate, as the sphere of
noumenon. Thing in itself is “an object of our sensible intuition”, while noumenon is not
which presuppose a special mode of intuition namely ‘intellectual intuition.” Man can never
comprehend the noumenon because the intellectual intuition, which comprehends
noumenon, is of a special kind, which he can never possess. The concept of intellectual
intuition is based on Kant’s assumption that, “...we cannot assert of sensibility that it is the
sole possible kind of intuition”. Therefore, there must be an intellectual intuition in which
noumenon can be given. Thing-in-itself can never be given in a manifold of sensible
intuitions and the categories of understanding cannot be applied to them. Therefore, things-
in-themselves, things as they are independent of our concepts, remain unknown and
unknowable.
TRANSCENDENLISM
Kant assumes the existence of the thing in itself on the basis that there must be an
external cause to our sensibility. But causation according to him is a category of
understanding and as such it is inapplicable to the thing in itself. This contradiction cannot
be resolved by regarding the thing in itself as the ground of appearances because the ground
itself is nothing but the category of cause unschematized. The struggle between idealism
and materialism lies at the roots of Kantian enlightenment. And Kant’s solution to the
problem lies in separating the two from each other and it is the transcendental
consciousness or the noumenon self which gives rise to maxims of morality or the
categorical imperatives. In obeying these maxims one realizes freedom. As a matter of fact,
Kant’s views on freedom are greatly influenced by the Enlightenment movement of the
time. Kant’s concept of reason and human rationality is another attempt to justify the
claims of Enlightenment. The concept of freedom is located in human subjectivity in as
much as causation is situated in the objective reality. The dialectic argument between
freedom and causation emerges when reason comes to an unavoidable situation to postulate
absolute totality of the series of conditions. It is the totalizing effort or attempt to apprehend
series of appearances in totality or the cosmological idea of the totality of the composition
of the appearances of a cosmic whole that lays at the centre of Kant’s solution to the
antinomy between freedom and causation.
Kant differs from Hume’s distinction of knowledge between relations of ideas and
matters of fact, because such a distinction cannot make scientific knowledge as synthetic
apriori possible. Kant tries to show that the propositions of Mathematics, Geometry and
Physics are not only apriori but also synthetic. Kant, therefore, demonstrates that the
‘transcendental consciousness’ consists of the ‘forms of intuition’ (space and time) and
‘forms of understanding’ (the concepts) which are not static forms but forms of operation
that exist only in the act of apprehending and comprehending sensibility. The forms of
intuition synthesize the manifold of sensibility into spatio-temporal order. By virtue of the
categories, they are brought to the universal and necessary relations of cause and effect,
Modern Western Philosophy 42
School of Distance Education
substance, quality, limitation, etc. And this entire complex is unified in the ‘transcendental
consciousness’, which relates all experience to the ‘thinking ego’, thereby giving
experience the continuity of being ‘my’ experience. The ‘transcendental consciousness’ is
the matrix, the ultimate source through which the order and regularity in the field of
appearance is given. The knowledge that comes out is what Kant calls synthetic apriori. As
synthetic, it amplifies the concept of subject in the predicate and as apriori, it expresses
universality and necessity. What we require in knowledge is such ampliative knowledge
with the characteristics of universality and necessity. But knowledge as synthetic apriori,
Kant warns, has a ‘limit’ i.e., it is limited to the phenomenal world and it cannot penetrate
into the noumenal world; i.e., the ideas of reason, like immortality of soul, freedom of will
and existence of God. Here Kant proposes a critique of pure reason. He says, “Human
reason has this peculiar fate that in one species of its knowledge, it is burdened by questions
which, as prescribed by the very nature of reason itself, it is not able to ignore, but which as
transcending all its powers, it is not able to answer.”
Kant maintains that moral laws can be derived neither from sensibility nor from
inclination, but only from reason, so that they can be regarded as a command to all rational
beings under all circumstances, whatsoever. An act, to be virtuous, must exclude the
influence of desire and be the outcome of a pure regard for the moral law. Good will is
autonomous or free and is independent of any property of the objects of volition. Will is
autonomous when it acts solely from a sense of duty. Will becomes heteronomous when it
is subject to a desire for an end beyond itself. The will is heteronomous when it is guided by
some end or moved by desire. ‘Duty for duty’s sake’ is the true rule of life. Moral
autonomy is the source of freedom. We are autonomous when we act according to duty,
according to the categorical imperative. On the other hand, we are dependent or
heteronomous when we act according to our feelings and pleasures, which indicate our
bondage. Kant's freedom, then, is not a freedom of indeterminism. A man who is subject to
his passions and emotions is a slave; only the rational man is free, for he recognizes the
validity of moral laws.
Good will should be prompted by pure respect for the Moral Law, or consciousness
of duty. It is this: “Duty is the necessity to act out of reverence for the law.” Perhaps it
would be better to say that to act on the maxim of doing one’s duty for its own sake is to act
out of reverence for the law. Moreover, the rightness or wrongness of an act does not
depend on its effects or consequences; it is immaterial whether happiness or perfection
results, so long as the motive of the agent is good. Pure respect for the law is the sole
motive of genuine morality. This law is the supreme test of what is right and wrong. In the
opinion of Kant, a right action should satisfy two conditions: (1) it should conform to the
moral law revealed by reason (2) the agent should perform it out of pure respect for the
moral law. The categorical Imperative or the moral law has no reference to any external
ends, but simply to the right direction of the will itself. The Categorical Imperative is the
universal Moral Law; it applies to all persons; it is common to all mankind
Maxims of Morality
Kant tries to make the moral law or categorical imperative more definite by laying down the
following maxims.
Formula 1: The Formula of Autonomy or of Universal Law:
Formula 2: The Formula of Respect for the Dignity of Persons:
Formula 3: The Formula of Legislation for a Moral Community:
(1) The first maxim of morality shows that what is right is universal, and that what is
expedient is not universal. Kant illustrates the maxim by the example of breaking promises
and committing suicide. It is wrong to break a promise, because this act cannot be
Modern Western Philosophy 44
School of Distance Education
universalized. If it were made a universal rule-if every one were to break a promise;
promises, in fact, would cease to be made. And if they were not made, they could not be
broken. Hence, it would be impossible for everyone to break his promise. To commit
suicide out of disgust with life is not moral because it will lead to the annihilation of human
life if it is universalized. “Act in such a way as you could will that everyone else should act
under the same general conditions.” This is the first maxim of morality. This law, or
categorical imperative, is a universal, necessary law, a priori, inherent in reason itself. Its
claim is recognized even by the common man; though he may not be clearly conscious of it,
it governs his moral judgments; it is his standard or criterion of right and wrong.
(2) “Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in
the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end”.
Second maxim orders us to treat personality as of absolute worth. A person is an end-in-
himself. He should never be treated as a means. No one should enslave himself or others. A
corollary from the second maxim is the following: “Try always to perfect thyself, and try to
conduce to the happiness of others, by bringing about favorable circumstances, as you
cannot make others perfect.” A person can make himself perfect, because he can control his
own will and make it conform to the moral law. But he can never make others perfect,
because he cannot control their wills. Moral will has to be cultivated by a person himself-
and not to be imposed upon him by any other person. Perfection is to be achieved, and not
to be given. So what a person can do for others is to bring about circumstances that are
conducive to their happiness. Kant illustrates this maxim by example of breaking promise
and committing suicide. In suicide the person is treating himself as a means to the removal
of the disgust of life and is not regarding himself as an end. Similarly, by making a false
promise, say, by not paying a debt, one is making use of another person as a means and is
not regarding the person as an end.
(3) “Act as a member of a kingdom of ends.” Third maxim of morality says that treat
yourself and every other human being as of equal intrinsic value; behave as a member of an
ideal republic in which each citizen is a sovereign and a subject in which each is a means
and an end, in which each realizes his own good in promoting the good of others. A
“Kingdom of ends” is an ideal society of rational persons following the Moral Law. A
“kingdom of ends” would be an ideal society in which every person would act in a rational
way and follow the categorical imperative and thus live in perfect harmony with everybody
else. In the ideal commonwealth of mankind the law would be willed and obeyed by each
and all. In all our personal and social relationships, we should have respect for self and
others as persons. And the more we cultivate mutual understanding and good will, the more
we shall attain to freedom and sovereignty or autonomy.
The first formula is said to be concerned with the form of a moral maxim-that is, with its
universality; the second with its matter-that is, with its ends; while the third combines both
form and matter. The moral imperative insures the freedom of the will.
Postulates of Morality
As is well known, Kant assumes three postulates without which morality, in his
opinion, cannot be explained. They are: Freedom of the will, Immortality of the soul and the
Existence of God. A man cannot have any duty or cannot be responsible for what he does,
if his will is not free. ‘Thou oughtest implies thou canst’-Free will is implied by morality- is
a famous saying of Kant. If the will is not free, morality becomes impossible. The second
moral postulate is immortality of the soul. It is a demand of morality that the virtuous shall
be rewarded. But if the virtuous are not rewarded here, they will be rewarded hereafter.
Hence the soul must be immortal. Finally, as the relation between virtue and happiness is
not analytic, but synthetic, there is not certainty that happiness will automatically follow
virtue; hence there must be some external agency, viz., God , to unite virtue with happiness.
In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant rejects all the old arguments for the freedom of the
will, the existence of God, and the immortality of the soul; the outcome of the first Critique
is negative in this respect. In the Critique of Practical Reason, these three notions are
reinstated on the basis of the moral law.
Defining Enlightenment, in his famous pamphlet known as “An Answer to the Question:
‘What is Enlightenment?”(1784) Kant says, “Enlightenment is man’s emergence from his
self-incurred immaturity. Immaturity is the inability to use one’s own understanding
without the guidance of another. This immaturity is self-incurred if its cause is not lack of
understanding, but lack of resolution and courage to use it without the guidance of another.
The motto of enlightenment is therefore: Sapereaude! (Dare to know!) Have courage to use
your own understanding!” This is in contrast to the state of humanity in its immaturity in
which the prescription runs: ‘Don’t think, just follow orders’. The basic idea of
enlightenment was the abandoning of socially held irrational dogmas and beliefs, in order to
pursue that which was rational, universal and readily demonstrable. The overthrow of the
authority of tradition and the enthronement of critical rationality in its place were the central
movements in this process. There are four interrelated aspects of Kant’s project of
Enlightenment. These are freedom, the public and private use of reason, criticism of
religion and tolerance.
or office he needs to maintain the confidential aspects and it cannot be made public;
whereas civil rights like citizenship, right to property, etc- are of public use of reason.
Out of the public and private use of reason, Kant comes to the issue of the criticism
of religion. During the time of Kant, in the German society there was a strong dominance of
clergymen concerning all affairs of political, economic and cultural life. Kant proposes
enlightenment to undermine the dominance of religion and thereby to support the new
rising bourgeoisie. The original destiny of mankind is proposed by Kant in terms of
“progress”. This progress is possible only under the enlightenment and not under the
dominancy of the clergy. Kant says “it is absolutely impermissible to agree, even for a
single lifetime, to a permanent religious constitution which no one might publicly
question”. If religion is to be preserved, it has to serve the purpose of reason. Man’s
emergence from his self-incurred immaturity is possible only if the “matters of religion” are
put aside.
The next point that Kant comes to is the tolerance. In this context, Kant is supporting
the role of the Prussian Kingdom. Whereas clergy is against human freedom, the king
Frederick and the Price are in favour of complete freedom but at the same time to be
tolerant in religious matters. Praising the King Frederick, Kant says “he deserves to be
praised by a grateful present and posterity as the man who first liberated mankind from
immaturity (as far as government is concerned), and who left all men free to use their own
reason in all matters of conscience”. Kant believes that we do not live “in an enlightened
age, but in an age of enlightenment”. This means that enlightenment is a process of coming
out from the dominance of the clergy to the free public use of human reason. ‘Reason’, the
supreme faculty, has an emancipatory goal. But this is contrasted by apriorism of the
faculty of understanding, which can vindicate only a limited theory.
The attempt to get rid of self-imposed immaturity is both self-critique and self-
reflection with the aim to attain emancipation. Emancipatory self-reflection depended on
giving rational reconstruction of the universal conditions of reason. To use the Kantian
analogy, only when we understand the possibility, validity and limit of theoretical
knowledge and the categorical imperatives does it become intelligible to specify what must
be done to attain autonomy and emancipation.
Kant’s Enlightenment occupies a central role in the justification for the movement
known as ‘modernism’. Modern means something which is not traditional, to break with the
endless reiteration of classical themes, topics and myths; to offer a critique of existing
feudal super structure (political, moral, religious and legal systems), to defend and develop
scientific explanation of every phenomenon, and to explain reality not only objectively but
also as experienced by the subject. Modernist was a shift from faith to reason.
Enlightenment is held to be the source of critical ideas, such as the centrality of freedom,
democracy and reason as being the primary values of a society. In this view, the tendency of
the philosophers in particular to apply rationality to every problem is considered to be the
essential change. From this point on, thinkers and writers were held to be free to pursue the
truth in whatever form, without the threat of sanction for violating established ideas.
CONCLUSION
Kant on the one hand, has resolved the conflicting epistemological claims of the
Continental rationalism and the British empiricism and on the other hand he has divided
human experience into three kinds: Science, Ethics and Art, which become the milestones
of the European modernity. In his epistemology, Kant tries to confine human cognition to
the realm of phenomenon alone but in his enlightenment project, he tries to give universal
emancipation to mankind. Post Kantian philosophers observe a fundamental contradiction
in the above claim of Kant which results into totalitarian thinking. The limit-riddled
constitution of human reason and its Kantian resolution remains an issue for the post-
Kantian philosophers. Two points concerning this issue, namely, the dualism of noumenon
and phenomenon and the unknowability of the noumenon provide the basis for criticism and
reconstruction of Kant’s theory.
KEY WORDS
Deontological: Derived from the Greek word for “ought” and referring to any ethical
system which makes the morality of an action depend on one’s acting out of a sense of duty.
Synthetic a priori: That which is not contained in the very concept of subject but at the same
time is known independently of experience
Postulates: Postulates are the presuppositions of reason from a pure practical point of view.
In Kant’s practical philosophy, they are freedom, God and immortality.
Part C-(Each answer not to exceed 150 words each question carries 2 weightages)
2. They are not empirical percepts, but are a priori or pure percepts.
6. Schematism: Kant makes a sharp distinction between sense and intellect but then the
concepts must be applied to the sensible in order to constitute knowledge. However,
the concepts are universal; involving no elements of time; but the sensible is
essentially temporal. For example, the concept of causality being a logical category
is timeless and yet being applied to the sensible something is necessary succession in
time . Now there is the need for something which will mediate between the
heterogeneous elements of sense and understanding. It is the form of time which is
the forms of all perceptions, whether external or internal. Time is pure like the
concepts and is yet at the same time sensuous. Every concept then to be applicable to
the sensible must be cast in the form of time i.e. the abstract concept is to be imaged
in the time-form. Each concept requires a general picture, an ideal particular. For
instance the category of substance is the idea of something which is always a subject
and never a predicate. When it schematized then it stands for something permanent
in time. ‘A secret art in the depths of the human soul’ translates the intangible
conception into a schema-a sort of generalised image, a universal which is withal
sensuous: not so much a picture itself, as a general formula or recipe for drawing
pictures’. The concepts come to be applied to the sensible through the time-schema.
Our real thinking in science is pictorial, always tinged with imagination. Thus the
need for shcematism ties down the intellect to a sensuous form, but then for the
limitation to the sensible alone the schematism clothes the concepts in reality.
9. Antinomies: There are four antinomies according to quantity, quality, relation and
modality which respectively refer to the fourfold problem of composition, division,
origination and dependence of existence. Both the thesis and anti-thesis are formally
valid and can be proved with equal show of reason. Nonetheless they are opposed
and inconsistent with each other.
THESIS AN.TI-THESIS
10. The Ideal of Pure Reason: The ideal of reason is not a mere idea, but is an ideal. It
contains the sum of all possibility. The ideal seems to be farther removed from
objective reality than the ideas of the world and soul. Further, this ideal refers to an
individual, popularly known as a personal God. The transcendental dialectic has
shown the impossibility of knowing the three regulative ideas of Soul, World and
God. Attempts to know these three Ideas of Reason lead to three transcendental
illusions called paralogisms (concerning Soul), antinomies (with regard to the
World) and Ideals of
11. reason (in relation to God). There is nothing real corresponding to the ideas of
reason. But these ideas have certain functions to perform:
1. They point out the model knowledge, the highest unity of which our
reason is capable. Their use is not imminent for they do not constitute
2. They are the limiting concepts pointing out the utmost reaches of
knowledge beyond which we must not venture.
3. They regulate the understanding by pointing out the ideal of
knowledge. Sense and understanding can guarantee the actual i.e. what
is; but reason points out the existence of what ought to be.
4. The reality of God, the immortality of Soul and the freedom of will
cannot be proved and known but they cannot be disproved either. They
are unknowable and the doubt about their reality is as indefensible as
the dogmatic assertion about them. Kant thus speaks about the
dogmatists and sceptics.
5. The ideas pave the way for faith in morality and religion. As a matter
of fact it is the need for morality that keeps the transcendental illusion.
Kant, Immanuel, ‘An answer to the Question: ‘What is Enlightenment’ trans. Lawrence. E.
--- Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N.K. Smith London: The MacMillan Press Ltd, 1933.
--- Ground work of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. H.J. Paton. New York: Harper &
Row, 1964.
Singh R.P, Kant and Hegel: Methodology, Ontology, Epistemology, Dialectic and Ought,
New Delhi: Galaxy Publications, 1990.
UNIT IV HEGEL
reaches truth is also the immediate expression of the innermost life of existence: when we
think existence, existence thinks in us.
The simplest way of explaining Hegelian dialectic will be to give a concrete example.
For the sake of illustration we may take the following triad of categories of Hegelian logic.
i. Being - Thesis
ii. Nothing - Anti-thesis
iii. Becoming - Synthesis
Fichte for the first time introduced into German philosophy the famed triad of thesis,
antithesis and synthesis. But he did not believe that antithesis could be deduced from the
thesis. And, in his view, synthesis achieves nothing more than “uniting” what both thesis
and antithesis already established. For Hegel the thesis or ‘Being’ means ‘pure’ being or
entirely abstract idea of being, or being-as-such. Such a ‘being’ has in it no determinations.
It is therefore, absolutely indeterminate, completely empty or a pure vacuum. The “Being”
is the same as ‘nothing’. It means that the concept of “pure being” contains the idea of
‘nothing’. Consequently, we have a third category namely, the “idea of passage” or
“Becoming”. The category of “Becoming” deduced from the relation between the two
categories of “Being” and “Nothing”. The remarkable thing about Hegelian dialectic is that
the first category in each triad is always an affirmative category; the second is always a
negative or opposite of the first. This second is always contained in the first and the first
category produces it out of itself. The first category contains its own ‘opposite’ and is
‘identical’ with it. This implies that the opposite categories are applicable to the same thing
at the same time. But it is impossible to rest on this contradiction. The third category,
therefore, resolves the contradiction. It contains within itself the “opposition” of the other
two: but, at the same time, contains their underlying harmony and unity. This third category
or synthesis presents itself as a new affirmative category, which thereby becomes the thesis
of a new triad. The next point is that the ‘thesis’ is always regarded by Hegel as
characterised ‘immediacy’. The second term is “mediate”. The third term is the merging of
mediation in a new “immediacy”. Hegel believes in the two-fold activity of ‘syntheses’.
viz., abolishment and preservation. In this way, as the dialectic proceeds nothing is ever
lost. The higher category contains the lower categories “explicitly”, while the lower
categories contain the higher ‘implicitly’. Thus his dialectical is of logical nature. Hegel
distinguishes between ‘Intellect’ or ‘Understanding’ and ‘Reason’. According to him, the
intellect can do nothing but distinguish, oppose and relate; it cannot conceive the unity of
opposites. Understanding deals with the static law of non-contradiction. Hegel says that
“Speculative Reason” can proceed ahead due to the contradictions towards an all-
harmonious Absolute, which is an “identity of opposites’.
The synthesis of a triad both abolishes and preserves the differences of the thesis and the
antithesis. This activity of the synthesis is expressed by Hegel as aufheben or sublation
which is the operative term of his dialectic. It may be seen as the manifestation of three
distinct yet mutually interrelated, moments. “First it has the moment of ‘transcendence’, in
which it goes beyond a ‘limit’ or ‘boundary’; secondly it is ‘negation’ of this first negation,
this ‘limit’, in which it is the moment of ‘preservation’, in which what has been ‘gone
beyond’ or transcended is brought again into a new relation”. Sublation may be seen as
manifesting the moments of transcendence, negation and negation of negation. These three
moments of sublation, though distinct, form a unitary process of Logic which is
differentiated into its various components only for the purpose of helping an 'understanding'
of the process itself. The very process by which a category 'passes beyond itself' and posits
another category to which it is intimately related is at one and the same logical moment the
process by which it transcends its limited abstract self-identity negates that identity and
emerges into a connected unity or nexus in which it is preserved as an intrinsic part of some
greater whole. The differences between the first and the second member of each triad are
sublated by the third. In this process Hegel explicates three basic laws of dialectic (i) unity
and struggle of opposites. (ii) transition from quantity to quality and vice-versa and (iii)
negation of negation. These laws are operation in the whole process of Hegel's deduction of
categories.
In the process of the deduction of categories from one another, Hegel arrives at the
“system of subjective Logic” in the science of Logic. Hegel, here, develops the concept of
subject which is the same thing as the doctrine of Notion in which the categories of Being
and Essence are merged into a unity. With Notion, we come to the point where subjectivity
is the true form of objectivity. The Logic of Being and the Logic of Essence finally
culminate in the Logic of Notion which is nothing but the self-consciousness of the Geist.
This means that all the categories of the objective Logic are ultimately derived from the
Subjective Logic. So the dialectical laws operating in the deduction of the categories are
ultimately derived from the Geist. Here it echoes Aristotle’s philosophy where, “matter and
form are really correlative, though logically distinct; informed matter and inmattered form
are two different ways of looking at the same thing”. And since material things are
constantly changing, so with them the forms and concepts also manifest such movements.
Aristotle attempted to formulate the concepts and categories in dynamic terms. Hegel’s
analysis of it goes in the following scheme: “the true form of reality requires freedom.
Freedom requires self-consciousness and knowledge of the truth. Self-consciousness and
knowledge of the truth are the essentials of the subject. The true form of reality must be
conceived as subject.”
The Notion presents an objective totality in which every particular moment appears
as the ‘self-differentiation’ of the universal that governs the totality. That is to say, every
particular moment contains, as it’s very content, the whole, and must be interpreted as the
whole. For explanation, let us refer again to the Phenomenology of Spirit where “the true is
the whole. But the whole is nothing other than the essence consummating itself through its
development.” The Notion designates the general form of being in which being, through
development by means of contradiction and sublation, realizes its essence. At the same
time, Notion expresses the free subject which adequately represents the true being. The
free-subject exists in a movement from lower to higher modes of self-realization. Hegel
calls the highest form of this self-realization-the Geist.
The Geist in its final form is the ‘free-subject’, the Notion. Its otherness and negation
is the object, being. And both the Notion and its otherness are constantly overwhelmed by
the ontological conceptions of Hegel’s absolute idealism. Hegel’s Science of Logic thus
ends where it began, with the category of being. This, however, is a different being that can
no longer be explained through the concept applied in the analysis that opened the Logic.
For, being now is understood in its Notion, that is, as a concrete totality wherein all
particular forms subsist as the essential distinctions and relations of one comprehensive
principle-the Absolute Truth.
It may here be recalled that just as Socrates’ dialogue, due to contradictions,
eventually ends with the participants in the same state of perplexity; similarly Hegel’s logic
and with it his dialectic ends where it began. This similarity is, evidently, because of the
similar driving force operating behind the possibility and progress of both the dialogue and
the dialectic.
In the Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel postulates that man first seeks to aufgehoben the
material world through the exercise of his Will. In the Independence and Dependence of
Self-consciousness: Lordship and Bondage or which is generally known as Master/Slave
dialectic, Hegel demonstrates what are the social consequences for mankind of his attempt
to construct his own sense of self, his need for recognition by another man, upon the basis
of an exercise of will. There is an immediate conflict of Wills between Master and Slave
with each one attempting to extract from the other an enforced ‘recognition’. This conflict
is only resolved when one of them, under the threat of death, so to say, from the other,
yields his will and grants a forced recognition of the other. In this moment one becomes the
dominant and the other the subservient and there is created the realm of Lordship and
Bondage. But as a result of the conflict of Wills there is also created something more than
this mere domination of one man by another. As Hegel appreciates that the resolution of
this conflict has produced, on the one hand, an enforced recognition, and, on the other, a
sense of unease. Says Hegel, “the lord relates himself mediately to bondsman through a
being (a thing) that is independent, for it is just this which hold the bondsman in bondage; it
is his chain from which he could not break free in the struggle, thus proving himself to be
dependent, to possess his independence in thinghood”. The Master can never know that the
Slave has recognised him out of the exercise of his, the Slave’s own will. The recognition
that the Master receives is but his own will reflected back to him via the Will of his Slave.
The will of the slave is nothing more than the will of the Master and therefore the Master in
effect merely recognises himself.
The Slave, on the other hand, having been granted no recognition, has been forced to
exercise what remains of his own Will upon the physical material world. He thereby begins
the task of ‘overcoming’ the otherness of the material world through his physical labour and
the development of the skills entailed therein. Hegel understands that the outcome of the
struggle of
Wills between the Master and the Slave for recognition is the creation of an unstable
situation, a Master who is not confirmed in his Lordship, and a Slave who works for another
without the recognition of himself as a Self. The outcome of Master/Slave dialectic is the
creation of two realms in which the former dominates the latter. This analogy has its
reflection in Hegel’s formulation of dialectic in the realm of concepts and ideas, and then its
application to the external material reality. Just as Master becomes the exerciser of the
Mental labour, of formulating ideas, planning and so on; and the Slave is the bearer of
Physical labour, one who brings those ideas and plans into reality; similarly and exactly in
the same process the dialectic of concepts are applied to the external material reality. The
dialectic operating in the realm of concepts command the world of ideas; and the
transformative activity performed in the material world is aimed towards the satisfaction of
the dialectic of ideas.
There is yet another way of looking at Hegel’s attempts to apply the dialectic of
concepts to the actual reality. In the Preface to Philosophy of Right, Hegel writes: “What is
rational is actual and what is actual is rational. On this conviction the plain man like the
Philosopher takes his stand, and from it philosophy starts its study of the Universe of mind
as well as the universe of nature”. Actuality is that in which the discrepancy between the
possible and the real has been overcome. Its fruition occurs through a process of change,
with the given actuality advancing in accordance with the possibilities implicit in it. As
stated earlier, ‘contradiction’ is the basis of all movement and ‘sublation’ is the basis of all
development. And these together are operative terms of Hegel’s dialectic. A given
‘actuality’ moves, because of some contradiction, because it strives to express its
potentialities. A given ‘actuality’ develops because the lower stage is not annihilated but
assimilated in the higher stage. What is actual is rational because it is the actuality of an
entity that undergoes through the whole process of growth-the reality of an entity. And the
whole process of growth or development of every actuality is always dialectical and in it
alone consists its distinction from mere transpassing of facts of Logical Atomism and
Positivism. If, therefore, we understand by Hegel's dialectic as a gradual explication and
development of the 'connectedness' of the categories of Logic, then dialectic is operating in
our thought alone. But such a dialectical nexus of concepts is not itself sufficient to account
for our knowledge of the objective reality. Dialectic must come out of thought and confront
the world which is given. That is to say, it must have a relation to the objective world into
which man daily finds himself thrown. Hegel recognizes this fact. He shows that everything
that surrounds us maybe viewed as an instance of dialectic. We are aware that everything
finite as that which in itself is other than itself is forced beyond its own immediate or
natural being to turn suddenly into its opposite. Hegel demonstrates that the laws of
dialectic are not only operating in our thought but are also the fundamental features of the
change and development taking place in the material reality. So, the dialectic has this dual
function to perform, viz., to show that dialectic is operating in thought and that,
Modern Western Philosophy 58
School of Distance Education