Historical Materialism 19.2 - Historical Materialism
Historical Materialism 19.2 - Historical Materialism
Historical Materialism 19.2 - Historical Materialism
nl/hima
Abstract
The recent economic crisis has brought to the fore another crisis that has been going on for many
years, that of (orthodox) economic theory. The latter failed to predict and, after the event, cannot
offer an explanation of why it happened. This article sketches out why this is the case and what
constitutes the crisis of economics. On this basis, the case is made for the revival of an
interdisciplinary political economy as the only way for offering an explanation of the workings
of the (capitalist) economy in general and of economic crises in particular.
Keywords
capitalism, crisis, economic theory, political economy
1. Introduction
It is a great honour and a privilege to have been awarded the Deutscher
Memorial-Prize for From Economics Imperialism to Freakonomics: The Shifting
Boundaries Between Economics and Other Social Sciences, not least because it
reflects the considered judgement of a set of highly-regarded Marxist scholars.
To be acclaimed by one’s peers is as good as it gets in the realm of scholarship
apart from seeing intellectual work exercise an influence on practice.
Unfortunately, socialism is not on the performativity-agenda, as opposed to its
understandable infatuation with finance. But we might anticipate future
studies of Marxism as ineffective performativity, not least as the latter’s chief
1. See Callon, Méadel and Rabeharisoa 2002 and Fine 2003 for a critique.
2. Milonakis and Fine 2009.
3. See <http://www.deutscherprize.org.uk/Past%20Recipients.htm> and its references to the
books for which prizes were awarded.
B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31 5
The way of phrasing these propositions, let alone their meaning and validity,
is controversial. But this is not our concern here so much as emphasising how
financialisation is the key-factor in the slowdown over the past thirty years (as
opposed to some reductionist notion of the law of falling profitability, for
example) as well as in explaining the crisis, despite working-class acquiescence
and other favourable conditions for capitalism. And financialisation is crucial
in understanding both the cause and course of the crisis itself.
This is not, however, to put aside agencies other than finance in the processes
of restructuring. But industrial capital itself has been embroiled in the
speculative profit-making attached to financialisation (with more-or-less half
of the profits of non-financial corporations being made out of financial
dealings in the USA). And the state has played an active rôle in promoting
financialisation at the expense of, and as the form taken by, the accumulation
and restructuring of capital, not only through liberalising financial markets
and regulation but also through privatisation, commercialisation, and so on.
Such slavish devotion to the cause of finance is indicative of the shifting
nature of contemporary politics or, at least, its increasing flexibility in dealing
with the dysfunctions of financialisation. Underpinning this is the emergence
and/or strengthening of national- and international-financial élites. This works
not only through the pressure of the markets, rating agencies and so on, but
through the changing form and nature of politics itself as financialisation
displaces the location of decision-making to the vagaries of financial markets
and financiers. This is what has sustained what we call neoliberalism over the
past thirty years – the imperatives of finance with commitment to free markets
or not as a matter of more-or-less convenient mythology – without which
neoliberalism in practice seems incomprehensibly heterogeneous and has been
rejected as such by some progressive scholars for being a simple vernacular of
abuse and an incoherent descriptor of contemporary reality.
To the contrary, to sustain financialisation, the state has pressed, if unevenly,
for imposition of the classical aspects of neoliberalism, associated with
authoritarianism, privatisation, fiscal discipline and, in the context of
developing countries, the ‘Washington Consensus’. Equally, though, each of
these aspects is expendable in response to shifting requirements, not least in
the current crisis. Indeed, neoliberalism might best be seen as falling roughly
into two phases – the first as the shock-therapy associated with Reagan and
Thatcher, Latin America, and the Soviet bloc, and the second with the social
market, Third-Wayism and the post-Washington-consensus. This second phase
has been rationalised and promoted as a reaction against the first phase in light
of the latter’s horrendous dysfunctions beyond finance, but essentially is
concerned to keep financialisation going. As Stiglitz, pioneer of the post-
B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31 7
Washington consensus, so clearly puts it:5 ‘The left now understands markets,
and the role they can and should play in the economy . . . the new left is trying
to make markets work’. What this means is: how do we keep globalisation,
financialisation and capital-accumulation going? And, again, unduly
generalising, the more centre- rather than right-leaning political parties are
better able to deliver the imperatives of finance, as this is then the sole objective,
as opposed to authoritarianism. Irrespective of ideological form, the coalition-
government in the UK, PASOK in Greece, and so on make Thatcher seem like
a snatcher of sweets from the pram.
We will return to Stiglitz later, but observe for the moment what, at least for
him, the ‘new left’, as he calls it, has become. To the contrary, the crisis is
indicative of the strongest possible case for socialism and not just because a
bigger-than-ever crisis has hit. The simplest and single most telling aspect of
the crisis is that as observed by Naudé in commenting on a G-20 Summit:6
Many have already remarked on the fact that huge amounts of money have been
found at short notice to bail out banks, but that money to bail out the world’s
bottom billion can never be mobilised. Contrast, for instance, the $50 billion
agreed on for developing countries at the summit with the estimated $8.4 trillion
for bailing-out banks. As Oxfam recently remarked, the latter amount is sufficient
to end extreme poverty worldwide for 50 years.
As Homer Simpson might have pondered: Bail out the banks or eliminate
world-poverty for fifty years – hard choice! And this is just the tip of the
iceberg in terms of the mismatch between the productive capacities of
contemporary capitalism and its record of delivery, whether for the environment
or stability of food- and energy-prices, whilst there is, uniquely for this crisis,
a total absence of blame on the part of working people who must, nonetheless,
bear the costs. The implication of the need for alternatives is irrefutable. Yet
the very factors that have sustained neoliberalism for so long – in terms of
financialisation, the growing hegemony of finance, and the decline of
progressive opposition – also serve as major obstacles to the emergence of, and
struggle for, alternatives. This is, then, a crisis within, not of, neoliberalism,
which has already emerged, at least so far, strengthened from the crisis in
terms of the politics and policies of governance. Neoliberalism remains
everywhere, but its contradictory and shifting combination of ideology, policy
in practice and scholarship across time, place and issue needs to be carefully
5. Stiglitz 2008, p. 2. For critique of the continuing shenanigans of the World Bank, see
Bayliss, Fine and van Waeyenberge (eds.) 2011, forthcoming.
6. Naudé 2009.
8 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
11. No less than 139 banking and currency-crises have been identified between 1973 and
1997, that is, during the earlier phase of financialisation, as compared with ‘only’ 38 financial
crises during the so-called ‘golden age’ of regulated capitalism between 1945 and 1971 (cf.
Eichengreen and Bordo 2002). See also Wolf 2009, p. 31. The difference between these crises
and the most recent one is that they did not become global.
12. Taleb 2007.
13. Cassidy 2010a, p. 28.
14. Krugman 2009, p. 52.
10 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
volatility’ – that the chairman of the Federal Reserve Board, Ben Bernanke, has
partly attributed to ‘improved performance of macroeconomic policies’.15 This
was also the era of the emerging consensus in macroeconomics. A consensus
based on the most-horrendously unrealistic assumptions of the representative
agent holding rational expectations and the market-efficiency hypothesis. As
Greenspan himself has admitted, all of this collapsed in September 2008.
Before coming to current theoretical developments, let us first take a look
at what happened back in the thirties. Although the interwar-period was an
era of pluralism in economics, with different schools of thought using vastly
different types of organon and with different conceptual frameworks
flourishing, for the whole period until the 1929 Wall Street crash, the view
that was dominant within ‘neoclassical’ economics was that markets are
efficient, and, if left alone, they would tend to get back to full-employment
equilibrium. The result of these beliefs was that, after the 1929 crash,
the market was left on its own to cope with the consequences of the crisis. The
ensuing deepest crisis and depression of the twentieth century shook the
credibility of neoclassical theory and the belief in the self-regulating abilities
of the market almost beyond repair. This whole intellectual edifice collapsed
after the 1929 crash. Or so it seemed at the time.
The theoretical gap was filled by John Maynard Keynes’s General Theory.
This is one instance for which it can safely be said that the dramatic changes
in the economic sphere brought about significant changes in economic
thought. Keynes’s aim was to save capitalism from its own excesses, putting as
his central goal the achievement of full employment. Another reason why
Keynes’s work had the potential for a revolutionary-scientific paradigm-shift
à la Kuhn was that, despite its weaknesses, the changes it could potentially
bring about were changes from without, in the sense that it broke with
neoclassical economics in important and radical ways. Firstly, he got rid of
the individualistic, utilitarian overtones of neoclassical economics as well as
the representative individual. Secondly, he denounced the self-equilibrating
tendency of the economy through the concepts of ‘deficient demand’ and
‘unemployment equilibrium’. Third, he placed emphasis on the rôle of systemic
uncertainty. These are certainly radical innovations. But did they revolutionise
economics?
Although Keynes’s work did have a significant effect policy-wise, at least for
the period 1945–70, its revolutionary effects on economic science in the
longer run are more questionable, and certainly limited. As far as economic
policy is concerned, Keynes’s new ideas did gain considerable currency after
World-War Two. ‘The Beveridge Report of 1942 in Great Britain and the
it was the failure to properly price such risky assets that precipitated the crisis. In
recent decades, a vast risk management and pricing system has evolved, combining
the best insights of mathematicians and finance experts supported by major
advances in computer and communications technology. . . . This modern risk
management paradigm held sway for decades. The whole intellectual edifice
collapsed in the summer of last year.20
‘Useless but true’: in these three words of Krugman can be found what is
essentially wrong with modern economics: it is all about theoretical exercises,
mostly taking a mathematical form, which may be valid mathematically,
although the analytical robustness of some of these models is also questionable,
but useless in any other sense and empty of any practical relevance. This is the
problem of formalism in economics, the triumph of form over substance.27
The seeds of the appearance and further development of this tendency
within economic science go back to the marginalist revolution. The explicit
attempt since then has been to transform economics into a ‘rigorous’ science
on a par with positive sciences and devoid of any normative statements
or value-judgments. This was done partly by borrowing tools and concepts
such as equilibrium and optimisation from the physical sciences, particularly,
to begin with, from static mechanics, and then subsequently from
thermodynamics. ‘The pure science of economics’, says Walras, one of the
protagonists of the marginalist revolution, ‘is a science that resembles
the physico-mathematical sciences in every respect’.28 And, what is more, ‘the
scholar has the right to pursue science for its own sake’, equating geometry
with economics in this respect.29
Such formalism did not become dominant within the profession until after
the Second World-War. It was given a new impetus by the works of Hicks’s
Value and Capital, and Samuelson’s Foundations of Economic Analysis,
culminating in the mathematical proof for the existence of equilibrium by
Arrow and Debreu in 1954.30 Since then, the Samuelsonian tool of constrained
optimisation borrowed from thermodynamics became the symbol of the new
Imagine a world ravaged by a plague, and suppose that the year’s Nobel Prize for
Medicine is awarded to researchers whose whole career is based on the assumption
that plagues are impossible. The world would have been outraged. That is precisely
how we should feel about yesterday’s announcement of the recipients of the 2010
Nobel Prize. . . . Interestingly, these three fine mathematical economists have one
thing in common, other than their work on labor markets: in their voluminous
theoretical output on unemployment and the like, there is not a smidgeon of a
hint, of a mention, of an economic crisis which may boost unemployment in
every sector and for all types of workers. Not one!40
To this should be added the direct vested interests of many academics, especially
in the financial sector, a feature that was exacerbated during the
financialisation-era. Philip Mirowski asks:41
Does anyone care that Martin Feldstein was on the board of AIG in the run up
to its disastrous failure? Or that Paul Krugman once consulted for Enron (and got
radicalised after the New York Times made him foreswear such perks)? Is anyone
curious about the tangled history of funding and organisation of the Chicago
School of Economics? Does anyone care that Larry Summers worked for
numerous hedge funds and investment firms before they had to be rescued by an
administration that included . . . Larry Summers?
40. Varoufakis 2010. One of the laureates, Christopher Pissarides of the London School of
Economics, just a few days before the award was announced, in an article with Azariadis and
Ioannides on the Greek economy advocated the sale of all public enterprises to the private sector
and the reduction of the number of public employees by 400,000 by the year 2015; see Azariadis,
Ioannides and Pissarides 2010.
41. Mirowski 2010, p. 39.
42. Ferguson 2010, p. 3. A recent study has shown that, out of nineteen economists examined
‘who have played prominent and influential roles in recent public policy debates, . . . 13 . . . had
private financial affiliations indicative of some possible conflict of interest, but only 5 had clearly
B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31 17
and the growing power and influence of the financial sector that these have
brought about all played an important rôle in the latest developments in
economic science. Deep down, however, it is the very nature of the system and
the ideological need for its justification that lies behind this type of theory. As
Georg Lukács has said, ‘[t]he capitalist process of rationalisation based on
private economic calculation requires that every manifestation of life shall
exhibit [an] interaction between details which are subject to laws and a totality
ruled by chance. It presupposes a society so structured’.43 Hence the
conceptualisation of the current crisis as a chance-occurrence, a black swan,
that could not be predicted and, once there, cannot be explained other than as
a chance-occurrence intractable by scientific knowledge. In short, the interests
of the capitalist system, and of finance in particular, not only dominate
economic discourse, but the latter also dysfunctionally suffers the orthodoxy
that it deserves, the mindless pursuit of financial stability on the basis of
models of both the more-or-less-perfect-market hypothesis and of the more-
or-less perfectly-rational individual.
So what are the chances that this time it will be different as far as the impact
of the global crisis on economic science is concerned? The picture we have
drawn so far of the state of our science does not leave much room for optimism.
Despite some heavy criticism coming mostly, but not exclusively, from the
Keynesian and neo-Keynesian camps (including Krugman, Stiglitz, and
Skidelsky, but also the Chicago economist Richard Posner), the reactions so
far do not lend themselves to much optimism. For Chicago economists like
Eugene Fama (the main modern exponent of efficient-market theory) and
John Cochrane, it is business as usual. As Fama puts it,
We don’t know what causes recessions. Now I’m not a macroeconomist so I don’t
feel bad about that. (Laughs) We’ve never known. . . . Economics is not very good
at explaining swings in economic activity.44
and publicly revealed their affiliations’ (Epstein and Carrick-Hagenbath 2010). This study has
led 300 economists to sign a letter (written by Epstein and Carrick-Hagenbath) to the President
of the American Economic Association, asking for a new professional code of ethics for
economists (cf. Epstein and Carrick-Hagenbath 2011).
43. Lukács 1990, quoted in Choonara 2010.
44. Cassidy 2010b.
18 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
What [the] efficient markets [hypothesis] says is that prices today contain the
available information about the future’.45 So all the information about the
future is available and yet crises are not just unpredictable from within this
model, they simply cannot happen, just like giant waves within the linear
models of wave-formation.
For others, at least willing to recognise that something more by way of
explanation is required, we need better models that would either take into
account market-imperfections like the ‘New Keynesians’,46 or market-dynamics
through the use of a ‘different type of mathematics’ or other sophisticated
models coming from engineering, computing or physics,47 much like what
happened in wave-theory and oceanography following the discovery of giant
waves and the adoption of models from quantum-mechanics. Thus, for Solow,
there are other traditions in economics which include ‘various market frictions
and imperfections like rigid prices and wages, asymmetries of information,
time lags, and so on’ which provide better ways of doing macroeconomics.48
A more genuine return to Keynes is the third escape-route. This is done
mostly by emphasising some aspect of Keynes’s economics which has been
totally forgotten by mainstream-economics. The aspect most commonly
chosen is radical uncertainty and the animal-spirits of capitalism associated
with it.49 This, especially in the case of Akerlof and Shiller, is associated with
the behavioural school in economics, which seeks the explanation of economic
phenomena by delving deeper into the psyche of individuals. The emphasis
here is laid on the psychological and even ‘irrational’ factors influencing
human behaviour, such as confidence, fairness, corruption, money-illusion,
etc., which are seen as the ‘ultimate drivers of the economy’.50 Of these factors,
only the rôle of confidence in the economy has anything to do with Keynes’s
work. The usual story is that uncertainty causes sharp changes in expectations
and confidence, which cause major changes in share-prices, bringing about
sharp alterations in consumption, investment and employment. What is not
explained, however, is the source of this uncertainty and the epistemological
foundations of such ‘irrational’ behaviour, both of which must be sought in
itself in line with it. Indicative of this is that, in their book, The Changing Face
of Economics, Colander et al. have interviewed eleven ‘cutting-edge economists’,
as they call them, coming mostly from the ranks of the ‘inside-the-mainstream’
heterodoxy-group.56 Nine of them do highly technical model-building work.
Generally, this is true for both pure-theory models and applied-policy models.
The old distinction between the science of economics (theoretical economics)
and the art of economics (applied economics) has disappeared under the
impact of the formalist dmodelling method. Indeed, modern economics is
defined by little else. This also applies to new fields of research such as
evolutionary game-theory and experimental economics which, in other
respects, may deviate from neoclassical economics, but not from the use of
highly technical model-building.57
What modern orthodox economists fail to understand is that what is at
fault is not some specific assumption or characteristic of the models used, but
the method of deductive-mathematical modelling itself. In addition to their
universalistic nature and lack of historical specificity, the method of
mathematical-deductive reasoning, as Lawson has shown, presupposes, first, a
closed system in which event-regularities or correlations, ‘that connect events
standing in causal sequence, in order to deduce that this event happened
because of, or followed from, that event’58 occur, and, second, the isolated-
individual agent.59 Because of the erroneous character of both of these
presuppositions as far as social and economic phenomena are concerned,
mathematical modelling is inappropriate as a leading, let alone an exclusive
tool for the analysis of such phenomena. To axiomatic model-building should
also be added another attribute which most (but not all) of these new
approaches share with neoclassical economics: methodological individualism
and the emphasis on the individual.60
Where does all this leave the issue of pluralism? It means that all approaches
and schools that do not accept technical model-building as their method of
analysis simply do not get a hearing and are left out of the picture altogether,
being considered unacceptable as scholarly economics. As Colander et al.
themselves admit, the élite of the profession is open-minded to new ideas, but
closed-minded to alternative methods and approaches. ‘If it’s not modeled, it’s
into the brain itself to discover the key to human behaviour beyond the pursuit
of self-interest.
Why is this, and what is different from the 1930s when something did
happen in the form of the impact of Keynes’s work on economic policy and,
to a lesser extent, on economic theory? The differences lie mostly in the
prevailing socio-economic conditions, and the situation within the profession.
In the 1930s, when the West was plunged into the vagaries of the Great
Depression, the Soviet Union was a rapidly expanding economy. So the
Keynesian call for greater government-intervention in the economy fitted the
needs for pragmatism and of ‘the urgent political imperative to counter
communism’.68 Following the collapse of the Central- and Eastern-European
economies and the triumph of neoliberalism in the West, coupled with
the crisis of social movements, no such imperative exists any more. And,
within the profession, the interwar-period was characterised by a true scientific
pluralism of methods and approaches. Although neoclassicism was already
ascendant, it had not yet dominated the profession, with American
institutionalism being the dominant school in the United States. Economics
was a much more discursive and much less technique-based discipline.69
In sum, as far as the possible effects of the crisis on economic science are
concerned, the emerging picture is one in which the response to crisis ranges
from ‘business as usual’, to pleas for better models by changing some underlying
assumption or moving to more-dynamic ones, to delving deeper into the
human psyche. All in all, as Steve Keen puts it, although ‘the “irresistible
force” of the Global Financial Crisis is indeed immense, so too is the inertia of
the “immovable object” of economic belief ’. The twin pillars of this ‘immovable
object’ are, firstly, the focus on the individual, whether rational or otherwise,
and the model-building approach. The only hope for a truly alternative theory
lies with political economy that breaks away from both of these pillars. So
what does the future hold for political economy?70
4. . . . to political economy
As we have seen already, one reaction within economics from those at least
willing to recognise the need for something more by way of explanation, is
only to draw upon existing models of market-imperfections newly applied.
And the leading representative in this respect is Joseph Stiglitz, by virtue of
There will be political battles ahead. Special interests will try to block many of the
reforms. The future of our nation will depend in no small measure on the outcome
of those battles.72
This is a vivid invitation to analyse special interests, power and conflict. Indeed,
Stiglitz claims to ‘understand the unbridled enthusiasm of special interests,
which found the arguments for deregulation profit enhancing’. Yet, he
immediately continues, ‘I am not so clear what motivated so many economists’.73
What is, however, clear is what he would have motivate their understanding,
namely attention to ‘irrationality’ and ‘intellectual inconsistency’, ‘highly
correlated movements in house prices’, ‘fat-tailed distributions’, ‘new
asymmetries of information’, ‘perverse incentives’, ‘banks too big to fail’,74
inducing the conclusion that ‘our financial system failed in its core missions –
allocating capital and managing risk’,75 leading to the previously cited
conclusion that ‘[t]he left now understands markets and the role markets
should and can play in the economy . . . the new left is trying to make markets
work’. This is not the stuff of political economy, other than as a point of
departure. And it might be observed that the balance of asymmetric information
within economics is all on the side of political and heterodox economists who
must command the orthodoxy, but not vice-versa. But power within the
discipline is totally the other way around. In short, vested interests and
ideology are not matters of asymmetric information and market-imperfections,
whether in the economy or within economics.
71. See Bayliss, Fine and van Waeyenberge (eds.) 2011, forthcoming.
72. Stiglitz 2009, p. 281.
73. Stiglitz 2009, p. 293.
74. All citations within Stiglitz 2009, p. 294.
75. Stiglitz 2009, p. 296.
24 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
But the second feature around the social sciences in the last two decades has
been the retreat from the extremes of neoliberalism – although this is better
seen as the second phase of neoliberalism rather than as its demise. Making
imperfect markets work, and reforming institutions are its intellectual marker,
especially within economics, the better to make globalisation work. In contrast,
across the other social sciences, the reaction against the extremes of neoliberalism
in-and-of-itself as well as an agenda-setting device is well-illustrated by the rise
of globalisation as the most significant of concepts across the social sciences as
a focus for gaining a critical handle on the realities of contemporary capitalism.
Its literature, even the word itself, did not exist before 1990. And it was a
neoliberal idea: that the state was withering away, and that this is a good thing.
Subsequently, the academic literature has taken a different view. It has devoted
attention to specifying contemporary capitalism as a world-system; it has
acknowledged the continuing importance of the state; and it has not denied
globalisation, but argued that it is complex, with a diversity of outcomes across
place, time and aspect. So the rise of globalisation as a concept has demonstrated
the reaction against neoliberalism within the social sciences by rejecting
the original notion, at least, of the reality and desirability of the withering
away of the state. After all, neoliberalism has always been about the interventions
of the state to promote the interests of private capital, especially in its
internationalisation (with financialisation to the fore in the current period).
So there are reasons to be cheerful around the prospects for political
economy across the social sciences, although the exact content by topic and
discipline is variegated. But what of the stimulus of external events as a
potential source of brighter prospects for heterodox political economy? We
do not have the external pressures for progressive policy and corresponding
scholarship that arose with the Keynesian period, and, until the balance
of forces are more conducive to alternative forces, the best that can be hoped
for, as far as the economics-profession is concerned, is a move away from the
monolithic approach to economic science characteristic of mainstream-
economics, which fetishises model-building, towards a pluralism of methods
and approaches, and away from atomistic approaches towards more-systemic,
aggregative, dynamic, historically-specific and socially-embedded types of
analysis of capitalism.
Institutionally, heterodox economists and political economists can explore
ways of organising themselves in pursuit of this prime objective. In Europe,
we already have enough ‘Heterodox Political Economy Associations’, including
the European Association of Evolutionary Political Economy (EAEPE), the
Association for Heterodox Economics (AHE), the International Initiative for
Promoting Political Economy (IIPPE), the Post-Keynesian group and the
26 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
amorphous mass of orthodoxy definitely lies on the wrong side of the borders.
But, by the same token, there is plenty of heterodoxy, at least in principle, that
straddles the border and is located on the side other than orthodoxy, so
extensive is the potential even for marginal but destructive deviations from it.
This suggests the need for a unity of purpose in criticising the mainstream and
in posing alternatives. For, if there is one thing as counterproductive as a
mainstream-economist, it is a political economist who knows he or she is right
and everybody else is wrong. So let those committed to political economy
learn from one another through friendly fire rather than perishing by it. For
yesterday’s philosophers are today’s economists. As Marx observed of them,
paraphrasing for modern times:79
Hitherto economists have had the solution of all riddles lying in their mathematical
models, and the stupid, exoteric world of finance had only to provide the data for
the roast pigeons of absolute-econometric knowledge and vast fortunes to fly into
it. Now economics has become mundane, and the most striking proof of this is
that economics itself has been drawn into the torment of the crisis, not only
externally but also internally. But, if constructing the future and settling
everything for all times are not our affair, it is all the more clear what we have to
accomplish at present: I am referring to ruthless criticism of all that exists, ruthless
both in the sense of not being afraid of the results it arrives at and in the sense of
being just as little afraid of conflict with the powers that be.
References
Akerlof, George A. and Robert J. Shiller 2009, Animal Spirits: How Human Psychology Drives the
Economy, and Why It Matters for Global Capitalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Arrow, Kenneth J. and Gerard Debreu 1954, ‘Existence of an Equilibrium for a Competitive
Economy’, Econometrica, 22, 3: 265–90.
Azariadis, Costas, John Ioannides and Christopher Pissarides 2010, ‘Proposals for a New
Development Policy’, Kathimerini, 9 October, available at: <http://news.kathimerini.
gr/4dcgi/_w_articles_economy_100048_12/10/2010_418274>.
Backhouse, Roger E. 2000, ‘Progress in Heterodox Economics’, Journal of the History of Economic
Thought, 22, 2: 149–55.
Bayliss, Kate, Ben Fine and Elisa van Waeyenberge (eds.) 2011, The Political Economy of
Development: The World Bank, Neoliberalism and Development Research, London: Pluto Press.
BBC News 2010, ‘Jane Austen’s Style Might Not Be Hers, Academic Claims’, 23 October,
available at: <http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/entertainment-arts-11610489>.
Bernanke, Ben S. 2004, ‘Remarks by Governor Ben S. Bernanke: At the meetings of the Eastern
Economic Association, Washington, DC’, available at: <http://www.federalreserve.gov/
BOARDDOCS/SPEECHES/2004/20040220/default.htm>.
79. For the original letter from Marx to Ruge, see Marx 1975.
28 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
Blaug, Mark 1999, ‘The Formalist Revolution, or What Happened to Orthodox Economics
After World War II’, in From Classical Economics to the Theory of the Firm: Essays in Honour of
D.P. O’Brien, edited by Roger Backhouse and John Creedy, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
—— 2003, ‘The Formalist Revolution of the 1950s’, in Samuels, Biddle and Davis (eds.)
2003.
Boland, Lawrence A. 2006, ‘On Reviewing Machine Dreams: Zoomed-In vs. Zoomed-Out’,
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36, 4: 480–95, available at: <http://www.sfu.ca/~boland/
dreamsR.pdf>.
Broad, William 2006, ‘Rogue Giants at Sea’, The New York Times, 11 July, available at: <http://
www.nytimes.com/2006/07/11/science/11wave.html?8dpc>.
Brus, Włodzimierz 1975, Socialist Ownership and Political Systems, translated by R.A. Clarke,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Buiter, Willem 2009, ‘The Unfortunate Uselessness of Most “State of the Art” Academic
Monetary Economics’, Financial Times, 13 March, available at: <http://blogs.ft.com/
maverecon/2009/03/the-unfortunate-uselessness-of-most-state-of-the-art-academic-
monetary-economics/>.
Callon, Michel, Cécile Méadel and Vololona Rabeharisoa 2002, ‘The Economy of Qualities’,
Economy and Society, 31, 2: 194–217.
Cassidy, John 2010a, ‘After the Blowup’, The New Yorker, 11 January: 28.
—— 2010b, ‘Interview with Eugene Fama’, The New Yorker, 13 January, available at: <http://
www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/johncassidy/2010/01/interview-with-eugene-fama.html>.
—— 2010c, ‘Interview with John Cochrane’, The New Yorker, 13 January, available at: <http://
www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/johncassidy/2010/01/interview-with-john-cochrane
.html>.
Choonara, Joseph 2010, ‘Economic Development’, International Socialism, 127, available at:
<http://www.isj.org.uk/index.php4?id=665&issue=127>.
Coddington, Alan 1983, Keynesian Economics: The Search for First Principles, Hemel Hempstead:
George Allen and Unwin.
Cohen, Avi J. and Geoffrey C. Harcourt 2003, ‘Whatever Happened to the Cambridge Capital
Theory Controversies?’, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 17: 1, 199–214, available at: <http://
dept.econ.yorku.ca/~avicohen/Linked_Documents/JEP_Cohen_Harcourt.pdf>.
Colander, David 2000, ‘The Death of Neoclassical Economics’, Journal of the History of Economic
Thought, 22, 2: 127–43, available at: <http://sandcat.middlebury.edu/econ/repec/mdl/
ancoec/0237.pdf>.
—— 2001, ‘The Death of Neoclassical Economics’, in The Lost Art of Economics, Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar.
Colander, David, Hans Föllmer, Armin Haas, Michael Goldberg, Katarina Juselius, Alan
Kirman, Thomas Lux and Brigitte Sloth 2009, ‘The Financial Crisis and the Systematic Failure
of Academic Economics’, in Kiel Working Papers, 1489, available at: <http://www.debtdeflation.
com/blogs/wp-content/uploads/papers/Dahlem_Report_EconCrisis021809.pdf>.
Colander, David, Richard P.F. Holt and J. Barkley Rosser, Jr. 2004, The Changing Face of
Economics: Conversations with Cutting Edge Economists, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press.
Davis, John 2006, ‘The Turn in Economics: Neoclassical Dominance to Mainstream Pluralism?’,
Journal of Institutional Economics, 2, 1: 1–20.
Doidge, Norman 2007, The Brain that Changes Itself: Stories of Personal Triumph from the Frontiers
of Brain Science, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Eichengreen, Barry and Michael D. Bordo 2002, ‘Crises Now and Then: What Lessons from the
Last Era of Financial Globalization’, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper,
8716, available at: <http://www.nber.org/papers/w8716>.
B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31 29
Epstein, Gerald and Jessica Carrick-Hagenbath 2010, ‘Financial Economists, Financial Interests
and Dark Corners of the Meltdown: It’s Time to Set Ethical Standards for the Economics
Professions’, Political Economy Research Institute Working Paper Series, 239, available at: <http://
www.peri.umass.edu/fileadmin/pdf/working_papers/working_papers_201-250/WP239.
pdf>.
—— 2011, ‘Letter to Robert E. Hall, President of the American Economic Association’,
available at: <http://www.peri.umass.edu/fileadmin/pdf/other_publication_types/AEA_letter_
Jan4.pdf>.
Ferguson, Charles 2010, ‘Larry Summers and the Subversion of Economics’, The Chronicle of
Higher Education, 3 October, available at: <http://chronicle.com/article/Larry-Summersthe/
124790/>.
Fine, Ben 2003, ‘Callonistics: A Disentanglement’, Economy and Society, 32, 3: 478–84.
—— 2010, Theories of Social Capital: Researchers Behaving Badly, London: Pluto.
—— 2011, ‘Neo-Liberalism in Retrospect? – It’s Financialisation, Stupid’, in Developmental
Politics in Transition: The Neoliberal Era and Beyond, edited by Ben Fine, Kyung-Sup Chang
and Linda Weiss, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Fine, Ben and Dimitris Milonakis 2009, From Economics Imperialism to Freakonomics: The
Shifting Boundaries Between Economics and Other Social Sciences, London: Routledge.
Frey, Bruno and Matthias Benz 2004, ‘From Imperialism to Inspiration: A Survey of Economics
and Psychology’, in The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy, edited by John B.
Davis, Alain Marciano and Jochen Runde, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Friedman, Milton 1999, ‘Conversation with Milton Friedman’, in Conversations with Leading
Economists: Interpreting Modern Macroeconomics, edited by Brian Snowdon and Howard R.
Vane, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Gamble, Andrew and Paul Walton 1972, From Alienation to Surplus Value, London: Sheed and
Ward.
Gough, Ian and Len Doyal 1986, A Theory of Human Need, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Greenspan, Alan 2008, ‘The Financial Crisis and the Role of Federal Regulators’, available at:
<http://house.resource.org/110/org.c-span.281958-1.pdf>.
Heilbroner, Robert L. and William Milberg 1995, The Crisis of Vision in Modern Economic
Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Henrich, Joseph, Robert Boyd, Samuel Bowles, Colin Camerer, Ernst Fehr, Herbert Gintis and
Richard McElreath 2001, ‘In Search of Homo-Economicus: Behavioural Experiments in 15
Small-Scale Societies’, American Economic Review, 91, 2: 73–8, available at: <http://www.
santafe.edu/~bowles/InSearchHomoEconomicus2001.pdf>.
Hicks, John Richard 1939, Value and Capital: An Inquiry into Some Fundamental Principles of
Economic Theory, Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
—— 1967 [1937], ‘Mr. Keynes and the Classics’, in Critical Essays in Monetary Theory, Oxford:
The Clarendon Press.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2009, ‘The Great Crash of 2008 and the Reform of Economics’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 33, 6: 1205–21.
Hoover, Kevin 2003, ‘A History of Postwar Monetary Economics and Macroeconomics’, in
Samuels, Biddle and Davis (eds.) 2003.
Keen, Steve 2009, ‘Mad, Bad and Dangerous to Know’, Real World Economics Review, 49: 2–7,
available at: <http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue49/Keen49.pdf>.
Keynes, John Maynard 1973 [1936], The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money,
Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Klamer, Arjo and David Colander 1990, The Making of an Economist, Boulder: Westview Press.
Krugman, Paul 1978, ‘The Theory of Interstellar Trade’, available at: <http://www.princeton.
edu/~pkrugman/interstellar.pdf>.
30 B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31
—— 2009, ‘How Did Economists Get it So Wrong?’, The New York Times, 2 September,
available at: <http://www.nytimes.com/2009/09/06/magazine/06Economic-t.html?_r= 1>.
Kurz, Heinz D. 2010, ‘On the Dismal State of the Dismal Science’, Homo Oeconomicus, 27, 3:
1–22.
Lebowitz, Michael A. 2003, Beyond Capital: Marx’s Political Economy of the Working Class, Second
Edition, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Lee, Frederic 2009, A History of Heterodox Economics: Challenging the Mainstream in the Twentieth
Century, London: Routledge.
Lawson, Tony 2003, Reorienting Economics, London: Routledge.
—— 2009, ‘The Current Economic Crisis: Its Nature and the Course of Academic Economics’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 33, 4: 759–77.
Lukács, Georg 1990 [1923], History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics,
translated by Rodney Livingstone, London: Merlin Press.
Marx, Karl 1975 [1843], ‘Letters from the Deutsch-Französische Jahrbücher: Marx to Ruge,
Kreuznach, September 1843’, available at: <http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/
1843/letters/43_09.htm>.
Milonakis, Dimitris and Ben Fine 2009, From Political Economy to Economics: Method, the Social
and the Historical in the Evolution of Economic Theory, London: Routledge.
Mirowski, Philip 2002, Machine Dreams: Economics Becomes a Cyborg Science, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
—— 2010, ‘The Great Mortification: Economists’ Responses to the Crisis of 2007–(and
Counting)’, The Hedgehog Review, 12, 3: 28–41, available at: <http://www.iasc-culture.org/
publications_article_2010_Summer_mirowski.php>.
Naudé, Wim 2009, ‘After the G-20 Summit: What Prospects for Global Development?’,
available at: <www.wider.unu.edu/publications/newsletter/articles/en_GB/09-04-09-g20/>.
Niehans, Jürg 1990, A History of Economic Thought: Classic Contributions, 1720–1980, Baltimore:
The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Patterson, Scott 2010, The Quants: How a New Breed of Math Whizzes Conquered Wall Street and
Nearly Destroyed It, New York: Crown Business.
Posner, Richard A. 2009, ‘How I Became a Keynesian: Second Thoughts in the Middle of
the Crisis’, The New Republic, 23 September, available at: <http://www.tnr.com/article/
how-i-became-keynesian>.
Rizvi, S. Abu Turab 1994, ‘The Microfoundations Project in General Equilibrium Theory’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 18, 4: 357–77.
—— 2001, ‘Philip Mirowski as a Historian of Economic Thought’, in Historians of Economics
and Economic Thought: The Construction of Disciplinary Memory, edited by Steven G. Medema
and Warren J. Samuels, London: Routledge, available at: <http://www.nd.edu/~pmirowsk/
pdf/Rizvi_on_Mirowski.pdf>.
—— 2003, ‘Postwar Neoclassical Microeconomics’, in Samuels, Biddle and Davis (eds.) 2003.
Rowthorn, Bob 1980, Capitalism, Conflict and Inflation: Essays in Political Economy, London:
Lawrence and Wishart.
Samuels, Warren J., Jeff E. Biddle and John B. Davis (eds.) 2003, A Companion to the History of
Economic Thought, Oxford: Blackwell.
Samuelson, Paul A. 1947, Foundations of Economic Analysis, Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University
Press.
Skidelsky, Robert 2009, Keynes: The Return of the Master, London: Allen Lane.
Solow, Robert M., 1997, ‘How Did Economics Get that Way and What Way Did It Get?’,
Dædalus, 126, 1: 39–58.
—— 2010, ‘Building a Science of Economics for the Real World’, available at: <http://
democrats.science.house.gov/Media/file/Commdocs/hearings/2010/Oversight/20july/
Solow_Testimony.pdf>.
B. Fine, D. Milonakis / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 3–31 31
Stiglitz, Joseph E. 2008, ‘Turn Left for Sustainable Growth’, Economists’ Voice, 5, 4: 1–3, available
at: <http://www.unizar.es/departamentos/estructura_economica/personal/vpinilla/documents/
Stiglitz_turnleft.pdf>.
—— 2009, ‘The Current Economic Crisis and Lessons for Economic Theory’, Eastern Economic
Journal, 35, 3: 281–96.
Taleb, Nassim Nicholas 2007, The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable, London:
Allen Lane.
The Economist 2009, ‘Monsters of the Deep’, 17 September, available at: <http://www.economist.
com/node/14446734>.
Varoufakis, Yannis 2010, ‘Adding Insult to Injury: On the 2010 Bank of Sweden Economics
Prize in Memory of Alfred Nobel’, Monthly Review, 12 October, available at: <http://mrzine.
monthlyreview.org/2010/varoufakis121010.html>.
Walras, Léon 1954 [1874], Elements of Pure Economics, translated by William Jaffé, London:
Allen and Unwin.
Wolf, Martin 2009, Fixing Global Finance: How to Curb Financial Crises in the 21st Century,
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 33–34 brill.nl/hima
The artist David Mabb has created an artwork especially for Historical
Materialism. Titled Luibov Popova Untitled Textile Design on William Morris
wallpaper for HM 2010, the print is issued in a run of 100. Mabb’s picture is
made by screen printing a textile design by Luibov Popova in red and black
over a section of William Morris wallpaper including Fruit, Willow Boughs,
Trellis, Brier Rabbit, Medway and Daisy. As a consequence of the different
wallpapers employed and the registration process, each work will be unique.
The prints measure 52.5 x 70 cm, and each one is signed and numbered by the
artist.
The artwork is available for purchase at the price of £75 (unframed, postage
not included) and can be ordered from http://www.historicalmaterialism.org/
news/mabb-print-buy.
The print has already been bought by museums in the UK and America
including the Victoria and Albert Museum. We hope you will see this as an
opportunity to acquire a fascinating artwork.
Panagiotis Sotiris
Department of Sociology, University of the Aegean, Mytilene
[email protected]
Abstract*
This article attempts a Marxist critique of Alain Badiou’s positions. The importance of Badiou’s
ontology as an affirmation of the possibility of radical-historical novelty is stressed, but also its
limits. These limits have to do with Badiou’s abandonment of a dialectical-relational conception
of social reality, his refusal of any causal connection between social reality, political decision and
event, and the absence of a theory of ideology and hegemony in his work. Consequently, Badiou’s
notion of a ‘subtractive’ politics cannot be considered an answer to the open questions of
communist strategy, despite his endorsement of the ‘communist hypothesis’.
Keywords
Badiou, Marxism, dialectics, social theory, political subjectivity, communist politics
1. Introduction
Despite his long theoretical and political trajectory, from Sartre, to Althusser,
to militant Maoism and finally to his own highly idiosyncratic version of
ontology,1 it is only relatively recently that Alain Badiou’s work has drawn
widespread attention and made him one of the most influential radical thinkers
of our time. Badiou’s main preoccupations, the question of the event, the need
for militancy and the question of the political subject, respond to certain
aspects of the current historical conjuncture. His work can be seen as an
answer to the attempt at a complete closure of historical thinking that has
been an important aspect of the neoliberal imperative against the possibility of
* The writer wishes to thank Alberto Toscano and the anonymous referees of this article for
their suggestions and criticism.
1. For a general overview of Badiou’s theoretical and ideological trajectory, see Hallward
2003. In an autobiographical text, Badiou refers to Sartre, Lacan and Althusser as his philosoph-
ical masters (Badiou 2004b).
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2011 DOI: 10.1163/156920611X573789
36 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
any form of historical change. Although Badiou refuses the traditional notion
of possibility, since, for him, the event is what is ‘impossible’, what is not
included in the contours of a given situation, his work can still be read as
insisting on the possibility of new events and historical change. It can also be
seen as a theoretical intervention in the discussion of what meaning the
formation of collective subjects has today, especially in a time when mass-
movements and anticapitalist aspirations have returned.
Alain Badiou’s theoretical turn towards an ontology of the event has also
been seen as a response to the crisis of left-wing or generally radical politics in
the early eighties after the exhaustion of the revolutionary thrust of 1968 and
its aftermaths. It is the same feeling of crisis that can be traced as the background
to Althusser’s reformulation of an aleatory materialism of the contingent
encounter2 or to Foucault’s turn towards an ethics or aesthetic of the subject.3
In all cases, the underlying preoccupation is with the realisation that there
is no general tendency – in the sense of historical teleology or historical
mechanics – towards emancipation, and that the collective agents associated
with social emancipation – the French Communist Party, in the case of Althusser,
radical social and political movements, in the case of Foucault, the Maoist
movement in the case of Badiou – can enter periods of prolonged crisis.
This sense of historical crisis led Badiou to a rethinking of the very notion
of the event. On the one hand, the reference to the event pertains to May
1968, both as a violent break of historical continuity and as the bitter challenge
of dealing with its defeat and the question of its (im)possible repetition. On
the other hand, the event is a crucial question for any effort to rethink
emancipatory and transformative politics, since any such form of politics is
based on the premise that new events happen, that changes occur, that forms
alter. That is why we must stress, before proceeding to our points of criticism,
that Badiou’s theory of the event, which rejects any form of ontological
dualism, can be considered an important contribution to a materialist
conception of political practice, both in its negation of teleology and in its
affirmation of historical novelty. It also represents a certain break with idealism,
because Badiou rejects any subjective/objective dichotomy, treating the subject
as an essential aspect of the irruption of the event. Equally important is
Badiou’s rejection of the traditional notion of truth-as-subjective-stance and
his insistence on the truth of a situation as an ontological proposition: truth is
an actual possibility – or a potential exception – of the evental site itself.4 This
2. Althusser 2006.
3. Foucault 1984.
4. ‘Truths are materially produced in specific situations, and each begins from an event or
discovery that eludes the prevailing logic that structures and governs those situations.’ (Hallward
2003, p. xxv.)
P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59 37
5. ‘The vast majority of empirical political orientations have nothing to do with truth. We
know this. They organize a repulsive mixture of power and opinions.’ (Badiou 2003b, p. 70.) On
Badiou’s criticism of postmodern doxa, see also Žižek 1999, pp. 131–2.
6. Badiou designates this reference to discourses and bodies as ‘democratic materialism’, as
opposed to what he designates as ‘dialectical materialism’, which includes the reference to truth
(Badiou 2009a, pp. 1–4).
7. ‘[T]he one is not’ (Badiou 2005d, p. 23). On this point, see also Hallward 2005.
38 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
At bottom, ‘ensemble’, ‘social’ and ‘relations’ all say the same thing. The point is
to reject both of the positions (the realist and nominalist) between which
philosophers have generally been divided: the one arguing that the genus or
essence precedes the existence of individuals; the other that individuals are the
primary reality, from which universals are ‘abstracted’. For amazingly, neither of
these two positions is capable of thinking precisely what is essential in human
existence: the multiple and active relations which individuals establish with each
other (whether of language, labour, love, reproduction, domination, conflict
etc.), and the fact that it is these relations which define what they have in
common, the ‘genus’. They define this because they constitute it at each moment
in multiple forms. They thus provide the ‘only’ effective content of the notion of
essence applied to the human being (i.e. to human beings).17
1) To abstract from the historical process and to define the religious sentiment regarded by itself,
and to presuppose an abstract – isolated – human individual; 2) The essence therefore can by
him only be regarded as ‘species’, as an inner ‘dumb’ generality which unites many individuals
only in a natural way.’ (Marx 2002.)
16. Balibar 1995, p. 30.
17. Balibar 1995, pp. 30–1.
18. Macherey 2008, pp. 151–2.
19. ‘N’existent à proprement parler que des relations’ (Macherey 1979, p. 218).
40 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
However, during the past few years, Badiou has made an effort to answer some
of these criticisms and to offer a more complex version of his ontology. Logics
of Worlds sets out to provide what Badiou calls a ‘greater logic’.21 He attempts
to answer the questions left open in Being and Event, especially the problem of
grounding his ontology mainly upon the situation-event couple. This left out
the question of the possible forms of appearance of the elements of a situation
and of theorising how one possible world emerges instead of another.
What the 1988 book did at the level of pure being – determining the ontological
type of truths and the abstract form of the subject that activates them – this book
aims to do at the level of being-there, or of appearing, or of worlds.22
appear within this world.27 This problematic indeed adds to Badiou’s schema
a degree of complexity absent from the original formulation of his ontology. It
also offers a possibility to think some sort of social determination and causal
relation between different worlds. The main problem is precisely that this level
of appearing is added to the level of multiple-being, and the insistence on the
sharp distinction between these levels undermines any attempt at reconfiguring
historical causality apart from very specific and limited historical conjunctures.
Moreover, he refuses to offer a theorisation of the relation between an appearing
and the pure multiplicity of being, leading again to a notion of radical
contingency. As Peter Hallward has noted,
It is true that in this revised ontological schema, Badiou includes the notion
of the relation. However, we are still far from a relational conception. This
specific relational constitution is at the level of appearing of a particular world,
not of ontology. ‘That is why we will give the name “logic” to the laws of the
relational network which determine the worldly appearing of multiple-being’.29
Badiou defines a relation between two objects as a function between two sets,
a function that creates neither existence nor difference.30 That is why he insists
on presenting relations as ontologically subordinate to the elements that relate
to each other.
ontological, as derivative and not primary, replacing it with the notion of the
reverse.
It’s remarkable that what will serve to sustain negation in the order of appearing
is the first consequence of the transcendental operations, and by no means an
initial given. Negation, in the extended and ‘positive’ form of the existence of the
reverse of a being, is a result. We can say that as soon as we are dealing with the
being of the being of being-there, that is with the being of appearing as bound to
the logic of a world, it follows that the reverse of a being exists, in the sense that
there exists a degree of appearance ‘contrary’ to its own.32
The result is that anyone looking for a more dialectical conception remains
unsatisfied, especially since Badiou insists that relations cannot fundamentally
affect the elements that enter into a relation with each other. Contrary to the
insistence of Althusser or Poulantzas33 that classes do not exist outside of the
class-struggle, an antagonistic relation between social classes is not, according
to Badiou, the basic condition of their existence, nor does the balance of forces
affect their form of social being. As Peter Hallward has noted:
Not only is relation thus conceived as little more than a variation on the
elementary relation of order (greater-than or lesser-than), there is no clear sense
that it can qualify, shape or otherwise affect the objects related. A relation of
struggle between two interests or classes, for instance, does not here play a
constituent role in their being or becoming so much as illustrate the relative
difference in their ‘intrinsic’ intensity or strength. Such relation always comes
after its terms.34
Badiou rejects any constituent relation between truths and historical or social
‘development’, along with any detailed notion of interaction between levels of
32. Badiou 2009a, p. 136. ‘[T]he reverse is indeed a logical category (and therefore relative
to the worldliness of beings); it is not an ontological category (linked to the intrinsic multiple
composition of beings, or, if you will, to the mathematical world).’ (Badiou 2009a, p. 152.)
33. Althusser 1973, pp. 29–30. Poulantzas 2008, p. 328.
34. Hallward 2008, p. 115.
35. Hallward 2004, p. 12. According to Jason Barker, ‘[f ]or Badiou (knowledge of ) capitalism
is unable to determine events, and so has no direct grasp on political processes.’ (Barker 2006,
p. xx.)
P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59 43
Badiou is right to emphasise that the proposition that ‘one divides into two’
marks the line of demarcation between a militant and a conciliatory point of
view.40 However, the main question facing any attempt to think a materialist
dialectic has been not only to theorise division and antagonism, but how to
think social cohesion, the ‘One’, as always traversed by contradictions and
conflicts that not only entail the possibility of rupture, but also provide its
only possibility of unstable unity.
Badiou has always been preoccupied with the notion of the subject, as a
result of both his engagement with communist forms of militancy and his
interest in the work of Lacan.41 Badiou’s emphasis has always been that the
crucial moment is that of the emergence of forms of political subjectivity.
Along with the emphasis on truth, fidelity to the event, and correct ‘naming’,
it attests to Badiou’s post-Leninism.42 Badiou’s conception of antagonism is
also based upon this conception of the subject. In its first formulation in
Theory of the Subject, it takes the form of an antagonism between the political
subject par excellence, namely the proletariat, and the current configuration of
an historical situation. Indeed, the very notion of a political subject, which, in
Badiou, is always the result of a material process related to an event and not
something ‘subjective’, is structured around the notion of the proletariat as the
transformation of the working class into a specific political subjectivity. With
this, Badiou is indeed renewing the thinking of the collective-political subject
and its constitution. It is also in line with the conception of the proletariat in
the early writings of Marx, as that which exceeds and confronts the total
configuration of capitalist social and political constitution. In the Introduction
to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, Marx referred to the proletariat in
the following way:
[T]he formation of a class with radical chains, a class of civil society which is not
a class of civil society, an estate which is the dissolution of all estates, a sphere
which has a universal character by its universal suffering and claims no particular
right because no particular wrong but wrong generally is perpetrated against it; . . .
which does not stand in any one-sided antithesis to the consequences but in all-
round antithesis to the premises of the German state; a sphere, finally, which
cannot emancipate itself without emancipating itself from all other spheres of
society and thereby emancipating all other spheres of society[.] . . . This dissolution
of society as a particular estate is the proletariat.43
interiorisation of the relation itself, in such a way that the antagonistic terms
become the functions or bearers of this relation, the result being that we must see
class-relations as relations which the oppressed cannot avoid, unless they destroy
the relation of subjection itself, by this transforming themselves into individuals
other than the ones the existing relation ‘constitutes’.46
The problem here partly originates in the way in which Badiou treats the
notion of overdetermination. He refers positively to overdetermination as the
space of politics,47 but he treats it as the possibility of subjective-political
militancy and intervention.48 However, what is missing is exactly a conception
of overdetermination as the expression of the complexity of objective-causal
determination, of the historically specific and conjunctural condensation of
contradictions, of the possibility of displacements and/or ruptures and,
therefore, of the possibility of actually intervening politically in order to
change the balance of forces. Overdetermination, at least in its initial
theorisation by Althusser,49 referred to the possibility of a materialist conception
of political practice based on the complex, contradictory and, consequently,
open-to-change character of social reality, not simply to the possibility of
subjective intervention.
It is true that Badiou credits Althusser with opening the question of a
‘subjectivity without a subject’,50 but he insists that this designates a process of
thought that ‘balances over into the possible, and does so in accordance with
a partisanship, a prescription, that nothing guarantees, neither in the objective
order of the economy nor in the statist order of the subject, but which
nonetheless is capable of tracing a real trajectory in the situation.’51 Despite
the efforts by Badiou to distance his position from a subjectivist conception of
political subjectivity, I think that he is far from offering an adequate answer.
On the contrary, I think that we can still find in Althusser a highly original
conception of the ways in which particular collective ‘non-subjects’ emerge in
the over-determined terrain of the conjuncture, considered as a process without
52. See, for example, the following quotation from the Prison Notebooks: ‘One should stress
the importance and significance which, in the modern world, political parties have in the
elaboration and diffusion of conceptions of the world, because essentially what they do is to
work out the ethics and the politics corresponding to these conceptions and act as it were as their
historical “laboratory”. . . . The relation between theory and practice becomes even closer the
more the conception is vitally and radically innovatory and opposed to old ways of thinking. For
this reason one can say that the parties are the elaborators of new integral and totalitarian
intellectualities and the crucibles where the unification of theory and practice, understood as a
real historical process, takes place.’ (Gramsci 1971, p. 335, translation modified.) Hoare and
Smith use ‘intelligentsias’ instead of ‘intellectualities’, but I think that the latter is much closer to
the point. See also the French edition of the Cahiers de prison (Gramsci 1978, p. 187).
53. Badiou and Balmès 1976.
54. Badiou 2005d, p. 204.
55. Badiou 2001.
56. Toscano 2006.
48 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
57. For a reading of Gramsci that stresses the theoretical complexity of the notion of
hegemony, see Thomas 2009.
58. ‘Thinking is sufficient to change the world: such is the ultimate distillation of Badiou’s
idealism.’ (Brassier 2006, p. 74.)
59. ‘[T]he subject, as local situated configuration, is neither the intervention nor the operator
of fidelity, but the advent of their Two, that is, the incorporation of the event into the situation
in the mode of a generic procedure.’ (Badiou 2005d, p. 393.)
60. On Lacan’s conception of the subject, see Lacan 1973; Žižek (ed.) 1998.
61. ‘A subject measures the newness of the situation to-come’ (Badiou 2005d, p. 406). ‘[I]t is
possible to give the following definition of a subject: that which decides an undecidable from the
standpoint of an indiscernible.’ (Badiou 2005d, p. 407.)
62. For an insistence on Badiou’s decisionism, see Žižek 1999, pp. 158–61. For a criticism of
Žižek’s position, see Power 2006.
P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59 49
it is ‘the local status of a procedure’,63 thus treating the subject as the effect of
material processes64 and avoiding the voluntarism of traditional decisionism.
On the other hand, the sharp dichotomy between the situation and the event,
the absence of any direct causal relation between the situation and the irruption
of the event, and the notion of subjective fidelity, can, indeed, at the end,
notwithstanding Badiou’s own precautions, over-emphasise the transformative
effects of subjective decisions. In this sense, we are still faced with radical
aporiae concerning the theory of the subject, rather than definite answers.
Badiou tends to reject a ‘programmatic’ conception of politics, which would
be based upon knowledge of the terrain of struggle, suggesting, instead, a
conception of the political intervention as a wager, where any knowledge is
possible only retroactively.
of the insistence on the event as exception and radical break, as the rise of
the new.68
This can also be seen in the emphasis Badiou places on the void, as that
which is subtracted from presentation and thus makes possible the intervention
that will bring forward the unpresented.69 As a reference to social reality’s
character as always open to transformation and change, it is a necessary
‘ontological’ assertion. But the question of an immanent potentiality for change
(social change as objective possibility), the main question facing political
philosophy from the Enlightenment onwards, remains open, since Badiou’s
answer does not help us to get out of the oscillation between the idealism of
the distinction between objective reality and subjective intervention and the
teleology of a dialectics of immanence and potentiality. It is true that the more
complex social ontology offered in Logics of Worlds includes reference to the
inexistent, as what is and at the same time is not in a certain world,70 marking
the possibility both of exclusion but also of emergence, but we are still far
from an answer.
No wonder that the corollary to the radical undecidability of politics is a
rather historicist or metaphysical belief in the trans-historical potential of
popular uprisings in all of human history. I refer here to Badiou’s notion of the
communist invariants introduced in his 1976 pamphlet on ideology.71
According to Badiou, communism (in the sense of egalitarian and anti-statist
aspirations) is not a singular-political project, but a universal characteristic of
all forms of popular struggle, a position to which he is still faithful.72
68. On this point, see the way Slavoj Žižek opposes the notion of repetition in Deleuze
(Zizek 2007).
69. On Badiou’s treatment of the notion of the void, see Badiou 2005d, pp. 52–9. See also
the comments in Gillespie 2001.
70. ‘[G]iven an object in a world, there exists a single element of this object which inexists in
that world. It is this element that we call the proper inexistent of the object. It testifies, in the
sphere of appearance, for the contingency of being-there.’ (Badiou 2009a, p. 324.)
71. Badiou and Balmès 1976.
72. ‘From Spartacus to Mao . . ., from the Greek democratic insurrections to the worldwide
decade 1966–1976, it is and has been, in this sense, a question of communism.’ (Badiou 2003b,
p. 131.) See also the references to eternal truths in the Introduction to Logics of Worlds.
52 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
We now know that the question is to get rid of a representative vision of politics.
The canonical statement by Lenin, according to which society is divided into
classes and that classes are represented by political parties is out of date. In its
essence this statement is homogenous to the parliamentary conception.75
Rather than a warrior beneath the walls of the State, a political activist is a patient
watchman of the void instructed by the event[.] . . . There the activist constructs
the means to sound, if only for an instant, the site of the unpresentable, and the
means to be thenceforth faithful to the proper name that, afterwards, he or she
will have been able to give to – or hear, one cannot decide – this non-place of
place, the void.83
86. On Badiou’s political interventions, see Badiou 2003a, Badiou 2004a, Badiou 2005b,
Badiou 2006b, Badiou 2007.
87. Poulantzas 1980.
88. On the notion of Badiou’s ‘minimal Marxism’, see Toscano 2008.
89. See Badiou 2010, Chapter 4.
90. Badiou 2009b.
91. ‘Revolutionaries are divided and only weakly organized, broad sectors of working-class
youth have fallen prey to nihilistic despair, the vast majority of intellectuals are servile.’ (Badiou
2010, p. 259.)
92. Badiou 2010, p. 260.
93. ‘By combining intellectual constructs, which are always global and universal, with
experiments of fragments of truths, which are local and singular, yet universally transmittable,
we can give new life to the communist hypothesis, or rather to the Idea of communism, in
individual consciousnesses.’ (Badiou 2010, p. 260.) ‘[I]t is not the victory of the hypothesis
which is at stake today, but the conditions of its existence. This is our task, during the reactionary
interlude that now prevails: through the combination of thought processes – always global, or
universal, in character – and political experience, always local or singular, yet transmissible, to
56 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
6. Conclusion
There is no doubt that Alain Badiou’s endeavour has been one of the most
original contributions to a materialist ontology of the political combined with
an important and eloquent criticism of all forms of sociopolitical inequality
and oppression. However, there are limits and shortcomings in this effort.
These limits, in my opinion, have to do Badiou’s distancing of himself from
Marx’s highly original conception of social relations as dialectical contradictions,
his insistence that overdetermination, and, consequently, politics belongs to
renew the existence of the communist hypothesis, in our conscience and on the ground.’ (Badiou
2008b, p. 42.)
P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59 57
the subjective realm, his refusal of any form of historical causality and his
conception of a ‘subtractive’ politics ‘at a distance from the state’. Badiou’s
vigorous attempt to present his schema in a more complex and dialectical
way in Logics of Worlds and his endorsement of the communist hypothesis
do not transcend these limits, which represent fundamental aspects of his
problematic.
References
Althusser, Louis 2005 [1965], For Marx, translated by Ben Brewster, London: Verso.
—— 2006, Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 1978–1987, translated by G.M. Goshgarian,
London: Verso.
Althusser, Louis and Étienne Balibar 1990 [1968], Reading ‘Capital’, translated by Ben Brewster,
London: Verso.
Ashton, Paul, Adam John Bartlett and Justin Clemens (eds.) 2006, The Praxis of Alain Badiou,
Melbourne: re.press.
Badiou, Alain 1975, Théorie de la contradiction, Paris: François Maspero.
—— 1982, Théorie du sujet, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
—— 1985, Peut-on penser la politique?, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
—— 1989, Manifeste pour la philosophie, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
—— 2001 [1993], Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil, translated by Peter Hallward,
London: Verso.
—— 2003a, Circonstances, tome 1: Kosovo, 11 septembre, Chirac/Le Pen, Paris: Éditions Léo
Scheer.
—— 2003b, Infinite Thought: Truth and the Return of Philosophy, edited and translated by Oliver
Feltham and Justin Clemens, London: Continuum.
—— 2004a, Circonstances, tome 2: Irak, foulard, Allemagne/France, Paris: Éditions Léo Scheer.
—— 2004b, ‘L’aveu du philosophe’, available at: <http://www.lacan.com/badphilo.htm>.
—— 2005a, Le Siècle, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
—— 2005b, Circonstances, tome 3: Portées du mot “juif ”, Paris: Éditions Léo Scheer.
—— 2005c, ‘The Adventure of French Philosophy’, available at: <http://www.lacan.com/
badenglish.htm>.
—— 2005d [1988], Being and Event, translated by Oliver Feltham, London: Continuum.
—— 2006a [1998], Metapolitics, translated by Jason Barker, London: Verso.
—— 2006b, Polemics, translated by Steve Corcoran, London: Verso.
—— 2006c, L’être et l’événement: Tome 2, Logiques des mondes, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
—— 2006d, Theoretical Writings, Revised Edition, edited and translated by Ray Brassier and
Alberto Toscano, London: Continuum.
—— 2008a, ‘ “We Need a Popular Discipline”: Contemporary Politics and the Crisis of the
Negative’, Critical Inquiry, 34: 645–59.
—— 2008b, ‘The Communist Hypothesis’, New Left Review, II, 42: 29–42, available at: <http://
www.newleftreview.org/?view=2705>.
—— 2009a [2006], Logics of Worlds: Being and Event II, translated by Alberto Toscano, London:
Continuum.
—— 2009b, Second manifeste pour la philosophie, Paris: Librairie Arthème Fayard.
—— 2009c, L’hypothèse communiste, Paris: Éditions Lignes.
—— 2009d [1982], Theory of the Subject, translated by Bruno Bosteels, London: Continuum.
58 P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59
—— 2010 [2009], The Communist Hypothesis, translated by David Macey and Steve Corcoran,
London: Verso.
Badiou, Alain and François Balmès 1976, De l’idéologie, Paris: François Maspero.
Badiou, Alain and Slavoj Žižek (eds.) 2010, L’idée du communisme. Conférence de Londres, 2009,
Paris: Éditions Lignes.
Balibar, Étienne 1995 [1993], The Philosophy of Marx, translated by Chris Turner, London:
Verso.
—— 1997, La Crainte des masses. Politique et philosophie avant et après Marx, Paris: Galilée.
Barker, Jason 2006, ‘Translator’s Introduction’, in Badiou 2006a.
Bensaïd, Daniel 2004 [2001], ‘Alain Badiou and the Miracle of the Event’, translated by Ray
Brassier, in Hallward (ed.) 2004.
Bosteels, Bruno 2002, ‘Alain Badiou’s Theory of the Subject: The Recommencement of Dialectical
Materialism? (Part II)’, Pli, 13: 172–208.
—— 2005, ‘Post-Maoism: Badiou and Politics’, Positions, 13, 3: 575–634.
—— 2010, ‘L’hypothèse gauchiste: le communisme à l’âge de la terreur’, in Badiou and Žižek
(eds.) 2010.
Brassier, Ray 2006, ‘Presentation as Anti-Phenomenon in Alain Badiou’s Being and Event’,
Continental Philosophy Review, 39, 1: 59–77.
Foucault, Michel 1984, Histore de la sexualité, tome 3: Le souci de soi, Paris: Éditions Gallimard.
Gillespie, Sam 2001, ‘Placing the Void: Badiou on Spinoza’, Angelaki, 6, 3: 63–77.
Gramsci, Antonio, 1971, Selections from Prison Notebooks, edited and translated by Quintin
Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith, London: Lawrence and Wishart.
—— 1978, Cahiers de prison. Tome III, Paris: Éditions Gallimard.
Hallward, Peter 2002, ‘Badiou’s Politics: Equality and Justice’, Culture Machine, 4, available at:
<http://culturemachine.net/index.php/cm/article/view/271/256>.
—— 2003, Badiou: A Subject to Truth, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
—— 2004, ‘Introduction: Consequences of Abstraction’, in Hallward (ed.) 2004.
—— 2005, ‘Depending on Inconsistency: Badiou’s Answer to the “Guiding Question of All
Contemporary Philosophy” ’, Polygraph, 17: 11–25.
—— 2008, ‘Order and Event: On Badiou’s Logics of Worlds’, New Left Review, II, 53: 97–122.
—— (ed.) 2004, Think Again: Alain Badiou and the Future of Philosophy, London: Continuum.
Hewlett, Nick 2004, ‘Engagement and Transcendence: the Militant Philosophy of Alain Badiou’,
Modern & Contemporary France, 12, 3: 335–52.
Kouvélakis, Stathis 2000, ‘La politique dans ses limites ou les paradoxes d’Alain Badiou’, available
at: <ftp://ftp2.marxau21.fr/marxau/reserve/KOUVELAKIS_Paradoxes_de_Badiou.pdf>.
Lacan, Jacques 1973, Le Séminaire de Jacques Lacan, Livre XI: ‘Les quatre concepts fondamenteux
de la psychanalyse’, Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
Macherey, Pierre 1979, Hegel ou Spinoza, Paris: François Maspero.
—— 2008, Marx 1845. Les ‘thèses’ sur Feuerbach, Paris: Éditions Amsterdam.
Marx, Karl 1975 [1843], ‘Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law.
Introduction’, in Marx and Engels 1975.
—— 2002 [1845], ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, translated by Cyril Smith, available at: <http://www.
marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/theses/index.htm>.
Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels 1975, Collected Works, Volume 3, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Organisation Politique 2001, ‘Qu’est-ce que l’Organisation Politique?’, available at: <http://
humaniterouge.alloforum.com/organisation-politique-t2605-1.html>.
Poulantzas, Nicos 1980 [1978], State, Power, Socialism, translated by Patrick Camiller, London:
Verso.
—— 2008, The Poulantzas Reader, edited by James Martin, London: Verso.
P. Sotiris / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 35–59 59
Power, Nina 2006, ‘Towards an Anthropology of Infinitude: Badiou and the Political Subject’,
in Ashton, Bartlett and Clemens (eds.) 2006.
Thomas, Peter D. 2009, The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism, Leiden:
Brill.
Toscano, Alberto 2004a, ‘Communism as Separation’, in Hallward (ed.) 2004.
—— 2004b, ‘From the State to the World? Badiou and Anti-Capitalism’, Communication and
Cognition, 37, 3–4: 199–224.
—— 2006, ‘The Bourgeois and the Islamist, or, The Other Subjects of Politics’, in Ashton,
Bartlett and Clemens (eds.) 2006.
—— 2008, ‘Marxism Expatriated: Alain Badiou’s Turn’, in Critical Companion to Contemporary
Marxism, edited by Jacques Bidet and Stathis Kouvelakis, Historical Materialism Book Series,
Leiden: Brill.
Žižek, Slavoj 1999, The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology, London: Verso.
—— 2007, ‘On Alain Badiou and Logiques des mondes’, available at: <http://lacan.com/
zizbadman.htm>.
—— (ed.) 1998, Cogito and the Unconcious, Durham, NC.: Duke University Press.
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 brill.nl/hima
Vivek Chibber
New York University
[email protected]
Abstract
During the 1980s and 1990s, the debate on the Marxist theory of history centred largely around
the work of Robert Brenner’s property-relations-centred construal of it, and G.A. Cohen’s
attempt to revive the classical, determinist argument. This article examines two influential
arguments by Erik Wright and his colleagues, and by Alan Carling, which acknowledge important
weaknesses in Cohen’s work, but which also try to construct a more plausible version of his
theory. I show that the attempts to rescue Cohen are largely unsuccessful. And, to the extent that
they render the argument plausible, they do so at the cost of turning it, willy-nilly, into a kind of
class-struggle theory. I conclude that this spells the demise of the classical version of historical
materialism, but also observe that this does not leave us with a voluntaristic understanding of
history, as some of its defenders fear.
Keywords
Class, class-struggle, exploitation, mode of production, optimality-thesis, production-relations,
productive forces, social forms
Introduction
Over the past decade or so, the debate over the Marxist theory of history has
seemed to have run out of steam. This is not altogether surprising, given
the enormous energy that poured into the issue for around a quarter of a
century – no debate can last forever. On the other hand, lulls such as this can
be taken as an opportunity to take stock, as it were.1 This is especially true of
the debate on historical materialism, as this is an area where the protagonists
have striven to maintain clarity, and scrupulously followed the thread of one
1. I would like to thank Charles Post, Erik Wright and Robert Brenner for their extensive
comments on earlier versions of this paper, and also the Historical Materialism board. Special
thanks to Sebastian Budgen for persuading me to dust off the paper for publication. For a good
recent summing up of the debate since the 1990s, see Callinicos 2004.
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2011 DOI: 10.1163/156920611X573798
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 61
2. Cohen 1978.
3. Cohen 2002.
62 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
8. Wright 2005.
64 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
9. The element of coercion is, I think, necessary for any relation to be regarded a class-relation.
Purely voluntary transfers – donations, gifts, etc. – would not be considered exploitative. They
would count as class-relations only if it was discovered that their voluntary nature was an
ideological cover, and that they were systematic in their occurrence.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 65
the idea – to which Marxists most certainly hold – that exploitation necessarily
generates resistance, and, through that, class-struggle.
Class-struggle plays a dual rôle in the theory of history. On the one hand, it
forms a fundamental axis of political conflict in any social formation.10 On the
other hand, it constitutes the means by which societies traverse from one set
of property-relations to another – it is the mechanism that drives history
forward. This should not be cause for surprise. Class-struggle concerns the
terms on which actors secure access to the means of production – the security
of their property-rights, the pitch and level of exploitation, etc. It is a natural
corollary of this that such struggles should also lead to changes in the basic
framework of property itself. This much Marxists have stressed throughout
the previous century. It is Brenner’s contribution to have argued, correctly,
I think, that, until the advent of capitalism, all previous transitions have been
unintended consequences of the defence of existing property-rights.11 Transitions
have, in turn, been catalysed by deep economic crises, during which, normal
means of surplus-extraction break down, suddenly heightening the level of
conflict between producer and rulers. The resolution to the crisis – the
re-emergence of stable surplus-extraction – need not issue in the form of new
property-relations, but it does create a window for such epochal shifts to come
about. Whether or not they occur is a contingent outcome of class-struggle.
10. This is a somewhat controversial claim, even among Marxists. Some have averred that
class-struggle ought not to be privileged above other kinds of conflict, while others maintain that
it occupies a unique space. For the purposes of this essay, it is not important which of the two is
correct. But note that, even for the defenders of the weaker claim, class-conflict may not be the
central conflict, but it must be within the set of conflicts which are deemed central to the
dynamics of a social formation. Marxists have to commit to the view that it is a fundamental
cleavage, if not the most important one.
11. Compare this with Paul Sweezy’s account of the rise of capitalism, in which lords make a
more-or-less conscious switch to new property-relations to garner higher revenues. See his
contribution to the famous Dobb-Sweezy debate, contained in Hilton (ed.) 1976.
66 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
Hence, the actual sequence of social forms cannot be predicted on the basis of
this theory alone, since it stresses the contingencies of class-struggle.
It is at this stage that the theory of transitions steps in. This component of
historical materialism is directed specifically at the moment of transition from
one mode of production to another. Its main function is to stipulate a set of
conditions which constrain the transition to a new mode of production.
Whichever set of production-relations emerges as the new dominant form –
whichever class establishes its rule – must, on this theory, exhibit certain
properties. In fact, according to the traditional theory, the successor-class is
really only constrained by one particular property: it must be a class that can
oversee the continued development of the productive forces. At any historical
juncture, this drastically narrows the range of candidates that can succeed a
crisis-ridden social formation. How narrow the constraints are depends upon
how stringently the conditions are taken to operate – how strongly the theory
is interpreted. In its weakest form, the theory simply predicts that the new
mode of production will preserve the level of development fostered by the
previous one; in its strongest form, it insists that the class that establishes its
rule will be the one suited to the most rapid development of the productive
forces. The debate on historical materialism is basically about just how strong
a claim the theory can defend.
The term ‘historical materialism’ has, over the course of the twentieth
century, loosely encompassed both of the theories just outlined. For most
Marxists of the Second International and after, there was a basic division of
labour between the two components. The theory of social forms was primarily
concerned with individuating different types of social systems or modes of
production – it would identify their distinct relations of production, show the
‘laws of motion’ and the forms of class-struggle specific to each such type, and
the manner in which the struggle between classes led to the demise of one
social order and the rise of the next. The theory of transitions served to explain
how the transitions across modes of production were non-arbitrary, in a very
specific sense: the mode of production that replaced the previous one was not
simply determined by the vagaries of class-struggle, but was constrained by the
functional requirements of the productive forces. These constraints are what
impart a certain logic to the course of history. It is not simply that history is
driven forward by the contingencies of class-struggle. The resolution to class-
conflicts at certain key-junctures – namely, when social formations descend
into crisis – is itself governed by the demands of the productive forces. The
class that wins, which establishes its rule, will be the one that conforms to
these demands. It follows that the classes which did win at key-points were the
ones most suited to this task. And this, finally, means that there is a fairly
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 67
What is at stake
We can now appreciate what is at stake in the debate surrounding historical
materialism. The central issue would appear to be, which of the two components
of historical materialism should bear the primary explanatory weight, the
theory of social forms, or the theory of transitions? This, in turn, would seem
to depend on just how narrow are the constraints imposed by the productive
forces on new production-relations. The stronger the constraints, the lesser the
rôle of class-struggle in explaining the movement from one historical epoch to
another.
At its strongest, the theory of transitions insists that the functional demands
of the productive forces are so strong that, when modes of production descend
into crisis, the range of possible-successor production-relations can be
narrowed down to just one – that set which is best for the further development
of the productive forces. As we shall see, this seems to be the interpretation
offered by Cohen. On Cohen’s stringently-canonical historical materialism,
once production-relations set A descends into a final crisis, the candidates for
successor production-relations are winnowed down to just one – set B, since
this is the one that is best-suited for further developing the productive forces.
Class-struggle is the mechanism which brings about the transition to B, but
the fact that B followed A was, in a sense, hard-wired into the system. The
explanation as to why mode of production B follows mode A need make no
reference to the details concerning class-struggle. The explanation of why B –
and not production-relations sets C or D – followed A has to do with the
virtuous effects of B for the productive forces. Note that, on this version of
historical materialism, each of the two components does its work in a distinct
dimension: the theory of social forms explains the dynamics within a social
form, while the transition-theory explains the movement from one social form
to another.
Now consider the consequences if we make the constraints less stringent. A
weaker claim for the transition-theory would be that the production-relations
that might replace the crisis-ridden ones are not those that are best for the
12. I do not wish for this to be taken as an invitation to a debate about laws in historical
development. I have simply tried to explain what Marxists mean when they say that there are
such ‘laws’.
68 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
productive forces’s future development, but simply those which are adequate
to the ongoing development of the productive forces – even if it is at a less-than-
maximal rate. Now, the potential-successor production-relations at particular
historical junctures will expand from one set to several sets. Note how this
affects the burden carried by each component of historical materialism.
Suppose that we are concerned with explaining the transition from social form
A to form B, just as in the previous paragraph. In the more demanding version
of transition-theory, also as outlined in the previous paragraph, B’s following
A was hard-wired into the system, since B was in fact the set of production-
relations best suited to the further development of the productive forces. But,
if we drop this assumption, then the potential successors to A now broadens
to include not only B, but also C and D, if both of these would also foster the
continued development of the productive forces – even if it is at rates that are
lower than those brought about by B. Now, class-struggle begins to loom large
as an explanation of which set of production-relations takes its place after the
demise of A. On this less-demanding version of the theory of transitions, the
set of production-relations that in fact ends up succeeding A will depend on
the facts about the class-struggle. It could be set B, but, depending on which
classes are the best-organised and manage to win over other classes, it could
also turn out to be set C or D. The functional requirements of the productive
forces now only explain the range of potential production-relations that can
succeed A; the one that actually succeeds A from within that range is to be
explained by class-struggle. The explanatory work of the class-struggle – and
hence, the theory of social forms – has dramatically expanded.
As we continue to weaken the constraints that transition-theory places on
the process of transition, the explanatory burden on the theory of social forms
increases commensurately. As we ratchet downward the demands that the
productive forces place on successor production-relations, the explanation for
which production-relations in fact replace the ones in decline will rely more
on details of the class-struggle, and less on the ‘law-like’ relation between the
productive forces and the production-relations. The range of possible ‘futures’
at any nodal point, which marks the switch from one social form to another,
increases dramatically; crucially, this means that historical materialism’s power
as a theory of the overall historical record also weakens. It can explain why
human history did turn out the way it did, post hoc; but it cannot make a
strong argument that it had to take the course that it in fact did. Had class-
movements and organisational dynamics been different, the sequence of social
formations might also have been different, and so, on that basis, the overall
trajectory of history.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 69
The capacity to develop in this manner suggests a certain power that not only
stands independent of social structures and circumstances, but indeed stands
over them. As Cohen argues, the independent power of the productive forces
seems to be supported by the stylised fact that societal change rarely involves
a retrogression in the level of social-productive power. In fact, it appears that
social structures connected to production tend, on the whole, to be propitious
for the further development of the productive forces. From this, Cohen
suggests, we can hazard a further, stronger claim, viz.:
13. Cohen correctly observes that for the productive forces to have an autonomous tendency
to develop is not to be confused with the claim that the productive forces have a tendency to
develop autonomously. The latter construal can be taken to suggest that the productive forces
develop independently of the production-relations within which they are embedded. This is
impossible to maintain, since, as noted above, the structure of incentives for producers is set by
the production-relations within which they find themselves. The reproductive strategies that
they choose are thus responses to the production-relations, and it is these strategies that develop
the productive forces. In choosing the former claim, Cohen is arguing, not that the productive
forces develop autonomously of the production-relations, but, rather, that the production-
relations which endure do so because of their beneficial effect on the productive forces. The
productive forces thus develop because of the production-relations, but, if production-relations
were adopted which did not develop the productive forces, they would be discarded in favour of
more congenial ones. It is because of this power to select appropriate production-relations that
we can regard the productive forces as having an autonomous tendency to develop. See Cohen
1988, Chapter 5.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 71
14. See Cohen 1978, pp. 170–1. The significance of this point was first appreciated by Wright
and Levine 1980, and is amplified in Wright, Levine and Sober 1993, pp. 31–2.
72 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
15. This might appear as an odd assertion in light of the fact that Cohen has advertised
historical materialism as an instance of functional explanation, and these are often contrasted
with intentional explanations. Now, it is indisputable that Cohen does offer an intentional
version of his argument, once he is forced to unpack it. What is at stake, then, is whether this
means that he has abandoned his earlier commitment to the functional character of historical
materialism. I do not think anything of substance rides on the verdict to this question. If we
define functional explanations in such a fashion that they cannot advert to an intentional
mechanism in their defence, then, of course, we must conclude that Cohen, in relying on just
such a strategy, abandons the earlier commitment. This is Alan Carling’s verdict in Carling 1993,
p. 38. But if, instead, we allow that functional explanations may survive a causal rendering, then
his commitment to the former stands. Our verdict derives entirely from our definition of
functional explanations. But whatever we conclude on the matter, it carries no consequence for
the defensibility of the explanation itself.
16. Cohen 1988, pp. 89–92. In point of fact, Cohen does not say that actors actually choose
those production-relations which are optimal for the productive forces. What they in fact choose
is those production-relations which minimise their work-effort and thus maximise leisure, ceteris
paribus. It may be ventured, therefore, that what he offers is a version of a Darwinian mechanism,
in that, strictly speaking, the effect on the productive forces is, to the actors, secondary to the
effect on their work-leisure tradeoff. The effect on the productive forces just rides in the latter
and could vary independently of it. This is strictly correct, but, in the case of Cohen’s argument,
pedantic. It is certainly possible to imagine new production-relations which would decrease
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 73
Carling’s synthesis
Alan Carling has presented his version of historical materialism as not only
preserving the claim about the primacy of the productive forces, but also as a
synthesis of Brenner and Cohen. If successful, this effort can surely lay claim
work-time without developing the productive forces, simply from, say, increasing the monitoring
costs of the new ruling class, and hence making it easier for the labouring class to ‘slack’. But
Cohen clearly assumes that the minimisation is occurring through increasing labour-productivity.
In other words, this is taken as part of the preferences of the actors. Hence, in his theory, counter-
examples of the kind just offered are assumed away. To choose on the basis of effects on work-
time is just to choose on the basis of effects on productive forces. This may be wrong, of course,
but we are interested, for the moment, only in the details of his theory, not in its correctness.
17. See Carling 1993, pp. 39–40.
74 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
18. Both arguments can be found in Carling 1993, although the synthesis of Brenner and
Cohen is fully developed in Carling 1991.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 75
19. I infer this from other, more parenthetical remarks Carling makes, since he is frustratingly
vague on just how inter-societal competition conduces to replacing arthritic production-relations
with ones more congenial to growth. For example, there is nothing in his argument to exclude
the possibility that such replacement occurs through an extermination of the older production-
relations, along with the people who form their relata. This would be a direct – albeit sickening –
parallel to the story in natural selection. See Carling 1993.
76 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
21. Ibid.
78 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
will win out, even through a competitive struggle between economic systems –
unless we are taking as our example the transition to capitalism. But the point
is that the direction in which this transition was resolved does not seem to be
generalisable to other instances. And, until it can be, we cannot claim to have
found a mechanism that can save Cohen’s optimality-thesis.22
22. Carling’s views have evolved since his early work. For his more recent position, see Carling
2006; Carling 2009.
23. See Wright and Levine 1980. This article was in fact the first to highlight the centrality of
the optimality-thesis for Cohen’s theory. Cohen himself did not call attention to it in his book,
although he was apparently aware of its importance. In fact, this early article was clearly more
critical of Cohen than the later incarnations. The change seems to have come around the time of
Wright’s engagement with Giddens’s work, and his defence of Marxism against the latter’s
critique. This was the first time Wright unveiled his ‘sticky-downward’ version of directionality,
which has since, well, stuck. See Wright 1983.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 79
forces lack this capacity, then in what sense does Marxism have a theory of
history? What are the limits to the contingency that is now imported into the
theory? Wright, Levine and Sober argue that, while transitions to new modes
of production do become less predictable, there are still appreciable limits to
the possible variety of outcomes – it is not that ‘anything goes’. In particular,
while it is now possible for a larger variety of production-relations to be likely
candidates for selection, it is nonetheless also true, they argue, that the new
set will be one which, minimally, preserves the existing level of technical
development. So long as new production-relations are more likely to preserve
the existing level of development than they are to allow its regression, the
aggregate outcome will be that the productive forces’s development will be
‘sticky downwards’. This is not to say that they will never regress; such instances
of regression, however, will be historically rare, and it will be far more typical
that the productive forces will continue to advance, or, at worst, remain
stationary.
In this version of historical materialism, the theory of social forms occupies
a much more prominent position than in the version enunciated by Cohen.
Instead of there being one set of production-relations compatible with the
productive forces during a period of transition, there now emerge a range of
such sets. Which of these actually takes its place as a successor will depend on
the details of the struggle between social classes. So the explanatory burden,
when we try to apprehend the actual sequence of social formations, has already
shifted away from the theory of transitions in its classical form. The reason this
should be seen as a version of canonical historical materialism, and why it
could be seen as an interesting one, is two-fold: first, the range of production-
relations that is the ‘menu’ of options at a given juncture is still limited; it is
not the case that, once we jettison the optimality-thesis, ‘everything is possible
at every juncture’.24 Second, the limits on the range of candidates from which
a new set of production-relations will be selected are such that, whichever
production-relations take their place, they will preserve the ‘law-like’ relation
between the productive forces and the production-relations – that relation
being, of course, that the production-relations must be compatible with the
further development of the productive forces.25 This preserves what Wright,
Levine and Sober take to be the central motivation for historical materialism,
the idea that history has a clear direction, from lower to higher levels of
productivity.
If these conditions obtain, then the direction of history will be from less-
productive to more-productive productive forces. And, so long as this obtains,
there also exists a determinate limit to the variety of new modes of production
possible at any given level of the productive forces; if such a limit obtains, then
the abandonment of the primacy-thesis does not imply that ‘anything goes’.
Wright, Levine and Sober are tantalisingly brief in their discussion of the new
theory, as well as in their comparison of the new product to the older one. To
appreciate the burden of the new and weaker historical materialism, it is thus
of some interest to tease out its implications.
27. Wright, Levine and Sober 1993, p. 81. Note that this claim is at the micro-level. There
may be agents who have an interest in preventing reductions in the toil of others, and hence who
could have an interest in the reduction of toil socially.
82 V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91
This kind of increased presence would ‘overflow’ into other dimensions, like
freedom and autonomy, which, on historical materialism’s own assumptions,
form part of the core-preferences of human agents – no less than the desire to
decrease toil. Even if we ignore such externalities, there could, and often are,
other, more direct, odious effects of new innovations, like added risks, which
producers may not be willing to take on.
Not only is there no reason to believe that agents, upon considering their
net effects, will adopt new innovations in their own work-régimes; there is
good reason to believe that there may be agents with an active interest in
preventing the adoption of such technologies by others. This is most obvious in
the case of ruling classes, who have a direct interest, for example, in preventing
the adoption of technologies that might increase the autonomy of producers,
or increase their own monitoring costs, etc. Wright, Levine and Sober gloss
over this issue by pitching their argument at the level of the agent, while
abstracting matters from the social structures in which the agents are placed.
It is certainly true that agents will be inclined to adopt innovations that reduce
their own toil, since any such reduction is in their material interest. However,
in a class-society, the reduction in toil for one group may very well increase
labour-effort for others; it could very well destabilise the process of surplus-
extraction if it results in greater power for the immediate producers. Hence, it
is entirely possible that rulers will prefer a social order that is less productive,
as long as it promises their stable reproduction.
The upshot of all this is that, absent an appropriate environment, comprised
most crucially by the type of property-relations in place, there is simply no
reason to assume that the net impact of new innovations on agents’ interests
will be such as to facilitate the consistent acceptance of new innovations. Note
that what is at stake here is not the adoption of new technologies by particular
individuals, but, rather, the presence of a mechanism that allows their spread
throughout society at large. It is for this reason that Brenner, and some of his
defenders, have insisted that absent a compulsion to innovate, producers will
opt for more conservative strategies, focused more on protecting existing levels
of welfare, as against taking the kinds of risks required for increasing it. If the
trajectory of historical development depends on the net effects of the two
mechanisms adduced by Wright, Levine and Sober, in particular on the effects
of the second, then there is scant warrant for accepting weak historical
materialism over minimalist historical materialism.
If minimalist historical materialism is the version that Wright, Levine and
Sober’s reconstruction can support, then what we are left with is not a theory
that predicts an ongoing-upward ascent of the productive forces, but one in
which the productive forces are seen to simply resist regression – their level of
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 83
development tends to be ‘sticky downwards’. But, if this is the case, then the
theory must admit to the possibility of long periods of historical stagnation –
periods of ‘steady-state’ reproduction of the productive forces.28 This need not
occur only within a mode of production. There is every reason to expect that,
in transitions to new modes of production, non-developmental production-
relations will happily combine with the productive forces, so long as they do
not force a regression upon the latter.29
true, then it is hard to see why the actual course of history should be explained
by the ‘dialectic’ between the productive forces and the production-relations.
This duo now does exercise a constraint, but it is so wide as to make its
explanatory pay-off rather more meagre. The explanatory work in any concrete
analysis of historical transitions will be done, not by the causal influence of the
functional needs of the productive forces, but by the course of events as driven
by class-struggle.
A second reaction to the possible slide into minimalist historical materialism
is to claim the following: while it is indeed true that a modal crisis may not
trigger the emergence and consolidation of new, growth-enhancing production-
relations, this cannot remain an indefinite state of affairs. Sooner or later, a
class with the appropriate interests will also develop the requisite capacity.
Even more, we may presume that with each iteration of the cycle, this
probability increases, especially if the level of the productive forces is marginally
greater in each cycle.31 Hence, while the productive forces may not themselves
generate new, more-appropriate production-relations, they do serve to put
these latter on the agenda. In this case, the productive forces would still
be relevant explanatory factors in the event that new production-relations are
adopted, precisely because it was their prior development that created the
possibility for the rise of the new production-relations.
This is an argument that would parallel another argument Wright, Levine
and Sober endorse for the rise of the welfare-state. Marxists have traditionally
argued that the welfare-state is the product of class-struggle, in particular, the
growing organisational power of the working class. Their mainstream-critics
have rejected this argument, pointing out that other, non-class factors have
played a crucial rôle, a fact unjustifiably ignored by Marxists. Wright, Levine
and Sober point out that there are two dimensions to the rise of the welfare-
state, which need to be distinguished – the fact of its rise, and the variations
in its form, timing, etc. The fact that the welfare-state arose only within
capitalism, and, more specifically, the fact that it arose when it did within the
broad history of capitalism, is explained by the logic of class and class-struggle.
But the actual timing of welfare-legislation, and the varieties of such states,
may not be directly explained through class-struggle, as Marxists traditionally
tried to argue. It was the development of large working-class movements
in industrial countries which put this kind of state on the agenda; once it was
on the slate, the precise timing of its adoption, and well as the precise
institutional design it embodied, can be explained by other factors, to which
31. Erik Wright suggested this to me in comments to a paper I wrote some years ago.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 85
needs to be: as the level of the productive forces gradually increases over time,
crises in the mode of production will be resolved in a way that makes it
more likely that a new, more congenial set of production-relations will be
established. This is, in structure, much like the case of working-class power
and the welfare-state: if the causal factor is increasing in magnitude, it increases
the chances of the kind of outcome predicted by the theory. But there is a
difference – while there is a clear mechanism in the case examined above,
which links the putative cause to its effects, it is impossible to discern a
corresponding link in the case of the productive forces. Why, in other words,
should increases in the productive forces render a new, congenial set of
production-relations more likely?
If we were to hazard a thorough symmetry with the case of the welfare-state,
the argument would have to presume an interest on the part of social actors for
new production-relations, as well as an increase in their capacity to do so.
Given this interest in new production-relations, a growth in social actors’
capacity will be used to hasten the emergence of new production-relations.
But I have already argued that, while it is true that social agents have an interest
in increased productivity, ceteris paribus, it can be, and typically is, smothered
by other interests threatened by the externalities accompanying better-
productive forces. There is, therefore, no reason to assume that the class-
situation of historical actors will include an interest in this sort of development.
Furthermore, even if such an interest does exist, there is no reason to believe
that more powerful productive forces will increase the capacity of the relevant
actors in the necessary direction. It is true that better productivity will increase
the social surplus, and hence will generate greater resources. But the distribution
of these resources cannot be taken for granted. It may just as easily flow toward
social actors with a strong interest in the reproduction of the existing order.
Hence an increase in the technical level of the productive forces will have no
determinate effect on the likelihood of new production-relations replacing the
crisis-ridden ones. It is difficult to see how this can be prejudged. If the
divergences between this case and the case of the welfare-state is as explained,
then the option of regarding the productive forces as a structural cause behind
new production-relations is not available to Wright, Levine and Sober. And, if
it cannot count as a structural cause, then to say that it puts new production-
relations ‘on the agenda’ in the sense that working-class power put the welfare-
state ‘on the agenda’ is misleading.
V. Chibber / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 60–91 87
Conclusion
References
Aston, Trevor Henry and C.H.E. Philpin (eds.) 1985, The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class
Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Brenner, Robert 1986, ‘The Social Basis of Economic Development’, in Analytical Marxism,
edited by John Roemer, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 1989, ‘Marx and the Bourgeois Revolution’, in The First Modern Society: Essays in English
History in Honour of Lawrence Stone, edited by A.L. Beier, David Cannadine and James M.
Rosenheim, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Callinicos, Alex 2004, ‘Preface’, in Making History: Agency, Structure, and Change in Social
Theory, Second Edition, Historical Materialism Book Series, Leiden: Brill.
Carling, Alan H. 1991, Social Division, London: Verso.
—— 1993, ‘Analytical Marxism and Historical Materialism – The Debate on Social Evolution’,
Science and Society, 57, 1: 31– 65.
—— 2006, ‘Karl Marx’s Theory of History and the Recovery of the Marxian Tradition’, Science
and Society, 70, 2: 275–97.
—— 2009, ‘Problems of the Deep: Intention and History’, Science and Society, 73, 1: 97–109.
Cohen, Gerald Allan 1978, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
—— 1988, History, Labour and Freedom: Themes from Marx, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
—— 2002, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense, Second Edition, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Gellner, Ernest 1988, Plough, Sword, and Book: the Structure of Human History, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Hilton, Rodney (ed.) 1976, The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism, London: Verso.
Katz, Claudio J. 1989, From Feudalism to Capitalism: Marxian Theories of Class Struggle and
Social Change, Westport: Greenwood Press.
Mann, Michael 1986, The Sources of Social Power: Volume 1, A History of Power from the Beginning
to AD 1760, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Martin, John E. 1983, Feudalism to Capitalism: Peasant and Landlord in English Agrarian
Development, Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.
Rigby, Stephen H. 1987, Marxism and History: a Critical Introduction, Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Wright, Erik Olin 1983, ‘Giddens’ Critique of Marxism’, New Left Review, I, 138: 11–35.
—— 2005, ‘Foundations for a Neo-Marxist Class Analysis’, in Approaches to Class Analysis,
edited by Erik Olin Wright, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wright, Erik Olin and Andrew Levine 1980, ‘Rationality and Class Struggle’, New Left Review, I,
123: 47–68.
Wright, Erik Olin, Andrew Levine and Elliott Sober 1993, Reconstructing Marxism: Essays on
Explanation and the Theory of History, London: Verso.
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 brill.nl/hima
Stefano G. Azzarà
University of Urbino
[email protected]
Abstract
Liberalism is currently the hegemonic world-view, capable of dictating its terms even to the very
movements that antagonise it. But does the history of liberalism really coincide with that of
modern democracy? In two of his recent works, Liberalism: A Counter-History and The Language
of Empire, Domenico Losurdo demonstrates that this is not the case. At its origin, liberalism was
not a universalistic defence of the individual’s freedom. On the contrary, it represented a demand
for wresting complete self-government of civil society from the monarch. However, given that
each society is traversed by deep differences and bitter conflicts, the emancipation from absolute
power turned into the possibility for the strongest individuals and social forces to exercise an
unprecedented absolute power over subaltern classes and ‘inferior races’. It was only after the
confrontation and clash with the demands of radicalism and socialism and two world-wars that
liberal thought was forced to make peace with the principles of democracy. However,
contemporary liberalism seems to have forgotten its own most-recent achievements and to have
returned to its eighteenth-century form: will modern democracy survive this involution?
Keywords
liberalism, slavery, colonialism, radicalism, democracy, universalism
Introduction
Domenico Losurdo can be regarded as one of the most important contemporary
Italian philosophers of Marxist orientation. He is Professor of the History of
Philosophy at the University of Urbino and an internationally acclaimed
Hegel scholar, presiding over the Internationale Gesellschaft Hegel-Marx für
dialektisches Denken. His research has focused on German idealism, including
right-wing philosophers such as Nietzsche and Heidegger. Of equal importance
has been his engagement with the classical theorists of the workers’ movement,
such as Marx and Lenin, Gramsci and Lukács, in a labour of reconstruction of
historical materialism that has spanned the past thirty years. The critique of
liberalism is an important aspect of his current work. In many essays of the
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2011 DOI: 10.1163/156920611X573815
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 93
1. Petrucciani 2005.
2. Examples of the liberal critiques of Losurdo’s book can be found in Cofrancesco 2005
and 2006; Morelli 2005; Bassani 2006; Lattieri 2006. For more sympathetic, albeit reductive,
liberal-socialist readings, see Gravagnuolo 2005 and Bedeschi 2005 (the author is an ex-Marxist
scholar of Galvano Della Volpe). See also a Catholic interpretation, in Pellicciari 2005–6. Finally,
for a more academic reading, see d’Orsi 2005.
94 S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112
8. ‘Das Bekannte überhaupt ist darum, weil es bekannt ist, nicht erkannt’ (G.W.F. Hegel,
Phänomenologie des Geistes, Vorrede).
9. Losurdo 1994, p. 19.
10. On the programmatic use of this methodology of historical investigation, see Losurdo
1996b, pp. 33–5.
11. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 16ff.; Losurdo 2011, pp. 15ff.
96 S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112
over the control of the slave-trade. The same phenomenon occurred in England
after the Glorious Revolution, when, in the name of the freedom of civil
society and the interests of the individual, the political power of landowners
was established, placing rigorous limitations on the absolute powers of the
sovereign. The first move in foreign policy was to take the asiento away from
Spain and acquire the monopoly over the trade in black slaves, who were
destined for the mother country and the American colonies. Proto-liberal
England also distinguished itself by the harshness used in its subjugation of
Ireland, responding to the resistance of the local populations with systematic
oppression and massacre.12 At the level of domestic policy, this new liberal
England engaged in the promotion of primitive accumulation and the
development of industry, showing no hesitation in persecuting dispossessed
peasants and turning them into cheap labour by means of legislation that
punished vagrancy with imprisonment. In the 1800s, beggars and indigenous
populations in England were still persecuted to such an extent that they were
deprived of personal freedoms and confined to horrific workhouses, institutions
of forced labour.13 Finally, in the United States these contradictions were most
blatant.14 The United States emerged out of an act of rebellion that broke up
the unity between the liberal party and the Anglo-Saxon world, at a time when
the latter had already proclaimed itself the champion of liberty and of the
primacy of the individual, entrusted with the mission of exporting these values
to the rest of the globe where tyranny, war and oppression abounded. Colonial
powers rebelled in the name of a more accomplished liberalism, which entailed
emancipation from the despotism of the mother country and the constitution
of an entirely new, republican order founded on the representation of
individuals who were free by nature. However, the institutions of the American
republic were able to coexist with the most brutal form of slavery for over
a century, and only came to abolish it as a result of a bloody war that left
behind a persistent ‘ideology of white supremacy’15 and forms of hateful
discrimination that are yet to be overcome.16 The human nature of the
colonised people of colour was under question from the beginning of Western-
colonial expansionism. They tended to be seen as wild and dangerous beasts
whose subjugation or annihilation was not worthy of a raised eyebrow. In
12. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 21, 116–17; Losurdo 2011, pp. 19, 115–17. On the ferocious
English domination of Ireland and Scotland, see Losurdo 1996b, pp. 48–51, 71–2.
13. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 68ff., 117–20, 123ff., 180ff.; Losurdo 2011, pp. 67ff., 117–20,
123ff.
14. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 9ff.; Losurdo 2011, pp. 7ff.
15. Losurdo 1996b, p. 23.
16. See Losurdo 1996b, p. 62.
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 97
17. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 22–8, 32–6, 42–6; Losurdo 2011, pp. 22–7, 30–4, 40–4.
18. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 34, 310; Losurdo 2011, pp. 32–3, 314–15.
98 S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112
By the standards of the moral sensibility that was emerging in this period,
liberalism seems to take a leap backwards; unsurprisingly, a number of writers
perceived this contradiction at the time and subverted the assumption of
liberal theory and its ‘phenomenology of power’,19 in which the conflict
between freedom and slavery merely coincided with that between state and
civil society. Their hope was that a centralised political power – the crown,
government or church – could limit the unbridled exercise of power over
human property enjoyed by civil society and its strongest representatives since
the emancipation from absolutism, through despotic measures if necessary.
This was the case during the American Civil War, when those who defended
slavery in the South accused Lincoln of absolutist despotism and liberticidal
Jacobinism.20
‘The rise of liberalism and the spread of the commodity of slavery based on
race were born out of a twin birth’, because the rhetoric of ‘liberty’ and of the
‘self-government of civil society’ became linked to the ‘existence of an
unprecedented absolute power’.24 This power was exceptionally brutal to slaves
and also readily exercised upon the subaltern classes of the metropolis. The
latter were dehumanised and seen as in need of tutelage; their freedom and
civil, economic and social rights – not to mention their political rights – were
hardly recognised and guaranteed, as Losurdo demonstrates in his Democrazia
o bonapartismo.25 Even some members of the ruling classes ended up suffering
the oppression of this power when they did not completely adapt to the
dominant order of property and race.26
In the Anglo-Saxon world, the severe contradiction between this situation
and liberal ideals was resolved through a double process of ‘externalisation’ of
the negative. The proud liberal self-consciousness of England repelled slavery
from the sacred soil of its free island, as a form of contamination. Excluded
‘amongst us’, slavery was confined to places where it was still needed: distant
colonies where the border between civility and barbarism was blurred and the
state of nature still reigned.27
This spatial separation of the spheres of freedom and slavery was
unacceptable for the American settlers. They claimed that with their
independence they had picked up the flag of freedom that a tyrannical England
had thrown in the mud. In this new liberal country, civil society felt on a par
with English civil society and could not tolerate being excluded from the
‘community of the free’28 and assimilated to the blacks, so these two spheres
had to be redefined in racial terms: skin-colour marked the border between
freedom and slavery. Whilst the industrialised North tried to externalise this
crude reality again and confine it to the rural South, the South could never
uproot racial slavery. On the contrary, it explicitly defended it as a ‘positive
good’,29 so much so that slavery facilitated the development of a tendency
towards egalitarian relations within white communities in the States. The clash
of these different ‘liberal’ platforms led to the American Civil War, and its
outcome forced liberalism into a U-turn and repudiation of this institution, in
a slow and uneven ‘general condemnation’.30
Given these premises, from their foundation to the end of the nineteenth
century the United States can hardly be regarded as a ‘liberal’ country in the
contemporary sense of the term. They were ruled by a rigid separation of the
population into closed groups, each of which was subject to different legislation
and a different order of rights and duties: the conditions of whites, free blacks
and slaves were so different that one could almost call it a caste-system. For
Losurdo and other authors, such as Van den Berghe and Fredrickson, its most
apt definition is ‘Herrenvolk democracy’: ‘a democracy which applied exclusively
to the master race’.31 This democracy operates through a movement that pivots
on the axis of a distinction between a superior white race and the black race.
Given the increase of land available as a result of the expropriation of the
Native Americans during the advance towards the Western frontier, the
discrimination against blacks and their reduction to human property also
facilitated the development of a tendency towards egalitarian relations, even
though these were not free from contradictions and conflicts based on class
and status, within the community of free whites.32 ‘The members of an
aristocracy of class or race tended to celebrate themselves as peers’33 and the
‘manifest inequality imposed on the excluded was the other aspect of the
relationship of parity established between those who enjoyed the power to
exclude inferiors’.34
A similar argument might apply to the British Empire, where an intermediate
caste of serfs was growing between the castes of free whites and black slaves,
who were mainly confined to the colonies. This growing caste was made up of
whites whose ‘freedoms’ were incomparable to those of their masters. Given
the limitations and duties to which they were subjected, they could not be
defined as free. This ‘inferior race’35 was deprived of modern freedom, or
negative freedom, and, as eugenic and social Darwinism was being developed,
some authors came to regard it as a real ‘livestock’ breeding race36 that, from
the mid-nineteenth century onwards, also included wage-labour and the vast
realm of the poor forced to beg. Clearly, the right to vote could not be granted
to this ‘infant multitude’37 lacking in culture and political discernment. ‘A sort
31. Losurdo 2005, pp. 107, 333; Losurdo 2011, pp. 107, 321. Cf. Van den Berghe 1994;
Fredrickson 1981.
32. See Losurdo 1993, pp. 36–8. On the complex evolution of the American constitution
and domestic social relations, see Losurdo 1996b, pp. 56–7 and Losurdo 1994, pp. 69ff.
33. Losurdo 2005, pp. 107–8; Losurdo 2011, p. 107. Cf. Losurdo 1996b, pp. 76–7.
34. Losurdo 2005, pp. 107–8.
35. Losurdo 1993, p. 44. Cf. Losurdo 1994, pp. 24–6; here the terms of ‘liberal racialisation’
of the ‘subclasses of society’ and the ‘losers in life’ are defined.
36. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 114–16, 212–15; Losurdo 2011, pp. 113–15, 213–17.
37. Losurdo 1993, p. 42.
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 101
45. On the complex relations of integration and discrimination between the West and
Judaism, until the ‘Final Solution’, see Losurdo 1999c, passim; on the recuperation of Judaism
and the State of Israel within the framework of the sacred space of civilisation, see Losurdo 2007,
Chapter IV, ‘Antisemitismo’, pp. 114–52, and Chapter V, ‘Antisionismo’, pp. 153–86. On the
discrimination against the Arabs, see Chapter VI, ‘Filo-islamismo’, pp. 187–243.
46. Losurdo 2005, pp. 239–42; Losurdo 2011, pp. 242–6.
47. Losurdo 2005, pp. 240–1.
48. Losurdo 2005, p. 242.
49. Ibid.
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 103
his theory, Nietzsche was deeply motivated to write a ‘militant critique and
denunciation of the revolution and of modernity’50 in the form of a critique
and denunciation of the processes of democratisation that they had initiated.
His was a contestation of massification and homogenisation; in the name of
‘instrumental’ reason51 and principles of equality inherent to humanism and
modern ‘optimism’52 revolution and modernity had burnt the soil beneath the
genius’s feet, and hampered exceptional individuals, superior castes, and the
few fortunate examples who are worthy of the name of man and whose greater
mission is the production of culture, arts, and literature. Nietzsche’s criticism
was consonant with the parallel liberal denunciation of the radicalism spread
by the French Revolution, and with the defence of the privileges of property
and culture found in authors like Tocqueville and Constant.53 In the last phase
of his conscious life, Nietzsche came to posit, against the rebellion of subaltern
classes and modern wage-slaves, whose only reason to live was work and the
burden of social reproduction, the foundation of a ‘party of life’54 and
‘aristocratic radicalism’: the party of the well-to-do and the powerful who
neither felt guilty about their hierarchical rank nor were ashamed to reinstate
its ‘natural’ legitimacy. The Dionysian appeal to the superman, the Hellenising
fantasies of a ‘reintroduction of slavery’ in Europe and the positivist and
eugenic ‘breeding’ of a race of servants separated from one of masters signalled
the need to recognise a political programme that could ‘drastically radicalise’
the liberal positions that had been calling for the open subjugation of the
masses and the colonised peoples.55
Nietzsche invited the ruling classes to leave all reservations and moral
inhibitions behind, as these belonged to the Christian herd and universal
rationalism, and to respond to the challenge of the subaltern classes and
inferior races by waging a total war, by means of political Caesarism rather
than through compromise and consensus-democracy. In this, Nietzsche – and,
in many respects, Heidegger after him56 – was actually warning and defiantly
challenging the cowardly and ‘degenerated’ liberalism of his times.
Losurdo goes back to the core of the apparent paradox of liberalism and
reveals it to be traversed by a constitutive laceration between drives to
‘emancipation’57 and violent ‘dis-emancipation’. He had already effectively
adopted these two categories in his research on the constitution of modern
democracy. In other words, liberalism was the movement of emancipation of
both aristocracy and property-owners from the tutelage of a higher sovereign-
power and the imposition on the latter of a constitution that was agreed by
them. This emancipation did not involve the social totality: in fact, without
the exclusion of subaltern groups, popular classes, servants, slaves, and
colonised people, it would not have been possible, as it finally granted free
men a clear separation from the common people; prior to that, their shared
subjugation to the sovereign, which flattened society, had been an obstacle to
their freedom. As far as subaltern groups were concerned, one could speak of
a dis-emancipation, because the freedom of action of higher interests no longer
subjected to any constraints, whether political, cultural or religious, came to
rest on their subjugation. This entailed the ‘autonomization of the property of
those who already enjoyed recognition, of those who aspired to form themselves
into the community or caste of freemen’,58 and thus formed a ‘civil society’.
Civil society, far from being a neutral territory, ‘could in turn become the
hegemonic field of the bourgeoisie or the landed aristocracy and emerged
from a compromise between these two classes’.59
In Losurdo’s opinion, liberalism coincided with a reconfiguration of power-
relations that was founded on a clear separation between the recognised and
the unrecognised, rather than the limitation of power as such.60 On the one
hand, social relations amongst the recognised, emancipated from the absolute
power of the monarch, were increasingly free and egalitarian, and guided by a
proud individualistic affirmation of the group’s autonomy that abhorred any
constraint, whether issued by equals or by the higher power of the state. The
state was assigned the task of policing, but denied any right of intervention
that might lead to an equalisation of social disequilibrium in the sphere of civil
society. The unrecognised, on the other hand, did not gain any new liberal
right, whether civil or political, and the old power came to exercise new forms
of domination that were equally oppressive, resulting in ‘reification’61 or
of the revolutionary tradition’ is said to have found its highest expression: Losurdo 1996b,
pp. 32–3.
57. See Losurdo 1993, pp. 34ff.
58. Losurdo 2005, p. 316; Losurdo 2011, p. 329.
59. Losurdo 2005, p. 316.
60. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 180ff.; Losurdo 2011, pp. 181ff. Cf. Losurdo 1993, pp. 24–6.
61. Losurdo 2005, p. 298; Losurdo 2011, p. 302.
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 105
Jewish ‘pathogenic element’.68 The main liberal thinkers and ruling classes
always show a readiness to face the state of exception by means of a suspension
of the rule of law and the establishment of a strong personal and despotic
power, even by invoking ‘Caesarism’ and ‘dictatorship’.69 The questioning of
slavery legitimated the bloody conflict of the American Civil War. The
uprisings of subaltern peoples in Europe during the nineteenth century were
faced with a military and police repression that violated both political and
private freedoms, as well as numerous coups d’état theorised or practised by the
forces of liberalism in order to bring the revolutionary crises to a halt.70 Even
a conflict between nations that belong to the sacred space, as the experience of
the two world-wars demonstrated, called for the need of a total or totalitarian71
regimentation of civil society. This regimentation did not stop at the suspension
of rights and the introduction of measures such as deportation72 and
concentration-camps: in defiance of any presumed liberal ‘individualism’ it
relied on the enthusiastic celebration of the ‘Gemeinschaft’73 and the ‘destiny’74
of the motherland by inciting the organicist fusion of the social whole in a
‘total mobilisation’.75 An enlargement of the sacred space could only occur by
means of a selective co-optation from above operated by the ruling classes,
rather than an autonomous pressure from below carried out by excluded social
groups or subjugated nationalities.76 This significant crack in the liberal
movement would determine its evolutionary leap. The ruling classes gradually
opened the doors of freedom when they no longer had a choice, or when it
was necessary to consolidate the body of the nation or even find the lost unity
of the white people against non-Western barbarism. In these cases, the
inclusion of subaltern classes occurred passively through the development of a
68. Losurdo 1999a, p. 15. On the different forms of discrimination against Jews in Western
history, ‘anti-Judaism’, ‘Judeophobia’ and ‘anti-semitism’, see Losurdo 1999b, passim, where
Poliakov’s thesis on ‘eternal anti-semitism’ is criticised.
69. See Losurdo 2005, pp. 248ff.; Losurdo 2011, pp. 251ff. Cf. Losurdo 1993, pp. 66ff.,
97–116, 172ff.
70. See Losurdo 1993, pp. 35, 91–5, 157.
71. Losurdo criticises the wholly ideological meaning of the term ‘totalitarianism’, first used
in the Truman Doctrine to assimilate Nazism and Communism against liberal democracy, and
refers the genesis of total institutions to the colonial history of the West and liberal countries: see
Losurdo 1996b, pp. 188ff., and, in general, Losurdo 1998, passim.
72. See Losurdo 1996b, pp. 183–4.
73. Losurdo 1991, p. 41. The key-notion of all organicist and anti-modern theories is that of
‘community’, born out of liberal rhetoric: Gentz translates as ‘Gemeinschaft’ the ‘partnership’
defended by Burke in his Reflections on the Revolution in France: see Losurdo 1991, pp. 191–3.
74. Losurdo 1991, p. 4.
75. Losurdo 1991, p. 40. See Losurdo 1993, p. 165.
76. On the ‘radical’ pressure from below, see Losurdo 2005, p. 167; Losurdo 2011, p. 168.
On the evolution of liberalism, see Losurdo 2005, pp. 277–81; Losurdo 2011, pp. 280–5.
S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112 107
‘new mode of political and social control’, the Bonapartism that allowed
leaders to charismatically lead the masses.77
Other majority-electoral mechanisms were put in place in order to
undermine the autonomy of socialist and radical parties and to preventively
neutralise the formation of a popular majority.78 This movement of ‘passive
emancipation’ was also often associated with the revival of colonial expansionism
and fratricidal wars between liberal countries in moments of crisis when the
international borders of the sacred space were questioned. Emancipation then
turned into forms of aggressive and chauvinist nationalism, or an unbridled
‘pathos of the West and civilisation’79 that glorifies war and its rituals of
‘proximity to death’80 as an instrument of unification of the national community
(and in this, many liberal thinkers were largely in agreement with the
philosopher who was close to national socialism, Heidegger).81 This pathos fed
on fundamentalist war-myths of origins and produced conspiracy-theories
and delirious naturalistic, psychopathological and even racist visions of the
conflict between states:82 the ideology of imperialist nationalism was realised
through the drastic dis-emancipation and subjugation of other people and
countries, whose belonging to the sacred space was disputed and denied time
after time.
In conclusion, when seen in the perspective of historical revision, liberalism
seems to arise as the ‘self-consciousness of a class of owners of slaves or
servants’,83 who, at the outset of capitalism, demanded ‘self-government and
the quiet enjoyment of one’s property (including slaves and servants) against
the monarchical despotism of central powers, and for it to be sanctioned
by the rule of law’.84 Contrary to the common thesis of the liberal apologists,
Losurdo claims that liberalism is primarily ‘the theoretical tradition that most
rigorously circumscribed a restricted sacred realm’.85 Within this realm, which
is the result of a legacy that since the Old Testament was strongly rooted in the
ideology of Western culture, what matters most is not ‘the celebration of
freedom or the individual’ as such, but the ‘celebration of that community of
free individuals who define the sacred realm’ and who are increasingly distinct
from those who are relegated to the profane space.86
Conclusion
Here, we can trace some conclusions for this excursus, which aimed to place
the dogmatic self-consciousness of triumphant liberalism into question, and
to provide a preliminary introduction to the work of Domenico Losurdo.
Ideology-critique often runs a great risk: that of indulging in an attitude of
abstract and indeterminate negation, incapable of seeing things dialectically,
and thus of grasping the elements of truth present in the position under
critique. This is not the lesson of historical materialism. From Marx onwards,
historical materialism has taught us to walk the fine line between the critique
of modernity and the recognition of its legitimacy, that is, of the clear progress
that modernity and capitalism have signified with respect to feudalism and its
underdevelopment and villeinage. Marxian studies too often forget this lesson,
and the desire to subject to critique degenerates into a demonisation,
criminalisation and, ultimately, a subaltern misunderstanding of the object of
study, be it liberal theory or capitalist society as a whole. This signals an
unresolved relation to history that inevitably results in unsophisticated and
scientifically irrelevant analyses. A dialectical approach, as suggested by
Gramsci, is, on the other hand, fully endorsed by Losurdo, as he never sets out
to present a moralistic denunciation of liberalism as an ideological perversion
and an antechamber of terror, but aims to comprehend its genesis
materialistically, with its objective reasons and limits. It is therefore not a
matter of destroying the philosophical foundations of liberal thought in order
to go back to what preceded it. If anything, the historical premises of the
troubled evolution of liberalism and its current involution need to be
understood. The danger of detaching liberalism from democracy and returning
to eighteenth-century positions that were brutally proprietary is clear and
present. In such a scenario, modern democracy would be condemned to suffer
from a seemingly interminable illness.
References
Bassani, Luigi Marco 2006, ‘Review of D. Losurdo’s Controstoria del liberalismo’, Libero,
6 January: 27.
Bedeschi, Giuseppe 2005, ‘Libertà fondate sulla schiavitù’, La domenica de Il Sole 24 ore,
11 September: 31.
Bobbio, Norberto 1984, Il futuro della democrazia, Turin: Einaudi.
112 S. G. Azzarà / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 92–112
Cofrancesco, Dino 2005, ‘Ma l’Occidente non è mister Hyde. L’equivoco di Losurdo’, Corriere
della sera, 8 November: 47.
—— 2006, ‘Non fare di tutto Liberal un fascio clericale. In merito all’intervento della Pellicciari’,
Il Riformista, 26 January: 12.
d’Orsi, Angelo 2005, ‘Tocqueville nobile “schiavista”: è l’altra faccia del liberalismo’, La Stampa
Tuttolibri, 22 October: 7.
Fredrickson, George M. 1981, White Supremacy: A Comparative Study in American and South
African History, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gravagnuolo, Bruno 2005, ‘Liberalismo, ecco il suo libro nero’, l’Unità, 26 September: 21.
Lattieri, C. 2006, ‘Review of D. Losurdo’s Controstoria del liberalismo’, L’Indipendente, 8 January: 18.
Losurdo, Domenico 1991, La comunità, la morte, l’Occidente. Heidegger e l’«ideologia della
guerra», Turin: Bollati Boringhieri.
—— 1993, Democrazia o bonapartismo. Trionfo e decadenza del suffragio universale [Democracy
and Bonapartism: Triumph and Decadence of Universal Suffrage], Turin: Bollati
Boringhieri.
—— 1994, La Seconda Repubblica. Liberismo, federalismo, postfascismo [The Second Republic.
Liberalism, Federalism, Post-Fascism], Turin: Bollati Boringhieri.
—— 1996a, ‘Fenomenologia del potere: Marx, Engels e la tradizione liberale’ [Phenomenology
of Power: Marx, Engels and the Liberal Tradition], in Autore Attore Autorità, edited by Alberto
Burgio and Domenico Losurdo, Urbino: Quattro Venti/Istituto Italiano per gli Studi
Filosofici.
—— 1996b, Il revisionismo storico. Problemi e miti [Historical Revisionism: Problems and
Myths], Rome/Bari: Laterza.
—— 1998, Il peccato originale del Novecento [The Original Sin of the Twentieth Century],
Rome/Bari: Laterza.
—— 1999a, ‘L’ebreo, il nero e l’indio nella storia dell’Occidente’ [The Jew, the Black and the
Indian in the History of the West], Giano. Pace ambiente problemi globali, 33: 103–56.
—— 1999b, ‘Antigiudaismo, giudeofobia, antisemitismo’ [Anti-Judaism, Judeophobia and
Anti-Semitism], I viaggi di Erodoto, 13, 38/39: 139–60.
—— 1999c, ‘La crisi del processo di emancipazione degli ebrei: per un’analisi comparata’ [The
Crisis of the Process of the Emancipation of the Jews: a Comparative Analysis], in Nel nome
della razza. Il razzismo nella storia d’Italia 1870–1945, edited by Alberto Burgio, Bologna: Il
Mulino.
—— 2001 [1991], Heidegger and the Ideology of War: Community, Death and the West, translated
by Marella and Jon Morris, New York: Humanity Books.
—— 2002, Nietzsche, il ribelle aristocratico. Biografia intellettuale e bilancio critico [Nietzsche.
The Aristocratic Rebel: Intellectual Biography and Critical Assessment], Turin: Bollati
Boringhieri.
—— 2005, Controstoria del liberalismo, Rome/Bari: Laterza.
—— 2007, Il linguaggio dell’Impero. Lessico dell’ideologia americana [The Language of Empire.
Lexicon of American Ideology], Rome/Bari: Laterza.
—— 2011 [2005], Liberalism: a Counter-History, translated by Gregory Elliott, London:
Verso.
Morelli, Raffaello 2005, ‘Critiche alla controstoria del liberalismo’, Libro aperto, 43: 26–35.
Pellicciari, Angela 2005–6, ‘La tolleranza che viene dal cattolicesimo’, Liberal, 33: 44–5.
Petrucciani, Stefano 2005, ‘Il libro nero del liberalismo’ [The Black Book of Liberalism], Critica
marxista, 4: 32–3.
Van den Berghe, Pierre L. 1994, Race and Racism: A Comparative Perspective, New York: Wiley.
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 113–127 brill.nl/hima
Bill Bowring
Birkbeck College
[email protected]
Abstract
This response to Robert Knox’s very kind and constructive review1 of my 2008 book The
Degradation of the International Legal Order?: The Rehabilitation of Law and the Possibility of
Politics gives me the opportunity not only to answer some of his criticisms, but also, on the basis
of my own reflections since 2008, to fill in some gaps. Indeed, to revise a number of my
arguments. First, I restate my attempt at a materialist account of human rights. Next I explain
why, for me, the right of peoples to self-determination is absolutely central to a materialist
understanding of human rights; and also fill a serious gap in my own account in the book. This
leads me not only to a reply to Robert Knox on the question of ‘indeterminacy’ in international
law, but also to a disagreement with him on the use or misuse of the language of self-determination.
My fourth section returns to our very different evaluations of the significance and meaning of
the work of Yevgeny Pashukanis, and what, for me, is Pashukanis’s misunderstanding, for
reasons consistent with his general theoretical trajectory, of Marx and Lenin on the Irish
question. Finally, I present an outline of a re-evaluation of Marx’s principled position on
self-determination.
Keywords
Robert Knox, Bill Bowring, human rights, international law, self-determination, indeterminacy,
Pashukanis, revolutions, anticolonial struggles
1. Knox 2010.
2. Bowring 2008a.
3. See also Shaw 2009; Feldman 2008; Harvey 2008.
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2011 DOI: 10.1163/156920611X573833
114 B. Bowring / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 113–127
4. Knox 2008.
5. Knox 2010, p. 194.
6. Bowring 2008a, p. 112, as cited in Knox 2010, p. 194.
B. Bowring / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 113–127 115
there is any such thing. It is my contention that the international law to which
Martti Koskenniemi referred as the ‘gentle civilizer of nations’7 or for an
imagined and reactionary version of which Carl Schmitt had such nostalgia,8
and of which the USSR had throughout its existence such a rigidly positivist
account9, was thoroughly transformed in the post-World-War II period. The
creation of the United Nations by the victorious powers – all the permanent
members of the Security Council with the exception of China were colonial
powers at the time – was almost immediately subverted and transformed by
the bloody and tumultuous anticolonial struggles. This is why I refer, in my
first chapter, to the right of peoples to self-determination as the revolutionary
kernel of international law.
It is my case that the working-out of struggles for this right dominates the
international agenda to this day. My examples in the book, drawn from
practical experience, of the Kurds and the Chechens, are but two of a myriad
all over the planet.
Much of my book – incidentally, the sequence of chapters was re-ordered,
and chapters were in the process of being added and removed until a late
stage – is devoted not only to a working-out of my theses in relation to current
events, but also to responses to some of the most cogent opposing positions,
especially those of Habermas; of the postmodernists, especially Douzinas; and
of Badiou and Žižek, upon whose work I first drew for its powerful attacks on
contemporary human-rights discourse. Knox is, however, quite right in noting
my sympathy with Badiou’s political challenge, alongside and despite his
complex ontology, in respect of which I do have reservations – for example, I
reject Badiou’s critique of Spinoza, a topic for further work.
7. Koskenniemi 2001.
8. Schmitt 2003; Schmitt 2007.
9. Bowring 2008b.
10. See Löwy 1976, pp. 96–8, for a resounding defence of Lenin’s position.
116 B. Bowring / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 113–127
much alive. That is why my title, The Degradation of the International Legal
Order? has a question mark – and why it is followed by a pointer to the
‘rehabilitation of law’ and the ‘possibility of politics’. It is not the principles
concerned which could be said to have undergone a process of degradation,
but the real achievements of struggle in transforming international law.
Rather than lumping together the ‘active struggle of the USSR and the
Third World’, as Knox suggests,11 I show, in Chapter 1 of my book, and my
chapter in Susan Marks’s 2008 collection, how the USSR played a thoroughly
contradictory, indeed schizophrenic rôle after Lenin’s death. On the one
hand, self-determination movements were ruthlessly repressed both within
the USSR and its sphere of interest; on the other, huge diplomatic and
material resources were directed to the anticolonial and national-liberation
movements – and to the real struggle to elevate the right of peoples to self-
determination to the status of a right in international law in the United-
Nations human-rights covenants, in 1960, 1966 and 1970.
What was missing from my book and from my Susan Marks chapter was
Issa Shivji’s splendid critique of Soviet practice. I had most certainly read this
in 1992, but had forgotten it by 2007.
Shivji is one of the most radical African specialists in law and the constitution.
His Concept of Human Rights in Africa12 is a fine exposé of the malign influence
of Western individualised human rights in Africa. In his 1991 contribution to
William Twining’s Aberdeen collection13 he was perfectly clear that the
comprehensive theorisation of the ‘right to self-determination’ was carried out
by Lenin, and was put into practice in the 1918 Declaration of Rights of the
Working and Exploited People14 which proclaimed the complete independence
of Finland, evacuation of troops from Persia, and freedom of self-determination
for Armenia. Self-determination only appeared in the UN-Charter (as a
principle, not a right) at the insistence of the Soviet delegation.15
As for its application in Africa, Shivji refers to an important passage from
the October 1917 Decree on Peace, drafted by Lenin.16
In accordance with the sense of justice of democrats in general, and of the working
class in particular, the government conceives the annexation of seizure of foreign
lands to mean every incorporation of a small or weak nation into large or powerful
state without the precisely, clearly, and voluntarily expressed consent and wish of
that nation, irrespective of the time when such forcible incorporation took place,
irrespective also of the degree of development or backwardness of the nation
forcibly annexed to the given state, or forcibly retained within its borders, and
irrespective, finally, of whether this nation is in Europe or in distant, overseas
countries.
It was only a shame that Makau wa Mutua in his passionate 1995 article ‘Why
Redraw the Map of Africa?’22 did not refer – in his Section III, entitled ‘The
National Question and Self-Determination: Prospects for Alternative
Formulae’,23 to Shivji’s work at all, but only to the much-more conservative
and orthodox account by Abdullahi An-Na’im in Shivji’s own collection, also
published in 1991.24
V.I. Lenin, and played the crucial rôle in the development of international law
after WWII.
This was a new stage, a new situation, a new and higher level of struggle. And new
priorities corresponded to it. The bourgeois-democratic stage had passed, and
with it the formal legal demand for national self-determination – characteristic
of this stage – lost its former significance. The slogan ‘overthrow the rule of
the bourgeoisie on a world scale and set up the international dictatorship of
the proletariat’ became the immediate practical slogan. Does this mean that
national self-determination lost all significance; that it could be replaced with
the ‘self-determination of the proletariat’? Certainly not. This would have been
to ignore the presence of backward countries which had not passed through the
stage of bourgeois-democratic national revolutions. The communist proletariat
of advanced countries had to support these movements; with all its strength it
had to struggle so that the accumulation of centuries of ill will and the distrust
by backward people of the dominant nations – and of the proletariat of these
nations – was overcome as quickly as possible. It was impossible to achieve
this goal without proclaiming and conducting in practice the right of national
self-determination. Moreover, even for a socialist society moving towards the
elimination of classes the question of national self-determination still remains
a real one, since although based on economics, socialism by no means consists
solely of economics.37
We should recall what Pashukanis said a few pages earlier. He reported that
Lenin’s opponents – especially Rosa Luxemburg –had argued against the ‘right
to self-determination’ ‘under the pretext that “in essence” no “self-
determination” could exist under capitalism, and that under socialism it was
not necessary.’38 Lenin’s position as stated in 1916, correctly reported by
Pashukanis, was that ‘[t]he dispute is related to one of the forms of political
oppression, namely, the forceful domination of one nation by the state of
another nation. This is simply an attempt to avoid political questions.’39 But
Pashukanis went on to state that no one apart from him had noted that
Luxemburg’s position amounted to a ‘complete rejection of the legal form’.40
Pashukanis then cited a longer passage from Lenin’s 1914 major work on
The Right of Nations to Self-Determination.41
By the way, it is not difficult to see why, from a Social-Democratic point of view,
the right to ‘self-determination’ means neither federation nor autonomy (although,
speaking in the abstract, both come under the category of ‘self-determination’).
The right to federation is simply meaningless, since federation implies a bilateral
contract. It goes without saying that Marxists cannot include the defence of
federalism in general in their programme. As far as autonomy is concerned,
Marxists defend, not the ‘right’ to autonomy, but autonomy itself, as a general
universal principle of a democratic state with a mixed national composition, and
a great variety of geographical and other conditions. Consequently, the recognition
of the ‘right of nations to autonomy’ is as absurd as that of the ‘right of nations
to federation’.
The effect of this citation, out of context, is to render wholly obscure that
which is actually quite clear.
However, it so happened that the English working class fell under the influence
of the liberals for a fairly long time, became an appendage to the liberals, and by
adopting a liberal-labour policy left itself leaderless. The bourgeois liberation
movement in Ireland grew stronger and assumed revolutionary forms. Marx
reconsidered his view and corrected it.
The Fenian trial in Manchester was exactly as was to be expected. You will have
seen what a scandal ‘our people’ have caused in the Reform League. I sought by
every means at my disposal to incite the English workers to demonstrate in favour
of Fenianism. . . . I once believed the separation of Ireland from England to be
impossible. I now regard it as inevitable, although Federation may follow upon
separation.42
The trial in question was that of the ‘Manchester martyrs’ – William Philip
Allen, Michael Larkin, and Michael O’Brien – who were members of the Irish
Republican Brotherhood. The men were executed after having been found
guilty of the murder of a police-officer during an escape that took place close
to Manchester city-centre in 1867.43
That is, Marx was, in the words of the contemporary UK Terrorism Act of
2006, ‘glorifying terrorism’, and terrorism committed by bourgeois nationalists
at that. He would now face a stiff sentence.
Once Pashukanis’s quotation is placed in context, it is plain that Pashukanis
had wholly misunderstood both Lenin and Marx. And, influenced as he is by
Pashukanis, Knox has also, it appears to me, misunderstood. The issue at stake
between Lenin and Luxemburg was, as I point out in my book and chapter,
whether the component-parts of the Russian Empire should have the right to
self-determination and to break away to form new sovereign nations.
Luxemburg was convinced that the Empire should be preserved, and was as
opposed to Polish liberation as she was to Irish liberation.
In my book, I show in detail how Lenin put his theory into practice
immediately following the Bolshevik victory, supporting the independence of
Finland, the three Baltic states – Estonia, Latvia, Lithuania – and Poland. His
last struggle was with Stalin: Lenin on principle supported Georgian
independence, even under a Menshevik government – Stalin was totally
opposed.44 Lenin’s creativity was key to the struggles of the national-liberation
movements after World-War II.45
What are the reasons for this special interest of the workers’ party in the fate of
Poland? First of all, of course, sympathy for a subjugated people which, with its
incessant and heroic struggle against its oppressors, has proven its historic right
to national autonomy and self-determination. It is not in the least a contradiction
that the international workers’ party strives for the creation of the Polish nation.
Only a world war can break old England, as only this can provide the Chartists,
the party of the organized English workers, with the conditions for a successful
rising against their powerful oppressors. Only when the Chartists head the
English government will the social revolution pass from the sphere of utopia to
that of reality. But any European war in which England is involved is a world
war, waged in Canada and Italy, in the East Indies and Prussia, in Africa and on
the Danube.50
Nimtz shows how Marx and Engels reversed their earlier position and gave
support to religious-led Arab resistance to French imperialism in Algeria in
1857; expressed strong sympathy for the Sepoy Mutiny against Britain in
India in 1857–9; and by 1861 wrote, as the US Civil War loomed, that
US-expansion into Texas and what is now Arizona and New Mexico, brought
with it slavery and the rule of the slaveholders.51 At the same time, they were
quite clear that the ‘booty of British imperialism’ had begun to corrupt and
compromise the English proletariat.52
Pranav Jani, in turn, focuses on Marx’s response to the 1857 revolt in
British India.53 He maintains that ‘under the impact of the Revolt, Marx’s
articles increasingly turned from an exclusive focus on the British bourgeoisie
to theorise the self-activity and struggle of the colonised Indians’.54 Jani seeks
to show how Marx’s historical-materialist methodology allowed him to
transcend weak formulations and prejudices to achieve a more complex
understanding of the relation between coloniser and colonised, in much the
same way as the Paris Commune forced him to re-assess his theory of the
state.55 For Jani, Marx was thereby transformed from a ‘mere observer’ of the
anticolonial struggle to an active participant in the ideological struggle over
the meaning of the Revolt. This enabled him also to refute racist representations
of Indian violence in the British press ‘by drawing a sharp division between
the violence of the oppressed and that of the oppressor and dialectically linking
the two.’56 Jani concludes that if Eurocentrism makes Western Europe the
centre of the globe, then the Marx he presents is not Eurocentric.
And Marx is the progenitor of the revolutionary sense of self-determination
which I celebrate in my book.
Knox cites Rajagopal with approval.57 Yet I am perplexed by Rajagopal’s
contribution to the collection International Law and the Third World: Reshaping
Justice.58 He at any rate acknowledges (drawing on Morsink)59 that Britain
engaged in intense manoeuvring during the drafting of the UN’s Universal
Declaration of Human Rights in 1948 to prevent Soviet pressure from extending
the effect of the right to self-determination to the colonies.60 This did not
happen until 1966, following a tremendous diplomatic effort by the USSR
and its allies. On the following page, however, he cites Michael Ignatieff, of all
people, as authority for the utterly false proposition that the idea of self-
determination was the result of the anticolonial revolt against empire.61 It was
the other way round entirely: the right to self-determination as developed by
Lenin became the rallying-cry of the colonial revolt.
In the same collection, Vasuki Nesiah, in a flood of unbridled idealism,
seeks to persuade us that self-determination has failed – as a discourse. He
declares that ‘the failure of self-determination discourse is partly grounded in
the invocation of “self-determination” as a trans-historical signifier – a timeless
ground for the post-colonial imagination.’62 Whatever that means . . .
Conclusion
It will have been noted that Knox’s careful critique has required me to revise
my own position in a number of respects. He has pointed out serious gaps in
References
An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed 1991, ‘The National Question, Secession and Constitutionalism:
the Mediation of Conflicting Claims to Self-Determination’, in Shivji (ed.) 1991.
Badiou, Alain 2003, Infinite Thought: Truth and the Return of Philosophy, translated and edited
by Oliver Feltham and Justin Clemens, London: Continuum.
Bartolovich, Crystal and Neil Lazarus (eds.) 2002, Marxism, Modernity and Postcolonial Studies,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bowring, Bill 2008a, The Degradation of the International Legal Order?: The Rehabilitation of Law
and the Possibility of Politics, Abingdon: Routledge-Cavendish.
—— 2008b, ‘Positivism versus Self-Determination: the Contradictions of Soviet International
Law’, in International Law on the Left: Re-examining Marxist Legacies, edited by Susan Marks,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 2010, ‘Georgia, Russia and the Crisis of the Council of Europe’, in Conflict in the Caucasus:
Implications for the International Legal Order, edited by Christopher Waters and James Green,
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Cassese, Antonio 1979, ‘Political Self-Determination – Old Concepts and New Developments’,
in UN Law/Fundamental Rights: Two Topics in International Law, edited by Antonio Cassese,
The Hague: Sijthoff.
Falk, Richard, Balakrishnan Rajagopal and Jacqueline Stevens (eds.) 2008, International Law
and the Third World: Reshaping Justice, Abingdon: Routledge-Cavendish.
Feldman, Paul 2008, ‘The Meaning of the Struggle for Rights’, A World to Win, available at:
<http://www.aworldtowin.net/reviews/Degradation.html>.
Harvey, Richard 2008, ‘Shock and Awe Anti-Pessimism’, Socialist Lawyer, September: 38–9,
available at: <http://bbk.academia.edu/documents/0010/1942/BB_book_richard_harvey_
review_SL.pdf>.
Independent International Fact-Finding Mission on the Conflict in Georgia 2009, available at:
<http://www.ceiig.ch/Report.html>.
Jani, Pranav 2002, ‘Karl Marx, Eurocentrism, and the 1857 Revolt in British India’, in
Bartolovich and Lazarus (eds.) 2002.
Knox, Robert 2008, ‘Review of Degradation of the International Legal Order?: The Rehabilitation
of Law and the Possibility of Politics by Bill Bowring’, Law and Disorder, 2 April, available at:
<http://pashukanis.blogspot.com/2008/04/book-review-degradation-of.html>.
—— 2010, ‘Review of The Degradation of the International Legal Order?: The Rehabilitation of
Law and the Possibility of Politics by Bill Bowring’, Historical Materialism, 18, 1: 193–207.
Koskenniemi, Martti 2001, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law
1870–1960, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 2005, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich 1914, ‘The Right of Nations to Self-Determination’, Prosveshcheniye 4, 5,
and 6, in Collected Works, Volume 20, Moscow: Progress Publishers 1964.
—— 1916, ‘The Discussion on Self-Determination Summed Up’, Sbornik Sotsial-Demokrata, 1,
in Collected Works, Volume 22, Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1964.
—— 1917, ‘Report on Peace’ and ‘Decree on Peace’, Izvestia No. 208, October 27, 1917, and
Pravda, No. 171, November 10 (October 28) 1917, in Collected Works, Volume 26, Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1964.
—— 1918, ‘Declaration of the Rights of the Working and Exploited People’, Pravda, No. 2,
and Izvestia, No. 2, 4 (17) January 1918, Collected Works, Volume 26, Moscow: Progress
Publishers, 1964.
Löwy, Michael 1976, ‘Marxists and the National Question’, New Left Review, I, 96: 81–100.
Marx, Karl 1849, ‘The Revolutionary Movement’, Neue Rheinische Zeitung, 184, in Marx Engels
Collected Works, Volume 8, London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1977.
—— 1865, ‘Marx To Hermann Jung In London’, 20 November, Marx Engels Collected Works,
Volume 42, London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1987.
—— 1867, ‘Marx to Engels in Manchester’, 2 November, Marx Engels Collected Works, Volume 42,
London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1987.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels 1875, ‘For Poland’, in Marx Engels Collected Works, Volume 24,
London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1989.
McGee, Owen 2005, The IRB: The Irish Republican Brotherhood from the Land League to Sinn
Féin, Dublin: Four Courts Press.
Morsink, Johannes 1999, The Universal Declaration of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting and
Intent, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Nesiah, Vasuki 2008, ‘Resistance in the Age of Empire: Occupied Discourse Pending
Investigation’, in Falk, Rajagopal and Stevens (eds.) 2008.
Nimtz, August 2002, ‘The Eurocentric Marx and Engels and Other Related Myths’, in
Bartolovich and Lazarus (eds.) 2002.
Pashukanis, Evgeny 1980 [1924], ‘Lenin and Problems of Law’, in Pashukanis: Selected Writings
on Marxism and Law, edited by Piers Beirne and Robert Sharlet, New York: Academic Press.
Rajagopal, Balakrishnan 2008, ‘Counter-Hegemonic International Law: Rethinking Human
Rights and Development as a Third World Strategy’, in Falk, Rajagopal and Stevens (eds.)
2008.
Schmitt, Carl 2003 [1974], The Nomos of the Earth: In the International Law of the Jus Publicum
Europaeum, translated by G.L. Ulmen, New York: Telos Press Publishing.
—— 2007 [1975], Theory of the Partisan: Intermediate Commentary on the Concept of the Political,
translated by G.L. Ulmen, New York: Telos Press Publishing.
Shaw, Julia 2009, ‘Review of The Degradation of the International Legal Order?: The Rehabilitation
of Law and the Possibility of Politics by Bill Bowring’, Law and Society Review, 43, 3: 722–4.
Shivji, Issa G. 1989, The Concept of Human Rights in Africa, London: Codesria.
—— 1991, ‘The Right of Peoples to Self-Determination: an African Perspective’, in Issues of
Self-Determination, edited by William Twining, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.
—— (ed.) 1991, State and Constitution: An African Debate on Democracy, Harare: SAPES
Trust.
wa Mutua, Makau 1995, ‘Why Redraw the Map of Africa? A Moral and Legal Inquiry’, Michigan
Journal of International Law, 16: 1113–76.
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136 brill.nl/hima
Review-Articles
Walter Benjamin’s Archive: Images, Texts, Signs, Ursula Marx, Gudrun Schwarz, Michael
Schwarz, Erdmut Wizisla, Translated by Esther Leslie, London: Verso, 2007
Abstract
We are used to classifying different thinkers according to their general orientation: progressive
or conservative, revolutionary or nostalgic of the past, materialist or idealist. Walter Benjamin
does not fit into these categories. He is a revolutionary critic of the ideologies of progress, a
materialist theologian, and his nostalgia for the past is at the service of his Marxist dreams for the
future. It is therefore not surprising that so many different and conflicting readings of his work
have developed since his death, some trying to bring him back into the usual frames of thinking,
others trying to recruit him for the newest philosophical fads, and many simply damning him as
ridden with contradictions and therefore an intellectual failure. But there are also some happy
exceptions: those who try to take into account the irreducible singularity of his intellectual
and political endeavours. These three books, quite different in object and method – a collection
of documents from his archives, a biography, and a ‘Benjamin Handbook’ – belong to these
exceptions.
Keywords
Marxism, messianism, materialism, theology, progress, utopia
Images of Benjamin
We are used to classifying different thinkers according to their general orientation:
progressive or conservative, revolutionary or nostalgic for the past, materialist or idealist.
Walter Benjamin does not fit into these categories. He is a revolutionary critic of the
ideologies of progress, a materialist theologian, and his nostalgia for the past is at the service
of his Marxist dreams for the future. It is therefore not surprising that so many different
and conflicting readings of his work have developed since his death, some trying to restore
him within the usual frames of thinking, others trying to recruit him for the newest
philosophical fads, and many simply damning him as ridden with contradictions and
therefore an intellectual failure. But there are also some happy exceptions: those who try to
take into account the irreducible singularity of his intellectual and political endeavours.
There are many astonishing prophetic statements to be found in Benjamin’s works. We
are going to discuss some of them. But he could also err in his predictions, for instance on
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2011 DOI: 10.1163/156920611X573842
130 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136
the future of his own writings. In April 1934, Benjamin wrote to Karl Thieme – a now
largely forgotten theologian – thanking him for mentioning his work in an article; he
added the following sad comment: ‘For someone whose writings are as dispersed as mine,
and for whom the conditions of the day no longer allow the illusion that they will be
gathered together again one day, it is a genuine acknowledgment to hear of a reader here
and there, who has been able to make himself at home in my scraps of writing, in some way
or another’.1 Well, some seventy years later, not only have all his writings been carefully
and patiently gathered together and published in their original language, but most of them
have been also translated into French, English, Italian, Spanish and Japanese (amongst
other languages). Not to mention the enormous – and growing – mountain of secondary
literature, interpretations and commentaries.
How to explain the interest, nay, the fascination of so many people with his life and
works? It has certainly to do with the singularity of his writing, the beauty and intensity of
his enigmatic style, the tragic end of his road; but it may also be that his ferocious critique
of the illusions of ‘progress’ can be better understood in our day. In any case, the obsession
of the public with Walter Benjamin is so great that specialists have now collected and
published not only his articles and manuscripts, but literally all the scraps of paper in his
archives. I am referring, of course, to the book Walter Benjamin’s Archive. A brief survey of
its chapters may give an idea of how deep this archaeological research on the ruined remains
of Benjamin’s citadel has gone (the titles are quotations from Benjamin): 1) ‘Tree of
consciousness’: his activity as an archivist of his own writings. 2) ‘Scrappy Paperwork’: all
sorts of dispersed scraps, bits and pieces of paper with some written inscription. 3) ‘From
Small to Smallest Details’: samples of his micrographic writing. 4) ‘Physiognomy of the
Thing World’: his collection of photos of old Russian toys. 5) ‘Opinions et Pensées’: words
and expressions of his son Stephan as a child. 6) ‘Daintiest Quarters’: his note- and address-
books. 7) ‘Travel Scenes’: his postcard collection with scenes from Tuscany and the
Balearics. 8) ‘A Bow Being Bent’: his procedures for the organisation of knowledge.
9) ‘Constellations’: graphic forms for the presentation of ideas. 10) ‘Rag Picking’: the
Arcades Project as ‘rubbish-collection’. 11) ‘Past Turned Space’: Germaine Krull’s
photographs of the Parisian arcades. 12) ‘Hard Nuts to Crack’: word-games and brainteasers.
13) ‘Sibyls’: eight reproductions of Sibyls from the cathedral of Siena (with hardly any clue
as to their meaning for the collector).
Are these items interesting? Certainly! Do they reveal something about Benjamin’s
character? Probably. Do they give us significant elements to understand his writings?
I doubt it . . . It is very amusing to see the facsimile-reproduction of a sheet with an
advertisement for San Pellegrino mineral-water, containing one of Benjamin’s most subtle
definitions of aura. And it is even more ironic to find out that his famous definition of
revolution – humanity snatching the emergency-brake in the train of world-history – is
written on the reverse of calculations on the price of a lunch: Mitagessen: 0,50, 1,80, 1,70.
But how much do these amusing discoveries help us to understand his concepts of aura and
revolution?
It is true that Germaine Krull’s photographs permit us to see how the arcades looked
during the years when Benjamin visited them; and the images of the Russian toys are part-
and-parcel of his essay on the topic. But what should one make of the postcards from Ibiza,
or the Sybils from Siena? The lullaby-drawing on the effects of hashish – ‘Sleep, my little
Sheep Sleep’ – is very intriguing, it may perhaps be an illuminating complement to his
writings under the same drug; the same does not necessarily hold for other graphic forms
collected here. A complete list of all addresses in Benjamin’s Parisian notebook would be a
significant research-item, but the facsimile of one page with a few addresses under the letter
‘S’ is just a curiosity (I have been told that there exists a facsimile of the address-book, for
the pleasure of Benjamin fetishists). And the same applies to much of the interesting items
reproduced in this book . . .
It should be said, however, that at least in one of the sections there is a direct relation
between the presentation of Benjamin’s procedures, his ways of collecting, classifying and
ordering materials, and the content: the chapter on the ‘rag-picker’ and the Arcades Project.
What it describes and documents is precisely the meaning of the project: the author as
rag-picker wishes to collect the refuse of history, the materialist historian is the one that
picks up everything that has been ‘crushed underfoot’, discarded, torn into pieces. The
revolutionary meaning of the Arcades Project is intimately linked with the method
Benjamin proposes: the collection and appropriation of rags.
Much of the interest in Benjamin is certainly nourished by his tragic life-story, the life
of a ‘man in dark times’ (Hannah Arendt) who spent his last years in a precarious exile, and
committed suicide in September 1940 to escape from the Gestapo. Thus the multiplication
of biographies, of which Esther Leslie’s can be counted amongst the best. Unlike previous
works, she was able to use the archive-material made available during the last few years –
including the volume reviewed above, which she translated into English, and used
extensively in her own research. In fact, the most important new source is Benjamin’s
correspondence, finally published in an unabridged, complete and uncensored version by
Suhrkamp Verlag. Her book is not, strictly speaking, an intellectual biography: Benjamin’s
works are mentioned, of course, but not systematically discussed, with a few exceptions.
Since she had already published a – remarkable – book on his thought, Walter Benjamin:
Overpowering Conformism (2000), the aim, this time, was rather to deal with his life and
with the multiple facts of his personality: not only his political and cultural interests, but
also his erotic and financial troubles, and his idiosyncratic obsessions with graphology,
children’s books, etc. The book is very readable, in spite of some not-very-helpful chapter-
titles – except for the dates, they don’t tell us much about his life: ‘Making a Mark, 1917–
24’, ‘Books after Books, 1925–9’, ‘Man of Letters, 1930–2’, ‘Noms de Plume, 1933–7’,
‘Writer’s Block, 1938–40’ . . .
The one piece of Benjamin’s writing that Leslie does analyse in detail is the essay on
‘The Work of Art in the Age of its Technological Reproducibility’, perhaps his best-known
and most discussed writing. She analyses carefully the text itself, with all its ambiguities,
as well as various interpretations, emphasising its surprising conclusion: the essay seems to
celebrate modern technology – mainly cinema – but ‘the epilogue . . . reversed the optimistic
current – all the potential credited to art in the age of technology evaporated before the
techo-mysticism and class violence of the National Socialists. In the essay’s coda Benjamin
determined that fascists . . . too participated in technological modernity’ (p. 164).
Unlike other biographers – for example, Werner Fuld and Rainer Rochlitz – Leslie is
interested in and sympathetic to Benjamin’s political views. She points to the importance
of his meeting with the young Latvian Bolshevik Asja Lacis in 1924, which gave him,
according to a letter to Scholem, ‘intensive insight into the actuality of a radical communism’;
132 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136
she also refers to the astonishing insights of his Moscow diaries, written during his visit in
December 1926 – ‘the restoration’ had begun in the USSR and ‘militant communism’ was
being suspended – or of his letters to Fritz Lieb in 1937, criticising the policies of the
French Popular Front: ‘the leadership has managed within two years to rob their workers
of the elementary basis of their instinctive activity: that infallible sense of when and under
which circumstances a legal action must turn into an illegal, an illegal into a violent one’.
However, her discussion of Benjamin’s amazing essay on surrealism (1929) is not quite
satisfactory; she emphasises Benjamin’s criticism of the surrealists, while the main aspect of
the article is the importance of surrealism from a communist viewpoint, the viewpoint of
revolutionary pessimism. This is clearly stated in a phrase from Benjamin’s article which
she quotes, but does not discuss:
Surrealism has come ever closer to the communist answer. And that means
pessimism all along the line. Absolutely. Mistrust in the fate of literature, mistrust
in the fate of freedom, mistrust in the fate of humanity, but three times mistrust
in all reconciliation: between classes, between nations, between individuals.
And unlimited trust only in I.G. Farben and the peaceful perfection of the
Luftwaffe.2
Benjamin borrowed the concept of communist pessimism – obviously against the grain of
official Soviet, wildly-optimistic, discourse – from Pierre Naville’s book La Révolution et les
intellectuels (1928), which he describes as an ‘excellent’ work. Former editor of the journal
La Révolution surréaliste, and militant of the French Communist Party, Naville had just
joined, in those years, the Trotskyist Left Opposition, of which he would become one of
the main leaders. This ‘revolutionary pessimism’ enabled Benjamin to foresee – intuitively,
but with an astonishing acuity – the catastrophes awaiting Europe, perfectly summarised in
the ironic phrase on ‘unlimited trust’. Obviously, even he, the most pessimistic of all, could
not predict the destructions that the Luftwaffe was to wreak on the cities and civilian
population of Europe; nor that I.G. Farben would, barely a dozen years later, distinguish
itself by employing forced labour from the concentration-camps by the tens of thousands.
However, uniquely among Marxist thinkers and leaders of those years, Benjamin had a
premonition of the monstrous disasters to which a crisis-ridden bourgeois civilisation could
give birth.
This essay, as well as the contemporary book, One Way Street (1928) document a decisive
aspect of Benjamin’s thought: he is one of the few Marxists, in those years, to attempt a
radical break with the ideology of inevitable and linear progress. As he would later write in
the Arcades Project, his aim is to emancipate historical materialism from the bourgeois idea
of progress and of all ‘bourgeois habits of thought’.
Leslie discusses Benjamin’s increasing distance from the Soviet (Stalinist) brand of
Communism during the thirties, a process which culminates after the German-Soviet pact
of 1939, in his ‘Theses On the Concept of History’; written when it was ‘midnight in the
century’ (the title of a novel by Victor Serge), they constitute, as Leslie aptly summarises,
‘Benjamin’s reckoning with Social Democracy, Stalinism and bourgeois thought, none of
which were able to prevent the disaster of fascism’. In her conclusion, after surveying some
of the various interpretations of his life and work, she argues, with keen insight, that ‘his
writings envision a world not condemned to repeat its mistakes . . . a world in which the
political subject still has recourse to revolutionary praxis, unlike the disempowering theory
of a Habermas’ (p. 232).
Among the innumerable attempts to propose a synthetic view of Benjamin’s life and
works, one of the most ambitious and interesting is the recent Benjamin Handbuch, an
impressive collection of contributions by sixty of the best German-speaking specialists. In
his preface, Burkhardt Lindner, the organiser of the collection – with the help of two
colleagues, Thomas Küpper and Timo Skrandies – justifies the Handbook by the existence,
in recent years, of a critical edition of all of Benjamin’s existing writings, as well as of his
correspondence – the Gesammelte Schriften published by Suhrkamp Verlag in Frankfurt –
and by the need for a presentation that tries to cover the diversity of his philosophical,
political and literary interests. Lindner insists that the book does not propose a specific
image of Benjamin: the different contributions are not only diverse, but sometimes
contradictory; what they have in common is simply a willingness to take seriously his
stature as a philosopher, and not simply a literary essayist; this is probably a polemical barb
against Hannah Arendt, who considered Benjamin not as a philosopher, but as a homme
de lettres.
In its presentation of Benjamin’s writings, the Handbuch does not follow the criteria of
the Gesammelte Schriften, which separated, in distinct volumes, the pieces that appeared
during his lifetime from those which remained unpublished: a distinction, comments
Lindner, that was not at all taken into account by the reception of his œuvre. While one
can easily agree with him on this issue, his rejection of a chronological order seems to me
much more questionable. The reason offered is that such an order would wrongly give the
impression of a ‘progress’ in his thinking. Again, one can agree that the concept of ‘progress’
is inadequate; there exists nevertheless in the chronological sequence of his writings a
movement, sometimes in opposed directions – a passage from theology to materialism, a
return to theology without abandoning materialism – sometimes in the form of intellectual
experiments taken to their ultimate conclusion, and then abandoned; in other words, a
process which is not disconnected from historical events, but which is lost from sight if one
renounces chronology.
After the first section, ‘Life, Work, Influence’, which surveys the present state of the
publication of Benjamin’s collected works, and proposes a very interesting account of their
reception (by Küpper and Skrandes), and following a section entitled ‘Intellectual
Friendships’, dealing with his links with Gershom Scholem, Bertolt Brecht and the
Frankfurt School, most of the book discusses, under the general title ‘Analysis’, the writings
themselves, classed by themes, in four great parts: ‘Messianism, Aesthetics, Politics’,
‘Literary critique, avant-garde, media, journalism’, ‘Literary analysis and author-images’,
‘Philosophy of language and autobiographical writings’. It seems to me that these thematic
regroupings are quite arbitrary and heterogeneous; not to mention the fact that many of
Benjamin’s writings concern several topics and cannot be reduced to a single one. But these
artificial distinctions are the price to be paid for renouncing the chronological option.
In spite of this reservation, one must acknowledge the great quality of the whole, and of
the majority of the individual contributions. Since it would be impossible to discuss all
sixty papers, I will pick up on only a few, using as a guiding thread the issue – of central
importance in Benjamin’s thought – of the relation between theology and politics. No
134 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136
other issue has provoked so many polemics in the reception of his work, with conflicting
views trying to ‘purge’ Benjamin’s philosophy of some irritating element: for some, religion,
for others, materialism.
One can start with his ‘intellectual friendship’ with Gershom Scholem, as remarkably
studied by Stéphane Mosès. Since their first conversations in Switzerland during the First
World-War, which turned around the concepts of revelation, redemption and justice, until
their exchanges during their final meeting in Paris (February 1938), this issue never ceased
to occupy them. Scholem could never accept his friend’s turn toward communism, which
he considered, in a letter from 1931, as a ‘regrettable confusion between religion and
politics’. During their last conversations in Paris, Benjamin defended himself arguing –
according to Scholem’s memories – that his method consisted in ‘transferring metaphysical
and theological forms of thought into the Marxist perspective’, thus assuring them a
powerful vitality in a modern context.
Most of Benjamin’s writings on religion and politics are discussed in the chapter
‘Messianism, Aesthetics and Politics’, where, luckily, they are presented in chronological
order. Under the title ‘Writings on Youth’, Thomas Regehly examines some works
from the years 1912–15, beginning with the ‘Dialogue on the Religiosity of the Present’
(1912) – in my view, a striking example of Benjamin’s revolutionary-romantic critique of
modern civilisation. Unfortunately, his analysis of the documents contains some obvious
mistakes; according to Regehly, for Benjamin ‘social religion – “socialism as religion” – is
not an alternative, because it has “lost its metaphysical seriousness”’. Now, what Benjamin
says is quite different: modern social action, that suppressed the gods and transformed
everything into an affair of civilisation, ‘such as electric light’, has ‘lost its metaphysical
seriousness’; ‘socialism as religion’ presents itself precisely as an alternative to this ‘civilised’
and disenchanted modern social action, which has replaced the ‘heroic-revolutionary
efforts’ of the past by the pitiful ‘crab-like march’ of evolution and progress. Regehly
misses the point of this essay, which documents Benjamin’s precocious support for socialist
ideas, interpreted within a religious and revolutionary perspective, critical of civilisation
and progress.
In his discussion of the following document, ‘On the Life of Students’ (1914) Regehly
correctly mentions Benjamin’s critique of the ideology of progress in the name of utopian
images. But he fails to quote the next passage, were Benjamin explains, with the help of two
examples, what he understands by utopische Bilder: ‘the messianic kingdom and the French-
revolutionary idea’. This detail is essential, because it permits us to see, already in 1914, the
appearance of the constellation between messianism and revolution – as an alternative to
historicist evolutionism – that will become a central tenet in his reflections on history.
Regehly also mentions, en passant, as a proof of Benjamin’s rejection of socialism his
critique of Marx in the fragment from 1921, ‘Capitalism as Religion’. Now, as Uwe Steiner
shows in his very suggestive analysis of this difficult but fascinating text, Benjamin’s critique
of Marx – that he will abandon only after 1924 – is inspired by the libertarian – and
religious – socialism of the German-Jewish anarchist Gustav Landauer. The fragment,
which presents capitalism as a merciless religion leading humanity to ‘the house of despair’,
is directly inspired by Max Weber, but goes well beyond the ‘value-neutral’ arguments of
the sociologist, in the direction of a radical anticapitalism.
At the same time (1921) Benjamin wrote another enigmatic piece, the ‘Theological-
Political Fragment’ – a title given it by Adorno. Werner Hamacher’s interpretation
Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136 135
proposed in the Handbook seems questionable to me. In a first moment, he shows, quite
accurately, that Benjamin’s effort to separate messianism from history, by insisting that the
kingdom of God ‘is not the telos of historical dynamics’, is a polemical answer to Hermann
Cohen’s neo-Kantian theories. But I cannot follow Hamacher when he pretends that the
fragment should be called ‘Political-Atheological’, because, for Benjamin, ‘the theological
concepts are useless for political praxis’: this corresponds neither to the letter nor the spirit
of the fragment. If theological concepts are ‘useless’, why does Benjamin conclude his
fragment by referring to profane action as favourable to the coming of the messianic era?
After a long detour through Plato, Aristotle and Kant, which is not obviously of much help
in understanding this document, Hamacher attributes to Benjamin – without any textual
basis – the idea of an eternal distancing of the messianic times.
After the essay ‘Critique of Violence’ (1921), whose political-theological conclusion –
the revolutionary general strike as an expression of a ‘divine violence’ – is accurately
described by Axel Honneth, and the doctoral thesis – refused by the University of
Frankfurt – on the German-baroque Trauerspiel, discussed by Bettine Menke, theology
seems to disappear from Benjamin’s writings. It will return, several years later, in some
fragments of the Arcades Project, set to paper at the end of the 1930s. In his remarkable
study of this strange and massive unfinished manuscript, Irving Wohlfarth shows how
Benjamin tries, against his best – albeit opposed – friends, Scholem and Brecht, to hold
together theology and historical materialism; a comment by Adorno is the best definition
of Benjamin’s attempt: ‘to mobilise, in an anonymous way, the force of the theological
experience for the profane’.
It is above all in Benjamin’s last writing, his testament in a certain sense, the ‘Theses On
the Concept of History’ (1940), that theology, and its relationship to politics, becomes
again a central issue. In a brilliant exegesis of this complex piece, which was to exercise a
considerable posthumous influence, Jeanne-Marie Gagnebin proposes the following
hypothesis: theology is here the model of another conception of time, permitting us to
simultaneously think a critical historiography and a revolutionary practice. What interests
Benjamin is not ‘religion’ as such, but the explosive force of the theological – messianism
and the remembrance of past victims – against historicist conformism. Benjamin defined,
in the Arcades Project (specifically the section on the theory of progress) the relation of his
thought to theology as similar to that of the blotter to ink: it is soaked with it, but nothing
of what has been written remains. Thus, the theological dwarf hidden inside the puppet
called ‘historical materialism’ described in ‘Theses on the Concept of History’: theology
must remain invisible.
Jeanne-Marie Gagnebin’s interpretation is quite persuasive; but one has to take into
account the following paradox: the ink does not disappear, its traces are visible in the
blotter, as well as in the paper where the ink-pen had written something. Similarly, theology –
i.e. messianism – is not hidden in the ‘Theses’ from 1940, but is visible, from one end of
the text to the other.
None of Benjamin’s multiple heterodox and idiosyncratic ideas have provoked as much
incomprehension and perplexity as this attempt to combine Marxism and theology. And
yet, a few decades later, what in 1940 had been merely an intuition was to become a major
historical phenomenon, supported by hundreds of thousands: Latin-American liberation-
theology, condemned by the Holy Office (Cardinal Ratzinger!) of the Catholic Church
for its ‘indiscriminate’ use of Marxism . . . Of course, the Latin-American theology is
136 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 129–136
Christian and not Jewish, and its specific concepts are different from those of Benjamin’s
document – even if a critical distance with respect to the ideologies of ‘progress’ and
‘development’ is also present in the writings of Gustavo Gutierrez or Leonardo Boff;
moreover, the historical context of Latin America since the 1970s is very different from
Europe in 1940. However, the association of theology and Marxism Benjamin dreamt of
has turned out, in the light of historical experience, to be not merely possible and fruitful,
but a powerful stimulant for social struggles.
References
Benjamin, Walter 1978 [1929], ‘Surrealism: The Last Snapshot of the European Intelligensia’,
in Reflections, translated by Edmund Jephcott, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Leslie, Esther 2000, Walter Benjamin: Overpowering Conformism, London: Pluto Press.
—— 2007, Walter Benjamin, London: Reaktion Books.
Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 137–143 137
Abstract
This review-essay explores the theoretical and methodological innovations of Richard Godden’s
William Faulkner, arguing that it makes a signal contribution to historical materialism in literary
studies. The article focuses on Godden’s concept of ‘generative structure’, and relates the term to
earlier usages by Aglietta and Jameson. After summarising the close readings of Faulkner’s texts
performed by Godden, the article suggests an expanded rôle for biography in making the linkages
between economy, psyche and text which form the basis of Godden’s analysis.
Keywords
régime of accumulation; generative structure; master-slave dialectic; free indirect style
How are we to practise historical materialism in literary studies today? In this book, Richard
Godden suggests some answers by combining Marxist, psychoanalytical, and semiotic
approaches to create a powerfully interdisciplinary methodology, along with a tightly-
focused argument which is brought to bear on a central problem, that of ‘generative
contradiction’ (p. 119).
Economic relations, Godden argues, are the disguised form of social relations of
domination, coercion, and contract. These social relations are ‘a cause of what stories can
and cannot be told’, meaning that ‘economic structures may be read as the generative
source of fictional forms’ (p. 2). The economy generating Faulkner’s later fictional forms
was the New Deal, and, more specifically, the ‘Agricultural Adjustment Program’ (1933–
8). Under this programme, Southern landowners were given federal money to restrict
cotton-production in a bid to raise farm-prices. Landowners kept the greater portion of this
capital for themselves and paid a wage to former sharecroppers to plough the crop under.
The result was the creation of a new ‘regime of accumulation’, in which sharecroppers (who
formerly received a ‘share’ of the value of the crop nominated by the landlord) were ‘made
over into cash workers’ (p. 61).
Godden’s major influence here is Michel Aglietta’s A Theory of Capitalist Regulation
(1976). He shares Aglietta’s sense of capitalism, not just as a ‘social system’ regulated
towards ‘the continuous reproduction of social relations’, but as a structure whose basic
morphology is continually threatened by crises or ‘ruptures’.1 Such ruptures force the
system to adapt by creating a new ‘regime of accumulation’, a set of social practices sufficient
to ensure that surplus-value goes on increasing, ‘under the stable constraints of the most
general norms’.2 Drawing on historical work by Jonathan M. Wiener and Gavin Wright,
Godden describes how the South under the New Deal changed shape, responding to the
crisis of the Depression by shifting from its long-term dependence on surplus black labour
to a new reliance on Northern capital.3 In the process, black labour was finally removed
from its pre-modern condition of vassalage, as impoverished workers were forced into
out-migration.
The next component of Godden’s argument extends the central insight of his previous
book, Fictions of Labor (1997), which developed the implicitly Hegelian critique of the
master-slave dialectic in Eugene Genovese’s Roll Jordan, Roll.4 Under both plantation-
slavery and the sharecropping system, the white master was dependent on the black body
he dominated and exploited. While the slave or sharecropper found ‘in the work of his
hands the substance of his lord’, the slave or sharecropper literally gave substance through
that work to the white landowner (p. 44). Southern whites depended on blacks for their
very being, a contradiction they both recognised and disavowed. But, in the New-Deal
period and during the renewed Great Migration provoked by World-War II, the corporeal
presence of black people was progressively attenuated. Whites could not quite grasp the loss
of their integral blackness, or admit it to themselves as black labour relocated and Northern
capital flooded in.
For Godden, the necessary corollary to the generative economic structure of the New-
Deal economy is its psychic structure, one of self-division and ambivalence. Faulkner lived
in a world of ‘divided things (split referents)’ – landlords who took government hand-outs;
former vassals who upped sticks and left for Memphis or Chicago (p. 6). The New Deal
also generated a contradiction within a Southern owning class now made up of both
labour-lords who want to keep ‘their’ blacks in place, and land-lords who wanted
sharecroppers to make way for federal subsidies. But the structural transformation of the
owning class by the New Deal also led to a questioning of ‘white male authority’, a
‘loosening of ethnic restraints’, and a ‘threat to sexual categories’ (p. 117). Category-
collapse provided imaginative space to tackle structural contradiction. Faulkner countered
‘incipient structural loss’, Godden argues, by telling stories which imagine a range of
intimate bonds between black and white men, a homoerotic vision so taboo that it can be
easily denied.
In Godden’s analysis, ‘structure’ is grasped in a third sense, as the pattern of formal
elements in Faulkner’s texts. Just as the white self divides between the desire to retain black
bodies and the desire to be rid of them, language splits, its meanings multiplying under the
Southern economy’s contradictory pressures. Among these signal effects in Faulkner’s texts
are extravagant metaphors and torturous puns, forms of linguistic contradiction where
likeness is entertained alongside difference, setting up effects of cognitive dissonance. These
effects are pursued here through forensically close readings of The Hamlet (1940), Go
Down, Moses (1942), and A Fable (1954). Godden thus practices the immanent critique
called for by Fredric Jameson, who urges that ‘our discovery of a text’s symbolic efficacity
must be oriented by a formal description which seeks to grasp it as a determinant structure
of still properly formal contradictions’.5 As we shall see, Godden takes seriously Jameson’s
further point: that, because they are riven by contradictions, texts carry an ‘immense charge
of anxiety and libidinal investment’.6
Godden is uncompromising in his insistence that generative economic structure must be
read out of the text itself, rather than wheeled in as ‘historical context’, to which the text
stands merely as illustration or symptom. He pursues readings which unpack the multiple
meanings compressed into Faulkner’s language, ‘subsemantic whisperings latent in a
ramifying resemblance’ (p. 16). His method is to amplify these whisperings – at the
admitted risk of ‘exaggerating’ (p. 48) or sounding ‘strained’ (p. 49) – so as to hear history
re-sounding in the echo-chamber of the text. The signal distinction of Godden’s analysis is
the wealth of hermeneutic resources it deploys from Paul Ricœur, Paul de Man, and
Michael Riffaterre, among others – a salutary richness in a period of de rigueur demonstrations
of theoretical competence and contextual information-gathering in which close reading has
become a dying craft, more honoured in the breach than in the observance.7 To follow this
book’s argument closely thus requires a finely tuned ear, as well as some familiarity with
Faulkner’s texts, filled as they are with ‘luminous innuendo’ (p. 52). This is not so much
close reading as intense listening, likely to alienate the determinedly tone-deaf.
It is difficult to convey the full import of Godden’s readings of Faulkner’s texts, which
derive their weight and power from a dual strategy: an insistent probing of textual details
which produces an extended field of signification, and a boiling down of plot-elements in
a kind of reductio ad absurdum that reveals the novels’ stark narrative-core. The Hamlet’s
story begins in Mississippi in 1887, when Flem Snopes arrives for work as a clerk in Will
Varner’s store at Frenchman’s Bend, wearing a ‘brand new white shirt’ marked with ‘his
own particular soiling groove’. Godden builds his interpretative case from the historical
resonances of the single word, ‘soiling’. While an established critical tradition sees Snopes
as the straightforward personification of capitalism – calculating, mercenary, materialistic,
fixated on market-opportunity – Godden points out that he comes from sharecropper-
stock, from rented fields and ‘a coercive, credit-led labor regime’ (p. 24). These antecedents
cling to him, just as his skin ‘soils’ his white shirt. Furthermore, his father, Ab, was a barn-
burner, a form of protest at landed-class domination associated with a ‘disaffected black
tenantry’ (p. 15). Flem’s pretentious black tie resembles Ab’s club-foot, a dissonant image
which Godden loops back in time to recover a radical past of labour-insurrection, even as
the present moment tips towards the hegemony of the capitalist market. ‘Soiling’ is
therefore one of the ‘complex words’ of Godden’s title, with its nod to William Empson’s
The Structure of Complex Words (1951), words which signify within a textual economy and
derive accretions of meaning from the literal economy ‘outside’ the text.
The crucial aspect of Faulkner’s story is that it is narrated from the point of view not of
Snopes, but of the former-sharecropper-turned-sewing-machine-salesman, Ratliff. To
Ratliff, Varner’s horse-drawn buggies connote Varner’s daughter, Eula, who rides in them
and provides potential access, via courtship and matrimony, to his property. Ratliff
associates the buggies with the excremental, equine odour of the stable, and the textual
metaphors which proliferate from this association figure Eula as both vagina and anus, ‘the
earth’s orifice’ (p. 27). While Eula represents land as both property and elemental filth, Ike
Snopes’s sexual congress with a cow grants him ‘access’ to his ‘true love’, the soil (p. 52).
Meanwhile, Mink Snopes’s bull grazes the Bend’s pastures in militant defiance of private
property. All three figures represent the revivifying energy of a ‘residual social structure’, a
peasantry not wholly dominated by the merchant-capitalist class (p. 55). The peasantry
represents what Ferdinand Braudel calls ‘the lowest stratum of the non-economy, the soil
into which capitalism thrusts its roots, but which it can never really penetrate’ (p. 29). Its
‘seed, milk, and earth’ counter the ‘semen, shit, and coin’ of the money-economy, whose
pricing mechanisms nevertheless inflict a ‘perverse stain’, as when Snopes barters sex with
a black field-hand for some lard from his store (p. 30).
But all this turns out to be sheer ideology, ‘a story that will ease [Ratliff’s] own sense of
having betrayed his class of origin’, while allowing him to ‘seve[r] his own awkward and
increasingly archaic’ ties to the tenantry (p. 31). In order to appease his conscience, Ratliff
tells himself that he represents ‘the better face of the coercive economy’ and turns
‘subsistence producers bound by debt to the ground’ into sexualised, bucolic fantasy
(p. 36). For Godden, what can be recuperated is not Ratliff ’s nostalgia for the pre-market
economy but Snopes’s unstable, insurrectionary force. He is less ‘capital’s epitome’ than a
resentful iconoclast, grubbing his way up from, and out of, the sharecropping system
(p. 41). His actions bespeak not capitalist hegemony, but resignation ‘in the face of the
insufferability of the available social options’ (p. 41).
The central premise of Godden’s argument is that ‘a radical restructuring of labor
necessarily forces to prominence archaic and perhaps resistant features of the system it
displaces’ (p. 61). He goes on to read the disruptive effects of New-Deal restructuring in
‘The Fire and the Hearth’, a story from Go Down, Moses in which the reveries of the white
landlord, Roth Edmunds, turn his black tenant, Lucas Beauchamp, into a troubling
revenant. Roth’s father, Zack, took Lucas’s wife, Molly, as his own, to nurse the infant
Roth, compounding the miscegenated blood-line binding black and white families. Lucas
is minded to kill Zack, but the master-slave dialectic links them so intimately that he
cannot achieve an act that will amount to self-slaughter. Lucas stays on as the ‘archaic
tenant of a modernizing land lord’, refusing the machines and chemicals which are in the
process of cementing the new régime of accumulation in the form of agribusiness (p. 71).
Roth comes to a partial recognition of his own hybrid nature as the white child of a black
home, beginning to acknowledge that ‘the physical labors of the rural working class
materialise the substance and wealth of those who own the land’ (p. 81). But, like Ratliff,
he sentimentalises that knowledge, perfecting the safely manageable image of Lucas as a
peasant bound by blood and sweat to the natal soil.
Faulkner’s free, indirect style, mixing the voices of white narrator and black character,
allows him to ‘move between racialized subject positions’, performing an ‘authorial shuffle’
in which the cathected black body is both cast out and retained (pp. 76, 77). This shuffle is
performed most elaborately in ‘Pantaloon in Black’, another story from Go Down, Moses,
by the figure of the black wage-earner Rider, who is both a ‘labor radical’ (p. 96) and sexual
athlete, the black phallus as white fetish. Godden argues that Faulkner ‘mask[s] himself as
black as a prelude to casting the black from himself ’ – ‘Rider’, in a Faulknerian pun, is the
‘writer’ (p. 106). Faulkner’s excited identification with Rider’s tumescence indicates the
extent to which he has discovered his own psychic investment in blackness, at the very
moment when the black body is displaced by New-Deal restructuring and the imminent
war-time mobilisation of black labour in 1940–1. ‘What greater loss to an owning class’,
Godden asks, ‘than the loss of that body whose labor substantiates the class body of those
who own?’ (p. 112). To desire the black phallus is ‘to desire the labour through which it
stands and glimpse a consolatory fiction of amity between male bodies’ (p. 112).
The starkest version of this consolatory fiction is unearthed from ‘The Bear’, whose
protagonist, Ike McCaslin, obsessively reads the ledgers from his family’s plantation in
search of evidence for his grandfather’s incestuous miscegenation. Buried in the ledgers,
beneath this all-too-familiar and tellable story of the perfidy of the planter-class, is an
Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 137–143 141
occulted and less-relatable tale, which Godden reconstructs in collaboration with another
Faulkner scholar, Noel Polk. McCaslin’s father, Buck, had an incestuous homosexual
relationship with his brother, Buddy; after the death of their father, the brothers domicile
their slaves in the master’s house and live together in a log-cabin built with their own
labour. Buck then purchases a slave, Percival Brownlee, who serves as his sexual partner
before escaping to become a male prostitute to the Union-troops in the Civil War. Ike’s
fixation upon his grandfather’s heterosexual incest is an attempt to displace and refuse
more profound and disturbing ‘interethnic intimacies’, his father’s ‘desire for a bound man’
bearing the tacit recognition that his own property and substance is ‘the work of abjected
hands’ (p. 148). By telling this story, Faulkner can both repudiate and retain the black male
body ‘as an object of deniable desire’ at the very moment of out-migration, when ‘black
bodies are seen to depart’ from their accustomed place (p. 132).
Godden concludes by reading A Fable’s tale of a mutiny among American and British
soldiers fighting in France in World-War I as an allegory of the militarisation of the
American economy in the post-World-War-II period. Again, Godden builds his contextual
argument from densely-assembled textual particulars. The corporal at the ‘focal point (and
origin) of the serially organized panic’ is a ‘black Jew’, a figure of ‘opacity, disorder,
boundary-collapse, and slippage’, both alien from, and essential to, the project of paranoid
self-definition that creates what C. Wright Mills called the ‘permanent arms economy’
(p. 164). With federal funds dispersed geographically to create a national-security state, the
South emerged as the major beneficiary of this economy, completing its long-delayed
process of modernisation. Another régime of accumulation emerges, a ‘machine for making
death and money’ (p. 195). By 1954, with the movement of black labour from plantation
to factory consolidated and the civil-rights movement underway, black has definitively
broken from white: ‘Faulkner’s lost thing was lost and gone, separated from the white
owning class by a decade of economic transition’ (p. 196).
An Economy of Complex Words shows how a basic contradiction in the social relations
underpinning economic practices can run so deep as to become structural, a part of the
material conditions by which everyday life is carried on. Godden’s achievement is to
demonstrate how such structures ‘generate’ contradictions which embed themselves in
both the collective psyche, and in the multilayered texts that issue from a psyche as
apparently idiosyncratic as that of William Faulkner. What elevates Godden’s work far
above both conventional literary exegeses and ‘cultural-studies’ approaches is the feeling he
demonstrates for both the historical weight of words – their traceable derivation from a
closely-specified context – and for the figural play of language – the linguistic mutations
performed by equally specifiable instances of tropes such as metaphor, synecdoche, ellipsis,
chiasmus, and allegory. Godden’s unmatched facility with the terms of grammar, rhetoric
and semiotics means that he is able to detect what others simply miss, picking up meanings
which lie, in Raymond Williams’s words, ‘on the very edge of semantic availability’.8 In
this, he combines a rigorous historical-materialist methodology with the hermeneutic
sophistication associated with poststructuralists such as Paul de Man and Jacques Derrida.
Godden insists on difficulty because the material of the text is difficult. Dense, occluded
and resistant, the text is haunted by its own revenants, by cancelled hopes, repressed wishes,
and contradictory desires. I hope to have demonstrated at least something of the scope and
power of Godden’s analysis. My one demurral concerns biography, perhaps the least
fashionable (but most popular) form of literary criticism.
Godden tends to take it as read that Faulkner was an ‘apprentice to a planter economy’
(p. 132), that he identified so closely with the Southern landowning class as to act as ‘its
contemporary and historian’ (p. 5). But the method, which generally steers clear of the
intentional fallacy, does not permit such biographical certainties. Godden asks whether
Faulkner’s interest in Lucas’s story turns on his own commitment to ‘an archaic regime of
accumulation’, one that might ‘resist modernity’ and so prevent the trauma of ‘the black
separated, the black in motion, the black urbanized’ (p. 75). He answers that we cannot
know what Faulkner’s authorial intentions were because he adopted a free, indirect
narration which allows for no interpretive ‘finality’ (p. 75). There is thus a disparity between
the fully-fledged, historicised body of Rider, and the oddly anonymous, place-less figure of
the author, ‘Faulkner’. We need to know in more biographical detail the extent of Faulkner’s
identification with capital in order to fully appreciate his psychic investments in labour.
Another paradox of Godden’s argument is that it posits a sharply defined generative
structure – the Agricultural Adjustment Program – which ‘yields disconcerting levels of
textual undecibability’ (p. 75). This is unproblematic when it comes to purely textual
ambiguity: Faulkner’s text both mourns the separation of black from white and disavows
that any separation has taken place, until the permanent arms-economy makes the breach
final. But, because of the biographical lacuna identified above, textual ambiguities cannot
be traced to ambivalences in Faulkner’s own mind. The lacuna becomes particularly
problematic when the utopian potentialities of the text are concerned. The value Godden
wants to attach to a ‘residual social structure’ of ‘subsistence’ and ‘use-value’, to ‘non-
monetary modes of exchange’ is necessarily uncertain (p. 55). The same can be said for the
extent to which labour (ploughing) as the exercise of independent consciousness is
potentially liberating, or populist revolt (barn-burning) potentially emancipatory. These
are latent themes recoverable from Faulkner’s text, but it is not clear whether Faulkner’s
premodern, archaic class-location made him, at some level, an anticapitalist; or whether he
finally threw his lot in with modernisation and agribusiness and produced a set of elegiacs
which falsified and obscured the restructuring of the South. ‘Split subjects and divided
objects’ provide plentiful hermeneutic resources for opening up the text, but they tend to
divorce Godden from the kind of directly articulated politics for which, on the lower
frequencies, his argument seems to yearn (p. 74).
The concept that links economic structure and literary text in Godden’s analysis is the
psyche, a space of repressed desires whose origins ultimately lie in economic interest, and
whose topography is recoverable from the encrypted traces it leaves in the signifying
substance of words. But the link back to economic structure from the text can only be
made, it seems to me, if the psyche is posited alongside the biographical record, a record
which has itself to be interpreted, but which is nonetheless crucial in suggesting how
economic power and interest take psychological form. My sense is that, without this
additional form of mediation, the analysis risks becoming over-immersed in the purely
psychic life of power, rather than being directed equally at power understood economically
and politically. The complexities of régimes of accumulation as generative structures
(Agricultural Adjustment Program; permanent arms-economy) tend to be displaced by
what they generate (the text).
Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 137–143 143
Having read An Economy of Complex Words one wants to know more about how central
the AAP was to the Southern neo-plantation economy, and more about Faulkner’s own
recognition of its effects in his correspondence, essays, and journals. Such evidence might
substantiate Faulkner’s ‘concer[n]’ with the New Deal’s ‘reformation of labor and its
ruination as it was forced out of the forms into which “dependency” and an archaic regime
of accumulation . . . had cast it’ (p. 40). It would be fascinating to know, not just how the
Southern owning-class resolved its contradictory need to keep blacks on the land, and to
turn them into mobile wage-earners, but how Faulkner himself sensed and responded to
that dilemma. One also wants to know how the ‘forcing-out’ affected white sharecroppers,
and whether their plight had any affinity with that of black-migrant labour – whether, that
is, the less-successful Snopeses sensed, or resisted, the possibility of common experience or
common cause with their black counterparts, and whether that recognition or disavowal
took narrative form in the work of other Southern writers.
These caveats aside, it seems to me that Godden’s concept of generative structure is of
vital interest to anyone wishing to develop a genuinely-historical materialism within the
field of literary studies. Among the effects by which a landmark-study might be known are
that it provides the basis for a new methodology, while provoking a fresh set of research-
questions. Measured by these criteria, An Economy of Complex Words is such a work.
References
Aglietta, Michel 2000 [1976], A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The U.S. Experience, translated
by David Fernbach, London: Verso.
De Man, Paul 1979, Allegories of Reading: Figural Landscape in Rousseau, Rilke, and Proust, New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Genovese, Eugene D. 1974, Roll, Jordan Roll: The World the Slaves Made, New York: Pantheon
Books.
Godden, Richard 1997, Fictions of Labor: William Faulkner and the South’s Long Revolution,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 2007, William Faulkner: An Economy of Complex Words, Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Jameson, Fredric 1981, The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act, London:
Methuen.
Ricœur, Paul 1978, ‘The Metaphorical Process as Cognition, Imagination, and Feeling’, Critical
Inquiry, 5, 1: 143–59.
Riffaterre, Michael 1980 [1978], Semiotics of Poetry, London: Methuen.
Wiener, Jonathan M. 1979, ‘Class Structure and Economic Development in the American
South, 1865–1955’, American Historical Review, 84, 4: 970–92.
Wright, Gavin 1986, Old South, New South: Revolutions in the Southern Economy Since the Civil
War, New York: Basic Books.
144 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159
Capital as Power: A Study of Order and Creorder, Jonathan Nitzan and Shimshon Bichler,
London: Routledge, 2009.
Abstract
Nitzan and Bichler’s Capital as Power suggests that conventional theories of capitalism, Marxist
and liberal alike, are unable to answer the question: what is capital? They argue that the basic
units of Marxist economics, abstract labour and value, are unobservable and immeasurable, and
hence ‘non-existent’ and ‘fictitious’. Against Marxists, they argue that capital is not an ‘economic’
entity, but a symbolic quantification of power.
This review contends that what Nitzan and Bichler present as a critique of Marxism as such
pivots on an incomprehension of dialectical thinking, and thus misses the mark. Furthermore,
this absence in their readings of Marx is strictly correlative to the limits of their own theory-
building. Capital as Power simply inverts the vulgar economism it finds in Marxist theories,
presenting us with a theory in which capital is financial rather than productive, and symbolic
rather than material. In doing so, it reproduces the one-sidedness it criticises, while discarding
the possibility of analysing capitalism dialectically as a totality consisting of contradictory, but
mutually presupposing, moments.
Keywords
Nitzan and Bichler, capital, power, Marx, dialectics
Capital is power. It is around this simple proposition that political economists Nitzan and
Bichler build their most ambitious book to date, the four-hundred page long Capital as
Power. This book can be read as a clarification and elaboration of the theoretical
presupposition at the centrepiece of their previous productions, especially the excellent The
Global Political Economy of Israel of 2002.1 In a dazzling outburst of ambition and
dissatisfaction with existing theories of capital, the first part of Capital as Power attempts to
clear the ground for a new theory through the rejection of neoclassical as well as Marxist
economics. While intertwined with the arguments of the first half, their own theory of
capital-as-power takes centre-stage in the second half of the book. Conceptualising capital
in terms of ownership rather than production, the basic subject-matter is not economics as
such, but capital – capital understood as a question of organised and quantified power.
In order to demonstrate the obsolescence of neoclassical and Marxist approaches to
capital, Nitzan and Bichler engage in criticisms of an impressive range of theories. On
account of the sheer number of readings that form the base of their argument, their
criticisms are more engaged, detailed and informed than most exchanges between
neoclassical and Marxist economists themselves. In short, they have read their enemies.
Certainly they have, but how, and how well? This question with regards to Marxism, and
1. In 2005, Nitzan and Bichler alleged that their Global Political Economy of Israel had been
plagiarised by the Retort Collective in their successful analysis/manifesto on ‘military neo-
liberalism’, Afflicted Powers (Retort Collective 2005). Nitzan and Bichler have published their
extensive and well-documented complaints on their website <http://bnarchives.yorku.ca/>.
While Nitzan and Bichler’s complaint seems technically valid – Retort does rely on unreferenced
passages from their book – the essayistic style of Afflicted Powers could warrant a plea for
largesse.
in particular the Marxian dialectic, will structure the review at hand, leaving their instructive
discussions of neoclassical economics to one side. As will be argued, Nitzan and Bichler fail
to exhibit an understanding of the dialectic at play in Marx’s Capital. This focus, however,
is not to be understood as the Marxologist’s defence of the ‘true’ Marx, but, rather, as a way
to throw light upon Nitzan and Bichler’s theory of capital itself, on its wants and merits.
Thus, the assessment of Capital as Power will take a detour through the analysis of its
method and epistemology, in an attempt to offer a critique of the structuring ideas of the
book. In doing so, this review will try to practise the form of in-depth methodological
analysis it finds lacking in Nitzan and Bichler’s reading of Marx. Through this analysis,
I will argue that Nitzan and Bichler’s inability or unwillingness to engage with Marx’s
dialectical method marks the limits of their own approach. Specifically, their critiques of
non-dialectical Marxist theories of value and capital remain stuck in a positivist or empiricist
framework, which their own theory does not respect, and which the Hegelian Marx had
more convincingly overcome – or sublated – a hundred and fifty years ago. I will thus argue
that the poverty of their critiques of questionable Marxisms is an index of the limits of their
own theory-building.
Capital as power
Before we depart on the discussion and analysis of Nitzan and Bichler’s problematic
relationship to Marx, it is useful to sketch out the basic tenets of their theory of capital. At
the very root, the authors follow the American economist and social critic Thorstein Veblen
in defining capital as a power to incapacitate, to decide over the use of things, or rather to
decide not to use a thing. They illuminate this point by referring to the origins of the word
‘private’ in the Latin privatus, restricted, and to the verb privare, to deprive (p. 228). Thus,
the defining characteristic of capital is not related to production and the extraction of
surplus-value, but directly to private property itself, which is nothing but the power to
deprive. ‘The most important feature of private ownership is not that it enables those who
own, but that it disables those who do not’ (ibid.). Capital as defined qua private property
is thus not a mode of production, but an institution of exclusion. This means that capital
must be defined as a form of organised power separate from production, which is merely
under the control of capital qua ownership. In this way, Nitzan and Bichler oppose two
general ‘entities’: on the one hand humane society, and, on the other, capitalist ‘creorder’,
denoting ‘a paradoxical fusion between being and becoming’ of the capitalist system,
imposing itself on society (p. 18). The former follows no preset pattern, and thus cannot be
theorised; it is a mostly latent and invisible potentiality, which occasionally erupts ‘often
without warning, to challenge and sometimes threaten the institutions of capitalist power’
(p. 21). Nitzan and Bichler more-or-less leave considerations of what we could call class-
struggle at that remark, and proceed to what can be theorised, namely ‘the dynamic order
of those who rule’, the capitalist creorder (ibid.). In effect, private property, which, for
Marx, is a presupposition of capital (necessary, but not sufficient), for Nitzan and Bicher
becomes capital-as-such, while the sine qua non of capital – the extraction of surplus-value
through exploitation – becomes external to the concept of capital itself. The concept of
capital is thus on the side of ownership, rather than what dynamically relates ownership
and non-ownership.
146 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159
Since capital is understood in terms of property, the source of the dynamic of the
capitalist creorder is sought on the plane of the distribution, rather than of the production,
of wealth. What, however, is found on this plane is simply a number of concrete, empirical
capitalist actors, and the question of the dynamic of capital thus becomes one of the logic
of those in possession of capital. In short: as property-ownership relations are the privileged
nexus of the theory of capital, of capital understood as a ‘creorder’, questions of wage-
labour, exploitation and class-struggle are disregarded. Hence Nitzan and Bichler
understand modern industry to be subordinated to the ends of business-enterprises, which
have only one interest: the accumulation of pecuniary wealth (p. 220). This statement,
seemingly close to Marxism, is not simply taken to mean that production is ruled by the
profit-motive. Rather, it is used as a lever to suggest that capital must be understood from
the viewpoint of the business-investor, for whom capital ‘has long been stripped of any
physical characteristics’ (p. 231). Thus, Nitzan and Bichler suggest that we leave behind
production-centred theories of capital, and understand it as the business-investor does, as
‘a pecuniary capitalization of earning capacity’ expressed not in equipment or physical wealth,
but in terms of expected future earnings (ibid.).
Before we can introduce their reasons for not pursuing a theory of capitalist production,
it is useful to look at their idea of capitalisation as capitalism’s specific difference from other
modes of private-property power.
perception, hype and the expected rate of return. Thus, capitalisation is strictly a forward-
looking question of how property can be capitalised, how power to deprive can be enhanced.
Hence, it neither relates to the productivity of a fixed asset, nor to the abstract labour
embodied in any asset, but to the power of a corporation’s owners:
For the capitalist, the real thing is the nominal capitalization of future earnings.
This capitalization is not ‘connected’ to reality; it is the reality. And what matters
in that reality is not production and consumption, but power. (p. 182.)
form of capital, that is finance. Nitzan and Bichler’s claim to be instituting a new paradigm
in the study of capital is based on this idea that capital is pecuniary rather than productive.
Readers of Historical Materialism will know that this opposition – productive or pecuniary –
is problematic; capital, for Marx, is inherently both. Nitzan and Bichler’s critique of
Marxism can here help us understand the method and epistemology of Capital as Power.
The question is how Nitzan and Bichler set up their rejection of Marxism and what readings
of Marx they thereby preclude.2
In a passage from the book’s introduction, we find distilled both Nitzan and Bichler’s
reading and their rejection of Marx. Echoing Marx’s claim to put Hegel on his feet, they
write that
If Nitzan and Bichler are here coquetting with Hegel, it serves not to clarify their position.
Rather, as we will see, it covers up the absence of what we could call ‘the dialectic’ (or rather,
of a dialectical way of thinking, to avoid its reification as system or method) in their reading
of Marx, as well as in their own theory of capital. According to the authors, Marx got things
wrong because he was caught up in analyses of the concrete labour-process of workers and
technology, and never managed to integrate the dependence of the labour-process on
capitalist control, that is, on the accumulation of universal ownership-titles, viz. the ‘form
of capitalism’ (p. 85). Nitzan and Bichler’s claim is that Marx was preoccupied with the
‘content’ of capitalism, neglecting the analysis of its ‘form’.3 Briefly put, Nitzan and Bichler
read Marx’s Capital as a productionist-materialist doctrine of political economy which
leaves the power-dynamics of capitalism largely ignored. Marx, they assert, is caught in a
‘materialistic trap’ (p. 85). Following Veblen and the idea of money as the universal symbol
of capital-as-power, Nitzan and Bichler asserts that ‘capital simply is not a double-sided
entity’, but ‘only a pecuniary magnitude’, a nominal sphere ruling the material, quantity
ruling quality (p. 231).
The conclusion that capital is the abstract rule of the universal equivalent (money) over
the heterogeneous qualities of living labour and use-values mimics a dialectically informed
Marxist critique of, say, the economism of the Second International, but the assertion that
capital is not double-sided is a clear marker of Nitzan and Bichler’s incomprehension of
dialectical thought. For Marx, capital is not simply the abstract rule of money, but, more
importantly – since money is the form of appearance of value – the real rule of value over
living labour. Being unable to think capital dialectically, Nitzan and Bichler’s criticisms of
economism and empiricist materialism (wrongly presented as critiques of all Marxism tout
court) hardly produce much more than the mirror-image of what they criticise. In their
4. Adorno 1997.
5. Adorno 1997, p. 88.
6. See the section ‘Distribution and Production’ in the 1857 Introduction (Marx 1973,
pp. 94–98).
150 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159
(industry/production/labour) and the disembedding of the latter from the former (business/
distribution/capital). In this vision, class-struggle proper cannot be theorised: it is absent
from both industry and business. The struggle, then, is a humanist one between the two. It
is between two sets of abstract signifiers (industry/creativity/democracy vs. business/power/
control), both of which, all too obviously, give away their moral value. If this is correct,
then Nitzan and Bichler’s political doctrine simply states, in all banality: one must stand on
the side of good social relations against the bad.
7. Sweezy 1942; Steedman 1977; Fine and Harris 1979; Foley 2000.
8. The field of Marxism as a whole cannot be judged from within Marxism, as this
presupposes its being an object external to the subject of the judgement, or, in other words, that
the subject of the judgement is not part of the object itself.
Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159 151
necessary abstract labour-time as the ‘elementary particle’ of Marx’s system, as that which
underlies and founds the whole system, ‘Marx’s science’ (p. 122). Nitzan and Bichler
understand Marx’s socially-necessary labour-time as the undifferentiated universal quantum
that founds all value-rations. Furthermore, it is, they hold, the ultimate code of prices (as
mediated through the labour-theory of value). Without the concept of socially-necessary
labour-time, Marxism cannot understand wages, income-distribution and class-power, as
well as crisis-tendencies and the historical development of capitalism. Having conjured up
a beautiful and complete structure rising from the single elementary particle of abstract
labour-time, Nitzan and Bichler sarcastically quip ‘[t]he key difficulty is that this particle –
like God or the Ether – is forever beyond our reach’ (p. 88). This is the heart of Nitzan and
Bichler’s ornate and extensive critique of Marxism. Indeed, their catalogue of criticisms of
theories gathered under the signifier ‘Marxism’ circles around the critique of the concept of
socially-necessary abstract labour-time, uniting their different criticisms theoretically. The
problem with socially-necessary abstract labour-time, Nitzan and Bichler assert, lies in
converting a given individual labour-time to socially-necessary labour-time and a given
amount of concrete labour to abstract labour. This, they argue, amounts to a ‘make-or-
break-predicament’ for Marx. For, if Marx bases his theory on these conversions and they
cannot be performed, Marx’s theory has no basic unit and thus is no theory at all (p. 89).
As value and surplus-value do not exist, Nitzan and Bichler reject the concept of exploitation
as analytically distinct from oppression (p. 281).
For Nitzan and Bichler, the concept ‘abstract labour’ is materialist in a way most Marxists
would consider vulgar, and a positive concept that can be understood in isolation from
monetary relations. Since socially-necessary labour-time and value are supposed to be the
ground for Marx’s theory of prices, they cannot at the same time be expressed in prices, as
this would mean confusing that which is to be explained with its explanation, the
explanandum with the explanans. The basic move of Nitzan and Bichler is to postulate that
Marx tries (and fails) to derive the theoretical concept of abstract labour from empirically
existing concrete labour, and to quantify either without recourse to money (p. 97). It is by
ascribing to Marx this method of linear argument from empiricist premises that Nitzan and
Bichler can set up the problem of this transformation from value to prices as the decisive,
and ultimately insuperable, problem of Marx.
which Marx found unsatisfactory.9 Indeed, concrete labour and use-value are both abstract
concepts that jumble together activities and things that are fundamentally heterogeneous.
In a certain sense, this formless mess of different activities and things is only grounded
retroactively with the concepts of value and exchange-value. Whereas it might pragmatically
make sense to fashion a common name such as use-value or utility to speak of all objects
that people find useful, this point of unification is in the name; it is merely linguistic,
naming difference from without. With the commodity-form, however, these fields of
difference find an objective unitary expression beyond the subjective mental synthesis of
the philosopher-economist.
What makes Marx’s method fundamentally different from any empiricist approach is
that the question of what commodities have in common in order to exchange does not so
much point towards a shared substance existing in them prior to their exchange, but at
what the commensuration of commodities in exchange posits. That is the question of what
the becoming-commodity of the product of labour, i.e. its exchange in the market, does to
the labour itself. The answer is not that it turns concrete labour into abstract labour, as
Nitzan and Bichler would have it (along with some of the authors in their selective Marxist
bibliography), but that it gives concrete labour an abstract social form. In general, as
production of products becomes production for the market, commodity-production, the
aim of producing use-values becomes subordinated to that of producing exchange-value.
In short, concrete labour and use-value become dominated, but not eradicated, by
the compulsion of market-competition to produce at or below the socially necessary
labour-time.
This answer in turn only makes sense if, as Christopher Arthur has convincingly argued,
one reads Chapter 1 of Capital as the initial breakdown of the systematic relations of
generalised exchange, rather than of ‘simple commodity-production’. This means that, in
the dialectical reconstruction of how concrete labour ‘becomes’ abstract, capitalist
production and thus money and wage-labour are all presupposed, but bracketed. It is
precisely not a theoretical construction from some element which is understandable in
isolation, but a reconstruction, which means that every element can only be understood in
relation to the whole of which it is a part. Taking the first sentence in Chapter 1 of Capital
into account, it is clear that Marx is not examining questions of production and wealth in
general, but specifically ‘[t]he wealth of societies in which the capitalist mode of production
prevails’.10 Marx starts his critique with the commodity, not because it is the foundation on
which capitalism rests, some isolatable ‘basic unit’, but because it is the ‘elementary cell’ of
capitalism, through which one can enter into the study of the system as a whole and study
what really matters: the logic that unites and propels the system forward. And this we
might call the dialectic: it is the thinking from the cell to the body, and from the body to
the cell, in a movement of thought which declares primary neither a unit (as if it were a
building block), nor the whole (as if it were a self-sustaining machine, a complete system),
but rather places ‘primacy’ in the contradictions running through the different layers of
the totality.
The question of socially-necessary abstract labour cannot be divorced from the question
of money: capitalism is essentially a monetary system.11 When Marx asks the question of
what commodities have in common, we should avoid reading him as asking for a concrete
shared material substance or origin. Rather, the question is how generalised exchange, for
which both money and capitalist production are conditions, constitute the unity of
commodities and labours practically.12 Instead of reading Marx’s exposition as a linear
sequence describing how an amount of concrete labour becomes, or is calculated as, an
amount of abstract labour, the logic of the commodity works both ways; as anticipation of
a value expressed by a price, and as determination of value in the sale. Commodity-
production and exchange describe this circle of constant anticipation and retroaction. The
concrete labour expended on a product, of course, may be of no value if the product cannot
be sold as a commodity: only from the point of view of the endpoint of the circle, the sale/
non-sale, are the previous moments validated. In the actual price, the value of the
commodity is being determined as a function of the fluctuations within the world of
commodities; abstract labour is ruling concrete labour rather than simply being its
product.
Within the value-relation and the value expression included in it, the abstractly
general counts not as a property of the concrete, sensibly real; but on the contrary
the sensibly-concrete counts as the mere form of appearance or definite form of
realisation of the abstractly general.13
Abstract labour, thus, cannot be equated with any particular kind of labour-expenditure.
On the contrary, it is the determination that any particular kind of labour-expenditure can
fall under in so far as the labour is waged (i.e., sold as the commodity labour-power) and
its product, be it a good or a service, is traded as a commodity. Abstract labour is not
something that can be observed or measured directly, but the abstract social form of
concrete labour under capitalist conditions of production.
And yet, in the Marx of Nitzan and Bichler, such ideas are absent. By and large, they
read Capital not with or against Hegel, but as if Hegel had never lived. For instance, we can
read their claim that capital is not a double-sided entity as an index of the absence of
dialectical thought. Whilst the pertinence of a dialectical reading of Capital is indisputable,14
the rather tokenistic invocations of the word ‘dialectics’ throughout the book do nothing
to make up for this absence.15 Lacking in the staging of the make-or-break predicament
Capital as Power sets up against Marx are two fundamental dialectical principles. Firstly,
the reconstruction of an integrated totality, viz. the task of dialectics, is inimical to linear
arguments; each concept within the exposition makes sense only in relation to other
concepts. Abstract labour must thus not only be read in relation to those concepts that
precede it (such as concrete labour), but also in relation to the concepts that follow upon it
(i.e. value and money), and within the totality of the exposition itself (importantly relating
it to surplus-value, which, ultimately, is what gives sense to the capitalist chain, M–C–M',
and hence to abstract labour). Secondly, whilst Nitzan and Bichler ascribe to Marx an
empiricist or positivist dualism between concepts and their objects, between theory and
reality, between thinking and being, Marx does no such thing. As we will see, the absence
of the dialectic in Nitzan and Bichler’s account of Marx has the effect that socially-necessary
labour-time is unthinkable as real or practical abstraction, and as an effect of commodity-
fetishism. This, of course, means that it becomes difficult to understand how, for Marx, the
specificity of power in capitalism is its abstract and impersonal character. As we will see,
Marx, contrary to Nitzan and Bichler’s claims, does have a concept of power, and an
extremely dynamic one at that. Furthermore, I will argue, the poverty of their Marx can be
read as a symptom of the poverty of their theory.
in the statement that ‘neoclassical political economy is largely an ideology in the service of the
powerful ’ (p. 2), it is not without a tinge of instrumentalism, a limited mode of thought
prevalent in the Marxian tradition – but mostly subordinated in Marx’s writings.
Because of their elimination of a dialectical reading of Capital, Nitzan and Bichler must
claim an immediate identity between capital and power in ‘capitalist society as a whole’,
and that the duality between economics and politics is a pseudo-fact, ‘a theoretical
impossibility, one that is precluded by the very nature of capitalism’ (p. 30).16 In simply
refuting these distinctions as false, the authors fall short of Marx’s insights into the
mystifications of capital as products of capitalism itself and how these relate to relations of
dominance in capitalism. For example, Capital as Power merely points out that power-
relations become mystified and naturalised under capitalism, but does not explain how.
When Nitzan and Bichler write that ‘Marx’s insistence that power pervades the system does
not reject but rather necessitates the liberal duality of politics and economics’ (p. 26), as an
argument that Marx’s theory is flawed, the central Marxian insight that the distinction
between the political and the economic is not merely an illusion, but a product of social
relations themselves, is missed. Nitzan and Bichler replace the possibility of thinking the
unity in contradiction of objectivity and subjectivity, of being and thought, with the fantasy
of a theory that plainly states the facts; instead of the complex immanent relation between
contradiction and mediation, we get the external relation of immediacy and truth as
opposed to plain lies, illusions and falsities. Meanwhile, we look in vain for reflections on
the position from which Nitzan and Bichler speak their truths, and the ontological/
epistemological status of these truths.
Fetishism as power
For Marx, the duality between economics and politics is not only a passive effect of the
capitalist mode of production; it also gives form to subjectivity. It is a necessary appearance
that has an effect of its own. This is the point of the account of commodity-fetishism, in
which the relations between producers ‘take on the form of a social relation between the
products of labour’ and appear as merely ‘economic’ relations.17 Fetishism is not simply
illusion or an ideological ‘instrument’ of the powerful, but, rather, an effect of commodity-
exchange itself, the subjective side of the objectivity of the value-form. Thus, Marx writes,
when the social relations between producers do not appear directly as social relations, ‘but
rather as material relations between persons and social relations between things’, they
‘appear as what they are’.18 When Nitzan and Bichler distinguish capitalism from previous
‘mega-machines’, they do so, not by offering a theory of commodity-fetishism, but by
16. In a brief and otherwise sympathetic reading of Giovanni Arrighi, they reject what they
describe as his idea of a ‘contradictory interdependence’ of state and business, on the grounds
that in this model the two remain ‘fundamentally distinct’ (pp. 277–8). It is useful here to
remind ourselves of Gramsci’s good Hegelian point that the distinction between political society
and civil society is methodological rather than organic. See Notebook 4, §38 (Gramsci 1996,
pp. 177–87).
17. Marx 1976, p. 164.
18. Marx 1976, p. 166, my italics.
156 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159
names, from the point of view of empirical analysis as frames. As names, these work as
abstract universals or analytical constructs whose criteria of application are pragmatic rather
than entailed by the accompanying descriptive efforts. As frames they simply work as
tautologies: that totality within which individual capitalist action makes sense is that of the
‘capitalist nomos’. What this seems to miss from a Marxian viewpoint is the thinking of
capital as a totality rather than as name, and the tools to explain rather than describe the
distribution of wealth.
Since both the statistical dynamic and the abstract names are descriptive and denotative
rather than explanatory, we must ask how the process can be explained. It seems that the
introduction of abstract wholes such as mega-machines and capital cannot carry this burden.20
The centrality of the concept of capitalisation can be read as symptomatic of an unanswered
question of explanation: does this lie with the whole, the nomos, or the motives of the actors
compared in the statistical models? What we can find here is a tension between individual
subjectivity and social objectivity, the relation between which is nowhere made explicit.
While the concept of the capitalist nomos as a power-architecture enslaving even its masters
seems to stress the primacy of social objectivity (the universality of the nomos as social
order), the theorisation proper of capitalisation as the dynamic axiomatic of capital is not
integrally conceptualised as the logic of a system sui generis. Instead, capitalisation appears
to be the subjective logic of capitalists from whose interactions the system springs. In the
theory of capitalisation, objectivity is treated descriptively and capitalist agency becomes
explanatory, whilst in the idea of the capitalist nomos, capitalist agency is very loosely
described as an effect of social objectivity. Since the relations between these theoretical
constructions are not made explicit, the oscillation appears as an inconsistency: is one or
the other primary? It seems that Nitzan and Bichler would reject this opposition and say
that they co-constitute each other. But, since their relation is simply postulated rather than
demonstrated or reconstructed (something which is the very forte of dialectical thought)
we are left with a circular argument or a tautology: the whole (the capitalist nomos) is
nothing but its parts (capitalist enterprises), and the parts are nothing but those that act
according to the norms of the whole. This means that Nitzan and Bichler’s theory proper
of the logic of the development of capitalism – that of capitalisation – becomes agent-
centred, bound up to a concept of power as an attribute and property of agents and their
possessions, whilst the origin of the subjectivity of these agents is loosely referred to as the
capitalist nomos, a somewhat more idealistic concept than the Marxian ‘mode of production’.
The idea of the nomos prioritises the agency and subjectivity of capitalists (capitalisation as
a ‘universal creed’) over the objectivity of social relations in general – including the relation
between labour and capital. Hence, one class within the system becomes the privileged
agent, whilst class-struggle in both its objective and subjective dimensions is disregarded.
On the level of epistemology, we might say that a similar displacement to the agent takes
place, here centring on the scientist himself. We can discover this unity by going back to
the gap between description and naming, between statistics and the names of social wholes,
or between the empiricist critique of Marx and pragmatic theory-building of Capital as
Power. Underlying all these is a certain nominalism, bridging on the level of epistemology
the methodological gap between the two: the basic structuring presupposition is that the
20. This argumental movement is the exact opposite of Marx’s method of dialectical
reconstruction of a whole from the abstract to the concrete.
158 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 144–159
Conclusion
Capital as Power provides valuable discussions and criticisms of political economy, Marxist
as well as neoliberal. However, it never reaches the level of a critique of political economy
proper, the level where Marxism moves beyond ‘critical political economy’, and becomes a
theory – situated within the conflictual relations of bourgeois society – of the conditions of
possibility of political economy, the categories of political economy, and the practices and
agencies of capitalism.
The book is often informative and piquant in the detail, and very often fully compatible
with Marxist insights, and interesting also when it is not. However, despite its grand
ambitions, it never comes together as a whole. Caught in a critique of a reductionist and
economistic Marxism, and without the tools of dialectical analysis, Nitzan and Bichler
reproduce the dualisms ascribed to their enemies, replacing a supposedly one-sided theory
of exploitation and class-struggle with an equally biased and agent-centred account of
intra-class competition. Instead of a claim of the rock-bottom reality of production and the
mystified realms of finance, we get the notion of the hard reality of capitalisation and a
romanticised vision of ‘industry’. Nitzan and Bichler strive to overcome the vulgarities of
economistic Marxism, but end up inverting them. Indeed, if economistic Marxism is a
vulgarisation proper to Fordism, we could say that Capital as Power’s lopsidedness is fitting
for post-Fordist financialised capitalism.
As rare as paradigm-shifts are, it is hardly surprising that Nitzan and Bichler’s book fails
to convince overall. The reason for this failure is not, however, ambition as such. Ambition,
surely both a cause and effect of the sweeping criticisms of Marxism, explains nothing;
rather, as this review has argued, the problem lies in the very mode of thought proper both
to the critique and the project itself, its detached nominalism and political humanism, so
fitting to the rôle of the concerned social scientist. Hence, in the background of this
marginal squabble with the errant knights of Veblen lies a significant insight, unintentionally
confirmed by the shortcomings of Capital as Power: Perhaps only with the dialectic can
Capital, and only with Capital can capitalism be understood. Thus, living under the
dominance of capitalism, we need the dialectic more than ever.
References
Adorno, Theodor W. 1997 [1967], Prisms, translated by Samuel and Shierry Weber, Cambridge,
MA.: MIT Press.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2002, The New Dialectic and Marx’s ‘Capital’, Historical Materialism
Book Series, Leiden: Brill.
Aristotle 2000, Nicomachean Ethics, edited and translated by Roger Crisp, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Backhaus, Hans-Georg 1980, ‘On the Dialectics of the Value-Form’, Thesis Eleven, 1: 99–120.
Fine, Ben and Laurence Harris 1979, Rereading ‘Capital’, New York: Columbia University
Press.
Foley, Duncan 2000, ‘Recent Developments in the Labor Theory of Value’, Review of Radical
Political Economics, 32, 1: 1–39.
Gramsci, Antonio 1996, Prison Notebooks, Volume 2, edited and translated by Joseph A.
Buttigieg, New York: Columbia University Press.
Harvey, David 2006, Limits to Capital, London: Verso.
Marx, Karl 1976 [1867], Capital: Volume 1, translated by Ben Fowkes, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
—— 1978 [1867], ‘The Value-Form – Appendix to the 1st German Edition of Capital, Volume
1’, translated by Mike Roth and Wal Suchting, Capital and Class, 4: 130–50, available at:
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/appendix.htm>.
—— 1973 [1953], Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy (Rough Draft),
translated by Martin Nicolaus, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
McNally, David 2009, ‘From Financial Crisis to World-Slump: Accumulation, Financialisation,
and the Global Slowdown’, Historical Materialism, 17, 2: 35–83.
Nitzan, Jonathan and Shimshon Bichler 2002, The Global Political Economy of Israel, London:
Pluto Press.
—— 2005, ‘The Scientist and the Church’, available at: <http://bnarchives.yorku.ca/185/
01/050731NB_The_Scientist_and_the_Church.pdf>.
—— 2009, Capital as Power: a Study of Order and Creorder, London: Routledge.
Retort Collective 2005, Afflicted Powers, London: Verso.
Rubin, Isaak Illich 2008 [1928], Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value, New Delhi: Aakar Books,
available at: <http://www.marxists.org/archive/rubin/value/>.
Sweezy, Paul M. 1942, The Theory of Capitalist Development: Principles of Marxian Political
Economy, New York: Modern Reader Paperbacks.
Steedman, Ian 1975, ‘Positive Profits With Negative Surplus Value’, The Economic Journal, 85,
337: 114–23.
—— 1977, Marx After Sraffa, London: New Left Books.
160 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 160–174
The Philosophy and Politics of Bruno Bauer, Douglas Moggach, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003.
Krise und Kritik bei Bruno Bauer: Kategorien des Politischen im nachhegelschen Denken,
Massimiliano Tomba, Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 2005.
Abstract
In this review, both readings of Bruno Bauer are analysed in light of a broader post-Hegelian
context. Douglas Moggach deliberately avoids this issue, since his main focus is on establishing
a connection between Bauer’s philosophy and politics, without immediately exposing him to, for
instance, the alleged ‘caricature’ Marx made of him. This ‘caricature’, however, is of some
importance, since it opens a debate on Bauer’s position among the post-Hegelians, his followers
and his adversaries. Marx’s criticism is particularly interesting, since it was not of a philosophical
nature but, rather, of a political one. Some readers – and Marxists in particular – might, in fact,
be a bit disappointed by the choices Moggach has made, but I am fully convinced that his study
has more to offer than they might suspect. That is why this article broadens the perspective by
discussing Massimiliano Tomba’s Krise und Kritik bei Bruno Bauer. Tomba reaches conclusions
similar to Moggach’s, but differs from the latter by giving, among other things, a different
account of the origins of the older Bauer’s conservatism. In so doing, Tomba illuminates Marx’s
criticism of his contemporaries, while drastically altering our perception of post-Hegelianism in
general.
Keywords
Bruno Bauer, Hegelianism, crisis, criticism, Max Stirner, Karl Marx
Introduction
Both works are the product of years of sustained research, and deal with a variety of subjects
ranging from the philosophical to the political, the historical and back again. In so doing,
they both easily establish themselves as long-awaited standard-works on Bruno Bauer.
Douglas Moggach, however, tends to focus on the continuity in Bauer’s writings throughout
the 1840s, while Massimiliano Tomba situates the older Bauer’s conservatism well before
the revolutions of 1848. I do not intend to settle this debate, but will try to enrich it by
referring to the criticism of two of Bauer’s contemporaries: Karl Marx, and, in particular,
Max Stirner. The differences in approach between Moggach and Tomba bear testimony to
an ongoing debate over the extent to which a creative rendering of Hegelian philosophy
was intertwined with distinct political positions, and distinct ethical programmes in the
Vormärz.
Moggach’s book is organised primarily around Bauer’s major themes and texts. It starts
with an introduction entitled ‘The Friend of Freedom’, which immediately focuses on
Bauer’s main concerns, freedom and history, while sketching out the subsequent chapters
which are both of a biographical and thematic nature. The first chapter deals with Bauer’s
prize-winning essay on Kant’s aesthetics which, according to Moggach, already contained
the foundations that would animate his work throughout the 1830s and 1840s: aesthetics,
ethics and republicanism. The critique of the ‘Old Order’ thus seamlessly flows into Bauer’s
own emancipatory project, which he eventually evaluated in a rather bitter and harsh way
in light of the events of 1848. Moggach’s analysis, however, obscures some of the
incompatible strains in Bauer’s thought. Bauer claimed that only self-emancipation was
possible, without, however, neglecting the objective conditions which could contribute to
the emancipation of others. Still, inner-emancipation preceded outer-emancipation, which
meant that the subjective concept of freedom was pursued at the expense of the rational
idea of freedom. Freedom, thus, becomes an abstract ‘ought’, of the sort that Bauer criticised
elsewhere. The notion of ‘emancipation’ is, therefore, crucial to an understanding of Bauer’s
ambiguous relation to the dialectics of revolution, and comes to the fore in Tomba’s analysis
of the axis of ‘crisis’ and ‘criticism’ in Bauer’s thought.
while convincingly arguing that eventually the post-Hegelians’ struggle against the political
theology of Restoration-Germany was a struggle over the complicity between concepts of
the self and of sovereignty.5 Bauer’s Hegelianism set itself apart from the readings by other
post-Hegelians in that its own revolutionary stands were attributed explicitly to Hegel.
Bauer’s politics were thus firmly intertwined with his philosophical views. It is therefore to
Douglas Moggach’s merit to have established this link in The Philosophy and Politics of
Bruno Bauer. Whereas the older literature on Bauer considered him a radical subjectivist
and aligned him more closely to Enlightenment-rationalism than to Hegel, Moggach
convincingly insists on Bauer’s creative use of Hegel’s account of subjective spirit. In so
doing, he emphasises the continuity throughout the Vormärz of Bauer’s thought, as opposed
to the interpretations that insist on Bauer’s abandonment of the post-Hegelian agenda
after 1843.
What was so particularly ‘Hegelian’ about the ‘post-Hegelians’, however, is still under
debate. This is not a strictly historical question, since it allows us to understand the debates
in the Vormärz without immediately seeking refuge in categories that reduce the post-
Hegelians to mere epigones of Hegel. Massimiliano Tomba addressed this issue in Krise und
Kritik bei Bruno Bauer, and it is of great importance to compare the differences in approach
between him and Moggach in detail. Tomba rightly denounces the dichotomy of right-left
or young-old Hegelianism, for it fails to grasp the differences between such authors as
Cieszkowski, Gans or Rosenkranz, and, eventually, Bruno Bauer himself.6 Moggach has
recently tackled this issue by referring to the young Hegelians as the ‘New Hegelians’, thus
emphasising their own creative use of a variety of sources including Hegel and Fichte, but
also Spinoza and Kant.7 This is not a semantic discussion, but actually deals with the
manifold-ways in which the post-Hegelians responded to what they clearly conceived as the
end of an era, first and foremost the end of the estate-order, and, eventually, the end of
philosophy itself as it was embodied by Hegel. The absolute state seemed to have restored
itself rather easily in the 1830s. This happened not despite, but, rather, thanks to the further
dissolution of the estate-order that was slowly but gradually replaced by an anonymous
mass, which had turned into an atomistic society that was characterised by, among other
things, the assertion of individual property-rights. Post-Hegelianism was spawned by this
crisis and tried to reflect upon it. This would eventually lead to a quest for a new organising
principle which could forge the atomistic mass into a new whole, and consecutively
produced a series of theories of history which projected it into the future.8 The quest for
‘emancipation’ actually tried to fill in the void that was left by the destruction of corporative
privileges.9
Tomba, therefore, drops the term ‘Hegelianism’ altogether, and, inspired by Koselleck,
concentrates on a crisis which was of both a socio-political and philosophical nature. His
deliberate avoidance of an overtly Hegelian interpretation of Bauer and the so-called ‘Young
Hegelians’ should be considered the main reason as to why he presents us with a different
interpretation of Bauer’s philosophy throughout the 1840s. He focuses on how Bauer
conceived and acted upon this crisis, the ways in which Die Kritik eventually became the
crisis itself, and the extent to which (or if ) it sought to reconcile the individual and the state
anew. According to Tomba, Bauer never intended to fill in the void between the individual
and the state. Slowly but gradually, he moved towards a conception of history that left no
room for a new synthesis. He turned his back on an emancipatory project and eventually
on philosophy in general.10
Moggach, on the other hand, immediately focuses on Bauer’s republican interpretation
of Hegel. He hence offers us a very coherent overview of Bauer’s meandering thought, held
together, not by the axis Krise-Kritik, but by his theory of infinite self-consciousness and the
Hegelian unity of thought and being. Such an approach will unavoidably emphasise the
extent to which Bauer clung to his philosophy of self-consciousness throughout the 1840s,
while understating certain evidence, brought forward by Tomba, that its political
implications might have shifted over the course of this period.
Picking up on Tomba’s argument that crisis and criticism were closely intertwined in
Bauer’s thought, his reading of Bauer appeals more to a Marxist audience than Moggach’s.
By aiming his attention at the unity of thought and being in Bauer’s writings of the 1830s
and 1840s, Moggach nearly renders Bauer immune to Marx’s virulent criticism, while, at
the same time, establishing the former as a major thinker in his own right.
which was the ultimate synthesis of the universal and the particular, and was, in Bauer’s
opinion, synonymous with ‘the conquest of egoism’ (p. 124). Religious consciousness was
marked by both the particular and the universal, which meant that particular interests were
legitimised out of an abstract universality (pp. 76–7).
By denying the universal character of self-consciousness and by projecting it as an
abstract, transcendent universality onto countless particular interests, the religious
arrogation of universality abandoned the community to ‘egoism’ (p. 13). Religious
consciousness indeed denied the claims of the self to rise to universality by its own efforts.
False universals such as the absolutist state and the fetishist-objects of religion all transcended
this power of individuality, yet all their attempts to assert freedom on the basis of particular
interests were irrational and, therefore, doomed. Infinite self-consciousness, on the other
hand, meant both freedom and humanity, and eventually it dissolved both substance and
the ‘transcendent absolute’. The absolute surpassed religious consciousness and – in turn –
was dissolved in the criticism of individual consciousness. Universal consciousness was thus
literally ‘victorious over egoism’.11
as ‘anti-Semitic’.12 The older Bauer’s anti-Semitism was, however, quite different from his
stances in the Vormärz, and should be analysed alongside Bauer’s neo-conservatism and
anti-socialism.13 Moggach analyses the younger Bauer’s criticism of Judaism within Bauer’s
wider critique of Christianity and religion in general. In 1843, Bauer radicalised his earlier
critique of Christianity, claiming that its religious form distorts and hinders the concrete
realisation of freedom in personal, social, and political life. Bauer’s critique of Judaism
should thus be considered as implicated in his more radicalised critique of Christianity and
religion in general, as a tool to elaborate on alienation in history, with its specific religious
and political dimensions, which according to Bauer indeed share common defining
attributes (pp. 145–9). Tomba goes well beyond this issue, by relating Die Judenfrage to the
much broader impact of Bauer’s notion of ‘exclusiveness [Ausschlieslichkeit]’. Exclusiveness
was a logic-structure common to religion and the state. Bauer’s Die Judenfrage, therefore,
analysed emancipation from a framework that combined both theological and political
traits. Emancipation, for Bauer, implied the eradication of the possible conditions of
exclusion.14 This is related to another novelty in Moggach’s interpretation. He convincingly
argues how Bauer’s critique of religion was connected to his critique of the modern
economy. The crisis of the estate-order had paved the way for ‘atomism’ and ‘egoism’, which
translated themselves into narrow economic interests, which, in turn, defined personality
and ultimately served as an obstacle to political engagement (pp. 54, 127). This was not a
product of religion, but a development that ran parallel to it.
Both forms of alienation shared an abstract ‘beyond’, which eventually legitimised
particular interests and egoism. It was from this alienated root that both God and the state
derived. The real solution to the problem of Jewish emancipation was, therefore, not only
the renunciation of religion, but primarily the rejection of the Christian state of Restoration-
Prussia as a whole (pp. 86–7).
Karl Marx, on the other hand, entered the discussion by criticising both political
liberalism and Bauer, while still linking Christianity and the sovereign individual to
egoism.15 He had already used a ‘transformative method’ (man-as-subject and thought-as-
predicate) in his dissertation on Epicurus and Democritus, and linked it to a criticism of
so-called ‘abstract individual consciousness’.16 The notion of ‘egoism’ as it was developed
throughout the works of Feuerbach, Bauer and Marx allows us to further elaborate on this
issue. Hegel had linked civil society to ‘atomism’ (individualism), and this thesis was almost
literally translated into a criticism of religion by Feuerbach, Bauer and Marx who interpreted
it as ‘egoism’.17 Feuerbach drastically radicalised Hegel’s remark that Judaism did not
consider nature as the embodiment of the divine.18 According to Feuerbach, Judaism had
reduced nature to an object of self-interest, taking ‘egoism’ as its basic principle.19 Feuerbach
criticised both Judaism and Christianity because they spoke of ‘a creation out of nothing’,
and he linked this to the ‘absolute personality to whom nature was nothing’.20
Bauer concluded in a similar way that Judaism was even further removed from ‘freedom’
than Christianity, since it ‘felt at home in egoism’.21 Marx, however, argued in Zur Judenfrage
(1843) that it was the alleged ‘political emancipation’ of Bauer that reduced men to
members of civil society and therefore to ‘egoistic men’.22 Marx’s criticism of the theological
treatment of the ‘Jewish question’ meant that ‘egoism’ as an ‘element of society’ had to be
overcome before Judaism itself would disappear.23 This is the consequence of a thesis upon
which Feuerbach had elaborated before, since, according to Feuerbach, egoism was not the
product of religion, but religion gave legitimacy to ‘Jewish egoism’.24 Christianity had
spiritualised egoism and thus replaced ‘earthly bliss’ with ‘heavenly bliss’.25 The criticism of
‘egoism’ was both a political and social criticism, but, implicitly, also a moral criticism.
What was clearly at stake in Hegel, Feuerbach, Bauer and the young Marx was the
overcoming of ‘atomism’ or ‘egoism’ as it was spawned by the crisis. These debates will prove
to be crucial in understanding the vicious attacks of one of Bauer’s and Marx’s most
infamous contemporaries, Max Stirner. In Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, Stirner no longer
criticised ‘egoism’ but embraced it fully, which was not so much a serious anti-ethical or
philosophical stand, but rather a political one, for it implied that Stirner embraced the crisis
and criticised and ridiculed the emancipatory project (and its implicit morality) of his
contemporaries while seeking refuge in his own individuality. Tomba’s interpretation is
highly illuminating in this regard.
In his assessment of the French Revolution, Stirner claimed that it had brought about a
much more absolute monarchy than the ancien régime. The ‘dissolution [Auflösung]’ of the
estate-order had left the individual powerless before the state, the sole master-on-high. The
end of the estate-order had led to the annulment of the individual. What his liberal
contemporaries were striving for had realised itself beyond their wildest expectations, but
confined within the boundaries of the modern state.26 This is in accordance with Bauer’s
proper assessment of the French Revolution, but Stirner went on to expand Bauer’s criticism
of nivellement until it encompassed Bauer’s ‘humane liberalism’ as well. In the chapter on
his contemporaries (‘Die Freien’), Stirner distinguished ‘political liberalism’ (liberalism)
from ‘social liberalism’ (socialism and communism) and, eventually, ‘humane liberalism’
(Bruno Bauer). According to Stirner, the development of ‘freedom’ throughout history
meant that ‘spirit’ or thought became free, and thus held the greatest possible power of
subjugation over the concrete individual.27 Political liberalism liberated the egoist from ‘the
master’, but replaced him by a ‘ghost’: the state. Social liberalism got rid of the difference
between rich and poor, but put all property in the hand of a ‘ghost’: society. Humane
liberalism (Bruno Bauer) likewise got rid of the personal God, but replaced it with a new
faith: mankind or freedom.28 Bruno Bauer thus came at the end of Stirner’s parodic
historical account. The development of so-called ‘freedom’ as the cornerstone of Hegel’s
entire system found its highest culmination-point in Bauer, and meant the absolute
annulment of the individual. Stirner’s Einzige (‘unique’), however, escaped the dialectic of
nivellement, since it was extra-conceptual and hence lay beyond philosophy or ‘criticism’:
This remark brings us to the core of Tomba’s analysis. What makes Tomba’s reading so
interesting is that it offers a new insight into two authors whom Friedrich Engels considered
to be ‘the only important philosophical opponents of Socialism – or rather Communism’.
Tomba refers to Bauer’s Selbstkritik der Kritik, which, according to him, meant Bauer’s
farewell to the dynamics of revolution. Criticism had to elevate itself to an understanding
of the crisis, while distancing itself from reality (‘pure criticism’).30 Bauer’s transvaluation of
the Revolution thus meant Bauer’s return to pure theory.31 Bauer and Stirner maintained
that the estate-order had only transformed itself in the opposition between the people and
the government, where the state eventually became the sole master-on-high. This dialectic
had led to an equality, which was both liberating and oppressing. In their very own way,
both Stirner and Bauer tried to fasten the crisis, which they judged irreversible, by destroying
the last remnants of the ‘old world’, while seeking refuge in their own individuality as a
means to escape the levelling (nivellement) effects of the crisis. Tomba thus describes Bauer
and Stirner as proponents of a radical and revolutionary aristocratism.32 It is exactly their
distancing from the workers’ movement which Marx criticised in both Die heilige Familie
and Die Deutsche Ideologie. Tomba rightly observes that Marx’s aim was to criticise those
contemporaries who tried to distance themselves from a revolutionary subject and even
social reality as a whole. Marx never intended to write a philosophical criticism of his
contemporaries, but immediately focused on their political dimensions and thus made a
strategic divide between Bauer and Stirner on the one hand, and Marx, Engels, Feuerbach
and Hess on the other, without, of course, ignoring his own criticism of Feuerbach
and Hess.
Marx aimed at convincing the radical intellectuals of the Vormärz to side with the
proletariat. In so doing, he eventually reformulated his previous criticism of ‘atomism’.
Bauer had claimed that only the state ‘held the separate, selfish atoms together’, while Marx
stated that ‘the members of civil society were no atoms’. In his strictly political engagement
with Bauer, he refused to relate atomism to just any form of society, but claimed that it was
in fact related to a specific form of society. In reference to the revolt of the Silesian weavers
in 1844, Marx considered isolation and atomism as the products of a very specific social
reality, which was not only related to the relation between the individual and the state, but
to a social divide which isolated the workers from ‘the true community of mankind’. By
using a humanist language, he actually bridged the gap between industrial workers and the
prospect of a political and social revolution.33
Moggach, on the other hand, claims that Bauer’s criticisms of mass-society did not imply
that he had abandoned the revolutionary cause altogether. Was ist jetzt der Gegenstand der
Kritik? (1844) and, indeed, the Selbstkritik der Kritik, as expressed in his writings in the
Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung and the Norddeutsche Blätter, were, according to him, a
judgment of the ‘social bearing’ of his commitment to ‘political revolution’ (p. 161).
Moggach maintains that Bauer still defended his republican commitment, but directed it
against the ‘inconsequence’, ‘vacillation’ and ‘unclarity’ in demands of the progressive party
(p. 161). In doing so, Bauer attacked both liberalism and socialism, while still maintaining
his aggressive position against the Restoration-order. Was ist jetzt der Gegenstand der Kritik?
judged Bauer’s previous ‘identification of his criticism with the struggle of the masses as
illusory’ (p. 161), but this should not, according to Moggach, be regarded as a retreat from
active political engagement. Republicanism, according to Moggach, still proposed ‘new
ways’ and ‘new goals’ to ‘transcend the liberal horizon’ (p. 162). This leads us straight to
Bauer’s distinction between a social and a political revolution. Whereas the social revolution
would eventually constitute the republican people, the merely political one, however, would
‘only liberate the atoms of mass society’ (p. 162). Bauer, therefore, develops the notion of
‘the people’ and opposes it to the idea of the masses, which meant that he advocated a much
broader revolution than a merely social or political one. This should be considered the main
reason why Marx mainly took aim at the articles in the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung and
tried to demonstrate how Bauer confused political emancipation with genuine human
emancipation. This was of, course, related to Bauer’s focus on a criticism of socialist and
communist theories after 1844 (p. 166).
An intriguing take on this debate between Moggach and Tomba stems from Stirner’s
criticism of Bruno Bauer and his subsequent reply. To understand Stirner’s assessment of
Bauer’s self-criticism in 1844, it is necessary to return to both his reviews of Bauer’s Posaune
des jungsten Gerichts and Hegel’s Lehre von der Religion und Kunst. It is regrettable, but not
surprising, that none of the past and present Bauer-scholars ever bothered to study these
texts from one of Bauer’s closest acquaintances among the post-Hegelians, and, indeed, one
of Marx’s prime targets in Die Deutsche Ideologie. The literature on Stirner itself hardly ever
mentions these texts, and merely interprets them as a bridge between Hegel and Stirner’s
alleged radicalisation of Bauer’s philosophy of self-consciousness. A study of these texts also
illuminates Bauer’s own ‘Hegelianism’. Moggach convincingly argues that Bauer’s creative
rendering of Hegelianism should not imply that Bauer attempted to be consistent with
Hegel’s own explicit intentions. Bauer did not consider Hegel an atheist, for instance, but
revised his philosophy altogether, while drawing on Hegelian elements that enabled such a
revision. Moggach thus offers a very balanced analysis, often understated in the literature
on the subject. There is, however, a very subtle sense of irony to Bauer’s approach, where
Hegel is radicalised using Hegelian elements, but it cannot and should not be confused
with Stirner’s use of irony in Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. On the contrary, Stirner
related to his criticism of both religion and the state, and, therefore, by no means a ‘small
war’ against egoism. The ‘small war’ would have been a war against egoism-as-such, whereas
the ‘big war’ was a war against everything that was related to it: a criticism of religion and
the state. His review of Bauer’s Hegel’s Lehre, on the other hand, was a full-frontal attack
against Bauer’s philosophy as a whole and was published just five months after his review of
Die Posaune. It was published in Die Rheinische Zeitung, where Bauer had published all his
writings between Die Posaune and Hegel’s Lehre.
It is hard to tell what might have caused Stirner’s shift, but it is consistent with Stirner’s
criticism of Bauer in Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. Stirner returns to Hegel’s three-fold
‘Kunst-Religion-Philosophie’ in order to attack Bauer’s criticism of religion and his
philosophy as a whole, which tried to reconcile thought and being. Stirner attacked Bauer
by claiming that art gave birth to religion by ‘satisfying the urge’ of some men ‘to split
themselves up’ between ‘that which they are’ and ‘that which they should become’ (Stirner’s
ironic use of Hegel’s ‘unhappy consciousness’).38 By satisfying man’s ‘urge’, and thus
completing the unhappy consciousness, art created an object of worship for religion.39 Man
was henceforth confronted with an object, which it tried to integrate within itself, but
failed to do.40 Bauer, on the other hand, had claimed that art was much more closely related
to philosophy based on their shared determinacy and clarity, and a common ethical root
(p. 37).41 Stirner, however, claimed that art in fact created an object for religion, and could
thus by no means be related to what he considered to be ‘philosophy’. Stirner left philosophy
out of the dialectical triad (art-religion-philosophy), by claiming that philosophy ‘doesn’t
bother itself with objects’ (religion) nor did it ‘create an object’ (art).42 It was religion itself
that ‘makes the object empty’ (through ‘reflection’) and when it was empty, art reclaimed
its object by ‘showing’ that the object was in fact empty (by turning religion into a
‘ridiculous comedy’) and that ‘man’ should no longer hold to it. In doing so, art shook off
its ‘alienation’ (religion had alienated art from its object) and could create a new object.43
In short, Stirner claimed that Bauer remained (in both Die Posaune and in Hegel’s Lehre)
stuck between art and religion, and that he endlessly created and destroyed religion, only to
recreate it anew. ‘Philosophy’, on the other hand, was something completely different in
Stirner’s account. It did not bother itself with ‘objects’, and, therefore, literally remained
‘indifferent’ to religion or ‘God’, which was ‘nothing but a stone’ to it.44 By reconciling
thought and being, Bauer only tried to solve a problem, which he had created first by
making a divide between subject and object. Stirner’s definition of ‘philosophy’ implied
that his post-Hegelian contemporaries, and Bauer in particular, were as religious as the
‘object’ they tried to criticise: religion. This argument, in a nutshell, contained a position
Stirner was to elaborate more fully in Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. Kunst und Religion
contained, as it were, Stirner’s criticism of Bauer’s ‘universal self-consciousness’ as it took
shape around 1842, while Der Einzige und sein Eigentum elaborated more fully upon its
political dimensions and its relation to the crisis.45 Stirner’s alleged ‘philosophy of egoism’
should be read as an attempt to beat Bauer with his own weapons by touching what had
become the very heart of his emancipatory project around 1843; his criticism of ‘egoism’
and ‘particularism’ as a well-established and fully integrated part of his philosophy of self-
consciousness.46 This might seem at odds with Marx’s claim that Bauer and Stirner were
two sides of the same coin, but can be elaborated further by focusing on Stirner’s remark
concerning Bauer’s 1844 writings.
Tomba is right to attach great importance to Stirner’s ‘remark’ on Bauer’s articles in the
Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung. Stirner had to return to Bauer even after finishing his book,
because of Bauer’s Was ist jetzt der Gegenstand der Kritik? Stirner claimed that Bauer had
expanded his ‘criticism’ to the state itself, which, according to Stirner, eventually came
down to the fact that Bauer ‘sees the inhuman everywhere’ except ‘in his own head’. In spite
of his ‘shift’, Bauer still clung to his ‘humanism’ and his critique of ‘egoism’, and therefore
never changed any of his ‘presuppositions’:
It may now, to conclude with this, be clear that in the critic’s new change of front
he has not transformed himself, but only ‘made good an oversight,’ ‘disentangled
a subject,’ and is saying too much when he speaks of ‘criticism criticizing itself ’;
it, or rather he, has only criticized its ‘oversight’ and cleared it of its ‘inconsistencies.’
If he wanted to criticize criticism, he would have to look and see if there was
anything in its presupposition.47
Stirner actually forced Bauer to reconsider the logical conclusions of his own theory, by
abandoning his ‘humanism’ and political engagement altogether, since it only existed ‘in
his own head’. It is no coincidence that his ‘postscriptum’ contained the clearest expression
of Stirner’s criticism of Bauer and indeed philosophy itself:
The ‘postscriptum’ thus no longer tried to ironise Bauer, and hence contains no references
to his parody of the Vergegenständlichungsdialektik [subject-object thinking]. Tomba
rightfully claims that Bauer had given up on his notion of ‘autonomy’ around 1843 and
hence his emancipatory project, but this changed very little for Stirner because he had not
yet given up on either ‘humanism’, ‘thought’ itself and his philosophy of self-consciousness
or ‘criticism’. Stirner claimed that, despite Bauer’s ‘self-criticism’ in the Allgemeine Literatur-
Zeitung, he remained trapped in his own constructions, of which, for instance, both Stirner
45. This helps to explain why Stirner continued to criticise ‘egoism’ in another article just
before Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, and claimed that it is in fact opposed to ‘self-determination’.
See Stirner’s Einiges Vorläufige vom Liebesstaat, published in 1843, just before Der Einzige und
sein Eigentum (Stirner 1986b, pp. 123–6).
46. For an analysis of Stirner’s criticism of Bauer, see De Ridder 2008, pp. 296–7.
47. Stirner 2000, p. 167; Stirner 1995, pp. 134–5.
48. Stirner 2000, p. 164; Stirner 1995, pp. 132–3.
172 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 160–174
and Tomba say that he sees ‘the inhuman’ everywhere except ‘in his own head’. Bauer thus
actually drew the logical conclusions of his ‘humanism’, according to Stirner, but ‘would
have to look and see if there was anything in its presupposition’ in the first place. Tomba
relates Stirner’s extra-philosophical stand to Bauer’s very own point of view, as expressed in
his criticism of nivellement, and brought to the fore for the very first time in his seminal text
Was ist jetzt der Gegenstand der Kritik? (1844). Stirner indeed picked up on Bauer’s criticism
of nivellement, but suggested that Bauer himself completed this by juxtaposing living
human beings to his idea of ‘man’. Stirner urged Bauer to abandon his ‘humanism’, by
seeking refuge in his own individuality against the levelling effects of the crisis.
Tomba offers an interesting insight to the developments in both Bauer and Stirner’s
writings after 1844. He argues that – despite Stirner’s criticism of Bauer – their philosophical
‘radicalism’ was very similar and dealt with the crisis. Tomba argues, for instance, that Bauer
gave up on his emancipatory project while replacing it with a ‘new history’. He understood
that he had to give up on conceptualising the present and the future and started to write a
series of historical studies, which no longer referred to his initial philosophy of self-
consciousness.49
Bauer’s review of Der Einzige und sein Eigentum might be highly illuminating in this
regard. It was actually part of Bauer’s criticism of Feuerbach, which contained both a
criticism of Stirner, as well as a very clear appropriation of Stirnerian arguments which were
directed against Feuerbach. In his review of Stirner, Bauer defended his philosophy of self-
consciousness against Stirner’s attacks, and, in fact, related Stirner to Feuerbach’s Spinozistic
reading of Hegel, thus relating Stirner to Feuerbach, just as Stirner had related Bauer
himself to Feuerbach.50 He refused to deal with Stirner’s main criticism (from the
‘postscriptum’) that ‘he tried to dissolve thought through thought itself, while only
thoughtlessness can save me from thought’. Instead, Bauer focused on Stirner’s parody of
the Vergegenständlichungsdialektik [‘egoism-ownness’]. Stirner, however, never intended to
present a ‘new’ subject-object philosophy or a new ‘solution’ to it, but tried to destroy it
altogether just as he had already tried to do in ‘Kunst und Religion’. Bauer’s review confirms
that Bauer still clung to his philosophy of self-consciousness, but, interestingly enough, no
longer refers to its political and social dimensions.
Conclusion
Moggach’s study focuses on Bauer’s philosophy and politics without immediately exposing
him to Marx’s virulent criticism. Marx’s criticism of Bauer was indeed of a highly polemical
nature and deliberately tried to obscure Bauer’s own philosophical project. His writings,
however, shed light on how the political implications of Bauer’s philosophy were perceived
by his contemporaries of the Vormärz.
By meticulously analysing how Bauer’s philosophy of self-consciousness was intertwined
with his republican programme, Moggach manages to correct a couple of misunderstandings
regarding, for instance, Bauer’s criticism of Jewish emancipation in Prussia or his alleged
‘subjectivism’. Other than merely amending the existing interpretations of Bauer’s work in
the Vormärz, Moggach also introduces a number of novelties, such as Bauer’s criticism of
the modern economy, etc. In order to understand the criticism of Bauer’s contemporaries,
however, I have also dealt with Massimiliano Tomba’s Krise und Kritik bei Bruno Bauer.
Tomba’s research offers a different account of Bauer’s post-Vormärz conservatism and
considers it the outcome of Bauer’s gradual abandonment of the dynamics of revolution
around 1844. Tomba’s interpretation is refreshing in that it focuses on the ways in which
crisis and criticism were intertwined in Bauer’s work. In so doing, he emphasises the broader
political implications of Bauer’s philosophy and allows us to shed new light on the criticism
of Bauer’s contemporaries. I have tried to enrich this debate by referring to the criticism of
one of Bauer’s closest acquaintances among the post-Hegelians, Max Stirner. Stirner’s
criticism is particularly interesting, because it helps to elaborate on Marx’s criticism of
Bauer in Die heilige Familie (1844). Neither Moggach nor Tomba pay any attention to
Stirner’s reviews of Bauer prior to his seminal work Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. This is
not surprising, since these reviews are generally considered a prelude to Stirner’s alleged
‘radicalisation’ of Bauer’s ‘subjectivism’. Moggach and Tomba both successfully rebuke
Bauer’s alleged ‘subjectivism’. Such an interpretation of Bauer is confirmed by Stirner’s
criticism around 1844. His earlier reviews, however, reveal that Stirner had already distanced
himself from Bauer’s philosophy of self-consciousness, even before Bauer’s rather
controversial stands regarding Jewish emancipation in Prussia. This means that Stirner’s
seminal work should be considered as dealing primarily with the social and political
bearings of Bauer’s philosophy. This is particularly important when dealing with Bauer’s
writings for the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, which, according to Tomba, contained Bauer’s
farewell to the dynamics of revolution. Stirner returned to these writings even after
completing his book, but interprets Bauer’s contempt for the masses as the completion of
his ‘humanism’ and ‘criticism’. Bauer finally sees the ‘inhuman’ everywhere except in ‘his
own head’, without, however, giving up entirely on thought or humanism as such. Stirner’s
criticism seems to confirm that Bauer still clung to his philosophy of self-consciousness
around 1844, but adds fuel to Tomba’s interpretation in that it no longer focuses on Bauer’s
emancipatory project, but still attacks his philosophical pretensions and presuppositions.
Bauer’s review of Stirner, on the other hand, defended his own philosophy of self-
consciousness without referring to its emancipatory implications either. In short, Moggach’s
study should be read back-to-back with Tomba’s when studying the older Bauer’s
conservatism, for their debate is, among other things, crucial to an understanding of Marx’s
criticism of both Bauer and post-Hegelianism in general. Both Moggach’s and Tomba’s
work are essential for understanding Marx’s early writings and the gradual shaping of
historical materialism as a defensive mechanism against the philosophical and political
pretensions of his contemporaries.
References
Bauer, Bruno 1842, Hegel’s Lehre von der Religion und Kunst: Von dem Standpuncte des Glaubens
aus Beurtheilt, Leipzig: Wigand.
174 Review-Articles / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 160–174
FLN’s official organ, El Moudjahid, essays billions of people into extreme poverty, hun-
from which were compiled in two further vol- ger and suffering.
umes: A Dying Colonialism (1959) and Toward The concept of ‘psychic violence’ is used to
the African Revolution (posthumously, 1964). comprehend the mechanisms through which
In addition to his political work, he simulta- racism and colonialism debase their victims to
neously undertook medical duties at seven dif- such an extent that they begin to doubt their
ferent locations in Tunis and regularly travelled own value as human beings, accepting and
to guerrilla-camps on the Moroccan and Tuni- internalising their inferiority. The dominant
sian borders to give medical training and treat culture denigrated the language, the religion,
the wounded. Once, seriously injured by a the social mores, the very biological-genetic
land-mine, he was sent to Rome for medical composition of the conquered people. The
care and narrowly escaped two assassination- colonised were declared to be mere savages,
attempts. Diagnosed with leukaemia, he died sub-humans, dependant upon the conqueror
in December, 1961, just weeks after the publi- for tutelage and protection from themselves.
cation of The Wretched of the Earth. Deprived of his or her very humanity and self-
respect, the dominated person internalised a
2. Theory of Violence. – It was Fanon’s dis- sense of shame and disgrace – the self-hatred
cussion in The Wretched of the Earth of the role of the colonised. In Fanon’s view, the black
of violence in the anticolonial revolution that man internalised the idea that the more he
was by far the most controversial aspect of his adopted the cultural standards and language
political theory. What is often ignored is his of the white man, the closer he would come to
differentiation of the concept of violence, into being a real (‘civilised’) human being. In order
immediately physical, structural and psychic to achieve an approximation of whiteness, he
violence. In particular, the context of his reflec- must denounce his own blackness. (cf. ‘The
tions has sometimes been neglected: namely, Negro and Language’ and ‘The Fact of Black-
the extent of French barbarism in Algeria. ness’ in Black Skin, White Masks and ‘Con-
During the first four decades (1830–70) of cerning Violence’ in The Wretched of the Earth).
colonialism, an estimated one-third of the For Fanon, the moment in which the
Muslim population was eliminated; in 1945, ‘native’ rejects his humiliation, his de-human-
40,000 people were massacred in less than a isation, his self-hatred, is the moment in which
month at Sétif alone. During the years of the the revolution actually begins. Only through a
liberation struggle (1954–62), over one million radical claim of self-love could the disease of
Algerians, overwhelmingly non-combatants, self-hatred be expunged. This self-redemption
were killed; nearly 12 % of the population. By and self-purification could be accomplished
comparison, fewer than 12,000 French lost by an uncompromising will toward action,
their lives during the entire war and of these, which Fanon chose to call violence. Fanon’s
9,000 were soldiers (Humbaraci, 2–55). In conceptualisation of human renewal is, in cer-
this context of massive French brutality, the tain respects, an extension of that position
use of physical violence to liberate the country that Marx and Engels formulate in The Ger-
was seen by Fanon as legitimate and morally man Ideology, where they argue that both ‘for
justifiable, though he did not hesitate to warn the production on a mass scale of this com-
in the penultimate chapter of The Wretched of munist consciousness, and for the success of
the Earth of the dangers inherent in a reliance the cause itself, the transformation of men on
on mere physical violence. a mass scale is necessary, a transformation
Fanon employs the concept of ‘structural’ which can only take place in a practical move-
violence to describe the existing international ment, in a revolution’ (MECW 5, 52–3; trans.
capitalist system. The expansion of Europe modified).
into Africa, Asia and the Americas over the Fanon argues that this lost humanity can
previous 500 years had created a global system only be recovered through an absolute and
of exploitation so rapacious that it forced uncompromising rejection of the entire con-
W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182 177
cept of – external and internal – colonialism: Marxist and psychological categories (Gend-
its cultural values, its political principles, its zier, 199). Caute says simply that he was not
economic system. The more or less spontane- a ‘traditional’ Marxist (Caute, 76). Jinadu
ous assertion of one’s self-worth alone cannot considers Fanon to be broadly within the
carry through a permanent transformation. It Marxist-Leninist tradition ( Jinadu, 98), while
must be accompanied by organised resistance Woddis, an orthodox Communist, rebukes
(Chapter 2, ‘Spontaneity: Its Strengths and Fanon as a Third-World upstart who was not
Weaknesses’). Organisation, in its turn, cre- sufficiently appreciative of socialism’s Euro-
ates obstacles as the movement toward a col- pean origins, and insists that he had no under-
lective national liberation is in danger of standing of Marxism (Woddis, 173). Geismar
falling under the domination of particular ele- argues that his concept of Communism was
ments, using nationalist slogans, who establish not that of joining a party, but of joining a
themselves in the name of the nation as a post- revolution (Geismar, 19).
colonial ‘state class’ and instrumentalise the In fact, Fanon was influenced by and
revolution for their own narrow class-interests. engaged in the non-Communist, Marxist Left
during his student days. His antipathy toward
3. Nationalism and the culture of liberation. – the PCF had two sources: first, the Party’s
Differently from the majority of the chief fig- dedication to a chauvinist conception of
ures of African nationalism he met in recently French civilisation led it, at best, to vacillate
independent Ghana in 1960 as a FLN-repre- on the colonial question and, at worst, to out-
sentative, Fanon pointed to the necessity of a right racism; second, the rigidly hierarchical,
dialectical relation of national liberation with ‘Leninist’ form of party-organisation was at
internationalism: the national consciousness distinct odds with Fanon’s democratic con-
that needed to be created, in order for it not to ception of a socialist party.
turn into a new form of domination, must be Nevertheless, Fanon was deeply influenced
articulated internationally. Aimed both against by Marxism, which is attested to not only by
‘progressives’ who claimed that an emphatic the repeated use of Marxian categories and the
emphasis upon nationality corresponded to an explicit and implicit references to Marx and
obsolete stage of human development as well Engels. Even more decisive is the fact that
as against autocratic nationalists, Fanon saw Fanon argues that ‘Marxist analysis should
the most urgent tasks of the African intellec- always be slightly stretched every time we have
tual in the development of his nation, but to do with the colonial problem’ (Fanon
which would only be able to represent the 1961, 5). ‘Classical’ Marxism, whose treat-
expressive will of the people if it were accom- ment of race and nationality as mere epiphe-
panied by the discovery and creation of uni- nomena concealed a Eurocentric approach,
versalising values. Here, Fanon’s concept of had not been able to do that.
‘culture’ is decisive: ‘If culture is the expression
of national consciousness, I will not hesitate to 5. ‘Race’ and ‘class’. – Central to Fanon’s
affirm that in the case with which we are deal- analysis of the colonial social formation was
ing it is the national consciousness which is the phenomenologically comprehended con-
the most elaborate form of culture. [. . .] It is at cept of race, of being the other. One’s skin
the heart of national consciousness that inter- colour was an inescapable badge of subordina-
national consciousness lives and grows. And tion that determined the black person’s exist-
this two-fold emerging is ultimately the source ence and forced him to accept his own
of all culture’ (Fanon 1961, 199). inferiority. Consequently, the simplistic trans-
ferral to the colonies of class-categories devel-
4. Fanon and Marxism. – Biographers differ oped in the European context and appropriate
regarding their assessment of Fanon’s relation to an understanding of industrial societies that
to Marxism. Gendzier, for example, argues were racially relatively homogenous was a sig-
that Fanon’s writing fluctuated between nificant intellectual error because it ignored
178 W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182
the racial-national dimension (and could, in the colonised population into four classes: the
turn, lead to negative political consequences). peasant-majority, the large and growing lumpen-
Fanon’s saw the chief contradiction of colo- proletariat, the tiny full-time working class
nial societies as that of race; those who ruled and the national middle class.
were those who came from elsewhere, those The perspective of the colonial or postcolo-
who declared themselves as belonging to a nial reality required a revision of the Eurocen-
superior species. The essential criterion of tric dogmas canonised by Marxism-Leninism.
their right to rule was not based on their own- The typical African colony was a vast sea of
ership of capital, but on their belonging to a impoverished peasants surrounding relatively
particular race. ‘When you examine at close small islands of urbanisation. African cities
quarters the colonial context, it is evident that were not areas of industrial production, but
what parcels out the world is to begin with the primarily administrative centres whose task
fact of belonging to or not belonging to a was to supervise the extraction of wealth in the
given race, a given species. In the colonies the form of agricultural and mineral products.
economic substructure is also a superstructure. Third-World Marxists, following the ‘Leninist’
The cause is the consequence; you are rich model, argued that, despite its minuscule size,
because you are white, you are white because the leading revolutionary class must be the
you are rich’ (Fanon 1961, 5). working class under the leadership of a prole-
Fanon therefore did not simply ignore class tarian party. The peasantry was seen as a neces-
as an analytical category. His argument was sary, but subordinate ally.
that, in the colonies, class and race had a sym- The minuscule colonial working class, while
biotic relationship; the latter was dominant, nationalist, was not particularly revolutionary.
but only insofar as colonialism continues. In They were relatively well off compared to the
The Wretched of the Earth, Fanon makes it peasantry and the lumpenproletariat and more
clear that, with independence, the barriers to interested in preserving and increasing their
socialism are no longer racially determined, existing privileges than they were in funda-
and the revolution must be transformed into a mental revolutionary change. In this context,
social (class-) revolution. In Fanon’s view, the Fanon deployed the theory of the ‘labour aris-
colonial society in transition had two alterna- tocracy’ developed by Engels and then later
tives: either it could make a total break with Lenin. With his use of the term ‘working
imperialism and begin the construction of class’, Fanon was explicitly referring to only a
socialism based on a thoroughly humanist- small minority of all those engaged in wage-
democratic programme that addressed the labour; those with regular, relatively skilled,
political, spiritual, cultural as well as the eco- relatively well paid, full-time employment
nomic needs of the broad masses; or it could (ibid.). He was not referring to the thousands
sink into being a neocolonial appendage of of migrant workers, casual and day-labourers,
world-capitalism that would keep the people workers on white farms, nor the masses of per-
in bondage. The alternative chosen would be sonal and household-servants. In the typical
determined by the configuration of class- African colony, these latter groups of workers
forces as they were formed during the colonial constituted 95% of the wage-earning class. In
period but, more importantly, as these forces order to designate this majority, Fanon refor-
were influenced and re-shaped morally and mulates the concept of ‘lumpenproletariat’
politically by the struggle for independence. that had been negatively deployed by Marx
and Engels – motivated in part by the inten-
6. Social analysis. – In Fanon’s model, colo- tion to provoke the French Left, whose cow-
nial society was divided into two racial groups ardice and arrogance on the question of
that were simultaneously expressed in five Algerian independence he despised.
class-categories. At the summit of this pyra- Fanon clearly does not conceive of the
mid the dominant race and the dominant lumpenproletariat in the European sense; as a
class were interchangeable terms. He divided marginalised minority, what Marx called a
W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182 179
social scum made up of vagabonds and thieves. standing the nature of this class and how it
Rather, Fanon’s lumpenproletariat was made would function when in power.
up of peasants recently deprived of their land
who had migrated to the urban areas in search 7. Revolution, party, democracy. – Fanon’s
of work and survival (sometimes he refers to theory of revolution departed significantly
this class simply as a fraction of the peasantry). from Lenin’s model of the vanguard-party. He
It was in the lumpenproletariat that social emphasises the significance of the radical
rebellion would find its ‘urban spearhead of intelligentsia and particularly its ability to
the revolution . . . one of the most spontaneous bring leadership to the spontaneously revolu-
and the most radically revolutionary forces of tionary masses. In Fanon’s model, however,
a colonized people’ (Fanon 1961, 81). the radical intelligentsia, while providing the
Fanon’s analysis of the ‘national middle initial leadership, also learns from and becomes
class’ or ‘national bourgeoisie’ is his most as one with the masses. Fanon’s idea of radical
important and most prophetic contribution to leadership means that as the exploited classes
an understanding of postcolonial society. as a whole experience revolutionary politics
Fanon was referring to that portion of the they also gain the knowledge and skills to exer-
colonised population who had benefitted from cise self-leadership. The party, consequently,
a European education and were engaged as develops a completely different internal organ-
small businessmen, doctors, lawyers, teachers isational culture. It becomes a mass, radical
and employees within the colonial bureauc- and democratic movement in which the ‘grass
racy. The upward mobility of this class was roots’ feel power in their newly found self-
also inhibited by the racism inherent in colo- confidence, in their ability to participate in
nial society. Consequently, they were the first decision making and to determine the direc-
to begin organised nationalist agitation and tion of the revolution they are creating –
assumed the leadership of the emergent a concept clearly marked by Luxemburg’s
nationalist organisations that began demand- influence.
ing independence. Fanon saw this class, Having theorised his ideal party, Fanon
however, not as a potential revolutionary lead- embarks on a devastating criticism of the one-
ership, but as one whose primary interest was party state. He was referring not only to dan-
in assuming positions of political and eco- gers he saw inherent in the evolving
nomic dominance that would be available contemporary politics of the African revolu-
upon independence. Their interest was in tak- tion. His scathing reference to ‘that famous
ing the place of the Europeans in the colony, dictatorship whose supporters believe is called
and then serving as middle-men, mere busi- for by the historical process’ (Fanon 1961,
ness-agents of European capitalism. The colo- Chapter 3; trans. modified) is an unmistakable
nial middle class demanded the nationalisation allusion to the ‘Leninist’ concept of the prole-
of various sectors of the postcolonial economy, tarian dictatorship and democratic centralism.
not in the interest of the new nation as a ‘The incoherent mass of the people is seen as a
whole, but to gain control of the postcolonial blind force that must be continually held in
state to advance its own interests. To accom- check either by mystification or by the fear
plish this, they were perfectly willing to act as inspired by the police force’ (ibid.). Leader-
subordinates of international capitalism and ship gains its possible ‘value and strength only
continue the exploitation of the people as it from the existence of the people in struggle. It
had existed under colonialism. is literally the people who freely fashion a lead-
It is important to realise that Fanon wrote ership for itself, not the leadership that toler-
his analysis of the emergent national middle ates the people’. Similarly, Fanon undertakes a
class in early 1961: that is, at a time when it critique of the ‘cult of personality’: ‘The leader
was only assuming power and the euphoria of the people no longer exists today. The peo-
surrounding independence was nearly unani- ple are no longer a herd; they do not need to
mous. Fanon was virtually alone in under- be led. If the leader drives me on, then he
180 W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182
should know that at the same time I show him work of cultural destruction (36 et sq.). Nev-
the way’ (ibid.). ertheless, Fanon believed that the conflict
Fanon argues, in a way reminiscent of both between men and women could find its reso-
Luxemburg and Kautsky, that, in a one-party lution in the context of the revolutionary
state, free and democratic political life is grad- struggle, which itself requires changes in the
ually stifled so that eventually only the party- female-male relationship. The success of the
bureaucracy makes decisions. The single party revolution required the active participation of
is content to give orders and remind the peo- women, as a consequence of which the veil
ple constantly that the government expects lost its inviolability. The liberation-struggle
from them only ‘obedience and discipline’ thus, ultimately, led to entirely new perspec-
(ibid.). Socialism, in order to exist, must also tives in the relations between men and women
incorporate a free and democratic political and to the breakup of the traditional mono-
life: ‘the choice of a socialist regime, a regime lithic family. The historical process had pro-
which is clearly oriented toward the will of the duced conditions wherein men and women
people as a whole and based on the principle were changed and, in turn, were forced to
that man is the most precious of all posses- change conditions. – The outcome of the
sions, will allow us to go forward more quickly revolution in postcolonial Algeria, however,
and harmoniously, and thus make impossible turned out to be quite different from Fanon’s
that caricature of society where all political utopian vision (cf. Humbaracci 1966; Scheil
power is held in the hands of a few’ (ibid.). 1969).
That epigones of Marxist-Leninist ortho-
doxy quite clearly understood the implications 9. During his lifetime, Fanon was little
of Fanon’s thinking explains the virulence of known outside the ambit of the French left-
the attacks against him as well as the severe wing intelligentsia and the Algerian Revolu-
restrictions on access to his work. In the GDR, tion. This changed dramatically with the 1963
for example, Fanon’s writings were only pub- English translation of The Wretched of the
lished in 1986 (more than 20 years after they Earth. Translations of his other works into
were published in the BRD) and, even then, English as well as other languages followed
in a severely truncated form. shortly after. His fame spread in the political
context of the mid-sixties, a high point of
8. The woman question. – References to the revolutionary optimism in the Third World.
women’s struggle are found throughout In the United States the civil-rights movement
Fanon’s work, but he devotes particular atten- had become a potent political force, while,
tion to the question in A Dying Colonialism throughout Western Europe and North Amer-
(1958). His points of departure are the veil ica, the New Left was posing a challenge both
(Chapter 1) and the family (Chapter 3) and to bourgeois capitalism and state-socialism.
the ways in which the meaning and structure In this situation, there developed a sort of
of these were changed by the revolutionary proxy-war around and over Fanon’s theses. In
experience. Traditionally, the Algerian woman the United States, the centre of the ‘Fanon
had been completely dominated by men: controversy’, the assault was undertaken by an
father, husband, brother. The veil had been amalgam of liberals, social democrats and
one of the most significant symbols of that some orthodox Communists, with the goal of
domination, but colonialism itself had trans- maintaining ideological and political control
formed the symbolic meaning of the veil. over the activists in the new progressive move-
French colonial policy was predicated on the ments, who referred to Fanon, alongside other
destruction of Algerian culture and, in part, figures.
this necessitated gaining control over Algerian Both sides concentrated their attention on a
women (Fanon 1958, 35–67, 99–120). To very narrow interpretation of Fanon’s theory of
this end, the French discouraged wearing the violence. Critics charged Fanon with revelling
veil, in order to make women ‘allies’ in the in bloodshed, advocating a Sorelian fascism
W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182 181
and having an almost Satanic influence over there has been a marked increase in Fanon
young radicals. The best known of these critics studies, particularly in the United States, but
was the philosopher, Hannah Arendt. In On also in Africa, the Caribbean, Britain and, to a
Violence, a diatribe tinged with racism against lesser extent, in Latin America. (E. Hansen,
the New Left and the revolts of the (in her Onwuanibe, Bulhan, Jinadu and Sekyi-Otu).
eyes, unqualified both socially and intellectu- Fanon’s writings have also influenced Third-
ally) African-Americans, she argued that the World women’s studies. African (as well as
influence of Fanon was responsible for endan- West-Indian and African-American) writers
gering social peace. While polemicising against have acknowledged his influence on their fic-
Fanon’s supposed glorification of violence tion (Lazarus). The Wretched of the Earth and
(Arendt, 14–20, 65–96), she downplayed Black Skin, White Masks came to be regarded
both the ‘naked violence’ of the colonial pow- by literary theorists as important examples of
ers as well as the role of violence in American modern protest-literature. – The collapse of
history, above all, violence directed against state-socialism has also led to a re-evaluation
humans with dark skin. Finally, she utterly of Fanon’s views on the revolutionary party in
failed to see the violence of a brutal, racist war light of democratic theory and the failure of
the United States was then waging against the the ‘Leninist’ proletarian dictatorship (Gordon).
Vietnamese people. – Most of Fanon’s defend- Fanon’s thoughts on the symbiotic relation-
ers contented themselves with revolutionary ship of race, ethnicity, gender and class become
posturing. Only a few interventions, often by even more relevant the more the multiracial,
African-American intellectuals, attempted to multi-ethnic and multicultural nature of
analyse Fanon within the context of his over- Euro-American societies is widely recognised.
all work. However, it was generally the anti-
Fanon critics who published their views in Bibliography: H. Arendt 1969, On Violence,
widely read journals and, therefore, domi- New York; P. Bouvier 1971, Fanon, Paris; H.A.
nated the debate. The consequence was that Bulhan 1985, Frantz Fanon and the Psychology of
Fanon was politically demonised. Oppression, New York; D. Caute 1970, Fanon,
By the seventies, the epoch of the neocon- New York; F. Fanon 1952 (1967), Black Skin,
servative ‘roll-back’, Fanon played no role in White Masks, New York; F. Fanon 1958 (1965),
the political debate any longer. This occurred A Dying Colonialism, New York; F. Fanon 1961
at the very point that his prophetic analysis (2004), The Wretched of the Earth, New York;
of the state-class in postcolonial society was F. Fanon 1964 (1967), Toward the African
proving so unerring in its accuracy. A number Revolution, New York; P. Geismar 1971, Fanon,
of scholars began producing analytical bio- New York; I. Gendzier 1973, Frantz Fanon: A
graphies (Gendzier, Geismar, Caute, Perin- Critical Study, New York; L.R. Gordon 1995,
bam) and studies of various aspects of his Fanon and the Crisis of European Man, New York;
political and social thought (Zahar, E. Hansen, L.R. Gordon et al. 1996, Fanon: A Critical
Onwuanibe, Bouvier, Lucas, McCulloch). Reader, Oxford; E. Hansen 1977, Frantz Fanon:
Social and Political Thought, Columbus, Ohio;
These studies gave impetus to a return to
W.W. Hansen 1996, Frantz Fanon, Mainz;
Fanon’s work for insights regarding the nature
A. Humbaraci 1966, Algeria: A Revolution that
of neocolonialism, of continuing racism, of
Failed, New York; L.A. Jinadu 1986, Fanon:
corrupt dictatorships and the deterioration of In Search of the African Revolution, London;
the state in the Third World. A new genera- N. Lazarus 1990, Resistance in Postcolonial Afri-
tion of African intellectuals who were trying can Fiction, New Haven; P. Lucas 1971, Sociolo-
to analyse the disintegration of their own soci- gie de Frantz Fanon, Algiers; J. McCulloch
eties not only developed a far deeper under- 1983, Black Soul, White Artifact: Fanon’s Clinical
standing of Fanon’s writing on violence, but Psychology and Social Theory, Cambridge; K. Marx
also gave much needed attention to his and F. Engels 1975–2005, Marx Engels Collected
thoughts on democracy, the party and the Works (MECW), London; R.C. Onwuanibe
postcolonial state. Since the mid-eighties, 1983, A Critique of Revolutionary Humanism:
182 W. W. Hansen / Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 175–182
Frantz Fanon, St. Louis; B.M. Perinbam 1982, revolution, relations of force, self-organisation,
Holy Violence: Fanon, An Intellectual Biography, slavery/slave-holding society, state-class, Third
Washington DC.; C.J. Robinson 1983, Black World, transitional societies, universalism, West-
Marxism: The Making of the Black Radical Tradi- ern Marxism, woman question, working class,
tion, London; A. Sekyi-Otu 1997, Fanon’s Dia- vanguard, violence.
lectic of Experience, Cambridge, MA.; J. Woddis
1972, New Theories of Revolution, New York; Antikolonialismus, Arbeiteraristokratie, Arbe-
U. Wolter 1999, ‘Algerien entschleiert. Frantz iterklasse, Avantgarde, Bauern, Befreiung,
Fanon in der feministisch-postkolonialen Debatte’,
Black Marxism, Bündnispolitik, Chauvinis-
in iz3w, Nr. 235, 34–7, and Nr. 236, 37–41;
mus, Demokratie/Diktatur des Proletariats,
R. Zahar 1969, Kolonialismus und Entfremdung,
demokratischer Zentralismus, Dritte Welt,
Frankfurt/M.
Entkolonialisierung, Entwicklungsländer,
Ethnozentrismus, Eurozentrismus, Frauen-
frage, Führung, Gewalt, Graswurzelrevolu-
William W. Hansen tion, Hauptwiderspruch, Ideal, Imperialismus,
Internationalismus, islamischer Sozialismus,
Alliance-politics, anticolonialism, Black Marxism, Kaderpartei, Klasseninteressen, Klassenreduk-
cadre-party, chauvinism, chief contradiction, city/ tionismus, Kleinbürger, koloniale Produk-
country, class-interests, class-reductionism, colo- tionsweise, Kolonialismus, Kräfteverhältnisse,
nialism, colonial mode of production, cultural Kulturrevolution, Linksradikalismus, Lumpen-
revolution, cult of personality, decolonisation, proletariat, Luxemburgismus, Marxismus-
democracy/dictatorship of the proletariat, demo- Leninismus, Massen, Massenintellektueller,
cratic centralism, developing countries, ethno- Menschenwürde, Mittelschichten, nationale
centrism, Eurocentrism, grassroots-revolution, Befreiung, nationale Bourgeoisie, nationale
human dignity, ideal, imperialism, international- Identität, Nationalismus, Neokolonialismus,
ism, Islamic socialism, labour-aristocracy, leader- Neue Linke, neuer Mensch, Orthodoxie, Per-
ship, left radicalism, liberation, lumpenproletariat, sonenkult, Populismus, postkolonialer Sozial-
Luxemburgism, Marxism-Leninism, masses, mass ismus, Rasse und Klasse, Rassismus, Revolution,
intellectual, middle classes, nationalism, national Selbstorganisation, Sklaverei/Sklavenhalterges-
bourgeoisie, national identity, national libera- ellschaft, Staatsklasse, Stadt/Land, Übergangs-
tion, neocolonialism, New Left, new man, ortho- gesellschaften, Universalismus, westlicher
doxy, peasantry, petty bourgeoisie, populism, Marxismus.
postcolonial socialism, race and class, racism,
Historical Materialism 19.2 (2011) 183–184 brill.nl/hima
Notes on Contributors
Stefano Azzarà is Research Fellow at the University of Urbino. His publications include
Politica, progetto, piano. Livio Sichirollo e Giancarlo De Carlo a Urbino 1963–1990
(Cattedrale, 2009) and Pensare la rivoluzione conservatrice. Critica della democrazia e «grande
politica» nella Repubblica di Weimar (La Città del Sole, 2000; enlarged edition, 2004).
[email protected]
Bill Bowring is Professor of Law at Birkbeck College, University of London, a practising
barrister, and International Secretary of the Haldane Society of Socialist Lawyers. His most
recent publications include The Degradation of the International Legal Order: The
Rehabilitation of Law and the Possibility of Politics (Routledge Cavendish, 2008), ‘The
Russian Constitutional System: Complexity and Asymmetry’ in Asymmetric Autonomy and
the Settlement of Ethnic Conflicts, edited by Marc Weller and Katherine Nobbs (University
of Pennsylvania Press, 2010) and ‘ “Terrorist Lists” and Procedural Human Rights: A
Collision between UN Law, EU Law and Strasbourg Law?’ in Rights in Context: Law and
Justice in Late Modern Society, edited by Reza Banakar (Ashgate, 2010).
[email protected]
Vivek Chibber teaches sociology at New York University. He is the author of Locked in
Place: State-Building and Late Industrialization in India, (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2003), and numerous articles on economic development, Marxist theory, historical
sociology, and imperialism. He is now completing a critique of postcolonial theory, to be
published by Verso Books.
[email protected]
Ben Fine is Professor of Economics at the School of Oriental and African Studies, University
of London. His recent publications include Theories of Social Capital (Pluto Press, 2010)
and, in collaboration with Dimitris Milonakis, From Political Economy to Economics
(Routledge, 2008) and From Economics Imperialism to Freakonomics (Routledge, 2009).
[email protected]
Bue Rübner Hansen is a PhD student at the School of Business and Management, Queen
Mary, University of London.
[email protected]
Bill Hansen, a native of Cincinnati, Ohio, was an activist in the civil rights movement in
the sixties where he first read and became interested in Frantz Fanon. He was educated at the
universities of Maryland, SOAS London and Boston. Currently he teaches at the American
University of Nigeria, Yola where he was the founding head of the Politics Program. His
research interests have to do with identities: nationalism, race, ethnicity and religion.
[email protected]