GLENN, Paul J. Ethics PT 1, 2 Eth HO Ab
GLENN, Paul J. Ethics PT 1, 2 Eth HO Ab
GLENN, Paul J. Ethics PT 1, 2 Eth HO Ab
SYLLABUS
TLO1. RECOGNIZE THE MORALITY OF AN ACT
1. GENERAL ETHICS
1.1. HUMAN ACTS
explain the human act in itself
explain the voluntariness of human acts
explain the modifiers of human acts
a) DEFINITION OF THE HUMAN ACT
b) CLASSIFICATION OF HUMAN ACTS
i. The Adequate Cause of Human Acts.
(A) Elicited Acts: (a) Wish (b) Intention (c) Consent (d) Election (e) Use (f) Fruition
(B) Commanded Acts: (a) Internal (b) External (c) Mixed
ii. The Relation of Human Acts to Reason: (a) Good (b) Evil (c) Indifferent,
c) CONSTITUENTS OF THE HUMAN ACT
i. Knowledge ii. Freedom iii. Voluntariness.
THE VOLUNTARINESS OF HUMAN ACTS
a) KINDS OR DEGREES OF VOLUNTARINESS
i. Perfect and Imperfect ii. Simple and Conditional iii. Direct and Indirect iv. Positive and Negative
v. Actual, Virtual, Habitual, and Interpretative.
b) INDIRECT VOLUNTARINESS
i. When is the agent (doer, actor, performer) responsible for the evil effect of a cause directly
willed? ii. When may one perform an act, not evil in itself, which has two effects, one good, one
evil?
THE MODIFIERS OF HUMAN ACTS
a) IGNORANCE
i. IGNORANCE IN ITS OBJECT: (a) Ignorance of Law (b) Ignorance of Fact (c) Ignorance of Penalty
ii. IGNORANCE IN ITS SUBJECT: (a) Vincible Ignorance (b) Invincible Ignorance
iii. IGNORANCE IN ITS RESULTS (a) Antecedent Ignorance (b) Concomitant (c) Consequent Ignorance
FIRST to FOURTH PRINCIPLES (on ignorance
b) CONCUPISCENCE: antecedent; consequent
FIRST to THIRD PRINCIPLES (concupiscence)
c) FEAR
PRINCIPLE (fear)
d) VIOLENCE
PRINCIPLE (violence)
e) HABIT
PRINCIPLE (habit)
1.2. THE ENDS OF HUMAN ACTS
explain ends in general
explain the ultimate end of human acts
a) DEFINITION OF END
b) CLASSIFICATION OF ENDS
i. The end of act, and the end of the agent ii. Proximate and remote ends iii. Intermediate and
ultimate ends
THE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
a) THE OBJECTIVE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
b) THE SUBJECTIVE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
i. Kinds of Happiness: natural; natural happiness; supernatural ii. The Nature of Man’s Desire for
Happiness iii. The Manner in which Happiness is to be Possessed
2. SPECIAL ETHICS
2.1. INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 9HRS
2.1.1. RIGHTS AND DUTIES 135
explain individual ethics in rights and duties
2.1.2. MAN’S PERSONAL OFFICE 170
explain the duties of man towards his soul and his body
ASSESSMENT PLAN
FACULTY-IN-
WEE
COURSE OUTCOME TOPIC (HRS) DATE CHARGE FOR
K NO.
COA
1-9 CO1. recognize the 1. GENERAL ETHICS (27) Week 6 SAJOR, EB
morality of an act. 1.1. HUMAN ACTS 2019.09.09-
1.2. THE ENDS OF HUMAN ACTS 13
1.3. THE NORMS OF HUMAN ACTS
1.4. THE MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS
(IN MIDTERM)
1.5. THE PROPERTIES AND
CONSEQUENCES OF HUMAN ACTS
Week 9
Midterm Examination 2019.09.30-
10.04
10-18CO2. give 2. SPECIAL ETHICS (27) Week 15 SAJOR, EB
justification to a 2.1. INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 2019.11.25-
decided action 2.1.1. RIGHTS AND DUTIES 29
taken to be morally 2.1.2. MAN’S PERSONAL OFFICE
good or bad. 2.2. SOCIAL ETHICS
2.2.1. FAMILY
2.2.2. NATION
2.2.3. GLOBAL COMMUNITY
Week 18
Final Examination 2019.12.09-
13
1. DEFINITION
ETHICS is the practical science of the morality of human conduct.
a) Ethics is a science. It is a relatively complete and systematically arranged body of
connected data together with the causes or reason by which these data are known to be true.
Ethics squares with this definition, for it is a complete and systematically arranged body of data
which relate to the morality of human conduct; and it presents the reasons which show these
data to be true. Ethics is therefore a science.
b) Ethics is a practical science. If the data of a science directly imply rules or directions
for thought or action, the science is called practical. If the data of a science enrich the mind
without directly implying rules or directions, the science is called speculative. A speculative
science presents truths that are to be known; a practical science presents truths that are to be
acted upon. A speculative science enlarges our knowledge and enhances our cultural
equipment; a practical science gives us knowledge with definite guidance. Now the science of
Ethics presents data which directly imply and indicate directions for human conduct. Ethics is
therefore a practical science.
c) Ethics is a science of human conduct. By human act we mean only such human
activity as is deliberate and free. A deliberate and free act, an act performed with advertence
and motive, an act determined (i.e., chosen and given existence) by the free will, is called a
human act. Acts performed by human beings without advertence, or without the exercise of
free choice, are called acts of man, but they are not human acts in the technical sense of that
expression which is here employed. Ethics treats of human acts; human acts make human
conduct: Ethics is therefore a science of human conduct.
d) Ethics is the science of the morality of human conduct. Human conduct is free,
knowing, deliberate human activity. Such activity is either in agreement or disagreement with
the dictates of reason. Now the relation (agreement or disagreement) of human activity with
the dictates of reason is called morality. Ethics studies human activity to determine what it
must be to stand in harmony with the dictates of reason. Hence, Ethics deals with the morality
of human conduct.
e) The name Ethics is derived from the Greek word ethos, which means “a characteristic
way of acting.” Now the characteristic mark of human conduct is found in the free and
deliberate use of the will: in a word, this characteristic is found in human acts. Thus we perceive
that the name Ethics is suitably employed to designate the science of human acts, of human
conduct. – The Latin word mos (stem: mor-) is the equivalent of the Greek ethos. Hence we
understand why Ethics is sometimes called Moral Science or Moral Philosophy.
2. OBJECT
Every science has a Material Object and a Formal Object.
The Material Object is the subject-matter of the science: the thing, or things, with which
the science deals. The Material Object of Ethics is human acts, that is to say, human conduct.
The Formal Object of a science is the special way, aim, or point of view that the science
employs in studying or dealing with its Material Object. Now Ethics studies human acts (its
Material Object) to discover what these must be in order to agree with the dictates of reason.
Hence the special aim and point of view of Ethics is the right morality, or rectitude, of human
acts. We assert, then, that the Formal Object of Ethics is the rectitude of human acts.
3. IMPORTANCE
Ethics employs the marvelous faculty of human reason upon the supremely important
question of what an upright life is and must be. It is therefore a noble and important science.
Ethics furnishes the norm by which relations among men (juridical, political,
professional, social) are regulated. It shows what such relations must be, and indicates the
reasons that require them to be so. Thus, Ethics is fundamental to the sciences of Law,
Medicine, Political Economy, Sociology, etc. It is, in consequence of this fact, a very important
science.
Faulty ethical theories, as well as the lack of definite ethical principles, have been and
are still the cause of great disorders in the political and social world. This fact is apparent in
such things as Bolshevism, Nihilism, Socialism, Birth Control, Eugenics, Companionate
Marriage. Sound Ethics supplies the scientific knowledge which evidences the unworthiness
and unreason of such things. Ethics is therefore a science deserving a careful study.
4. DIVISION
Ethics has two major parts, viz., General Ethics and Special Ethics.
General Ethics presents truths about human acts, and from these truths deduces the
general principles of morality.
Special Ethics is applied Ethics. It applies the principles of General Ethics in different
departments of human activity, individual and social.
PART I
GENERAL ETHICS
The following sentence should be memorized, for it explains the sequence of this entire
Part:
Human acts, directed to their last end by law applied by conscience, are moral acts,
and as such are imputable to the agent, and beget in him habits of action.
Outline:
Chapter 1 defines human acts and classifies them. It analyzes human
acts to discover their constituent elements, and considers the things
Human acts,
that may modify them or make them less human. The Chapter is
called “Human Acts.”
Chapter 2 discusses the ends of human activity. It defines and
classifies ends in general. It determines the last end of human acts,
directed to their last
and shows that this exists as an objective thing towards which man
end
tends, and that it is attainable. The Chapter is entitled “The Ends of
Human Acts.”
Chapter 3 discusses the existence and character of the rules of action
by which human acts are directed to their last end, viz., Law and
by law applied by
Conscience. In particular, The Eternal Law, The Natural Law, and
conscience,
Positive Law are studied. The Chapter is entitled “The Norms of
Human Acts.”
Chapter 4 deals with morality. It explains the intrinsic good or evil or
human acts, and the extrinsic factors that influence or determine the
morality of such acts. Certain false doctrines in the matter of
are moral acts
objective morality are refuted. Subjective morality (i. e., the relation
of human acts to the individual conscience) is studied. The Chapter is
entitled, “The Morality of Human Acts.”
Chapter 5 discusses the properties of human acts, viz., imputability,
are imputable to the
merit, demerit. It also studies the consequences of human acts, viz.,
agent and beget
the habits called Virtues and Vices. The Chapter is entitled “The
habits.
Properties and Consequences of Human Acts.”
CHAPTER I
HUMAN ACTS
ARTICLE 1.
THE HUMAN ACT IN ITSELF
(f) Fruition: the enjoyment of a thing willed and done; the will’s act of satisfaction in
intention fulfilled.
Of the elicited acts listed, three appertain to the objective thing willed, and three to the
means of accomplishing it. Suppose the thing willed is a trip to Europe. Then:
I wish ……………………………………..
I intend ………………………….
I enjoy when accomplished ……
I consent …………………………..
I elect ………………………………………
I use my faculties ……………….
ii. The Relation of Human Acts to Reason. – Human acts are either in agreement or in
disagreement with the dictates of reason, and this relation (agreement or disagreement) with
reason constitutes their morality. On the score of their morality, or relation to reason, human
acts are:
(a) Good, when they are in harmony with the dictates of right reason;
(b) Evil, when they are in opposition to these dictates;
(c) Indifferent, when they stand in no positive relation to the dictates of reason.
Indifferent human acts exist in theory, but not as a matter of practical experience. A human act
that is indifferent in itself becomes good or evil according to the circumstances which affect its
performance, especially the end in view (or motive or purpose) of the agent.
b) INDIRECT VOLUNTARINESS
Indirect voluntariness, or voluntariness in cause, is present in that human act which is
an effect, foreseen or foreseeable, of another act directly willed.
We have seen that human acts are acts under the free control of the will. It is clear that,
since the will controls such acts, the will is responsible for them. In other words, human acts are
imputable (as worthy of praise or blame, reward or punishment) to their author.
Two supremely important ethical questions present themselves in the matters of
indirect voluntariness and imputability.
i. The First Question: When is an agent (doer, actor, performer) responsible for the evil
effect of a cause directly willed?
The agent is responsible for such an effect when three conditions are fulfilled, viz.:
(1) The agent must be able to foresee the evil effect, at least in a general way.
(2) The agent must be free to refrain from doing that which is the cause of the evil effect.
(3) The agent must be morally bound not to do that which is the cause of the evil effect.
ii. The Second Question: When may one perform an act, not evil in itself, which has two
effects, one good, one evil?
One may perform such an act when three conditions are fulfilled, viz.,
(1) The evil effect must not precede the good effect.
(2) There must be a reason sufficiently grave calling for the act in its good effect.
(3) The intention of the agent must be honest, that is, the agent must directly intend the
good effect and merely permit the evil effect as a regrettable incident or “side issue.” To explain
these conditions in detail:
(1) The evil effect must not precede the good effect.
If the evil effect comes ahead of the good effect, then it is a means of achieving the good
effect, and is directly willed as such a means. Now it is a fundamental principle of Ethics – a
clear dictate of sound reason – that evil may never be willed directly, whether it be a means or
an end to be achieved. We cannot do evil that good may come of it. The end does not justify the
means. There is no good, however great, that can justify the direct willing of evil, however
slight. If a lie – even a “harmless” lie – will save a life –even an innocent life – that lie may not be
told. Notice well that the principle here discussed requires that the evil effect do not precede the
good effect; we do not say that the good effect must precede the evil, but that the good effect
must either precede the evil or occur simultaneously with it.
(2) There must be a reason sufficiently grave calling for the act in its good effect.
If this condition be not fulfilled, there is no adequate reason for the act at all, and the act
is prohibited in view of its evil effects. The sufficiency of the reason must be determined by the
nature, circumstance, and importance of the act in question, and by the proportion this reason
bears to the gravity of the evil effects.
(3) The intention of the agent must be honest.
If the agent really wills the evil effect, there is no possibility of the act being permissible.
Direct willing of evil is always against reason, and hence against the principles of Ethics. But,
unless the agent directly wills the good effect, he is really willing the evil effect – else he has no
adequate motive for performing the act at all.
ARTICLE 3.
THE MODIFIERS OF HUMAN ACTS
By the modifiers of human acts we mean the things that may affect human acts in the
essential qualities of knowledge, freedom, voluntariness, and so make them less perfectly
human. Such modifiers lessen the moral character of the human act, and consequently diminish
the responsibility of the agent.
There are five modifiers of human acts that call for detailed study, viz., ignorance,
concupiscence, fear, violence, habit.
a) IGNORANCE
Ignorance is the absence of knowledge – and, for our purpose here, it may be defined as
the absence of intellectual knowledge in man. Ignorance is thus a negation of knowledge; it is a
negative thing. But when it is absence of knowledge that ought to be present, the ignorance is
not merely negative, but privative.
Ignorance has, indeed, a positive aspect when it consists not merely in the absence of
knowledge, but in the presence of what is falsely supposed to be knowledge. Thus, if I see a
stranger in the street, and realize that I do not know him, my ignorance of his identity is merely
negative. But if I am misled by poor eyesight or by a resemblance in the stranger, and judge him
to be a well-known acquaintance, my state of mind is positive towards him: I have what I judge
to be positive knowledge of his identity. Such positive ignorance is called mistake or error.
We are to consider ignorance in its effect upon human acts.
i. in its object, i. e., in the thing of which a person may be ignorant;
ii. in its subject, i. e., in the person in whom ignorance exists;
iii. in its result, i. e., with reference to the acts that are performed in ignorance.
i. IGNORANCE IN ITS OBJECT.
The thing of which a person may be ignorant is a matter of law, fact, or penalty.
(a) Ignorance of Law is the ignorance of the existence of a duty, rule, or regulation.
(b) Ignorance of Fact is ignorance of the nature or circumstances of an act as forbidden.
Thus, ignorance of fact is lack of knowledge that what one is actually doing comes under
the prohibition of a known law.
(c) Ignorance of Penalty is lack of knowledge of the precise sanction (i. e., an
inducement sufficient to make reasonable men obey the law) affixed to the law.
ii. IGNORANCE IN ITS SUBJECT.
In the person in whom it exists, ignorance (of law, fact, or penalty) is either vincible or
invincible.
(a) Vincible Ignorance (i. e., conquerable ignorance; ignorance that can and should be
supplanted by knowledge) is ignorance that can be dispelled by the use of ordinary diligence.
Such ignorance is, therefore, due to lack of proper diligence on the part of the ignorant person,
and is his fault. Vincible ignorance is, in consequence, culpable ignorance.
There are degrees of vincible ignorance:
If it be the result of total, or nearly total, lack of effort to dispel it, it is called crass (or
supine) ignorance.
If some effort worthy the name, but not persevering and wholehearted effort, be
unsuccessfully employed to dispel it, the ignorance is simply vincible.
If positive effort is made to retain it, the ignorance is called affected.
(b) Invincible Ignorance is ignorance that ordinary and proper diligence cannot dispel.
This sort of ignorance is attributable to one of two causes, viz.: either the person in whom the
ignorance exists has no realization whatever of his lack of knowledge, or the person who
realizes his ignorance finds ineffective his effort to dispel it. Hence, invincible ignorance is
never the fault of the person, in whom it exists, and it is rightly called inculpable ignorance.
Invincible ignorance has two degrees, viz.:
if no human effort can dispel it, it is physically invincible.
If such effort as good and prudent men would expend to dispel it – taking into account
the character and importance of the matter about which ignorance exists – is found to be
ineffective, the ignorance is called morally invincible.[1] [1] The word morally has no direct
relation in the present use of morality, but to characteristic action of men. Thus, ignorance is
morally invincible when such effort as would be truly characteristic of good and prudent men
in the circumstance, is found powerless to dispel it. In common language, ignorance is morally
invincible when it would be extremely difficult to dispel it.
iii. IGNORANCE IN ITS RESULTS.
Here we consider ignorance (of fact, law, penalty) with reference to acts performed
while ignorance exists.
(a) Antecedent Ignorance is that which precedes all consent of the will.
(b) Concomitant Ignorance is that ignorance which, so to speak, accompanies an act
that would have been performed even if the ignorance did not exist.
(c) Consequent Ignorance is that which follows upon an act of the will. The will may
directly affect it, or supinely neglect to dispel it. Thus, consequent ignorance does not differ
from vincible ignorance.
The ethical principles which emerge from our study of ignorance as a modifier of human
acts are the following:
b) CONCUPISCENCE
Concupiscence means those bodily appetites or tendencies which are called the passions,
and which are enumerated as follows: love, hatred; joy, grief; desire, aversion or horror; hope,
despair; courage or daring, fear; and anger.
We treat here of the passions in general. The passions are called antecedent when they
spring into action unstimulated by any act of the will; that is, when they arise antecedently to
the will-act.
They are called consequent when the will, directly or indirectly, stirs them up or fosters
them.
Antecedent concupiscence is an act of man, and not a human act. It is therefore a non-
voluntary act, and the agent is not responsible for it. Consequent concupiscence, however, is the
fault of the agent, for it is willed, either directly or indirectly, that is, either in itself or in cause.
The agent is, in consequence, responsible for it.
But what of the acts that come from concupiscence? We state the ethical principles in the
matter:
c) FEAR
Fear is one of the passions, and is included under the general denotation of the term
concupiscence, but it is usual to give it special mention in Ethics, because it is a very common
passion, and we should know in detail its relation to the morality of acts, and because it has a
characteristic distinctive among the passion, viz., that it usually (when it is the cause of an act)
induces the will to do what it would not do otherwise. We may, however, present the ethical
doctrine on the subject of fear in very short space.
Fear is the shrinking back of the mind from danger. More accurately, it is the agitation of
mind (ranging from slight disturbance to actual panic) brought about by the apprehension of
impending evil.
Actions may proceed from fear as their cause, or may be done with fear as an
accompanying circumstance.
PRINCIPLE (fear)
An act done from fear, however great, is simply voluntary, although it is regularly also
conditionally involuntary.
The principle speaks of an act performed from a motive of fear, an act proceeding from
fear, not an act performed with or in fear. A person may have full and unconditioned
voluntariness in that which is performed with fear,
An act performed from fear, however, great, is simply voluntary. If fear is so great as to
make the agent momentarily insane, the act done from fear is not voluntary at all, for it is an
act of man and not a human act. But as long as the agent has the use of reason, his acts
performed from fear are simply voluntary. For the agent effectively chooses to perform such an
act rather than undergo that of which he is afraid: he chooses the act as a lesser evil, and
effectively chooses it. But the act is also regularly involuntary inasmuch as the agent would not
perform it in other circumstance; were it not for the presence of an evil feared, the act would
not be performed.
The practical conclusion is this: Fear does not excuse an evil act which springs from it.
Fear does present a difficulty, but human acts are not necessarily easy acts. Still, the influence of
fear makes an act less perfectly human in character, although never to such an extent that the
agent is enabled to act humanly and still escape responsibility for his act.
The positive (“statute”) law of Church and State usually provides that an act done from
grave fear, unjustly suffered, and excited directly in order to force the agent to perform an act
that is against his will, is an invalid act or one that may be invalidated. Even though such an act
is simply voluntary, it would not be for the common good to allow an act extorted by fear to
stand as valid and binding.
d) VIOLENCE
Violence or coercion is external force applied by a free cause (i. e., by a cause with free
will; by man) for the purpose of compelling a person to perform an act which is against his will.
Violence cannot reach the will directly. It may force bodily action, but the will is not
controlled by the action, and since this command to make the bodily members offer due
resistance to violence, it concurs, insofar as such resistance is lacking, in the act done under
violence.
PRINCIPLE (violence)
Acts elicited by the will are not subject to violence; external acts caused by violence, to which due
resistance is offered, are in no wise imputable to the agent.
e) HABIT
By habit Ethics understand operative habit, which is a lasting readiness and facility, born
of frequently repeated acts, for acting in a certain manner.
PRINCIPLE (habit)
Habit does not destroy voluntariness; and acts from habit are always voluntary, at least in cause,
as long as the habit is allowed to endure.
Habit does not destroy voluntariness. The agent is fully responsible for human acts done
from what is called force of habit. Even if such acts be in themselves acts of man, the habit itself,
so long as it is not disowned, and a positive and enduring effort made to overcome it, is willed
as a human act, and its effects are voluntary in cause, and hence are human acts.
CHAPTER II
THE ENDS OF HUMAN ACTS
ARTICLE 1. END IN GENERAL
a) DEFINITION OF END
An end is both a termination and a goal. In other words, and end is that which
completes or finishes a thing, and it is that for which the thing is finished.
Every activity tends toward an end; and thus every activity is a tendency. Every tendency
may be called an appetite, or more properly, appetency.
When appetency exists without any sort of knowledge – as in plants and lifeless things –
it is called natural appetency, in a special limited, and technical sense of the term “natural.”
When appetency comes of knowledge, it is of two kinds, just as knowledge itself is of
two kinds. Appetency which is stirred into action by sensation (i. e., by knowledge acquired by
the senses) is called sense appetency or sensual appetite.
Appetency which is stirred into action by intellectual knowledge is called the will or
rational appetency. We have already learned in our study of Human Acts that the will springs
into action only when intellectual knowledge presents something desirable, satisfactory, or
simply good, to be achieved by action. Every will-act, that is, every human act, is the expression
of rational appetency or will: it is an act directed to an end known as desirable, that is to say, as
good to attain.
In Ethics we speak of the ends of human acts. Here, then, the end is that which is
apprehended as good, as desirable, and which attracts the human agent to the performance of
the act. It is the agent’s motive and reason for acting. It causes the agent to act and, insofar, the
end is the final cause of a human act – a cause called final, from the Latin word finis, which
means end. The agent is the efficient cause of his acts, for it is he that effects or performs them;
but he would not effect them were he not attracted by the end or final cause. No human act can
exist, therefore, without a final cause, that is to say, without an end apprehended by the agent
as desirable or good enough to attract the agent to action and to serve as his motive in the act.
The end or final cause of human acts must be apprehended as good. Evil cannot be
willed as such or for its own sake. Evil is done only when it assumes the aspect of good, as
something that will bring satisfaction or will lead to it.
Notice that it is a greater good that the sin is chosen. Of course, the agent’s judgment in
the matter is not sound; his sin will not lead to ultimate happiness or satisfaction, but inasmuch
as it is a judgment of the sin as good, it explains what is meant by the statement that evil is not
chosen as such, nor for its own sake, but only when it assumes the aspect of good. In our sense,
good is that which answers tendency or desire.
To define end: An end is a termination and goal of activity. In a human act the end is the
final cause, viz., that on account of which, or to attain which, the act is performed, and which is,
in consequence, apprehended as a good sufficiently desirable to motivate the agent in
performing the act.
b) CLASSIFICATION OF ENDS
Here we distinguish:
i. The end of act, and the end of the agent;
ii. Proximate and remote ends;
iii. Intermediate and ultimate ends.
i. The end of the act is the end toward which the act of its own nature tends. Thus, the
act of giving food and shelter to destitute persons tends of its nature toward the relief of
distress, and we say that the relief of distress in the end of act. –
The end of agent is the end which the agent intends to achieve by his act.
When we speak of the end in Ethics, we usually mean the end of the agent.
ii. The proximate end is the end intended as the immediate outcome of an act.
The remote end is that which the agent wishes to achieve later on, and toward the
attainment of which he employs the present act as a means.
Thus, a politician who gives money to the poor, wishes his good deed to be recorded in
the newspapers: his proximate end is favorable publicity. However, he does not desire publicity
for its own sake, but for the votes it will gain him in the coming election; and he wishes for
votes as a means to office. Thus, while publicity is his proximate end, votes and election to office
are remote ends.
iii. An end, whether proximate or remote, is willed either for its own sake or as a means
to an end more remote. If it is willed for its own sake, it is a last or ultimate end, and if it is
willed as a means to a further end, it is an intermediate end.
To illustrate:
A man gives money to the poor. He gives the money to gain favorable notice in the
newspapers (proximate and intermediate end); he wills publicity as a means to votes (remote
and ultimate end). This example shows us a chain or series of ends; and, since the ultimate end
of the series is not the general or unconditioned end of the man’s whole life and all its human
acts, but ultimate only in relation to the present series of ends, the ultimate end of the series is
called an end relatively ultimate. There must also be an end which is unconditionally and
unlimitedly the ultimate end of all human acts; and this we call the absolutely ultimate end. It
is the ultimate end which gives meaning to the intermediate ends that least to it. The
intermediate ends are subordinate to the ultimate end, just as the steps of a stairway are
subordinated to the top step. And as a man who wishes to reach the top of a stairway must take
many intermediate steps before reaching the top, but would not take any of them except to
reach the top, so in a series of ends, the agent must attain intermediate ends before achieving
the ultimate end, but he would not try to attain any of them except on account of the ultimate
end. Thus, we repeat, the ultimate end of a series of ends gives meaning and motive to the
whole series.
An ultimate end is both objective and subjective. The objective ultimate end is that
thing, that object, which, in last analysis, motivates a human act. The subjective last end
is the possession of the objective end and the satisfaction or happiness that is
apprehended as belonging to that possession.
ARTICLE 2. THE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
The ultimate end of human acts is that which, in the last analysis, serves as a
sufficient reason and motive for the acts. This end, considered as an objective thing toward
the attainment of which the acts are directed, is the objective ultimate end of human acts. The
possession of this objective end and the happiness which the agent seeks in that possession, is
the subjective ultimate end of human acts.
We have seen that a human act is always done on account of an end, and an ultimate end.
We now assert that all human acts are performed for a single absolute ultimate end.
Let us view man as a traveler standing at a point where many roads converge. The
traveler wishes to reach the City of Limitless Good. This city is the goal toward which the
traveler tends by a connatural and inevitable bent of his will. Now, the tendency of the traveler
will remain the same, even if he should choose a wrong road. In other words, man, the traveler,
will choose a road for the purpose of reaching the City of Limitless Good, even if, as a fact, the
chooses road leads away from his goal. It is obvious, then, that the reveler needs guidance; he
needs direction, lest perverse and mistaken judgment thwart his purpose and render
impossible the attainment of his goal. In a word, the traveler needs a map. More: he requires
ability to read the map, and to interpret it rightly where the road seems to fork or by ways open
invitingly. Now, the map, the guiding direction, is supplied to man, the traveler, by law; and the
application of law in individual acts – the reading and interpreting of the map at particular
curves and corners – is achieved by conscience. Human acts are directed to their true end by
law, and law is applied by conscience. Hence, law and conscience are the directives or norms of
human acts.
ARTICLE1.
LAW
a) DEFINITION OF LAW
St. Thomas defines law as an ordinance of reason, promulgated for the common
good by one who has charge of a society.
i. A law is an ordinance, i. e., an active and authoritative ordering or directing of human
acts in reference to an end to be attained by them.
ii. A law is an ordinance of reason, and not an arbitrary or whimsical decree of the
legislator’s will. A law does come from the will of the lawgiver, but from his reasonable will, that
is, from his will illumined by understanding of an end necessary or useful to be attained,
toward which the law serves as a proper direction. Hence, law must be reasonable, and this
means that it must be just, honest (not contravening a higher law), possible of fulfillment (not
exacting undue or extraordinary effort on the part of those bound by it), useful, and in some
degree permanent (not a fleeting or whimsical decree). To be reasonable, to be a true law, a law
must have all the qualities here enumerated. Besides it must be promulgated, that is, made
known to those who are bound by it. Hence, the essential qualities of a true law are these: it
must be just, honest, possible, useful, relatively permanent, and promulgated.
iii. A law is promulgated, i. e., made known to those bound by it, and these are called
subjects. This is a requirement of law as reasonable, as already explained. By promulgation a
law is put in application as an authoritative ordinance.
iv. A law is promulgated for the common good. This is the purpose of law. In this point a
law is distinguished from a precept, which is an ordinance issued by public or private authority
for the particular or private good of one or several persons. A law also differs from a precept in
the fact that a law is territorial and applies to subjects only while they are in a certain place;
while a precept is personal and binds its subjects wherever they may be. A law is always
enacted by public authority, while a precept may be issued by either public or private
authority.
Finally, a law endures in force until it is repealed by the authority that enacted it, even
though the actual persons who framed it be dead or removed from office; but a precept ceases
to bind with the preceptor’s death or removal from office.
A law, then, is for the common or public good. This is the purpose of law. Law is not
meant to impose hardship or needless restriction upon its subjects, but to promote their good,
and hence to protect and promote true liberty among them. When a law is truly a law, that is to
say, when it has all the requisite qualities of law, and is just, honest, possible, useful, relatively
permanent, and duly promulgated – then it inevitably acts as a liberating agency and not as an
enslaving one. True law tends to make men good, and tends to liberate them from the perverse
and mistaken judgments that would lead them astray in the quest for their ultimate end. The
man who accepts the direction of true law is the man who is free to attain his goal, just as the
man who accepts direction when seeking the road to a city he wishes to reach is the man who is
really free to go to that city. He who refuses direction – although he refuses, as he thinks, in the
name of freedom – is enslaved by his own liability to error. The purpose of law, therefore, is to
protect and promote true freedom among members of a society in common, by insuring the
unhampered and unthwarted exercises of free acts which will carry man forward to his proper
end.
v. A law is promulgated in a society. This is evident from the fact that law is for the
common good, and hence supposes a commonality of community of subjects; and a community
is a society. Law in the fullest sense can exist only in a perfect society, for such a society alone
has the full and perfect right to legislate (i. e., full jurisdiction) for all subjects. Now, the supreme
and perfect society in the natural order is called the State (i. e., a body of people politically
united under one government), and the supreme and perfect society in the supernatural order
is the true Church. In the fullest sense, therefore, human laws can come only from Church or
State.
vi. A law is promulgated by one who has charge of a society. By “one” is meant a
person, whether this be a single human being (physical person) or a body of men united to form
the governing power (moral person). Here we have indicated the author of law, i. e., the
lawgiver or legislator. A legislator has jurisdiction, which mean, literally, “the saying of what is
right.” One who has the just authority of “saying what is right” in a community is empowered to
enact and promulgate true laws. Almighty God is the Supreme Lawgiver, and properly
constituted human legislation has its power and authority, directly or indirectly, from God. –
The author of law enacts laws as ordinances of reason, and hence he must have a direct care
and concern about their observance. To insure observance the author of the law establishes
sanctions for law, i. e., inducements (rewards and punishments) sufficiently strong to lead
reasonable men to follow the prescriptions of the law.
b) CLASSIFICATION OF LAWS
i. According to their immediate author, laws are distinguished as divine laws, which
come directly from God (such as the Ten Commandments), and human laws, which are the
enactments of Church or State. Human laws enacted by the Church are called ecclesiastical laws,
while human laws enacted by the State are called civil laws.
ii. According to their duration, laws are temporal or eternal. The Eternal Law is
God’s plan and providence for the universe. We shall speak of this law in detail in the next
section of this Article. All human laws are in themselves temporal, although some of them give
expression to requirements of the Eternal Law.
iii. According to the manner of their promulgation, laws are distinguished as the
natural law and positive laws. The natural law, in widest sense, is that which directs
creatures to their end in accordance with their nature, and, so understood, it coincides with the
Eternal Law. Usually, however, the laws that govern irrational creatures in their being and
activities are called physical laws, while the moral law which is apprehended by sound and
matured human reason is called the natural law. In this restricted sense we shall understand
the term, the natural law; and we shall define it as the Eternal Law as apprehended by human
reason. Positive laws are laws enacted by positive act of a legislator, and these fall under the
classification already made as divine and human. Thus, the Ten Commandments are divine
positive laws, and the laws of the Church and State are human positive laws.
iv. According as they prescribe an act or forbid it, laws are affirmative or negative.
Negative laws are also called prohibitory laws. Affirmative laws bind always, but not at every
moment. Negative laws of the natural order bind always and at every moment. Thus, the law
“Thou shalt not kill,” remains continuously in force, and must be obeyed at every moment
without exception and in all circumstances.
v. According to the effect of their violation, laws are distinguished as moral (violation
of which renders the violator liable to an established penalty, but does not infect him with sin),
and mixed (violation of which involves both fault and penalty).
a) DEFINITION OF CONSCIENCE
Conscience is the practical judgment of reason upon an individual act as good and to be
performed, or as evil and to be avoided.
i. It is a judgment of reason, that is, it is a reasoned conclusion. Although the term
conscience is also used to designate the act of reasoning out the right and wrong of a situation
before choosing what to do, it is more properly employed, as in our definition, to signify the
judgment which is the conclusion of that act of reasoning. Now, an act of reasoning requires a
principle, or set of principles, which the process of reasoning proceeds. By principles we mean
things known with certainty with which we may compare new facts or proposed actions and so
discover new truths – new applications of the principles.
In matters of right and wrong, we must have moral principles to start with. We acquire
these principles, - many of them, - in early life, and when we have a workable grasp of them, we
become responsible for out conduct, we cease to be infants, and we are said to have “come to
the use of reason.” Now, this acquired equipment of moral principles is called synteresis.
Synteresis is the starting point of the reasoning process which ends in the judgment of
conscience. This reasoning process may proceed so smoothly and swiftly that we are not aware
of it as a reasoning process at all; indeed, this is ordinarily the case. Still, the process is always a
fact, if only an implicit fact. Thus, when we are confronted with a possible course of action, we
compare it mentally with our moral principles, and conclude that it is good and hence to be
done (or at least permitted), or evil and hence to be avoided.
For example:
Suppose I am face to face with a difficulty from which I might extricate myself by a
clever and fictitious explanation of my conduct. My moral reasoning goes on as follows:
ii. Conscience is a practical judgment. This means that it has reference to something to
be done, i. e., either the performance or the omission of an act. The reasoning process always
ends in a judgment, but not always in a practical judgment. It is a judgment that commands,
forbids, allows, or advises, according as it declares an individual act obligatory, prohibited,
permissible, or prudent. Conscience is a dictate.
iii. Conscience is a judgment upon an individual act, here and now, in these present
circumstances, to be performed or omitted. It is also a judgment upon an individual act after it
has been performed or omitted. But it is always an individual judgment upon an individual act;
it is not a general moral judgment or principle (for such judgments belong to syntersis), but it is
the reasoned judgment, drawn from a general principle and an individual act; it applies the
general moral principle in individual action. Before action, conscience judges an act as good and
to be performed (i. e., as something obligatory, advisable, or permissible), or as evil and to be
omitted. After action, conscience is a judgment of approval or disapproval.
b) STATES OF CONSCIENCE
i. When conscience is a judgment in accordance with fact, that is, when it judges as
good that which is really good, and as evil that which is really evil, then it is correct or true.
Strictly speaking, there is a distinction between correct conscience and true conscience, but for
practical purposes the terms may be regarded as synonymous. Conscience that is not true is
erroneous. Conscience that is erroneous without the knowledge or fault of the agent is called
invincibly erroneous or inculpably erroneous, while conscience that is erroneous through the
agent’s fault, is culpably erroneous.
ii. When conscience is an altogether firm and assured judgment, in which the agent
has no fear whatever of being in error, it is called certain conscience. Conscience, when certain,
must be obeyed, whether it be correct or invincibly erroneous. For reason demands that we
obey law as manifested with certainty by the intellect, and the dictate of certain conscience is
such a manifestation, even though the conscience be invincibly erroneous. – Conscience that is
not certain, i. e., that is hesitant, that is a judgment in which the agent is aware of the possibility
of error, is called doubtful or dubious conscience.
The agent whose conscience is dubious is said to be in doubt. If the doubt concerns the
existence or applicability of a law or moral principle, it is called speculative doubt; but if the
doubt concerns the lawfulness of an individual act to be performed or omitted, it is a practical
doubt.
It is never permissible to act while in the state of practical doubt. Such doubt must be
resolved, must be dispelled and replaced by certitude, before action can be good. To act while in
the state of practical doubt about the good or evil of an action, is to “take a chance” of the action
being evil, and is so far to approve of the action even as evil; but reason requires that evil be
positively avoided. When conscience is doubtful, but grounded upon solid reasons, it is called
probable conscience, and the agent is said to have a probable opinion. We shall discuss the
matter of probability (the doctrine of which is called probabilism) is the next section of the
present Article.
a) DESCRIPTION OF MORALITY
Morality is that quality of human acts which leads us to call some of them good and
some evil.
A thing is good inasmuch as it can answer a tendency, appetite, desire. In other words, it
is good inasmuch as it serves as an end of such tendency.
In the matter of human acts – where moral good or evil is the point in question – there is
always a last end towards which the action tends. Objectively, this is the Summum Bonum, the
Limitless Good, God. Subjectively, the last end of human acts is perfect happiness in the
possession of the Summum Bonum. Such being the end of human action, it follows that human
acts are good inasmuch as they serve to carry the agent on towards the attainment of this end,
and not good, or evil, inasmuch as they fail to lead towards the last end, or even lead away from
it.
c) DEFINITION OF MORALITY
Morality is the relation of human acts to their norm
Morality is that quality (or property) of human act whereby it measures up to
what it should be as a step towards the objective last end of human action, or fails so to
measure up. It consists therefore in the relation existing between human acts and the norm of
morality.
The morality of an act, its character as good or evil, is not a mere external denomination
or classification; it is not a mere label pasted on arbitrarily. It is something that belongs
inevitably to the human act as such, either to the act considered objectively as a deed
performed, or to the act considered as characterized by its circumstances, particularly the
circumstance called the end of the agent.
Some ethicians have placed the essence of the morality of human acts in freedom. This
doctrine is false. It is true that a human act is a free act; and, in a true sense, it is a moral act (i.
e., has morality, is right or wrong, good or evil) because it is free. But freedom does not
constitute morality. Morality is the property of a free act, that is, it is an inevitably present
characteristic of a free act. But it consists formally, as we have said, not in freedom itself, but in
the relation which the act bears toward the norm or measure of what it should be – toward the
Norm of Morality.
d) DIVISION OF MORALITY
i. Material and Formal
A human act considered in itself as a deed performed stands in relation to the Norm of
Morality as materially good or evil. A human act considered as conditioned by the agent’s
understanding and will, stands in relation to the Norm of Morality as formally good or evil.
Sometimes the terms objective and subjective are used respectively for material and formal in
this connection.
ii. Intrinsic and Extrinsic
Material or objective morality is intrinsic when the human act, as a deed performed,
stands by reason of its very nature in relation to the Norm of Morality as good or evil. Material
or objective morality is extrinsic when the stand or relation of an act to the Norm of Morality is
determined, not by the nature of the act itself, but by the prescription of positive law.
ARTICLE 2.
THE DETERMINANTS OF MORALITY
It is necessary to understand what phases of the human act may be measured by the
norm, show the act as measuring up or not measuring up to that norm; in a word, these points
determine the good or evil of the act. Hence, they are called the determinants of morality.
We list three determinants of morality, viz., (a) the act itself, i. e., the object; (b) the end of the
agent; (c) the circumstances other than the end of the agent.
A human act, to be a morally good act, must be found in agreement with the Norm or
Morality on all three points, i. e., it must be good in itself or objectively, in its end, and in its
circumstances. A human act is evil if it fails to conform with the Norm of Morality in any one of
the points or determinants.
a) THE OBJECT
By the object is meant the human act performed, the deed done. If an act as object
(i. e., in itself) is good or evil, we say that it has objective morality. If an act, considered
abstractly, is indifferent (i. e., neither good nor bad), its morality is determined by the end for
which it is performed and by the circumstances which affect it. Now certain actions are in
themselves, or objectively, good, and certain others are objectively evil: and this morality is
intrinsic, i. e., resides in the act independently of positive law prescribing or forbidding the act.
This assertion recommends itself at once to the normal mind as a true statement; yet some
moralists have denied it. It is therefore necessary to prove briefly that some acts are
intrinsically good, and some intrinsically evil.
Now those that deny the intrinsic morality of any human act must admit, as all other
men do, that there are certain acts which have always and everywhere been regarded as good,
and other which have been universally considered evil. The acceptance of these acts as
respectively good and evil is a fact to be explained. We explain it by stating the doctrine of
intrinsic morality: men have always regarded certain acts as good in themselves because, as a
matter of fact, they are good; and they have regarded others as intrinsically evil, because they
are evil.
Our opponents declare that what we call intrinsic morality is merely the result of long
established custom among men, or of special human legislation, or of the arbitrary decision of
God’s will that some acts are good and some evil.
i. Custom cannot account for the universal acceptance of some acts as good in
themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. How did the custom come into being? If as a
dictate of right reason, because all people saw that certain things were in line with their
rational desires and certain other things opposed to these, then the argument falls to nothing,
and is merely an indefinite restatement of the true doctrine that certain acts are perceived by
right reason as good and other acts as evil – in a word, that certain acts are perceived as
intrinsically good or evil. If the custom did not arise as a dictate of right reason among men,
then it arose out of circumstances. Since circumstance can be artificially arranged, it would be
possible to get current a movement to change the present moral views of men.
ii. Human legislation cannot account for the universal acceptance of some acts as good
in themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. If human legislation means law in the true
sense, then we are back in our won position, for true human law is an ordinance of reason in
line with the Eternal Law, and it exists because there really are acts good in themselves to be
prescribed, and acts evil in themselves to be forbidden. Acts are not good because true law
prescribes them; they are prescribed by law because they are good. Nor are acts evil because
true law forbids them; the law forbids them because they are evil.
Now if legislation be taken to mean, not a reasonable ordinance, but the whimsical and
arbitrary decree of a ruler or ruling body, then legislation may change the whole scheme of
morality.
iii. The arbitrary decision of God’s will cannot account for the universal acceptance of
some acts as good in themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. God is infinitely perfect;
His acts are therefore infinitely right and reasonable. Hence an arbitrary decision of the Divine
Will without reference to the Divine Reason is so impossible as to be absolutely unthinkable.
In view of the truth established – viz., that there is such a thing as intrinsic morality – we
are forced to reject many moral theories as false.
Among those so rejected we find:
i. The Theory of Moral Instinct or Moral Sense (called Moral Intuitionism or Moral
Sensualism), which asserts that we discern good and evil by a blind instinct or by a sense
faculty, and not by our understanding. We have seen that we know good and evil by the
conscience-judgment, by reason. When we do good or evil as a human act, we know, we
understand, that we are doing good or evil. Therefore, we do not act by blind instinct. Nor is our
conscience a sense-judgment. For the relation of acts to the Norm of Morality is an abstract
relation, not a material or bodily thing such as the senses require for their object.
ii. The Theory of Usefulness (called Utilitarianism), which asserts that what is discerned
as useful (to individual men or to human society) is good, and what is found harmful is evil. It is
true that good is ultimately useful, and evil harmful; but the usefulness comes from goodness,
not goodness from usefulness; and harmfulness comes from evil, not evil from harmfulness.
Certain human acts are, as we have proved, intrinsically good or evil; and hence their
usefulness or uselessness can have nothing to do with their nature. Further, the theory of
utilitarianism would make the code of morals as changeable as the stock market rates; for what
is useful (in a merely temporal and material sense) is variable and differs for times and
persons: but the Norm of Morality, to be a norm or law, must be a stable thing. Again, how
would the test of usefulness be established? Acts would have to be “tried out” first without any
rule at all to discover which acts might be listed as useful, and hence good, and which as
harmful, and hence forbidden as evil.
To sum up:
The object of a human act, the act itself as a deed done or to be done, that is, the act
considered as a fact, has often its own intrinsic morality. Even if the act be in itself indifferent, it
may have extrinsic morality, which is still objective, that is, as an object, the act may stand in
harmony or in disagreement with the prescriptions of positive moral law. Hence, in
determining whether any human act is good or evil, we look first to the object. The object is the
primary determinant of morality. If the object be evil, our quest ends there; the act is definitely
evil and forbidden; nothing can make it good. But if the act is good as an object, it may still be
vitiated by its circumstances, particularly by that circumstance called “the end of the agent.”
Hence, if we find an act good in itself as an object, we have still to look to the end of the agent
and to the other circumstances before pronouncing it good and permissible as an individual act.
c) THE CIRCUMSTANCES
Circumstances are conditions that affect an act – and may affect it morally – although
they do not belong to the essence of the act as such. In other words, circumstances are
conditions without which the act could exist, but which happen to affect or qualify it is its
concrete performance. Examples of circumstance are place, time, company, etc., in which an act
if performed.
We enumerate seven circumstances. Quis, quid, ubi, quibus auxiliis, cur, quomodo,
quando? which may be freely translated as follows:
ARTICLE 2.
THE CONSEQUENCES OF HUMAN ACTS
A man does more easily that which he has done before, and the more frequent the
repetition of an act, the easier becomes its performance. In a word, human acts tend to form
habits. Since human acts have morality, the habit of performing any human act will be a moral
habit. If it is a good moral habit, it is a virtue. If it is an evil moral habit, it is vice. Vice and virtue
are not matters of a single human act, nor of an act once or twice repeated, but of an act
frequently repeated. Frequent repetition of an act makes the agent strongly inclined towards
that act, and in this strong inclination lies the active or operative habit of so acting.
a) VIRTUES
A virtue may be natural or supernatural; it may be infused into the soul by God, or
acquired by repeated acts; it may be a physical virtue, an intellectual virtue, a theological virtue,
or a moral virtue. Thus, the native disposition one may have for study is a natural virtue; divine
Faith is supernatural virtue; fortitude is acquired virtue; bodily strength or perfection is a
physical virtue; wisdom is an intellectual virtue; faith is a theological virtue; fortitude is a moral
virtue. In Ethics, we deal only with acquired moral virtues.
An acquired moral virtue is a morally good operative habit. It is a moral habit of acting
in accordance with the dictates of reason.
The chief moral virtues are: prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance. These are
called cardinal virtues, and the name derives from the Latin cardo, a hinge; for as a door
depends for its proper action in opening and closing upon its hinges, so do all moral virtues
depend upon the “hinges” of the cardinal virtues.
i. Prudence is that virtue of the understanding which enables one quickly and clearly to
know, in concrete circumstance, the best means to an end, and it further inclines one to take
these means promptly and accurately. Strictly, then, prudence is an intellectual virtue, not a
moral (or “will” virtue), but we list it with the moral virtues because it has an immediate
connection with the actual willing of the means to an end which this virtue enables the
understanding to grasp. The marks of prudence, as we may learn from its definition, are a
certain watchfulness and clearsightedness, on the one hand, and cautious promptitude and
precision on the other. A prudent man is never precipitate or headlong; he does not embroil or
entangle a situation; he is not cocksure, headstrong, or self-confident. Nor, on the other hand, is
he weak, hesitant, or overcautious. The ancients counseled prudence in the axiom, “Virtue
stands in the middle,” that is, virtue does not run to extremes; prudence preserves the “meson”
or sane balance of Aristotle, and makes human action avoid the evil of falling too short or of
overwhelming its object; it makes human action fall just right according to the norm of right
reason.
ii. Justice is the virtue which inclines one with constancy always to render to everyone
his own. Man has, by his rational nature, a clear knowledge of something owed to God, to his
country, and to his fellowmen. Justice is the virtue which steadily inclines man to recognize and
pay this debt. A just man, therefore, is a religious man, an obedient, peaceloving, kind, grateful,
and truthful man.
iii. Fortitude is the virtue which inclines one to face dangers with intrepidity, especially
such dangers as threaten life. Fortitude, like all virtues, observes the “meson” or balance. It is
not rashness, overboldness, or presumptuous love of danger for its own sake or for ostentation;
nor, on the other hand, is it supineness or dead submission. It involves a largeness of mind and
soul, and combines with these the power of fadeless endurance.
iv. Temperance is the virtue which controls one in the pursuit and use of the pleasures
of life, especially of those pleasures that attract most strongly, and in which there is a
consequent danger of excess and disorder. Temperance keeps the desire and use of sense-
pleasure particularly, within the bounds of right and reasonable action. Temperance, therefore,
is not insensibility nor the extinction of natural tendencies. It is the regulation of tendencies,
the sane self-mastery which reason (conscience) dictates.
b) VICES
A vice is a morally evil operative habit. A single evil human act is a sin. Vice is the habit
of sin. We distinguish different vices inasmuch as different habits of sin stand opposed to
virtues. For vice is a habitual lack of virtue; and it stands opposed to virtue either by defect or
by excess. Virtue stands in the middle, being neither defective nor excessive when measured by
the requirements of right reason; while vice lies upon either hand.
To give but a few examples of vice as opposed to the cardinal moral virtues:
Opposed to prudence by defect we find, among other vices, imprudence, precipitateness
(to cause (something) to happen quickly or suddenly), lack of docility (lack of submissiveness,
lack of compliance, lack of passivity), carelessness, improvidence (extravagance, carelessness,
lavishness squandering), etc. Opposed to prudence by excess, we find the vices of oversolitude
(over+seclusion, isolation), smartness, trickery, fraud, etc.
Opposed to justice we find the vices of injustice, irreligion (absence, indifference,
rejection of, or hostility towards religion), impiety (wickedness, godlessness, ungodliness,
unholiness, irreligion), irreverence (disrespect, mockery), mendacity (deceit, falsehood,
dishonesty), ingratitude(thanklessness, lack of appreciation), cruelty, etc.
Opposed to fortitude we find weakspiritedness, inconstancy, impatience, etc. as vices by
defect; while we find the following as vices by excess: presumptuous (arrogant, presuming,
bigheaded), boldness, stubbornness, insensibility, etc.
Opposed to temperance by defect we find pride, lust, anger, gluttony, etc.; while we find
opposed by excess the vices of fanatical rigorousness, too great selfeffacement (too great
conduct oneself inconspicuously, too great act or fact of keeping oneself in the background), or
selfabjection (too great self-low, self-downcast state, too great self- degradation, to great self-
humbling), affectation (artificial and designed to impress, pretended feeling, showing off,
pretentiousness, exaggeration), morose (miserable, down, low, depressed) and gloomy conduct,
etc.
BOOK 1
INDIVIDUAL ETHICS
CHAPTER 1
RIGHTS AND DUTIES
ARTICLE 1.
RIGHTS
a) DEFINITION OF RIGHTS
Taking the word “right” as a substantive, we may view it objectively, or as a thing, as
when we say, “This is my right.” “That is his right.” “The wise man will see that he gets his
rights.” In this sense, right is defined as that which is owed or that which is due. Again, we may
view the term right subjectively, i. e., as residing in the one who possesses it (its subject), and
thus considered, it is a moral power residing in a person, - a power which all others are
bound to respect – of doing, possessing, or requiring something. It is in this subjective sense
that we use the term right in Ethics.
Right is founded upon law. For the existence of a right in one person involves an
obligation is all others of not impeding or violating the right. Now, it is only law that can impose
such an obligation. And whether this law, upon which right is based, be the natural law or
positive law, it is (as all true law) founded ultimately upon the Eternal Law. Hence, the ultimate
basis of right is the Eternal Law.
b) DIVISION OF RIGHT
i. Right is natural or positive according as it is founded upon the natural law or positive
law. Again, as positive law is both divine and human, we distinguish divine right and human
right. Further, according to the division of human law, we have ecclesiastical right and civil right.
The right to preserve one’s life is a natural right; the right of the Church to teach is a divine
right; the rights established by Canon Law are Ecclesiastical rights/ the right of citizens to vote
is a civil right.
ii. Right is also distinguished as right of property (or possession) and right of
jurisdiction. The right of property is the power one has of disposing of a thing possessed
according to one’s own wish or benefit: to sell, to keep, to lend, to change, to give away. The
right of property is called a right in property or possession when goods are owned, but not in
hand. Thus, my right to my books bought and paid for, but not yet delivered to me, is a right to
property. – The right of jurisdiction is the lawful power of a duly constituted superior to make
laws and to govern his subjects.
iii. Right is alienable when its subject (i. e., its possessor) may lawfully cede or renounce
it. Thus, I may renounce my right of eating meat on a nonabstinence day; thus, too, I may
renounce my right in property by giving it away. – Right is inalienable when its subject is not
free to renounce, but must retain it. Such is my right to life.
iv. Right is juridical (or perfect) when it is a legal right, a right strictly enjoined by law,
natural or positive. In other words, it is a right which must be respected, allowed, fulfilled, as a
matter of strict justice. Thus, the right of my grocer to the amount I owe him is a perfect or
juridical right; so also is the right of parents to the respect of their children. – Right is
nonjuridical (or imperfect), or moral, or “a claim”) when it is founded on a virtue other than
justice. Such a right is very often founded upon the virtue of charity. Thus, the right of a
benefactor to gratitude, or the right of a poor man to alms, is an imperfect or moral right, or a
claim. The things that are required by seemliness or the fitness of things are the object of
imperfect right. Thus, it is seemly and fitting that we be liberal and kindly in our dealings with
others: and we say that others have an imperfect right, a claim, to such conduct on our part.
c) PROPERTIES OF RIGHT
Since right is an inviolable moral power by its very definition – for we have defined right
as moral power which all are bound to respect – we do not list inviolability as one of the
properties of right. Inviolability belongs to the essence of right as such. We list three properties
of right, as follows: coaction, limitation, collision.
i. Coaction is the power which right enjoys of forcefully preventing its violation.
Ordinarily the moral power call coaction must be exercised through process of law. Between
man and man (not between man and society) coaction may be exercised by personal force or
violence only when all other means have failed.
ii. Limitation is the natural terminus of right, beyond which it cannot be exercised
without violating the right of another. A right ceases to be a right at the point where it impinges
injuriously upon another’s right. If I wish to remove my old house and to build a better one in
its place, I may not burn my present house, though that would be the easiest way to get rid of
old and useless lumber; such an action would endanger the houses of my neighbors, that is,
such an action would violate my neighbors’ right to the secure and unmenaced possession of
their property.
iii. Collision is the apparent conflict of two rights in such wise that one cannot be
exercised without violation of the other. We say it is an “apparent” conflict; for a real conflict of
rights cannot exist; when rights collide, the greater prevails and the lesser ceases to be a right.
All right is founded on law; all law is an ordinance of reason (when it is strictly and truly law);
and there can be no conflict between the ordinances of reason, for “it would not be reasonable
for reason to contradict itself.” In apparent collision of rights, that is the prevailing right, to
which the other cedes (or in face of which the other disappears), which: (1) belongs to the
more universal order; or (2) is concerned with the graver matter; or (3) is founded upon the
stronger title or claim. Thus, a soldier may place the welfare of his country ahead of his private
right to life; thus, the right to life which belongs to a man trespassing on my grounds is a
greater right than my right to privacy, and I may not take his life for the act of trespass; thus, the
claim upon my charity possessed by poor relatives is stronger than the claim possessed by
other poor persons.
a) DEFINITION OF DUTY
A duty considered objectively, i. e., as an object or thing, is anything one is obliged to do
or to omit. Thus, we speak of our daily work as our duty. Thus, too, we say, “It is your duty to do
this;” “It is one’s duty to avoid evil companionship;” “My duties are very numerous.”
Ethics takes the term duty subjectively, i. e., as affecting the subject bound by it, and
so considered duty is defined as a moral obligation incumbent upon a person of doing or
omitting (avoiding) something.
Duty is a moral obligation, i. e., an obligation resting as a requirement upon a free will.
Hence, the subject of a duty is a person, and only a person. Brute animals do not have duties.
We distinguish moral obligation from physical obligation. A person is morally obliged to assist
at religious services; he is, however, not bound and carried to the service by force. A moral
obligation binds the will; and, as we say in General Ethics (Ch. 1, Art. 3, d), the will is not subject
to physical compulsion.
A duty is the correlative of a right. A right in one imposes a duty on all others of
respecting it, of not violating it. Duty, like right, is based on law.
b) DIVISION OF DUTY
i. A duty imposed by the natural law is natural; a duty which comes from positive law is
positive. The duty of worshipping God is a natural duty; as also is the duty of preserving one’s
life. The latter example shows us that an inalienable right is also a duty. The duty of hearing
Mass on certain feast days is a positive duty, as is the duty of paying taxes.
ii. A duty which requires the performance of an act is affirmative; a duty which requires
the omission or avoidance of something is negative. The primary requirement of the natural
law, “Do good; avoid evil” gives us, in a single example, an instance of both positive and negative
duty. Again, we have the matter exampled in the Decalogue: “Honor thy father and thy mother”
is an affirmative law enjoining an affirmative duty; while negative duty is enjoined by the law,
“Thou shalt not kill.”
iii. A duty which obliges in strict justice, and so corresponds to a perfect right, is a
perfect or juridical duty. A duty which does not obligate according to justice, but according to
charity or some other virtue, and so corresponds to a nonjuridical right, is a nonjuridical, and
imperfect, or moral duty. The obligation of paying to an employee the wage agreed upon is a
perfect duty, while the duty of giving alms to the needy is a moral duty.
iv. There are greater and lesser duties, and where these seem to conflict, the lesser
ceases to be a duty, and the greater prevails. That is the greater duty (in an apparent collision)
which comes from the higher power, the higher law. Thus, duties towards God come before
duties towards men, and if a parent forbids his child to hear Mass on Sunday, the duty of
obeying parent ceases, in this instance, to bind the child, while the duty towards God prevails.
Similarly, if a superior commands his subject to steal, the subject has not, in this instance, the
duty of obedience, for the duty which comes from the natural law – the duty of justice –
prevails.
Again: where there is an apparent conflict of duties, that which is concerned with the
graver matter prevails, while the other ceases to be a duty.
Finally: when there is an apparent conflict of duties, that duty prevails – the other
ceasing to be a duty – which arises out of the more solid title or claim.
To sum up: In an apparent conflict of duties the greater prevails and the lesser ceases to
be a duty; and that is the greater duty which comes from the higher law, or is concerned with
the graver matter, or is grounded upon the more solid title or claim.
By office we mean duty or system of duties. By personal in our title we mean that which
is done by and to the acting person, the human agent. In a word, man’s duties towards himself.
These duties are concerned with matters of soul and of body.
ARTICLE 1.
DUTIES OF MAN TOWARDS HIS SOUL
The soul of man has two faculties or powers or capacities for action, viz., the knowing
faculty or intellect, and the choosing faculty or will. Duties are obligations, things to be
done. Hence, man’s duties of soul consist in things to be done by intellect and will.
a) LIFE
With regard to bodily life man has a twofold duty, viz., the duty of conserving it in
integrity, and the duty of avoiding death, mutilation, and needless danger. These two duties are
really only two views – one positive and the other negative – of the same duty.
Man does not own his body. God owns it. God alone has the right to dispose of it and of
its life and health. Life and health have been given to man as great blessings, as goods to be
conserved and used. Like all true goods that man may possess, life and health, and all that
pertains directly to these goods, are to be used for the achievement of man’s last end.
Therefore, absolutely speaking, man is bound to exercise ordinary care for the conservation of
life and health. Thus, he is obliged to maintain the integrity and perfection of his members, to
take such nourishment as is required for the proper development or maintenance of bodily life,
to observe the requirements of reason in matters of cleanliness and proper dress, to keep the
senses strictly under control. These are man’s positive duties with regard to his body.
Man’s negative duties with regard to bodily life and health oblige him to avoid suicide,
the needless mutilation of his members, intemperance, and all unreasonable use of objects or
practices that could be harmful to life or limb or bodily health.
Suicide is self-murder. It is the direct taking of one’s own life upon one’s own authority.
Suicide can never, under any circumstances, be permitted. Suicide, clearly regarded as simple
and direct self-murder, is absolutely contrary to the natural law, and is never permitted. Suicide
is an injury done to God, to society, and to the person committing it.
b) OTHER GOODS
Besides the goods of soul and body there are others, such as prosperity, good name,
honor, external liberty, etc. These are usually required, in greater or less measure, for the full
perfection of bodily life. They are also required by the man who has dependents. Hence, a man
must have employment or some means of livelihood. He must take care of those dependent
upon him and provide for their future. He must earn a good name and achieve an honest place
in the estimation of his fellows. Thus, ordinarily, a man must exert himself to obtain a
sufficiency of the good of this world.
But, apart from the necessity imposed by the duties of one’s state of life, man is quite
free to neglect the matter of worldly prosperity, nay, he may find it much to his advantage to do
so. For the absence of care about worldly possessions ordinarily favors one’s progress in virtue,
and removes many obstacles from the path in which one must walk to attain one’s last end. Of
course, it does not follow that the pursuit of honest prosperity, good name, etc., is wrong. As
long as both the matter and the manner of such a quest are kept within the moral law, they are
quite licit. Goods of fortune, fame, honor, liberty, etc., are gifts of God, though they are not gifts
of the first rank. As long as they are used according to reason, and not abused, they can be
made to serve man’s purpose in attaining his least end, notwithstanding the fact that they are
likely to be abused and to be a hindrance to man’s true work rather than a help.
BOOK SECOND
SOCIAL ETHICS
CHAPTER 1
THE FAMILY
ARTICLE 1. SOCIETY
a) DEFINITION OF SOCIETY
A society is a stable moral union of a plurality of persons for the purpose of
achieving a common end by the use of common means.
It is stable union, not a mere loose assembly or group; it is a more or less permanent
group, bonded in a common effort to achieve a common end. It is a moral union, not, on the one
hand, a flock or herd, nor, on the other hand, a number of individual human beings held by a
physical bond, as a line of prisoners are held by a chain. It consists of a plurality of persons, i. e.,
of some or many human beings, and these are allied together for the achievement of a common
end by the use of common means.
When we speak of society in general we mean the human race, for humanity is a society
permanently bonded by the common nature of its members, and tending by the use of means
available to all, to the common end, which is, objectively, God, and subjectively, eternal
happiness. Man is social by nature, and not, as some philosophers have taught, by free choice.
Human society is therefore a natural institution, or, more properly, an institution of God, the
author of human nature.
That society is natural to man is easily proved. Man cannot exist without others. Not
only does a man need parents in order to be born, but he needs the care of others for a very
long time after birth – something that is not true of brute animals, which are quickly able to
look after themselves. Again, a child must be supported and educated by others; he needs the
guidance and control of mature minds; he needs association with cultivated persons if he is to
develop his powers of soul; he needs society for the exercise of splendid tendencies (called
“social virtues”), such as benevolence, pity for the distressed, love of virtuous and heroic
conduct, etc. Finally, man needs society in his old age; wretched indeed would be his condition
if he had to battle through life as a solitary, and to lie down at the last to starve and die when his
poor strength was spent and his shrunken body unable to procure the means of its support.
The needs of man call for society, not merely the conveniences of man, as the “social compact
theorists” teach. These needs are natural; and hence society, in answering natural need, shows
itself a natural institution.
We may sum up the whole argument thus: Man has the natural right to life, health,
integrity of members, goods of reputation and honor, goods of soul, and certain goods of
fortune. But, it would be altogether impossible for man to procure and preserve these things
without society, and his natural right to them would be therefore an illusory thing, a thing
without meaning. Therefore, the very voice of nature which proclaims man’s rights, proclaims
the necessity of human society.
b) DIVISION OF SOCIETY
i. A society is natural or free, according as it is a requirement of human nature or the
result of free agreement among men. Human society achieves its reality in the Family and the
State; hence the Family and the State are natural societies. A debating club, or a workman’s
union, is a free society.
ii. A society is simple or composite according as it is or is not joined in confederation
with other societies. A confederation is a composite society, and its purpose is not to absorb the
minor societies (simple societies) which make it up, but to protect them and keep them
working harmoniously and according to order. Thus, an independent literary society is a simple
society; while the Catholic Students’ Mission Crusade is composite, being composed of various
individual Units, each of which preserves its own proper identity. If the confederation of
societies is such that the minor societies which make it up are fused into such union that their
proper identity is lost, the result is not a composite society, but merely a larger simple society.
iii. A society is perfect or imperfect according as it contains in itself all that its nature
demands, both as to end and means to the end, and is self-sufficient and independent; or, on the
other hand, lacks such self-sufficiency. Civil society (i. e., the State) and the Church are perfect
societies. All other societies are imperfect.
iv. A society is equal or unequal according as authority in the society is vested in the
entire social group, or is vested in one or more persons to whom the others are subjected. Thus,
a literary club which decides all matters by votes is an equal society, while the Family is an
unequal society with the chief authority vested in the father.
c) SOCIAL AUTHORITY
Authority is the right and power of ordering others to act in a certain manner, and
of exacting obedience. Such a right and power is a natural requirement of society. Authority is
necessary. For human society is a group of free beings who are made for the same end, but are
not necessitated or compelled in any particular action. Thus, we find the world full of varying
and opposed opinions, of men of entirely different dispositions, or selfish men, of ambitious
men. If there were not authority among men, what a disorder there would be! The human bond
of a common nature, and common natural requirements, would remain, it is true, and would
continue to make clear the natural character of human society; but the ends of that society
would be defeated; men would be at all manner of cross purposes, hindering and thwarting one
another in every conceivable way. Surely, if society is to serve its normal purpose of getting men
on towards their last end, of helping them to work together to this common end, there must be
order, there must be peace in the main, there must be forbearance, there must be endurance.
Society is futile without these things. But nature is never futile, being the expression of the
Eternal Reason and Wisdom. Hence, as nature requires society, nature requires order in society.
As order is impossible without authority, nature itself requires authority in society.
Social authority, then, must exist. What of its extent or its limits? It is obvious that its
limits are fixed by its purpose. Social authority exists alone for the right ordering of those
things that are necessary to the attainment of the end of society, and which could not exist
without authority. Hence, the government of a community, and the individual person in
authority, may not make use of place and power to enforce decrees that are mere whims. They
may not abuse their office. It is true indeed that “a public office is a public trust.” An office, i.e., a
place of authority in society, demands of the officer honesty and honor, prudence and fidelity,
courage and enduring attention to duty. The abuse of authority, by extending its limits beyond
their due and proper place, is injustice and tyranny, and against such abuse the subjects of
authority have the right to protest, and, when there is no other way of achieving justice, to
revolt.
ARTICLE 2. MARRIAGE
a) DEFINITION OF MARRIAGE
We may speak of the married state and of the act of marriage, i. e., the act of being
married. The married state constitutes conjugal society, and it is obviously of this that we
speak in the present Article.
Conjugal society is the stable union entered into by a man and a woman for the
procreation and education of children and for mutual support and helpfulness.
From this definition we learn that the parties to the marriage contract must be a man
and a woman, and these must be free to make the marriage contract. When we speak of the
indissolubility of marriage, we shall see that the existence of one such marriage contract
renders another impossible for either of the parties while both are alive. We also learn from the
definition that the primary end of marriage is the generation and education of children, for it is
by these means that the human race is kept in existence and brought to the proper
development of its mental and moral powers. Finally, the definition indicates the secondary end
of marriage, viz., the mutual love and helpfulness that the married persons are to find in this
state. Of course, both primary and secondary ends of marriage are subordinate to the last end
of man, viz., God, and everlasting happiness, and marriage is meant to help men towards this
great ultimate end.
The ends of marriage indicate that it is a natural institution. Marriage is natural because
rational nature inclines man towards it. It would not be necessary for the proper care and
training which rational nature inclines man to give to his children, for it is the good of offspring
that constitutes the primary end of marriage, and this includes not only birth, but rearing and
training. Parents naturally incline to the work of rearing their children safely to full maturity.
Hence, nature inclines man to a stable union; men are inclined by reason to marry, not merely to
mate. In the second place, nature indicates the necessity of marriage in the fact that the sexes
are not identical but supplementary, so that there is a general and normal need of one for the
other.
Marriage then is natural, and conjugal society is a natural society. But, it is not natural as
breathing is natural; it is not a thing absolutely required of every man and every woman. It is
natural, inasmuch as nature is evidently framed for it, and inclines man towards it; but is
actualization, the fulfillment of the natural inclination, is a matter of individual man’ free
choice. The primary end of matrimony, viz., the generation and education of children, is
sufficiently achieved without requiring every man and every woman to marry; and hence
nature does not impose it as a universal and individual duty. Exceptions are not only in accord
with the requirements of nature, but are sometimes very desirable and even necessary.
Mankind taken collectively, i. e., as a group, is bound by the obligation of the natural law to
marriage and the conjugal society; but taken distributively, i. e., as individuals, mankind is not
so bound. Hence, it is lawful for anyone (otherwise free) to marry or to remain single. Those
who choose to remain single are bound to the life of celibacy in perfect personal continence.
a) PARENTAL AUTHORITY
Authority is a natural necessity in any society. Hence, we may conclude at one that it
is a necessity in conjugal society. The ends of marriage cannot be served if there is a
disagreement and strife between parents upon the matter of procreation and education of
children; and, obviously, such discord is the direct frustration of the love and mutual
helpfulness which marriage is naturally meant to give to husband and wife. Therefore, there
must be authority in the family.
What is the source of this authority? It is nature, and not the State. Individual men
and women existed upon earth before there was any such thing as civil society, and at that time
they had the rights which were obviously the heritage and the intention of their nature, and
which could be fulfilled perfectly without civil society. These men and women had the right to
marry, the right to have children, and the right and duty of educating children. These rights,
then, belong to mankind by a title that is valid prior to any claims of civil society in the matter.
It is true, indeed, that the State itself is a natural society, and as such is necessary to man.
But, this necessity is not lodged in the individual man as such, but in individual men as
members of a considerable group. As soon as the number of persons in any locality or territory
is large enough to make civil authority an evident natural convenience; as soon as the number
of human beings is large enough to make possible the violation of one another’s rights, the
working of men to cross purposes, the rise of discord and turmoil, the existence of bullying,
domineering, injustice, and enslavement; so soon does civil society become a natural
requirement called State. The family is the foundation and the fountain source of the State; for
from the family comes the citizens that constitute the State. Hence, it is an absurd and topsy-
turvy piece of thinking that essays to trace the origin of domestic authority to the State.
Granted, then, that there must be authority in the family, and that this authority comes
from the natural law, a further question arises. In what member or members of the family
does this authority reside? In the parents, and not in the children; so much is obvious. But, in
which of the parents? The parents themselves, while not a family, constitute conjugal society;
and in this society there must be authority. Is that authority lodge equally in husband and wife?
It could not be so; for, although husband and wife are equals, and are meant to achieve
the ends of their state by harmonious effort, it is evident that, where there are but two
members in a society, equal authority could bring about a deadlock on any issue, and could
thwart the very end for which the society exists. It is unreasonable to think that a society, which
is a stable union, could be marked by essential instability; it is absurd to suppose that a society,
which is a union of persons working for a common end, could be so constituted as to render
impracticable and even impossible the achievement of any end at all. Yet this is precisely what
those must think and suppose who assert the equal authority of husband and wife in conjugal
society. One of the couple, therefore, must have the first place of authority. There must be one
head of conjugal society and of the family.
Parental authority, like all authority, must be exercised according to the dictates of
reason. It has its limits. It is itself an authority subject to the authority of God. Hence, parents
cannot require their children, and the husband cannot require his wife, to do anything that is
contrary to the law of God, of nature. Authority that is exercised for injustice ceases to be
authority, and has no binding force whatever.
a) LABOR
Labor or work is man’s effort applied to production of goods. It is effort of mind or
body partially or wholly applied to the production of utilities. While the term labor is
ordinarily used to denote hired labor, and sometimes manual or bodily labor, it really signifies
the effort of the professional man (clergyman, lawyer, physician, surgeon, actor, journalist,
businessman) as well as that of the mechanic, the “day laborer,” and the farmer. All human
effort unites in different proportions the activities of body (muscular effort), intellect (mental
effort), and will (moral effort). And any human effort, no matter what proportion of muscle,
mind, and will be involved, which tends partially or entirely to the production of goods, utilities,
commodities, values, results – in a word, that can in any manner be translated into terms of
dollars and cents – is labor or work.
Labor is a means of attaining to man’s last end, and indeed, speaking generally, an
indispensable means. For man’s faculties of body and mind were given him for the attainment
of his last end; these faculties require the maintenance of bodily, mental, and moral life and
effectiveness; and to this maintenance labor, or its fruit, is a direct means.
Labor is man’s right and duty. Speaking generally, it is a necessary means to his last end,
and therefore his inalienable right. Speaking particularly, labor of some kind is the duty of each
and all, for it is the opportunity of gaining merit for the life to come. Further, labor is a solace, a
source of interest and pleasure, of peace and happiness.
If labor be a thing productive of fruits that can be, in any manner whatever, translated
into terms of dollars and cents, what of intellectual and spiritual labor? What of the hard
study of the student? What of the continuous prayers of the contemplative? The student
prepares himself, ordinarily speaking, for gainful occupation; and even the recluse, the finished
scholar who studies and writes, pours out the wealth of his mind that takes shape in
manuscripts and books, and is transferred and circulated among men by buying and selling.
The contemplative, the rare soul called to “the better part,” wins countless favors for humanity;
in example and through the fruits of active divine worship, such a soul keeps the world from
forgetting the high principles of the Christian religion and morality which alone make labor
possible among the mass of men to whom it is a hardship in itself, a thing that requires effort
and perseverance and from labor so encouraged come the goods of material wealth.
Thus, there is a distinctly traceable relation between the highest and most spiritual
occupation, and the labor that leads to material goods. Still, practically speaking, we need not
go to such lengths to establish the justice of our definition of labor. In Ethics, we consider labor
chiefly in the sense that the term carries to the economist and the sociologist. We mean the
work that is done, wholly or partially, for self – support or gain, by the professional man, the
businessman, the farmer, the mechanic, and the man who uses bodily effort on “a job.” In a
word, we mean that which is done, wholly or partially, or in any manner, for a wage.
b) ASSOCIATIONS
Association is the active gathering together of men to form a society. Here, we do not
speak of the natural association inseparable from the family and from the human race (human
society) as such; nor do we mean by association the formation of the natural and perfect
society called the State, nor the higher perfect society called the Church. We mean the coming
together of men to form a private society for the better achievement of private ends. Thus, we
have associations that are religious, such as a sodality; political, such as a society for research;
industrial, such as a labor union; commercial, such as a board of trade; literary, such as a study
circle or debating club; etc.
To form associations with his fellows for the better achievement of lawful ends that the
associates as individuals could not achieve, or count not achieve readily, is the right of man, and
a natural right. For man is inclined by nature towards the orderly development of his faculties,
and to realize this natural disposition he needs to conjoin his powers with those of others in
association distinct from domestic and civil society. Such association masses and focuses the
powers and the efforts of individual; it coordinates, combines, intensifies, and directs these
efforts for the achieving of a lawful end. Thus, the end is achievable, and readily achievable, by
the conjoined work of the associates, whereas, though a lawful good towards which each may,
or even must, strive, it would not be so achievable by individual and separate effort. Hence,
association is often a better means to a lawful end than individual effort; just as “tow heads are
better that one,” and just as ten hands will lift a greater weight that two.
Now, man has a natural right to achieve lawful ends; hence, he has the natural right to
the use of the means, and of the better means, to that achievement. It follows that the right of
association is a natural right. again: as a single person requires the union of head and hands
and tools to accomplish a piece of work and a s he has the natural right to combine these things
in the production of the work, so, by a true parity, Tom and Dick and Harry may unite to achieve
a certain end, and they have the natural right so to unite; and in uniting they constitute a moral
person, a single moral personality, which has rights that are not to be limited more than those
of physical persons.
Now, if men may lawfully unite in association for the achievement of a lawful end,
workers may so unite. Thus, “professional associations” may lawfully exist. Of such
associations, the more important for Ethics (as being the most common, and as presenting the
most obvious field of application for matters of right) exist among industrial workers, and are
known as “labor unions,” or, collectively, as “organized labor.” With such associations we shall
deal in brief detail.
Workers are not machines, not tools, not workhorses. They are men. As men they have
rights to goods of soul, of body, and of fortune. They have duties too: duties to God, to self, to
fellowmen. When these facts or their implications are ignored by those that have the control of
the means of production (capitalists and employers), an injustice is done, and this is an
injustice against the natural law. So much is evident. Now, individual workmen are powerless to
combat such injustice if it exists, and to prevent its existence if it threatens. Organized labor can
resist or prevent such injustice. Hence, organization of labor is lawful as a necessary means to
protect natural right.
Labor unions must strive to obtain for workers that fullness of rounded human life, that
orderly development of faculties, and seemly use thereof, that belong to individual men by right
of nature. Therefore, the effort of such unions must be to secure to men true freedom in the
making of wage contracts, and there is no true freedom when the worker has the alternative of
accepting this sort of work, or wage, or working condition, or hours of work, or of starving.
Hence, labor unions must seek to establish and maintain decency in work, justice in wages,
humanity in the working schedule, sanitary conditions in the places of employment. In a word,
labor unions must seek to fix the conditions of labor justly, so that the workman may be kept
out of servitude, and may live free to do “all that may become a man,” neither attempting more,
nor accepting less.
Labor unions, like other moral and physical persons, must not exceed their rights. They
must fulfill their duties. If labor unions are not used for lawful ends, they are abused. They must
not, therefore, demand exorbitant returns for work, nor unreasonable hours, nor bring to
naught their efforts for a just wage and decent living conditions by prosecuting accidental and
trifling demands. Nor must hey be too quick to employ coercive methods in gaining their just
ends, but must reserve such methods (strikes, boycotts) as the last reluctant resort.
c) WAGES
Wages are the price of work. Wages are the sum of money, or money equivalent,
exchanged for a certain amount of work, or for a certain time of service. The nominal wage is
the sum named in the wage contract; the real wage is the exchange value of this sum.
In other words, the nominal wage is the face value of the money paid, and the real wage
is the amount of good this money will buy.
Workman and employer agree on the wage to be paid; the workman gives his labor, in
terms of products (piece of work) or of time (day-work, monthly work, etc.), and the employer
pays money. Thus, between the employer and the laborer there is a contract made, and this
contract is bilateral, since there is an obligation imposed by the contract upon both parties to it.
Now, as we have seen, a true contract requires freedom in the parties. But if the workman is
forced to accept the employer’s terms, or starve, he has no real freedom in the matter; and
unless the terms offered are humanly liberal, an injustice is done to the worker. Out of this
situation arises the question of a just wage. Certainly, the worker is entitled to justice; hence, he
is entitled to a just wage. But what, precisely, is a just wage?
If men were free to regard human labor as a material good to be disposed of like any
commodity; if they were free to buy and sell it as they are free to buy and sell tools, or land, or
domestic animals; then the matter of deciding upon the actual amount of a just wage would be
comparatively simple. Men would simply look for the market value of labor and dispose of it at
that price. It has a human element. It follows, therefore, that a wage contract, a contract in
which labor is exchanged for money, must not be an agreement which turns a man into a
chattel; it must not a an agreement to the detriment of man with the performance of duties of
vocation, such as the founding and supporting of a family, the provision for age and sickness in
himself and in his dependents. In a word, the wage contract must be such as takes into account
at least the minimum essentials of a proper, full, and rounded human life.
A just wage is obviously not to be computed in figures; no nominal just wage can be
fixed, for nothing is so variable as the exchange value of money. But something like a fixed
requirement for a just wage may be established in real terms, i. e., in terms of what such a wage
must be a living wage, i. e., such as will enable the recipient to live a decent and respectable, if
frugal, life, and to provide something for times of age, ill-health, or unemployment.
Thus far, we speak of a personal just wage. But what of a family wage, i. e., a wage
sufficient for the founding, support, and rearing (education) of a family? Sound economists and
ethicians are agreed that a family wage is a matter of moral obligation upon the employer,
although some of the authorities base this obligation upon charity, while others base it upon
strict justice.
The details of this matter must be worked out by the economist and the sociologist.
Ethics lays down basic principles, but cannot discuss all the particulars that must be considered
in the actual application of these principles. The elemental principles may be reduced to these:
Justice must be done. Justice means giving to every man what is his due. The worker must be
given, in the way of wages, what is his due. Now, certainly, it is just that the laborer be able to
live in humanly decent circumstances, and to support those who belong to him, by the fruits of
his work. In the matter of determining, at any time and in any circumstance, just what amount
will meet the requirements of justice in the wage contract, recourse must be had to the
consensus of opinion among wise, prudent, upright, and experienced men. And, the Christian
employer will not fail to meet in this matter the full demands of justice and the requirements of
Christian charity as well.
But what of the employer? Is he not entitled to a return, to a just profit, to his own
“wages” in fact? Certainly, he is. Yet if he cannot obtain a due return without injustice to others,
he has no alternative but to leave the ranks of employers and enter upon the state of an
independent worker or of an employee.
d) COERCIVE MEASURES
Workers and employers alike have human rights. Sometimes these rights require
defence. When there is no adequate defence except coercion, workers resort to strikes and
boycotts, and employers to lockouts. We must say a brief word on each of these coercive
measures.
i. Strikes. – A strike is a cessation of work by agreement of the workers for the purpose
of bettering the conditions of labor. A strike may be for the purpose of enforcing better wages,
shorter hours of work, better working conditions, or all of these together. It is a lawful measure
when used, under due conditions, for the defence or enforcement of the workers’ rights. The
conditions requisite for a just strike are: (1) That it be the only available means of reaching a
just settlement of the difficulties between employer and employees; (2) That the matter at
stake be of an importance sufficient to warrant the hardship and damage that must be borne by
the workers, the employers, the families of both, and the community at large; (3) That there be
a reasonable hope of success in obtaining the good for which the strike is called.
Hence, a strike that is called for the purpose of bettering conditions that are already just;
or a strike in violation of a just contract which the employer has not first violated; or a strike
that means direct violation of the rights of others or of the community; or a strike that is too
hastily undertaken where the matter might have been settled by arbitration; or a strike that is
obviously hopeless to begin with, and is therefore, not an apt means to the desired end – each
of these is an unjust and an unlawful strike. Yet, when the requisite conditions are present,
strikes are lawful; and the State has, therefore, no right to make a law prohibiting them . Still,
the State, within the just limits of its authority, ought to interfere to punish or prevent the abuse
of strikes. Thus, the State may break up a strike that is becoming a menace to society. The State
has the further duty of working out means to prevent the perpetual recurrence of strikes, and
to this end it should create boards of arbitration before which employers and employees could
adjust their relations with the secure hope of being justly dealt with.
ii. Boycotts. – A boycott is a refusal to have business (or social) dealings with a certain
person or institution. It is, when just, a moral force exercised upon a person (physical or moral)
to bring the latter to the practice of justice, or, more accurately, to make him give up the practice
of injustice. A boycott, to be just, must be directed against a true abuse, a truly unjust condition.
It must be kept within the limits of justice and charity. It must be a means that is apt; a means
that offers solid probability of success in the achievement of its end. It must entirely without
violence or the threat of violence. Like the strike, the boycott is to be regarded as last resort, to
be employed either when other available means have failed, or when there is obviously no
other means available.
iii. Lockouts. – A lockout is the refusal of an employer to furnish work to employees,
and is used to suppress injustice on the part of workers. The employer, like the worker, may
suffer injustice. The lockout is his last resource, just as the strike is that of the workers. And,
under due conditions – conditions which are, when duly adapted, essentially the same as those
required for a just strike – the lockout is lawful. When unlawful, the lockout is a grave injustice
against the workers and against the common good.
CHAPTER III
THE WORLD – FAMILY OF NATIONS
ARTICLE 1. INTERNATIONAL LAW
a) PEACE
Peace may be defined as a state of concord, order, and security among nations. It is
a positive thing, not to be defined as a mere absence of war. Peace is a term applicable also to a
single civil society when its citizens and its governing power are working harmoniously
together with mutual trust. Further, peace is the state of the individual man whose life is lived
in accordance with the requirements of law, when his conscience is tranquil, his mind and heart
unperturbed, yet manfully active. True peace comes to the individual and through him to the
nation and the world, by his steady effort to achieve his last end by the knowledge, love, and
service of God in the practice of the true religion.
Peace is not mere quiet, it is not inactivity, it is not repose, it is not laziness. On the
contrary, it is found in activity, in free human activity conducted in accordance with the
requirements of justice and charity, and marked by prudence, fortitude, and temperance. Peace
is the greatest earthly god for which men or nations may strive; it is the essential condition of
true development; it is the soul of security; it is the foundation of justice.
Good will means willingness to work for the attaining of the end for which life was given.
Good will is not the mark of the man who is content to sit with folded hands; it is rather the
mark of him who is ready to be up and doing, not with the unnatural fever of mere external
action, but with the prudent and persevering effort to live life in all acts as it should be live. And
to such a man is peace apportioned.
This does not mean an alertness of eye or body, but an alertness of soul and mind and
heart. Such alertness is best cultivated in the aloofness from the distraction that comes from sin
and from inordinate efforts exercised in the quest of material goods. One must not think,
therefore, that the life of the recluse, the hermit, the contemplative, is a lazy life, or an inactive
life; on the contrary, it is a life of the greatest alertness and of the most active strides in the
direction of the last end.
As peace in the home is an inestimable blessing, so peace in the world is an unbounded
good to all nations. Nations, therefore, have the right and the duty to foster peace. Peace is not
fostered by mere sentimental talk; it is not fostered by the evasions of diplomatists; it is not
fostered by jealousies, suspicions, emulations. Peace is fostered by the cultivation of morality.
We must leave the statement for the apologist (noun a person who offers an argument in defense
of something controversial.) to prove, for it is outside the province of Ethics to deal with the
matter in any detail; yet the fact truly is that men and nations will continue to cry “Peace,
Peace!”
b) WAR
War is defined as a condition of armed and active hostility between two or more
nations.
War is distinguished from rebellion, which is an unlawful uprising of citizens against
their government; from revolution, which is a justified resistance against tyranny; and from the
public conflict called civil war; for war is a conflict between nations.
Wars are divided into just and unjust, offensive and defensive. (1) A just war is one
that fulfills the conditions necessary to make war a lawful undertaking. We shall discuss these
conditions in a moment. (2) An unjust war is one that fails to meet the requisite conditions. (3)
An offensive war is one that injuring or destroying another State, or for the purpose of
enrichment at the expense of another State. Offensive wars are always unlawful. (4) A defensive
war is one that is undertaken upon provocation to protect the rights of citizens or to uphold the
honor of the State. We must notice that it is not always the offensive party that first declares
war; war may be first declared by the party of the defence.
The first offence may be in the nature of acts of hostility and injustice done before war is
declared and enduring in their effects to that time.
The conditions necessary for a just war are the following: (1) War must be declared
by competent authority, for a just cause, and it must be undertaken with an honest intention.
The last named requirement warn us that a war – granted the cause is just and that it is
declared by competent authority – is rendered unjust if undertaken for revenge, lust for power,
hatred of the opponent, etc. (2) War must be the last resource, undertaken only when all other
means of settlement have been found unavailing. (3) The war must offer a reasonable prospect
of success; else war would be a greater evil than the wrongs it seeks to right. (4) War must be
conducted in a manner approved by civilized peoples. Hence, there must be no wanton
slaughter or destruction which has no direct effect on the outcome of the war; there must be no
direct killing or maltreatment of noncombatants, there must be no use of inhuman and
barbarous methods, such as the poisoning of wells and streams, the using of envenomed
weapons, the poisoning of the air by noxious gases; there must be no use of means that are
intrinsically evil and against the natural law, such as lies, perjury, inciting to reason, etc.; there
must be no continuation of hostile acts after an armistice or peace has been declared.
War is licit when all the conditions mentioned are met. For, just as an individual has the
right to repel force with force, just as a man may defend himself, under certain conditions, by
the indirect slaying of his unjust aggressor, so may a nation defend itself. Now, the only means
available to a nation for repelling force with force is war. Again, the State has the duty of self-
preservation and of defending the rights of its citizens; and it is clear that there are times when
this duty cannot be performed by a State without repelling unjust aggression, i. e., without
waging war. Hence, wars are sometimes licit.
But, however lawful, wars are certainly regrettable. To prevent the great evils that wars
inflict upon the peoples of the world, the establishment of an international tribunal has long
been thought of, and more than once attempted, as a court before which nations could adjust
their difficulties without recourse to war.