Reasonable Doubt in Islamic Law
Reasonable Doubt in Islamic Law
Reasonable Doubt in Islamic Law
Volume 40
Article 3
Issue 1 Yale Journal of International Law
2015
Recommended Citation
Intisar A. Rabb, "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law, 40 Yale J. Int'l L. (2015).
Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjil/vol40/iss1/3
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Yale
Journal of International Law by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact
[email protected].
Article
II. THE CONVERSION OF "REASONABLE DOUBT" FROM JUDICIAL PRACTICE TO LEGAL TEXT ......... 69
A. The Canonization of Doubt Through Early Judicial Practice .................................... 70
1. Case of the Mysterious Pregnancy ................................................................. 71
2. Case of the Falsely Accused Butcher .............................................................. 72
3. Case of the Absentee Husband ...................................................................... 74
B. The Textualization of Doubt Through Juristic Interpretation .................................... 76
t Professor of Law, Harvard Law School. Thanks for many helpful conversations and
comments to William Alford, Mary Bilder, Tomiko Brown-Nagin, Ash BAli, Michael Cook, 1. Glenn
Cohen, Christine Desan, Charles Donahue, William Eskridge, Mohammad Fadel, Noah Feldman, Lani
Guinier, Wael Hallaq, Daniel Hulsebosch, Marion Katz, Adriaan Lanni, John Manning, Daniel
Markovits, Hossein Modarressi, Roy Mottahedch, William Nelson, Vlad Perju, Kim Scheppele, Jed
Shugerman, Carol Steiker, Laura Weinrib, James Whitman, and Adnan Zulfiqar; to participants of the
Legal History Roundtable at Boston College Law School, the "junior" and regular faculty workshops at
Harvard Law School, and the faculty workshop at NYU Law School; to my co-panelists at the American
Society of Legal History session on Late Antique and Medieval Islamic Criminal Legal History; and to
the tremendous efforts of Allison Day, Leslie Esbrook, Vivaan Nehru, Andrew Walchuk, and the other
editors of the Yale Journal of InternationalLaw. Unless otherwise noted, all translations from Arabic
and Persian are my own.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
- Robert M. Cover'
INTRODUCTION
1. Robert M. Cover, Violence and the Word, 95 YALE L.J. 1601, 1601 (1986) (footnote
omitted).
2. On the "open-textured" and thus indeterminate nature of general rules, standards, and
principles when applied to ordinary cases, see H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 125-28 (2d ed.
1994). On the discomfort with doubt that textualism seeks to alleviate, see Peter Linzer, The Comfort of
Certainty: Plain Meaning and the ParolEvidence Rule, 71 FORDHAM L. REv. 799, 802 (2002), which
discusses psychological comforts derived from perceptions of textualist "plain meaning" as providing
"predictive stability," and notes that "[i]t is reassuring to believe that the words on a page provide order,
and order is unquestionably comforting."
3. For an overview of American criminal law, see generally JOSHUA DRESSLER,
UNDERSTANDING CRIMINAL LAW (6th ed. 2012). Recognition of the special nature of criminal law led
the United States Supreme Court to make federal criminal law exclusively legislative and to require
criminal legislation to be clear. See McBoyle v. United States, 283 U.S. 25, 27 (1931) ("Although it is
not likely that a criminal will carefully consider the text of the law before he murders or steals, it is
reasonable that a fair warning should be given . . . of what the law intends to do if a certain line is
passed. To make the warning fair, so far as possible the line should be clear."); United States v. Hudson
& Goodwin, 11 U.S. (7 Cranch) 32, 34 (1812) (barring federal common law crimes).
4. See, e.g., United States v. Bass, 404 U.S. 336, 348 (1971) (noting an "instinctive distaste
against men languishing in prison unless the lawmaker has clearly said they should" (quoting Henry J.
Friendly, Mr. Justice Frankfurter and the Reading of Statutes, reprinted in HENRY J. FRIENDLY,
BENCHMARKS 196,209 (1967))).
5. For an accessible overview of Islamic criminal law, see generally RUDOLPH PETERS,
CRIME AND PUNISHMENT IN ISLAMIC LAW (2005), which describes Islam's three categories of offenses:
(1) fixed, nondiscretionary crimes and penalties, including four agreed-upon offenses: illicit sexual
relations, false accusations of illicit sexual relations, theft, and intoxication; and three of disputed status:
apostasy, blasphemy, and highway robbery; (2) the laws of murder and personal injury; and (3)
discretionary penalties.
6. See BERNARD WEISS, THE SPIRIT OF ISLAMIC LAW 38, 101-09 (1998) (identifying a
"textualist-intentionalist bent" among Muslim jurists to describe their historical reliance on text to
determine divine legislative intent, and illustrating the jurist-centric textualist-intentionalism in the
interpretation of the law of theft based on the Qur'dn and related sources).
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
7. See Konrad Moser, "IN DUBIO PRO REO": DIE GESCHICHTLICHE ENTWICKLUNG DIESES
SATZES UND SEINE BEDEUTUNG IM HEUTIGEN DEUTSCHEN STRAFRECHT 77 (1933), cited in George P.
Fletcher, Two Kinds of Legal Rules: A Comparative Study of Burden-of-Persuasion Practices in
Criminal Cases, 77 YALE L.J. 880, 881 n.5 (1968).
8. See JAMES Q. WHITMAN, THE ORIGINS OF REASONABLE DOUBT 334-36 (2008); see also
JOHN H. LANGBEN, THE ORIGINS OF ADVERSARY CRIMINAL TRIAL 334-35 (2003) (describing common
truth-defeating techniques that prosecutors, jurors, and judges used to mitigate the application of capital
punishment for petty crimes in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century England).
9. Fletcher, supra note 7, at 880-81 nn.2-3 (describing these presumptions as modem
Continental restatements of the ancient Roman law maxims in dubio pro reo and nulla poena sine
culpa).
10. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 362-63 (1970) ("[P]roof of a criminal charge beyond a
reasonable doubt is constitutionally required .... The standard provides concrete substance for the
presumption of innocence-that bedrock 'axiomatic and elementary' principle whose 'enforcement lies
at the foundation of the administration of our criminal law."') (citations omitted).
11. For the Court's earliest citation of the lenity rule, see UnitedStates v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S.
76, 95 (1820), stating that "[tihe rule that penal laws are to be construed strictly is perhaps not much less
old than construction itself." For recent applications, see, for example, Burrage v. United States, 134 S.
Ct. 881, 891 (2014), which applied the rule of lenity to reverse a sentencing enhancement against a
defendant for distributing cocaine that "result[ed]" in death, where the prosecution could not prove that
the defendant was the but-for cause of death; and United States v. Santos, 553 U.S. 507, 512 (2008),
which applied the rule of lenity to a money-laundering statute that left in doubt whether the statute's
prohibition on using "proceeds" from unlawful activity applied to "profits" or "receipts" from illegal
gambling activities. For recent rejections, see, for example, Abramski v. United States, 134 S. Ct. 2259,
2272 n.10 (2014), a 5-4 decision in which the majority concluded that the rule of lenity did not apply to
defeat the Court's defendant-disfavoring construction of a gun law provision because, "[a]lthough the
text creates some ambiguity, the context, structure, history, and purpose resolve it"; and United States v.
Hayes, 555 U.S. 415, 429 (2009), a 7-2 decision rejecting the rule of lenity on the grounds that the text,
purpose, and the drafting history clarify that "Congress defined 'misdemeanor crime of domestic
violence' to include an offense 'committed by' a person who had a specified domestic relationship with
the victim." Last Term, Justice Scalia registered his frustration with the Court's halting and inconsistent
application of the rule in strong terms: "If lenity has no role to play in a clear case such as this one, we
ought to stop pretending it is a genuine part of our jurisprudence. Contrary to the majority's miserly
approach, the rule of lenity applies whenever, after all legitimate tools of interpretation have been
exhausted, 'a reasonable doubt persists' [about the criminality of an act] .... " Abramski, 134 S. Ct. at
2281 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (quoting Moskal v. United States, 498 U.S. 103, 108 (1990)). For further
analysis, see Note, The New Rule of Lenity, 119 HARv.L. REV. 2420 (2006) (identifying a narrowed rule
of lenity in recent years through a review of the Rehnquist Court); and Sarah Newland, The Mercy of
Scalia: Statutory Construction and the Rule of Lenity, 29 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 197 (1994)
(discussing Justice Scalia's support for lenity as a textualist tool for statutory interpretation).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
12. See, e.g., MUjAMMAD BAQIR AL-$ADR, LESSONS IN ISLAMIC JURISPRUDENCE 73-86 (Roy
P. Mottahedeh trans., 2003); MUHAMMAD B. IDRIS AL-SHAFII, ISLAMIC JURISPRUDENCE 102-05 (Majid
Khadduri trans., 1961).
13. Muslims regard the Qur'dn as the first source of Islamic law and understand Muhammad
to be the last prophet to have received revelations directly from God, which he recorded in the Qur'an.
Muslims take Mubammad's life example (Sunna) to be a second source of Islamic law. The Sunna was
recorded in thousands of disparate reports of the Prophet's words and actions, called hadth (and for
mainstream Shi' Muslims, the Surma also includes reports from the series of twelve Im~ms who
succeeded the Prophet). For further discussion of the sources of Islamic law, see MOHAMMAD HASHIM
KAMALI, PRINCIPLES OF ISLAMIC JURISPRUDENCE 16-55, 58-60 (3d ed. 2003); and HOSSEIN
MODARRESSI, AN INTRODUCTION TO SHII LAW: A BIBLIOGRAPHICAL STUDY (1984).
14. See PETERS, supranote 5.
15. See infra Subsection I.A.2.
16. See infra Section ll.B.
17. For a comparison between legal canons in Islamic law and American law, see Intisar A.
Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims as Substantive Canons of Construction: Hudfid-Avoidance in Cases of
Doubt, 17 ISLAMIC L. & SOC'Y 63 (2010) [hereinafter Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims]. Elsewhere, I have
referred to the doubt canon as "the Islamic rule of lenity," when emphasizing the aspects of legal
ambiguity inherent in the concept of shubha. See Intisar A. Rabb, The Islamic Rule ofLenity, 44 VAND.
J. TRANSNAT'L L. 1299, 1327-51 (2011) [hereinafter Rabb, Islamic Rule of Lenity]. By contrast, this
discussion is more comprehensive. I seek here to show the expansive definition and historical legal-
institutional implications ofshubha as factual, legal, and moral doubt.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
Muslim world.25
Surprisingly-given its ubiquity-the doubt canon was not always well-
known to Islamic law. In fact, it turns out that the canon was not at all known
to the earliest Muslim jurists as a prophetic statement. The emergence and
growth of reasonable doubt during that period suggests that Muslim jurists'
interpretive moves were doing more work than their legislative supremacy
claims would suggest. The earliest written sources for Islamic law contain no
clear textual directives for "reasonable doubt," and certainly not in the form of
the doubt canon endowed with a prophetic pedigree. It is only the later sources,
some four centuries after the Prophet's death (after the tenth-century "closing
of the doors of interpretation"), that identify a prophetic-textual basis for doubt,
as a legal canon so solid that it came to be regarded as a prophetic report.
Despite indications that early Muslim jurists did not regard the doubt canon as
a hadath in the seventh through ninth centuries, by the tenth and eleventh
centuries, Muslim jurists spoke about the doubt canon as if it had been a
foundational text from the beginning. Yet, some contemporary sources assume
reasonable doubt doctrines were always present in Islamic law, and others
completely deny that it exists. Which is it? My examination of the principal
legal and historical sources from the long founding period of Islamic law
(seventh to eleventh centuries) explores what happened in the interim.
My central claim is that Muslim jurists generated a textual doctrine of
doubt in response to the changing socio-political context of the violent eleventh
century at a time when they were systematizing the law. In doing so, they
sought to define the boundaries of Islamic legitimacy for enforcing criminal
punishments in an attempt to decrease dubious caliph-ordered executions. Such
executions had always been problematic but were cast into relief with the
breakup of the Muslim empire and the accompanying need for jurists to further
systematize Islamic law. 26 Remarkably, these jurists used claims of doubt to
depart from the outcomes that Islam's foundational legal texts seemed to
authorize. Even more remarkably, they did so while claiming fealty to the text,
as faithful agents of a divine lawgiver who established the criminal laws in the
first place. That is, in view of Islam's strongly textualist ideal, these jurists hid
their role in constructing these doctrines under cover of textualism and divine
25. See, e.g., 2 AL-'Izz B. 'ABD AL-SALAM, AL-QAWA'ID AL-KUBRA 279-80 (Nazlh Kamdl
.Hammdd & 'Uthm5n Jumu'a Iumariyya eds., Dar al-Qalam 2d ed. 2007) (citing and listing various
applications of this standard formulation of the canon); IBN NUJAYM, AL-AS-BkH WA'L-NA/7,'IR 142
(Muhammad Muti' al-Hafiz ed., Dir al-Fikr 1983) (same); 4 SHMAB AL-DIN AL-QARAFI, ANWAR AL-
BUROQ F! ANWA' AL-FUROQ 1307 (D~r al-Salam 2001) (same); JALAL AL-DIN AL-SUYOTT, AL-ASHBAH
WA'L-NAZA'IR FTQAWA'ID WA-FURO' AL-SHAFI'IYYA 236-38 (Muhammad al-Mu'ta~im bi-llgh al-
Baghddi ed., Dar al-Kitdb al-'Arabi 1998) (same); see also INTIsAR A. RABB, DOUBT INISLAMIC LAW:
A HISTORY OF LEGAL MAxIMS, INTERPRETATION, AND ISLAMIC CRIMINAL LAW (2014) [hereinafter
DOUBT INISLAMIC LAW] (reviewing in Chapters 6 and 8 the history of Islamic substantive, procedural
and interpretive doubt after the eleventh century, in Sunni and Shl'! contexts, respectively).
26. Notoriously difficult to define, Islamic legitimacy as I use it most closely aligns to
Richard Fallon's helpfiul categories from American law of the legal, sociological, and moral criteria by
which jurists successfully assert their authority to define law. See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Legitimacy and
the Constitution, 118 HARV. L. REv. 1787 (2005). For further analysis in the Islamic legal context, see
infra Section I.B.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
Islam's foundational legal texts related to criminal law. Part II presents the
means by which Muslim jurists canonized, textualized, and generalized the
doubt canon. Part III explores the motives for which these jurists converted the
judicial canon into a foundational text. In the end, I conclude that Muslim
jurists operating in the eleventh century were systematizing the law and needed
a textual doctrine of doubt to solidify their authority, ameliorate their moral
concerns at authorizing punishment on dubious grounds, and check the political
ruler's arbitrary and excessive use of punishment. Even if the jurists could not
prevent executions, the newly textual status of the doubt canon rendered it a
powerful tool for them to argue against the legitimacy of punishment as a tool
for state violence and social control.
27. For an insightful analogy in the American context comparing the statutory approach of an
early U.S. Supreme Court case to constitutional amendment, see infra note 70.
28. See generally NOAH FELDMAN, THE FALL AND RISE OF THE ISLAMIC STATE (2008)
(analyzing the increasing popularity of calls for sharTa as a basis for state law in Middle Eastern
contexts); RAN HIRSCHL, CONSTITUTIONAL THEOCRACY (2010) (surveying the increasing role of
Islamic and other religious laws as modem state laws).
29. See Dawood I. Ahmed & Tom Ginsburg, ConstitutionalIslamization and Human Rights:
The Surprising Origin and Spread of Islamic Supremacy in Constitutions, 54 VA. J. INT'L L.
(forthcoming 2015) (providing an empirical review of all Islamic law constitutional clauses); Intisar A.
Rabb, We the Jurists:Islamic Constitutionalism in Iraq, 10 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 527 (2008) (providing a
qualitative review of one such clause in the context of three common types of Islamic
constitutionalization). For developments after the Arab uprisings, see S.A. Arjomand, Middle Eastern
Constitutional and Ideological Revolutions and the Rise of Juristocracy, 19 CONSTELLATIONS 204
(2012); Karim Mezran, Constitutionalism and Islam in Libya, in CONSTITUTIONALISM IN ISLAMIC
COUNTRIES: BETWEEN UPHEAVAL AND CONTINUITY 513 (Rainer Grote & Tilmann J. R6der eds., 2012);
Intisar A. Rabb, The Least Religious Branch? Judicial Review and the New Islamic Constitutionalism,
17 UCLA J. INT'L L. & FOREIGN AFF. 72 (2013).
30. Penal codes based on Islamic Law include Afghanistan, PENAL CODE of 1976; Brunei,
SYARIAH PENAL CODE of 2014; Iran, QANON-I MUJAZAT-I ISLAMI-YI IRAN [ISLAMIC PENAL CODE] of
1991, as amended in 1996 and 2013; Kuwait, QANON AL-JAZA' [PENAL CODE], Law No. 16 of 1960, as
amended by Law No. 31 of 1970; Libya, QANON AL-'UQOBAT [PENAL CODE] of 1953, as amended by
Law No. 70 of 1973 and Law No. 4 of 2002; Maldives, PENAL CODE ACT NO. 1/81 of 1961, as amended
in 2014; Oman, QANON AL-JAZA' [PENAL CODE] of 1974; Pakistan, PENAL CODE of 1860, amended by
Hudood Ordinance, Law Nos. 7 and 9 of 1979; Qatar, QANON AL-'UQOBAT [PENAL CODE], Law No. 14
of 1971, as replaced by Law No. 11 of 2004; Sudan, PENAL CODE of 2003; United Arab Emirates,
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
QANON AL-'UQOB.T AL-ITI.ADI [UNIFORM PENAL CODE], Law No. 3 of 1987; Yemen, [QANYN] AL-
JARKIM WA'L-'UQOBAT [CRIME AND PUNISHMENT CODE], Law No. 12 of 1994; as well as provinces in
Malaysia (Kelantan), SYARIAH CRIMINAL CODE (II) ACT OF 1993 [STATE OF KELANTAN]; Nigeria (ten
northern Nigerian states between 2000 and 2001: Bauchi, Gombe, Jigawa, Kaduna, Kano, Katsina,
Kebbi, Sokoto, Yobe, Zarnfara), BAUCHI STATE PENAL CODE of 2001; GOMBE STATE PENAL LAW of
2001; JIGAWA STATE PENAL CODE, Law No. 12 of 2000; KADUNA STATE PENAL CODE of 2002; KANO
STATE PENAL CODE of 2000; KATSINA STATE PENAL CODE of 2001; KEBBI STATE PENAL CODE, Law
No. 21 of 2000; SOKOTO STATE PENAL CODE of 2000; YOBE STATE PENAL CODE, Law No. 8 of 2001;
ZAMFARA STATE PENAL CODE, Law No. 10 of 2000; see also 4 PHILIP OSTIEN, SHARIA
IMPLEMENTATION IN NORTHERN NIGERIA, 1999-2006: A SOURCEBOOK (2007) (citing and reproducing
these Nigerian state penal codes where available); HAUWA IBRAHIM, PRACTICING SHARIAH LAW, app. D
(2012) (providing the text of the Sokoto and Zamfara State Shariah Penal Laws of 2000); and Indonesia
(Aceh), QANUN JINAYAT [PENAL CODE] OF 2009, as amended in 2014. Non-codified practices have
been reported informally in Algeria (in 1993), parts of Iraq controlled by the so-called Islamic State of
Iraq and the Levant (since 2014), Northern Mali (since 2012), the Swat Valley Region of Pakistan (since
2004), Somalia (since the 1990s), and Syria (since 2013).
31. For analysis, see generally Rudolph Peters, The Islamization of Criminal Law: A
ComparativeAnalysis, 34 DIE WELT DES ISLAMS 246 (1994). For country-specific studies, see ASMA
JAHANGIR & HINA JILANI, THE HUDOOD ORDINANCES: A DIVINE SANCTION? (1988); Mohammad
Hashim Kamali, Punishment in Islamic Law: A Critique of the HudFidBill of Kelantan, Malaysia, 13
ARAB L.Q. 203 (1998); Ziba Mir-Hosseini, Criminalising Sexuality: Zina Laws as Violence Against
Women in Muslim Contexts, 8 SUR - INT'L J. HUM. RTS. 7 (2011); Asifa Quraishi, Her Honor: An
Islamic Critique of the Rape Laws of Pakistanfrom a Woman-Sensitive Perspective, 18 MICH. J. INT'L
L. 287 (1996); Abdel Salam Sidahmed, Problems in Contemporary Applications of Islamic Criminal
Sanctions: The Penaltyfor Adultery in Relation to Women, 28 BRIT. J. MIDDLE E. STUDS. 187 (2001).
32. See, e.g., CLARK B. LOMBARDI, STATE LAW AS ISLAMIC LAW IN MODERN EGYPT: THE
INCORPORATION OF THE SHARI'A INTO EGYPTIAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (2006); Clark B. Lombardi,
Egypt's Supreme Constitutional Court: Managing Constitutional Conflict in an Authoritarian,
Aspirationally "Islamic" State, 3 J. COMP. L. 234-5 3 (2008).
33. E.g., Case No. 45 of Judicial Year 28, 12 SCC 1359 (Sup. Const. Ct. 2009) (Egypt)
(citing legal canons and Islamic principles in upholding personal status law reforms requiring that
marriages be registered to be recognized as valid); Case No. 23 of Judicial Year 20, 12 SCC 307 (Sup.
Const. Ct. 2007) (Egypt) (citing Qur'dnic verses and historical juristic interpretations of family law
provisions to uphold an Art. 2 "sharl'aclause" challenge to alimony requirements of personal status law
reforms); Case No. 62, Judicial Year 19, 12 SCC 92 (Sup. Const. Ct. 2006) (Egypt) (citing and applying
Qur'5nic verses and legal canons on contractual performance to uphold a challenged property law
statute). I have used SCC as the English initials for the name of the Supreme Constitutional Court and
its reporter, al-Mahkama al-Dustariyya al-'Ulya. For a translation and analysis of one SCC case, see
Nathan J. Brown & Clark B. Lombardi, Translation: The Supreme ConstitutionalCourt of Egypt on
Islamic Law, Veiling and Civil Rights: An Annotated Translation of Supreme ConstitutionalCourt of
Egypt Case No. 8 ofJudicialYear 17 (May 18, 1996), 21 AM. U. INT'L L. REv. 437 (2006).
34. See Rob Quinn, U.S. Firm Calls for Islamic Law in Lawsuit: Blackwater Boss Seeks
Sharia Law to Dodge Afghan Crash Suit, NEWSER (June 19, 2008, 7:51 AM), http://www.newser.com
/story/30373/us-firm-calls-for-islamic-law-in-lawsuit.html (describing Blackwater's request to apply
Islamic law in a federal suit for the deaths of three U.S. soldiers in Afghanistan, as the firm would
escape liability under classical Islamic "criminal" law rules of personal injury). The suit ultimately
settled.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
politicians have incorporated classical Islamic criminal law rules into state and
regional codes, usually in attempts to assert power as well as an Islamic
identity based on the popular notion of Islamic law as a text-based system of
harsh criminal rules. 35 Criminal defense lawyers operating in these regimes
have appealed to classical Islamic criminal law precepts-including the doubt
canon and the Case of Mj 'iz-to defend their clients, usually
36
in attempts to
bring more pragmatic understandings of Islamic law to bear.
In all of these modem manifestations, Islamic law reveals itself to be both
a textualist and an originalist legal tradition. That is, any invocation of Islamic
law in a modem constitution or code generally contemplates an appeal back to
Islam's foundational texts and its founding period.37 Yet, the scholarly and
judicial reviews of the history of doubt in Islamic law have been
impressionistic at best and overlooked at worst. 38 This Article explores the
35. The overwhelming majority of modern Islamic criminal law codes exclude the doubt
doctrine based on what seems to be an ahistorical textualist view of Islamic law adopted by the
parliamentarians who enacted them for political gains. See Vanja Hamzi6, Nigeria, in CONTROL AND
SEXUALITY: THE REVIVAL OF ZINA LAWS IN MUSLIM CONTEXTS 119 (Vanja Harnzi6 & Ziba Mir-
Hosseini eds., 2010) (arguing that "the introduction of hudad laws came as a consequence of political
crisis and opportunism characterized by patriarchal oppression and the misuse of religion as a means of
societal control") (citations omitted). The very texts of the codes suggest that, in a departure from
historical Islamic legal practice, the modem parliamentarians drafting them likely consulted
foundational and other early texts-which typically do not include the doubt canon. Neither trained in
Islamic law nor in Islamic history, these politicians attempted to construct new laws based on the Qur'dn
and hadth as well as basic abridgements of legal works, failing to account for the judicial practices that
historically incorporated doubt or to the developed works of substantive Islamic criminal law and legal
maxims, which included the doubt canon as central and counted the doubt canon as a foundational text.
For a list of codes, see supra note 30. One exception to that rule is a recent reform to the Iranian Penal
Code, which incorporated the doubt canon after much wrangling between textualist and pragmatic
jurists, the latter of which-trained as specialists in classical Islamic law and often in history-in
conjunction with secularly trained comparative lawyers and criminal law experts, demanded it. The
juristic, parliamentary, and popular debates giving rise to the recent Iranian criminal law reforms are the
subject of another study. For the relevant provisions, see QANiJN-I MUJAZAT-I ISLAMI-I IRAN [IRANIAN
ISLAMIC PENAL CODE] 1392 [2013], arts. 120-21.
36. A prominent example is the case of Amina Lawal, a woman convicted in 2002 of adultery
and sentenced to death under Nigeria's penal code. Lawal's lawyers successfully appealed to overturn
the conviction based on citation to the Case of Md iz, the doubt canon, and other procedural lessons that
were regular features of historical Islamic legal practice. See IBRAHIM, supra note 30, at 148-83
(describing the role of the defense counsel at trial and on appeal); OSTMEN, supra note 30, at 52-82
(providing case transcripts of the Amina Lawal proceedings); Philip Ostien & Albert Dekker, Sharia
and National Law in Nigeria, in SHARIA INCORPORATED: A COMPARATIVE OVERVIEW OF THE LEGAL
SYSTEMS OF TWELVE MUSLIM COUNTRIES IN PAST AND PRESENT 589-93 (Jan Michiel Otto ed., 2010)
(describing the adoption and application of Islamic criminal law in Northern Nigeria).
37. Cf FELDMAN, supra note 28, at 4-5 (comparing Muslims' "active and continuing
engagement with the constitutional past" to the way in which "Madison, Jefferson, and Hamilton
continued to shape the American constitutional tradition from beyond the grave [such that] it is
impossible to understand arguments about the American Constitution today without taking these
founding fathers into account").
38. I am aware of five articles and four monographs on the Islamic doubt doctrine (besides
my own), all of which are recent, and almost all of which (with the exception of the article by Maribel
Fierro) are Arabic or Persian catalogs of the legal doctrine that do not analyze its history or social
context. The articles are Muhammad Bahrdmi, BarrasT va tahlTl-ifiqh! va huqfq!-i qd 'idah-i 'tudra' al-
huduid bi'l-shubahit', 5-6 DIDGAHHA-YI IJUQOQI 19 (1997-8); Mubammad Mdsawi Bujnflrdi, LW
qd'idah-ifiqhi" Qa'idah-i 'tudra' al-.udfid bi'l-shubahat,' 8 FASLNAMAH-I DIDGAHHA-Y IJUQOQI 11
(1986-87); Fierro, supra note 23; Muhammad Muhammadi GilnI, Ashind 7 bd q& idah-i 'al-Hudfid
tudra' bi'l-shubahat,' 5 MAJALLAH-I QAI)A'T VA-IUQ3QI-I DADGUSTARI-I JUMHORI-I ISLAMI-I RAN 15-
16 (1996-97); RiO Usthdl, Qd 'idah-idar', 34 FIQH- AHL-I BAYT 46 (2005) (Part 1); and 37 id.at 71-94
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
history in question.
This section examines the debates about the famous Case of M 'iz, and
why these debates-and the jurists who engaged them-mattered so much
historically to definitions of Islamic law and governance. I argue that medieval
Muslim jurists' debates about Md'iz were their attempts to define the proper
boundaries of Islamic legal interpretation, institutions, and legitimacy.39 On the
interpretive level, jurists' internal debates about M5'iz reveal disputes about
how best to resolve uncertainty and doubt at the level of adjudication. On the
institutional level, the debates point to the scope of juristic competence to
resolve doubt. And on the level of legitimacy, the debates suggest that Muslim
jurists strategically used doubt and claims of their institutional competence to
resolve it as tools for asserting their own authority and thereby defining the
classical Islamic constitutional structure for legitimate applications of criminal
04
law.
Throughout this discussion, it is important to bear in mind that, in
historical Islamic contexts, there were no constitutionally defined institutions of
law and governance. 4' But to say that the institutions were not defined top-
down by a formal constitution is not to say that these institutions did not exist.
An informal constitutional arrangement unfolded whereby a class of scholar-
jurists assumed the power to interpret sharT'a as a system of law, and
monarchical rulers called caliphs assumed the power to enforce it.42 Between
them were judges, whom the caliph appointed and who looked to the jurists for
formulations of law. 43 From this arrangement, scholars commenting on Islamic
(Part II). The monographs are 'AQILA HUSAYN, AL-SHUBAHAT AL-MUSQITA LI'L-uUDOD (Dir Ibn Hazm
2003); SA'ID MANS13RI, QAVA'ID-I FIQH: BAKHSH-I JAZA'I-FIQH-1 TATBTQI-YI QAIDAH-I DAR' (Tadbir
1997); MUUAMMAD HASAN AL-RABBANT, QAIDAT AL-DAR' (Mu'assasat al-Nashr al-Islni al-Tabi'a li-
Jami'at al-Mudarrisin 2007); and SA'ID B. MISFIR AL-DAGHGHAR AL-WADI'!, ATHAR AL-SHUBAHT Fl
DAk' AL-HUDOD (Maktabat al-Tawba 1998).
39. Cf Fallon, supra note 26, at 1849-51 (outlining an "overall" legitimacy that combines
legal, sociological, and moral criteria for judicial authority).
40. Other scholars have recognized the link between jurists and legitimacy. E.g., FELDMAN,
supra note 28, at 2; WAEL B. HALLAQ, AUTHORITY, CONTINUITY, AND CHANGE IN ISLAMIC LAW 159-
83 (2001). But none have examined closely how jurists used interpretation to define institutional roles,
the elaboration of that process in significant part through criminal law, or the reasons that explain or
justify both moves. This section seeks to take up that task in the course of arguing that Muslim jurists
used specific interpretive maneuvers to expand their power over criminal law and limit that of the
executive through defining the contours of legitimate punishment.
41. In fact, there were no constitutions until Muslim-majority countries adopted American-
and European-style constitutions at the turn of the twentieth century (in the Ottoman Empire in 1876 and
in Iran in 1906), and then again after the post-World War II colonialism in large parts of the Muslim
World. Even where there were constitutions, there was a weak tradition of constitutionalism and few
inroads to democracy until the 2010 uprisings in the Arab world. See NATHAN BROWN, CONSTITUTIONS
IN A NONCONSTITUTIONAL WORLD (2002).
42. FELDMAN, supra note 28, at 2.
43. See WAEL B. HALLAQ, SHARI'A: THEORY, PRACTICE, TRANSFORMATIONS 176-81 (2009).
To be sure, several other officials exercised criminal law jurisdiction outside of the scheme. However,
this tripartite scheme provided the main pivots for law and order, and-as elaborated below-even in
those contexts, the caliphal officials were in principle subject to juridical articulations of law that set the
upper limits of punishment.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
Why so much ado about Ma'iz? For starters, the Case of M 'iz is a rather
complicated basis for an early precedent, as it is not entirely clear what
happened. As a text, it contained a "foundational uncertainty" that sparked
debates over its meaning and precedential value for criminal law.45 Here is the
full account:
44. FELDMAN, supra note 28, at 2, 4, 68 (noting an "institutional separation of scholars and
state").
45. For use of this term to refer to analogous problems that arise in constitutional and
international law, which also lack legislatures to specify and update legal norms, see Darryl Levinson &
Jack Goldsmith, Law for States: InternationalLaw, ConstitutionalLaw, Public Law, 122 HARV. L. REV.
1791, 1794 (2009).
46. See 9 IBN ABI SHAYBA, MUSANNAF nos. 21254, 29240-41 (Hamad b. 'Abd Allah al-
Jumu'a & Muhammad b. Ibr'him al-Lal.idan eds., 2007). In addition to this pre-canonical collection of
hadith, which records the earliest known version of the case, the Case of Md 'iz also appeared in the two
main canonical collections of prophetic reports. See 4 MUHAMMAD B. ISMAIL AL-BUKHARI, SAHIj no.
6824 (Mutafa al-Dhahabi ed., Ddr al-Hadlith 2000) [hereinafter BUKHARI]; MUSLIM B. HAJJAJ AL-
QUSHAYRI, SAIT, nos. 4198-4206 (AbOi Suhayb al-Karami ed., Bayt al-Afkdr al-Dawliyya 1998)
[hereinafter MUSLIM].
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
capital punishment, he exclaimed in dismay that they "should have let M!'iz
go!" If Md'iz had repented, the Prophet added, "God would surely have
accepted his repentance," which would have absolved him of punishment.47
Adultery in Islamic law was a serious moral infraction, with high criminal
stakes. The Qur'dn prohibits fornication and adultery (both called zin5) and
directs judges to "flog those guilty of zind, whether male or female, with 100
lashes each.",48 In addition, though stoning was not a Qur'dnic punishment,
early Muslims understood the Sunna as also authorizing death by stoning for
adultery convictions. 49 If his confession were to be believed, Md'iz had
violated the Islamic law against adultery and would be liable for punishment.
From his concluding statement, it appears that the Prophet had been
reluctant to punish Md'iz, and on one reading, he had never intended to enforce
the punishment at all. Even though he had convicted Md'iz, he had "doubt" (as
most later Muslim jurists would term it), perhaps about whether the law
covered the act of the defendant, whether the procedures deployed to assess the
defendant's act and his intent were sufficient to prove that he had committed
zind, or whether punishment was warranted. It was quite possible that Md'iz
would repent from the crime, or that he already had done so through confessing
and then attempting to flee, in which case the Prophet may have preferred to
avoid punishment. On these grounds, the Prophet-who of all people should
have been beholden to follow God's commands-was willing to set aside a
strict reading of the text.
47. See IBN ABI SHAYBA, supranote 46. The other ninth-century sources collecting prophetic
reports of early "cases" like these are replete with similar stories of individual confessions and hesitance
to punish. See, e.g., BUKHART, supra note 46, no. 6823 (reporting that a man came to the Prophet
confessing to having committed a serious crime multiple times, until the Prophet responded that his
joining of congregational prayers indicated repentance, so God had forgiven him).
48. See THE QUR'AN 17:32 (prohibiting zint--defined as fornication or adultery); id. at 24:2
(specifying a punishment of flogging or home imprisonment).
49. On the introduction of reports about stoning as a Qur'dnic punishment, see Hossein
Modarressi, Early Debates on the Integrity of the Qur'dn: A Brief Survey, 77 STUDIA ISLAMICA 5-10
(1993).
50. The case featured in the criminal law section of all the extant major collections of
prophetic reports (which provided the raw materials for the later tenth- and eleventh-century
systematization of law), from the eighth century through the eleventh century. See BUKHAR, supra note
46; see also 1 ABO AL-HASAN AL-MAwARDI, KITAB AL-IHUDOD MIN AL-.tkwT AL-KABIR 206 n.1
(Ibrahim b. 'Ali Sanduqji ed., 1995) (listing other major hadith sources, including 'Abd al-Razziq,
Ahmad b. Hanbal, Drimi, AbQ Ddwid, Tirmidhi, Ibn Majah, Ibn al-Mundhir, TahwI, Tabarani, al-
.Hakim al-Nayssbiri, and Bayhaqi). The case also featured in the criminal law chapters of all major legal
treatises (where the debates played out) from the eighth century through the present day. For a sampling
of those discussions in legal treatises, in chronological order by author, see ABO YOSUF, IKHTILAf ABT
H ANTFA WA-IBN ABT LAYLA 156 (Abi 'l-Wafa' al-Afghsni ed., Matba'at al-Wafa- 1938); ABO YOsUF,
KITAB AL-ATHAR 157 (AbY 'l-Wafia' ed., Lajnat lhya' al-Ma'drif a-Nu'mniyya 1936); 7 MLTUAMMAD
B. IDRIS AL-SHAFI'T, UMM 498 (Ahmad Badr al-Din Hassin ed., D~r Qutayba 1996); 2 JA$SA$, supra
note 22, at 108; 3 id. at 263-64; 11 ABO AL-HUSAYN AIMAD B. MUHAMMAD AL-QUDORT, TAJRID: AL-
MAWSO'A AL-FIQHtYYA AL-MUQARANA 5891, 5949-50 (Muhammad Abmad al-Sirj & 'AlI Jumu'a
Mulhammad eds., DAr al-Salgm 2004); MAWARDI, supra; 12 IBN IJAZM, AL-MUttALLA Bt'L-ATHAR 18-
22 ('Abd al-Ghaff-r Sulaymtn al-Bind.ri ed., Dar al-Kutub al-'lmiyya 1988); 2 BURItAIJ AL-DIN AL-
MARGHINANI, AL-HIDAYA SHARI BIDAYAT AL-MUBTADI' 735-36 (Muhammad Mulhammad T8rmir &
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
debates emerged in large part because the jurists could not agree on the precise
factual account or the normative significance of the case. They generally
agreed on the eventual outcome: Md'iz was punished despite the Prophet's
objections.51 They also agreed that the case was important: its provenance in
the founding period with the Prophet presiding as a judge made it a source of
normative guidance for future generations. But they disagreed about which
outcome (punishment
52 or release), and therefore which interpretive approach,
was correct.
H~fiz 'Ashiir Hfiz eds., Dar al-Salm 2000); and IBN ABI AL-QASIM, AL-WAD11I FT SHAR.U
MUKHTA$AR AL-KHIRAQT 413 ('Abd al-Malik b. 'Abd Allah b. Duhaysh ed., Dar Khidr 2000). For a
similar discussion in a well-known treatise of Islamic political theory, see IBN QAYYIM AL-JAWZ1YYA,
AL-TURUQ AL-1:IUKMIYYA FT 'L-SIYASA AL-SHAR'IYYA 87 (Muhbammad Jaml Ghdzi ed., Matba'at al-
Madani 1978).
51. To be sure, there are some questions about what happened: whether the Prophet
authorized punishment and then regretted it, whether Md'iz had in fact repented verbally or through
trying to escape once the punishment had commenced, or whether the Prophet's reasons for rebuking the
townspeople was out of mercy. Gaps in the "record" of this kind were typical for early cases, which
were reported in the hadTth literature with extremely sparse details about the litigants' conversations, the
outcome of the case, and the reasoning. These gaps helped provide the jurists with room for interpretive
maneuvering, that is, filling in the gaps about what happened with normative rules about what should
have happened based on the doctrines that they later devised-as this Article aims to illustrate through
tracing the evolution of the doubt doctrine from and as applied to the Case ofM 'iz. For further notes on
the historiography of cases in early Islamic legal sources, see infra note 148.
52. For example, compare QUDORI, supra note 50, at 5949-50 (demonstrating the pragmatic
textualist approach of a Hanafi jurist) with 12 IBN HAZM, supra note 50, at 18-22 (exemplifying the
strict textualist approach of a ZhirI contemporary of Qudfii).
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
For the jurists who maintained that the townspeople had properly
enforced the punishment against Md'iz, it was God himself who had required
the punishment. God was the sole legislator. The dictates of His texts therefore
bound both the Prophet and the townspeople. That is, not even the Prophet
could depart from the rule requiring punishment. The strict textualists looked to
the Case of Md 'iz alongside other early cases both to justify their interpretive
approach to that case and to distill specific textualist legal precepts about when
to enforce or avoid punishment.
Their argument was colorfully advanced by the Muslim jurist known as
53. I use this term to reflect the concept of pragmatic, practical, or dynamic statutory
interpretation elaborated by William Eskridge. See WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR., DYNAMIC STATUTORY
INTERPRETATION 275-306 (1994) (noting the ongoing use of legal canons as a feature of dynamic
interpretation); William N. Eskridge, Jr., Norms, Empiricism, and Canons in Statutory Interpretation,66
U. CHI. L. REV. 671, 671 (1999) (describing the eclectic approaches to statutory interpretation deployed
by judges and scholars as pragmatic); see also William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey, Statutory
Interpretationas PracticalReasoning, 42 STAN. L. REV. 42 321, 322 n.3 (1990) ("By 'practical reason,'
we mean an approach that eschews objectivist theories in favor of a mixture of inductive and deductive
reasoning (similar to the practice of the common law), seeking contextual justification for the best legal
answer among the potential alternatives."). To be sure, John Manning has insisted that modem
textualism is different from old formalist textualism, in that the modem version accommodates
"contextual readings of statutory text" by recognizing that "language has meaning only in its social and
linguistic context." John Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2455 (2003); see
also John Manning, Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 108-15 (2001)
("[M]odem textualists acknowledge that language has meaning only in context."). Acknowledging
Manning's inclusion of semantic and social context as his version of what Eskridge labeled the "new
textualism," Eskridge called Manning's approach "contextualist textualism." See William N. Eskridge,
Jr., No Frills Textualism, 119 HARv. L. REV. 2041, 2051 (2006) (reviewing ADRIAN VERMEULE,
JUDGING UNDER UNCERTAINTY: AN INSTITUTIONAL THEORY OF LEGAL INTERPRETATION (2006));
William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism, 37 UCLA L. REV. 621-91 (1990).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
Dawtid al-Zahir-that is, "D wdd the Textualist"-who established the strict
textualist school of Islamic law.54 To begin with, he argued, God required
judges to appeal only to the Qur'dn and authentic, clear reports of the Sunna
without permitting human interpretation." His approach to criminal law was to
apply each rule according to the plain meaning of the text. Whenever a crime
was established, judges were to enforce the associated punishment.5 6 Further, a
judge was not to express personal preferences or exercise any discretion in such
cases. 57 Considerations of mercy, moral concerns, or contextual facts were
irrelevant.
For proof, textualist judges looked to the Qur'an itself, which
commanded in the context of adultery prohibition and punishment: "do not let
mercy dissuade you from imposing the punishment." 58 Textualists also looked
to reports of other early cases that more clearly showed instances where the
Prophet acknowledged that even he was required to apply the punishments
specified in the Qur'dnic texts, without exercising discretion of his own. For
example, in the Case of the MakhzigmT Thief, Muhammad had convicted a
woman for theft. In that case, the elite members of society petitioned the
Prophet to avoid punishment and let the convict go. The petitioners were
members of Muhammad's family, as was the woman convicted of stealing. The
Prophet responded that even his hands were tied from pardoning the woman,
where the evidence proved her guilt. "Would you intervene on a matter
involving God's laws?" he asked. "I swear by God that even if Fatima [my own
daughter] had stolen, I would cut off her hand!", 59 Here, the Prophet was
54. For an outline of his textualist legal theory, as presented in his son's law manual, see
Devin Stewart, Muhammad b. Ddwtvd al-Z5hir's Manual of Jurisprudence,al-Wu~til i15 Ma'rifat al-
USal, in STUDIES IN ISLAMIC LEGAL THEORY 99, 139-54 (Bernard G. Weiss ed., 2002), which notes that
Dawtd made inferences from textual indicators, but rejected the use of analogy, equity, and other forms
of interpretation used by other Muslim jurists of his time. For a fuller account of his jurisprudence, see
'ARIF KHALIL MUI.AMMAD ABO 'ID, IMAM DAWOD AL-ZAHIRI WA-ATHARUH F 'L-FIQH AL-ISLAMI (Dir
al-Arqam 1984). Note that this brand of Islamic textualism differs from "first-" and "second-generation"
American textualism-though the former provides an analytical hook by which to grasp analogous
Islamic legal debates in the Zdhiri school. See John F. Manning, Second-Generation Textualism, 98
CALIF. L. REV. 1287 (2010) (outlining the tenets of old and new, or second-generation, textualism);
John F. Manning, Textualism and Legislative Intent, 91 VA. L. REV. 419, 420-21 (2005) (same).
55. Stewart, supra note 54, at 157-58 (arguing that allowing "interpretation" would permit
each judge to rule according to "whim, [giving a ruling] opposite that determined by the fancy of [the
next judgel").
56. MUIIAMMAD AL-SHATTT, RISALA FT 'L-MADHHAB AL-IMAM DAWOD AL-ZAHIRI 25
(Matba'at Rawdtat al-Shfm 1912) (collecting legal opinions attributed to Dawid b. 'AR from various
works, including the strict enforcement of criminal punishment even in cases where a criminal
defendant who confessed to a crime subsequently retracted the confession).
57. See Stewart, supra note 54, at 156-57 (quoting Dwfid al-Zfhiri making a case against
interpretation by quoting Qur'5n 4:105, "We have revealed the Book unto you with the truth so that you
may judge between mankind by that which God shows you. Do not be a pleader for the treacherous,"
and commenting that God did not say, "by that which you think for yourself' or "by that to which your
preferences and perceptions lead you").
58. THE QUR'AN 24:2. For analysis in a medieval legal-exegetical treatise on the import of
Qur'Anic verses about issues of law, see 3 ABO BAKR IBN AL-'ARABI, AHKAM AL-QUR'AN 334-35 (Ddr
al-Fikr 1978).
59. The term for "God's laws" here is hudfdAlldh. The early, Qur'dnic meaning of the term
referred simply to "Islamic law." The term later came to mean "Islamic criminal law." For reports of
this case, see 8 ABO BAKR AL-BAYHAQI, SuNAN no. 17004 (Muhammad 'Abd al-Qfdir 'Ata' ed., 1994);
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
referring to the Qur'dnic punishment for theft. 60 Together, the Case of M 'iz
and the Case of the Makhzfimr Thief were both foundational cases that textualist
judges understood to mean that even the Prophet's authority was restricted to
text. Like him, all judges were bound to a version of divine legislative
supremacy that required them to follow the strict meaning of the texts.61
Two centuries later, as other jurists were systematizing doctrines in their
respective schools of law, Dawild's famous disciple Ibn Hazm further
elaborated the Islamic legal school of strict textualism. Ibn Hazm began with
the common point that the Qur'dn and Sunna were the only valid sources of
law. For him, these sources specified that judges were to enforce criminal
punishments whenever the evidence established that a crime had been
committed. Not even the Prophet could diverge from the strict dictates of the
text. 62 Thus, the Case of Md'iz shed no light on whether and how the judges
should handle doubt. Precisely because the meaning behind the Prophet's
rebuke of the townspeople for punishing Md'iz was unclear, his statement was
not normative. According to Ibn Hazm, to interpret the Prophet's statement as
doubt about the propriety of punishment, as most jurists did, was mere
speculation. For him, the case itself did not suggest any legal role for doubt at
all. The only relevant question for criminal liability was whether there was
proof in court that a defendant had violated a textual prohibition. 63 Neither
doubt nor any other contextual consideration was relevant for the strict
textualists, because none of the authentic prophetic texts had mentioned those
factors.64 In short, Ibn Hazm and his strict textualist followers saw themselves
as arguing for text over spirit.
b. The Case for Avoiding the Punishment: Pragmatic
Textualist Readings of the Case of M5'iz
BUKHART, supra note 46, no. 6788; MUSLIM, supra note 46, no. 1688; 4 A..MAD B. SHU'AYB AL-
NASA'T, AL-SUNAN AL-KUBRA 330 (Iasan 'Abd aI-Mun'im al-Shalabi ed., 2001); and 4 ABO DAWOD
AL- SIJISTANI, SUNAN nos. 4373-74 (Muhammad 'Abd al-'Aziz al-Khalidi ed., 1996).
60. THE QUR'AN 5:38. For problems that Muslim jurists faced in interpreting the verse and
determining the associated punishment, see WEISS, supranote 6, at 104-09.
61. See 8 IBN HAZM, supra note 50, at 252.
62. 12 IBN HAZM, supra note 50, at 18, 22.
63. Id.
64. For Ibn H azm's rejection of the prophetic origin of the doubt canon, see id. at 47-63. For
discussion, see Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims, supra note 17, at 111-13.
65. E.g., MARGHINANT, supra note 50; MAWARDT, supra note 50, at 206; QUDORI, supra note
50, at 5949-50. For further discussion, see Rabb, Islamic Rule of Lenity, supra note 17, at 1327-49.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
66. This formulation recalls language from Church of Holy Trinity v. United States, 143 U.S.
457 (1892), which presented a conflict between a strictly textual reading and a purposive reading that
went beyond the text of an immigration and labor statute. See Holy Trinity, 143 U.S. at 459 ("[W]c
cannot think Congress intended to denounce with penalties a transaction like that in the present case. It
is a familiar rule, that a thing may be within the letter of the statute and yet not within the statute,
because not within its spirit, nor within the intention of its makers."). For the significance of the spirit-
versus-text controversy and the analogous importance of Holy Trinity, see infra note 70.
67. QUDORI, supra note 50, at 5949-50.
68. Id.
69. The looming question would be how to define doubt, which was expansive, as described
further below in Subsection III.B.3.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
The Case of Md 'iz became iconic in Islamic criminal law. 70 It is not that
the case by itself created the doctrine of doubt that lies at the heart of the story
about interpretation in Islamic law. To be sure, it was a part of the series of
early landmark cases on which Muslim jurists drew to outline a doctrine of
doubt-common law fashion-over the course of several centuries, until they
textualized the doctrine in the tenth and eleventh centuries. But the Case of
M 'iz itself was illustrative rather than generative of that end.
So why did debates about Md'iz matter so much? They were significant
because they went to issues of constitutional structure and legitimacy. I contend
that the Case of Ma 'iz demonstrates how jurists used interpretation to define
criminal law. They also used it to define institutions of law and governance,
organically and bottom-up.
Here is how. Recall that, in historical Islamic contexts, an informal
constitutional arrangement unfolded featuring a type of separation of powers:
the class of jurists assumed the power to interpret Islamic law, the caliphs
asserted the executive power to enforce it, and judges shuttled between the
two. 71 Neither judges nor jurists possessed the prerogative to make law, which
Islamic legal doctrine yields exclusively to a divine Legislator (who legislated
once in the seventh century). Thus, Islamic textualism debates are framed in
terms of legislative supremacy-a super-strong version of divine legislative
supremacy that requires a limited role of judges in order not to derogate from
divine directives. Islamic textualism also comes with a heavy intentionalist
imperative, prompting jurists to focus on legal texts to discover divine
legislative intent. These observations-read alongside the Case of M(Viz-
suggest that, whenever Muslim jurists interpreted texts alongside cases like that
of Md'iz, they defined their own role against that of other political actors.
70. For a sense of the importance of this case to Islamic interpretation debates, consider the
discussion surrounding Holy Trinity, and the conflict between text and extratextual context, in American
statutory interpretation debates. See, e.g., Frederick Schauer, ConstitutionalInvocations, 65 FORDHAM
L. REV. 1295, 1307 (1997) ("Church of the Holy Trinity v. United States is not only a case, but is the
marker for an entire legal tradition, a tradition ... emphasizing ... that there is far more to law than the
plain meaning of authoritative legal texts .... ") (citations omitted); cf ESKRIDGE, supra note 53, at 209
(labeling the case a "sensation" that inaugurated a trend of judicial use of legislative history); ADRIAN
VERMEULE, JUDGING UNDER UNCERTAINTY 88 (2006) (observing that most judicial and academic
commentaries on legislative history and statutory interpretation theory begin with Holy Trinity as "the
leading case in the legislative history debate," known for "endorsing countertextual interpretive
techniques"); Antonin Scalia, Common Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States
Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATrER OF
INTERPRETATION 3, 18-23 (Amy Gutman ed., 1997) (describing Holy Trinity as the "prototypical case
involving the triumph of supposed 'legislative intent' . . . over the text of the law"); Adrian Vermeule,
Legislative History and the Limits of JudicialCompetence: The Untold Story of Holy Trinity Church, 50
STAN. L. REv. 1833, 1835 (1998) (observing that Holy Trinity "elevated legislative history to new
prominence by overturning the traditional rule that barred judicial recourse to internal legislative
history"). For discussion of the interpretive process in Holy Trinity as a constitutional amendment akin
to the textualization process I trace in describing the history of doubt in Islamic law, see John Manning,
The Eleventh Amendment and the Reading of Precise ConstitutionalTexts, 113 YALE L.J. 1663, 1686
(2004).
71. FELDMAN, supranote 28, at 2; see also supra note 42 and accompanying text.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
Unlike the modem American context, where three branches are in dialogue
with each other in contests over institutional functions, medieval Islamic legal
contexts lacked an active legislature or other defined branches with which
jurists would communicate institutionally. 72 Instead, through textual inter-
pretation, jurists defined and adopted institutional roles separated not by
constitutional structure but by function. For example, in the exercise of their
juridical-cum-judicialfunction,they assumed an institutionalist stance that they
claimed was wholly subordinate to a divine legislator.73 Yet, their claims to
textualism cloaked other legislative functions that jurists also assumed, as
outlined in the next Part.
Moreover, Muslim jurists debated the fate of Md'iz against the backdrop
of divine legislative supremacy and with texts that were far from static or clear.
Questions of authenticity and meaning that arose from the dynamic nature of
the sources-that is, the texts in which the Case of Md 'iz and related early
cases were recorded-left ambiguities that pragmatic jurists took to demand
interpretation. Accordingly, debates between jurists about Md'iz played out in
the legal sources, including collections of prophetic reports about criminal law,
legal treatises, manuals for judging, advisory opinions about how to resolve
hard cases in criminal law, and collections of legal maxims about doubt, as
well as in historical sources, including judicial biographies and historical
chronicles that offer anecdotal evidence of criminal trials and punishment. 74 In
short, debates about Md'iz persisted in many of the extant sources for legal
theory and legal practice (which were general in nature and anecdotal at best)
from the ninth century through the present. For the jurists writing during the
early founding period, in the lead-up to the eleventh-century systematization of
Islamic law, there was only one legitimate way to resolve the debate about
Md'iz. They had to answer the broader question: what did God require? In this
way, despite (or perhaps because of) the fact that they could not simply ask the
lawgiver to update or clarify the law, what emerges from their treatment of the
case is that the jurists debating the fate of MR'iz framed their debates as a quest
for divine legislative intent.
All in all, debates about Md'iz and other interpretive controversies were
especially significant in Islamic law because Muslim jurists enjoyed an
outsized role in making authoritative pronouncements of law. Their
pronouncements distinguished the Islamically legitimate from the illegitimate,
and in the process, defined a delicate "constitutional" balance between key
institutions of Islamic law and governance.
72. On the dialogic nature of the communication between courts, Congress, and executive
agencies, see, for example, sources cited supra note 70.
73. For an elaboration of a similar idea in American statutory interpretation, see Jane S.
Schacter, Metademocracy: The Changing Structure of Legitimacy in Statutory Interpretation, 108
HARv. L. REV. 593, 594 (1995), noting that, when judges interpret text, they are implicitly defining their
own role "by defining the goal and methodology of the interpretive enterprise, and by taking an
institutional stance in relation to the legislature."
74. See generally RABB, supra note 25.
20151 "'ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
75. As detailed below, this picture emerges from the amalgamation of a wide array of
prosopographical sources, historical chronicles, and reproductions of documentary evidence, such as
judicial appointment letters, caliphal edicts, and reports of prophetic and post-prophetic events. See infra
Subsections I.B.1-3.
76. See, e.g., infra notes 82-96 (religious morality), 97-114 (institutional competence), 115-
123 (institutional constraints).
77. See infra Subsection I.B. 1.
78. For an accessible treatment of this well-known scheme, see, for example, HALLAQ, supra
note 43, at 197-220, describing the relationship between political authorities, jurists, and judges in early
Islamic political theory (siydsa shar'iyya).
79. Id.
80. See infra Subsection I.B.2.
81. See infra Subsection I.B.3.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
82. See HUGH KENNEDY, THE PROPHET AND THE AGE OF THE CALIPHATES: THE ISLAMIC
NEAR EAST FROM THE SIXTH TO THE ELEVENTH CENTURY 45 (2d ed. 1986).
83. When Muhammad migrated from Mecca to Medina in 622, he became the head of a
fledgling Islamic state. The people of Medina had invited him to be their head and agreed to implement
his new religious law. This migration (hyra) was an all-important event in the history of Islamic law and
governance. Tellingly, the Islamic calendar does not begin when the Prophet first received revelation as
a member of a persecuted fringe group in Mecca. It begins After Hijra (AH)-that is, after his migration
to Medina some 300 miles north-precisely because he had become the head of state. In Mecca,
Muhammad had gained only charismatic religious authority over followers with whom his message of
morality and ethics resonated. But in Medina, he gained political and legal authority as well. For a
general overview of law and governance during Muhammad's lifetime, see HALLAQ, supra note 78, at
27-71; and KENNEDY, supranote 82, at 50-81.
84. For overviews of the legal structure during the Prophet's lifetime and immediately after,
see SUBHI MAHIMA$ANI, THE PHILOSOPHY OF JURISPRUDENCE INISLAM 15-16 (Farhat J. Ziadeh trans.,
1961) (1946); and Roy P. Mottahedeh, Introductionto SADR, supra note 12, at 4-14.
85. The events following the Prophet's death have been labeled the first "crisis of Muslim
history." MAHMOUD M. AYOUB, THE CRISIS OF MUSLIM HISTORY: RELIGION AND POLITICS IN EARLY
ISLAM 7 (2003).
86. See KENNEDY, supranote 82, at 50-81.
87. See WAEL B. HALLAQ, THE ORIGINS AND EVOLUTION OF ISLAMIC LAW 38-39 (2005).
88. See KENNEDY, supra note 82, at 50-81.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
89. See HALLAQ, supra note 87, at 34-39 (describing shifting bases of Islamic legal and
political authority following the Prophet's death in year 632).
90. See, e.g., 10 ABO AL-'ABBAS AL-QALQASHANDI, SUBH AL-A'SHA FT$NA'AT AL-INSHA'
21, 79, 359 (al-Mu'assasa al-Mi~riyya al-'Amma 1981) (providing evidence that the caliphs appointed
judges and instructed them with general policies on judging, such as the famous letter from the second
caliph, 'Umar b. Khatpb, to AbQ Mlsd al-Ash'ari); AL-SHARIF AL-RAI)T, NAHJ AL-BALAGHA letter 53,
at 426-45 ($ubhi al-$Rlih ed., 1967) (explicating judicial and governing policies sent from 'All to Malik
al-Ashtar upon his deployment to Egypt to take over as governor). 'Umar also instituted lasting changes
over his ten-year rule (634-644), significantly to public law. See MAHMAsANI, supra note 84, at 110-14
(listing his directives concerning alms-tax, divorce, slave law, theft crimes, sex crimes, and discretionary
punishments).
91. WAKI', AKHBAR AL-QUI)LT 357 (Sa'id Muhammad al-Lalb.h m ed., 'Alam al-Kutub 2001)
(recounting the judicial appointment story of Shurayh).
92. See HALLAQ, supra note 87, at 29-56. For a contrary view, see PATRICIA CRONE &
MARTIN HINDS, GOD'S CALIPH: RELIGIOUS AUTHORITY IN THE FIRST CENTURIES OF ISLAM 2-3 (1986),
arguing that caliphs after Ab Bakr saw themselves as not just political authorities but also religious
authorities.
93. For a survey of Muslim dynasties, including a list of Umayyad and 'Abbasid rulers, see
CLIFFORD E. BOSWORTH, THE NEW ISLAMIC DYNASTIES (2d ed. 2004).
94. 2 IBN MANZOR, LISAN AL-'ARAB 299-303 (Dar $5dir 1997).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
the new caliphs did not claim to be scholars of the Prophet's life, nor therefore
could they assume authority over definitions of Islamic law. That is, caliphs did
not-and, no doubt, could not-assume sweeping religious authority over even
criminal law. That much was evident from their episodic but always failed
attempts to control the jurists. 95 Stripped of any scholarly competence under
Mu'dwiya and his successors, the term "caliph" largely lost its religious
meaning. The historical sources portray the early caliphate as having
transformed from an office of moral leadership concerned with establishing' 96a
just social order to one of tribal loyalties based on "might makes right."
Political leadership had shifted to the new caliphs, who no longer shared any
part of the religious morality of the Prophet, aside from the symbolic title of
"successor." Instead, as the next section will elaborate, religious leadership-
and the moral ability to define Islamic law-had shifted almost entirely to the
jurists.
2. Islamic Law as InstitutionalCompetence
95. See MUHIAMMAD QASIM ZAMAN, RELIGION AND POLITICS UNDER THE EARLY
'ABBAsIDs: THE EMERGENCE OF THE PROTO-SUNNI ELITE 82-85 (1997) (detailing the failed proposal of
the vizier Ibn al-Muqaffa' to place law under the authority of the caliph by attempting to capture the
jurists).
96. AYOUB, supra note 85, at 54-57 (arguing that this transformation to tribal loyalty began
with 'Uthman); cf LOUISE MARLOW, HIERARCHY AND EGALITARIANISM INISLAMIC THOUGHT 14-16
(1997) (detailing a social egalitarian bent during the early Islamic period that became explicitly
hierarchal during 'Uthm~n's time and that Mu'awiya's assumption of leadership based on bloodlines
ended "the opportunity for social equalising" on the basis of piety criteria).
97. See CHIBLI MALLAT, THE RENEWAL OF ISLAMIC LAW: MUHAMMAD BAQER AS-SADR,
NAJAF AND THE SHI'T INTERNATIONAL 79 (1993) ("[Tlhe quintessential constitutional question is about
who ultimately holds the power to 'say what the law is.' In view of the centrality of the shartfa in the
definition of an Islamic state, this issue represents the essential problem of contemporary Islamic law.").
Here, Mallat was referencing Chief Justice John Marshall's famous exposition of the judicial power
under the U.S. Constitution in Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803) ("It is
emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is."). For a long-view
survey of the major themes that have arisen in American constitutional interpretation based on Justice
Marshall's famous formulation, see CHARLES FRIED, SAYING WHAT THE LAW IS: THE CONSTITUTION IN
THE SUPREME COURT (2004).
98. For discussions of this hadlith in the context of Sunni law, see FELDMAN, supra note 28, at
26. For ShVT law, see LIYAKAT N. TAKIM, THE HEIRS OF THE PROPHET: CHARISMA AND RELIGIOUS
AUTHORITY IN Sm'ITE ISLAM (2006).
99. For the early development of this shift, see generally ZAMAN, supra note 95.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
100. This led to an uneasy balance with the government over law as well as more intense
discussions in legal-religious circles about what the law was. See Mottahedeh, supranote 84, at 6-8.
101. On the moral and "epistemological" basis for juristic authority and legitimacy, see
HALLAQ, supra note 40; cf ARON ZYSOW, THE ECONOMY OF CERTAINTY: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE
TYPOLOGY OF ISLAMIC LEGAL THEORY 1 (2013) ("From a very early period ...Muslims came to treat
the question of legitimacy along explicitly epistemological lines.").
102. See HALLAQ, supranote 40, at 1-24.
103. HALLAQ, supra note 43, at 197-221 (describing this tripartite scheme as a "Circle of
Justice" in which jurists, caliphs, and judges formed co-equal arcs necessary to complete the circle).
104. For accounts of the early schools, beginning in the Umayyad reign and lasting until the
formalization of legal doctrine under the early 'Abbdsids, see generally HARALD MOTZKI, THE ORIGINS
OF ISLAMIC JURISPRUDENCE: MECCAN FIQH BEFORE THE CLASSICAL SCHOOLS (Marion IH. Katz trans.,
2002); and NURrr TSAFRIR, THE HISTORY OF AN ISLAMIC SCHOOL OF LAW: THE EARLY SPREAD OF
HANAFISM (2004).
105. HALLAQ, supra note 87, at 52 (noting that "the sources are frequently unclear as to
whether or not these specialists were always physically present in the court, but [that] we know from the
beginning of the second century (c. 720 AD) judges were encouraged to seek the counsel of these
learned men and that, by the 120s/740s, they often did").
106. FELDMAN, supra note 28, at 27 (citing JOSEPH SCHACHT, INTRODUCTION TO ISLAMIC
LAW 5 (1964) ("[I]t was created and developed by private specialists; legal science and not the state
plays the part of a legislator, and scholarly handbooks have the force of law.")) (on the application of the
term "jurists' law" to Islamic law).
107. On parallel developments in the Shi' context, see, for example, HOSSEIN MODARRESSI,
CRISIS AND CONSOLIDATION IN THE FORMATIVE PERIOD OF SH'rrE ISLAM 29 (1993), noting that the
early mainstream Imami Shi'i community believed the authority of the Imams to have been founded on
them being learned and pious scholars; WILFERD MADELUNG, RELIGIOUS SCHOOLS AND SECTS IN
MEDIEVAL ISLAM (1985); WILFERD MADELUNG, THE SUCCESSION TO MUIAMMAD: A STUDY OF THE
EARLY CALIPHATE (1997); and compare Etan Kohlberg, al-UsuIA1-Arba 'umi 'a, 10 JERUSALEM STUDS.
IN ARABIC AND ISLAM 128-66 (1987).
108. For a comparison of these schools to corporations, see SHERMAN JACKSON, ISLAMIC LAW
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
hundreds of these schools in the first half of the founding period.10 9 By its end,
the multitude of schools had boiled down to four main Sunni schools, a
minority Sunni strict textualist school and a principle Shi'l school, also with a
textualist strand." 0 The head SunnY scholars, now regarded as the "founders" of
the surviving schools, all lived during the first half of the founding period:"'
Abu Hanifa of the Hanaff school, Mdlik of the Mdliki school, Shrfi'T of the
Shafi'T school, and Ibn Hanbal of the HanbalT school. The Zahiri strict
textualist school-though it eventually died out-was started by Dfwfld the
Textualist. The main ShI'T school traced back to this period as well: Ja'far al-
.Sdiq,the Sixth Imdm-with whom most of the proto-Sunni scholars happened
to have studied-articulated
12
the core doctrines and principles of interpretation
for Shi'i law."
Alongside the founders of the legal schools, another group of scholars
devoted themselves to collecting reports of the prophet's words and actions,
which formed the basis for the Sunna. These scholars sifted through tens of
thousands of prophetic reports in an attempt to distinguish false from authentic,
and therefore normative, statements of law." 3 Together, books outlining each
school's doctrines and the prophetic reports containing the Sunna would
provide the raw materials for more systematic treatises on Islamic law.
By the eleventh century, jurists had begun organizing the ad hoc rules and
multiple texts from the Prophet and early scholars into sophisticated treatises of
law. These jurists drew on this amorphous body of school doctrines and
prophetic reports to produce Islam's definitive works of legal doctrine (fiqh),
l 4
legal theory (us.il al-fiqh), and political theory (siydsa shar'iyya)." Through
this process, each legal school distinguished its doctrines and methodological
approaches through debates about the meaning of a common set of "texts": the
Qur'an and the Sunna. It was these treatises that laid down the definitive
doctrinal and methodological rules of Islamic law, including criminal law and
doubt.
AND THE STATE: THE CONSTITUTIONAL JURISPRUDENCE OF SHIHAB AL-DIN AL-QARAFT (1996).
109. See GEORGE MAKDISI, THE RISE OF COLLEGES: INSTITUTIONS OF LEARNING IN ISLAM
AND THE WEST 2 (1981) (estimating up to five hundred such proto-Sunni schools, most of which died
out by the end of the ninth century).
110. See M.AiMAsANT, supranote 84, at 63-66; MODARRESSI, supra note 107, at 52-55.
111. See, e.g., MAIMASANT, supranote 84, at 17-19 (calling this period the Golden Age, which
accompanied the major translation movement from Greek into Arabic, the flowering of literature, and
the patronage of arts and sciences).
112. See Mottahedeh, supra note 84, at 8-9.
113. For discussions of the collection and authentication process of prophetic reports (hadTth)
in the Sunni context, see JONATHAN BROWN, THE CANONIZATION OF AL-BUKHRT AND MUSLIM: THE
FORMATION AND FUNCTION OF THE SUNNI HADITH CANON 9 (2007), listing the six canonical Sunni
compilations of .adth-reports of the Prophet's words and practices. In the SI'I context, see
MODARRESSI, supra note 13, at 4-5, listing the four canonical ShV'1 compilations of reports of the
Prophet and Imdns' words and practices.
114. For a history of the legal theoretical works in the Sunni context, see WAEL B. HALLAQ, A
HISTORY OF ISLAMIC LEGAL THEORIES: AN INTRODUCTION TO SUNNI U$OL AL-FIQH 33 (1997). For the
Shi'! context, see MODARRESSI, supra note 13, at 7.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
119. See generally MICHAEL A. COOK, COMMANDING RIGHT AND FORBIDDING WRONG IN
ISLAMIC THOUGHT (2001) (detailing the understandings and applications of this directive in Islamic
history).
120. See Intisar A. Rabb, Islamic Legal Minimalism, in STUDIES IN ISLAMIC LAW AND
TRADITION 256-74 (Michael Cook et al. eds., 2012) (noting that mainstream Sunni communities
required trained jurists to interpret Islam's foundational legal texts).
121. See MAWARDI, supra note 118, at 250 (including enforcement of hudrd laws in a short
list often public duties that the executive authority of the state must fulfill).
122. See FELDMAN, supra note 28, at 44-48 (describing the jurists' relationship with the
executive as the classical Islamic separation of powers scheme).
123. For an analogous meditation by a Seljdk scholar and vizier who, like Mawardl, wrote as
an officer of the state as well as a prominent Shfi'l jurist, see generally IMAM AL-HARAMAYN AL-
JUWAYNT, GHIYATH AL-UMAM FTILTIYATH AL-ZULAM (Khalil al-Man tir ed., Dfr al-Kutub al-'Itmiyya
1997). For an analysis, see Rabb, supranote 120.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
proportions. Criminal law questions were "public" in that they required input
from jurists to articulate the law, political rulers to enforce the law, and judges
to mediate between the two. 124 They were "constitutional" in that jurists used
criminal law, in part, to constitute their own power and to negotiate relations
between these major institutions of Islamic law and governance. In other
words, during Islam's founding period, Muslim jurists had quickly gained vast
power to define Islamic law by successfully asserting a superior institutional
competence to articulate religious morality. They used this power to impose
constitutional constraints on the legitimate exercise of caliphal-executive
power.
As other historians and scholars of Islamic law have acknowledged, these
stages demonstrate the centrality of Muslim jurists and their interpretive
debates to questions of Islamic legitimacy in institutions of law and
governance. 5 Some historians have further clarified that criminal law was the
locus of considerable contestation among jurists and political authorities. 126
What other scholars in the field have not yet grasped is how jurists asserted that
power to define institutional relationships specifically through criminal law,
and why. The following discussion seeks to address both how and why by
examining the means and motives by which Muslim jurists used specific
interpretive maneuvers to expand their power over criminal law and limit that
of the executive.
In arguing that Muslim jurists used criminal law to expand their own
power and limit that of the caliph, I return to the central idea that the jurists'
power was itself constrained to certain interpretive ideals. From their internal
debates, it is clear that Muslim jurists believed their definitions of law to be
legitimate only if they could plausibly claim adherence to foundational texts
and to the divine legislative supremacy ideal. 127 The illustrative example is the
Case of Md'iz. All Muslim jurists believed that the option of avoiding
punishment was legitimate, in the Case of M 'iz and in subsequent cases, only
if that outcome represented divine legislative intent. But identifying avoidance
of punishment as the divine intent was not easy to accomplish through debating
the case alone. Islamic legal theory maintained that the divine legislative intent
was best represented through foundational texts, but the case itself contained a
foundational ambiguity as to what had happened. Jurists vehemently debated
whether the Prophet's pronouncement of guilt but his preference to avoid
124. Criminal law was unlike Islamic ritual law or family law, which could often be settled
privately. For overviews of ritual law and family law, see HALLAQ, supra note 78, at 271-95.
125. E.g., HALLAQ, supra note 40, at 166-83 (recognizing in general terms that jurists used the
power of their perceived legitimacy to help define institutional roles).
126. For an excellent study of the intellectual currents and enforcement mechanisms of
criminal law among Seljfq jurists and rulers, see CHRISTIAN LANGE, JUSTICE, PUNISHMENT AND THE
MEDIEVAL MUSLIM IMAGINATION 39 (2008).
127. See supra note 49 and accompanying text.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
128. Id.
129. Only the traditionalist, strict-textualist jurists-the .AhirTs and some Hanbalis-were
consistently attuned to the non-prophetic pedigree of the doubt canon. This realization caused many of
them to reject the doubt canon both as a hadith (in prophetic attribution) and as a substantive canon (in
legal application). See IBN HAZM, supra note 50. For further discussion, see Rabb, Islamic Legal
Maxims, supra note 17, at 106-13 (detailing Ibn Hazm's objections to the doubt canon, which turned out
to be largely ineffective).
130. See Rabb, Islamic Rule ofLenity, supra note 17, at 1327.
131. See infra Subsection l11.B.3.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
the jurists' estimation, the trend of judicial practices from the founding period
illustrated how often the founding figures avoided punishment. This frequent
avoidance helped them determine how Md'iz should have fared retrospectively
and how criminal defendants
32
should be treated prospectively. Consider the
following three cases.'
132. For a collection of twenty-five early criminal cases demonstrating trends of alternate
avoidance and enforcement of Islamic criminal punishment, see RABB, supranote 25, app. A.
133. See IBN ABI SHAYBA, supra note 46, no. 28,970; WAKI', supra note 91, at 71-72.
134. See supra note 49.
135. It is unclear from the facts recounted in the report whether she was married and who
brought the accusation, the sources mention that she was a thayyib (non-virgin), which placed her in a
category of female offender for which jurists of the eleventh century understood the case to be a sex
crime that would require stoning. Her husband (if indeed she had been married), or another family
member, would have made the accusation. See IBN ABI SHAYBA, supra note 46, no. 28970.
136. A common strategy for Muslim women of this period to contest adultery accusations in
other contexts appears to have been to claim that they were raped. See, e.g., Delfina Serrano, Twelve
Court Cases on the Application of Penal Law Under the Almoravids, in DISPENSING JUSTICE IN ISLAM
473, 475,491 (citing 11 IBN HAZM, supra note 50, at 291-93).
137. In another version of the story, 'Umar says to the woman, "perhaps you have been raped."
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
that he feared God's wrath "if [he] sentenced this woman to death." Instead of
punishing her, he fed her, clothed her, and instructed her people to treat her
well. 138
Later Muslim jurists took this case to be one of legal doubt, for which
heightened procedures were required, which in turn helped determine whether
the law against fornication and adultery covered the acts of someone who had
not formed the criminal intent to violate the law. 'Umar's questioning about her
mental state and character paralleled the Prophet's questioning of Md'iz. In this
case, was the pregnancy, without a confession or witnesses, sufficient to
convict of adultery? The answer was no. The doubt about the law's application
to the woman who claimed to have been raped, jurists concluded, explained
why 'Umar avoided punishment, using procedure to lead to that result.
See 12 SHWtA"B AL-DIN AL-QARA-F, AL-DHAKHIRA FTFURO' AL-MALIKIYYA 60 (Dir al-Gharb al-Islami
1994). For a similar version in an earlier source, see 7 'ABD AL-SALAM B. SA'ID SAItNfON, AL-
MUDAWWANA AL-KUBRA 2444 (D.r $dir, n.d.) (equating sex with a sleeping woman to rape).
138. IBN ABT SHAYBA, supra note 46, no. 28,970. For discussion of the jurists' antipathy
toward capital punishment read into scenarios like this one, see infra Section 1I.B.
139. For the Qur'5nic rle of retaliation, see THE QuR'AN 2:178-79; id. at 4:92; and id at 5:45.
For a discussion of the Islamic "reforms" to the ancient Near Eastern practice, see PETERS, supra note 5,
at 40.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
murder that you did not commit?!" he asked. The man explained that he
thought 'All would never take his word over that of the patrolmen who had
witnessed a crime scene wherein all signs had pointed to him as the perpetrator.
In reality, the man explained, he was a butcher who had just finished
slaughtering a cow. Immediately after the slaughter, he needed to relieve
himself, so he entered the area of the ruins, bloody knife still in hand. Upon
return, he came across the dead man and stood over him in concern. It was then
that the patrol encountered him. Figuring that he could not plausibly deny
having committed the crime, he confessed to the "obvious" and decided to
leave the matter in God's hands.
The second man offered a corroborating story. He explained that he was
the one who had murdered a man for his money and then had fled upon hearing
sounds of the patrol approaching. On his way out, he passed the butcher
entering the area and then watched the events unfold as the butcher had
described them. Once the butcher was condemned to death, however, the
second man felt compelled
1 40
to step forward. He did not want the blood of two
men on his hands.
This case presented yet a new set of doubts. Whereas the previous case
addressed legal doubt arising from questions of criminal intent and thus
criminal culpability, this case highlighted problems of factual doubt. That
someone was criminally culpable was clear. There was a dead man in the town
ruins who was brutally stabbed to death. But the conflicts between
circumstantial evidence and competing confessions created doubt about who
was culpable. There was a problem in the evidence, which seemed impossible
to resolve. The lack of certain proof against either defendant may then have
caused 'Alli to avoid punishment.
Later jurists read this case to support the rule that judges should avoid
enforcing the death penalty even when the ordinarily acceptable forms of
evidence seemed dispositive. 141 Typically, murder convictions required either a
confession or two eyewitnesses, preferably corroborated by knowledge of the
witnesses' credibility or by circumstances pointing to the reliability of the
testimony. Here, there was the perfect trifecta of evidence: a confession,
testimony of multiple eyewitnesses, and corroboration by strong circumstantial
evidence. Yet, even then, there was doubt. There was a plausible alternative
140. IBR,AM B. HASHIM AL-QUMMI, QAI),kYA AMIR AL-MU'MININ 'ALT B. ABI TALIB 88-89,
238 (Fris Hassin Karim ed., Mu'assasat Amir al-Mu'minln 2003). Both Sunni and Shil' scholars have
cited this episode as an example of clever doubt jurisprudence. For Sunni treatments, see, for example,
IBN QAYYIM AL-JAWZIYYA, supra note 50, at 82-84 (quoting Qaddya 'AlTand Aj,'ib (referring to the
ninth-century works by Ibrdhim b. Hashim al-Qummil and others called Qadtyd Amir al-Mu 'minin or
'Aj'ib ahkdm AmTr al-Mu minTu, now published as MUHSIN AL-AMIN AL-', MILI, 'AJA'IB AtI K'AM
AMIR AL-MU'MININ 'ALT B. ABT TALiB (Markaz al-Ghadir li'l-Dirasft al-Islmiyya 2000))). For Shit
treatments, see, for example, 2 AL-HURR AL-'AMILI, WASAIL AL-SHI'A 172 (Mu' assasat Al al-Bayt li-
Iby5' al-Turdth 1956); 7 MUIAMMAD B. YA'QOB AL-KULAYNI, KAF 289 ('Ali Akbar al-GhaffarT ed.,
1957) (quoting the story from lbrdhm b. Hshim al-Qumml as received through that author's son, 'Ali
b. Ibrahim al-Qummi).
141. See infra Section III.B.
142. See PETERS, supranote 5, at 12-17.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
story told by a second man who confessed to the crime, and no eyewitnesses or
reliable confessions. Because of pervasive problems in certain types of proof,
jurists read this case as support for avoiding capital punishment altogether.
3. Case of the Absentee Husband
These cases are important not for their historical accuracy, but for the
uses to which later jurists put them. 48 Pragmatic jurists writing at the end of
143. QUMMI, supra note 140, at 119 (citing variants in later Shi'T sources, including works by
prominent eleventh- to fourteenth-century ShV'T jurists Mufid and al-'Allma al-Hilli, as well as works
by prominent Sunni scholars Bayhaqi, Bqillani, and Ibn Hajar).
144. Id.
145. Id.
146. See IBN QAYYIM AL-JAWZIYYA, AL-TURUQ AL-I.IUKMIYYA FT'L-SIYA A AL-SHAR'IYYA 3,
43-80 (Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyya 1995).
147. Id.
148. Reports of these cases from the seventh century are available in written literature only
from the eighth to ninth centuries at the earliest. Rather than taking them as verbatim reports of what
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
the founding period in the eleventh century and afterward read these early cases
to express doctrines of doubt. 49 They then used these cases to support their
view in the Case of Mj'iz that the Prophet's comment that the townspeople
should have avoided punishing M 'iz was a normative rule based on the
doctrine of doubt. In that case, the Prophet had tried to deter Md'iz from
confessing, had come up with alternative explanations of the defendant's
actions that did not fall within the ambit of the law in order to excuse Md'iz,
and then had censured the people for carrying out the criminal punishment
against him. In short, one could characterize their treatment of the Case of
Md'iz as reflecting an understanding that the Prophet had expressed factual,
legal, and moral doubt.
Drawing on that precedent, Muslim jurists interpreted the Case of the
Mysterious Pregnancy to be an instance of legal doubt, with 'Umar displaying
an immediate willingness to ascribe no fault to the pregnant woman who
signaled she had no criminal intent and thus was not covered by the scope of
the law against fornication and adultery. They further interpreted the Case of
the Falsely Accused Butcher as one of factual doubt, wherein 'AlI declined to
punish the man who had confessed to committing murder, when he was no
longer certain of the criminal culpability of either defendant where there were
two competing confessions. And they interpreted the Case of the Absentee
Husband as one of moral doubt, where 'AlI and 'Umar managed to avoid
punishing a woman for adultery through procedural delay tactics where the
context of her husband's acceptance of the child and the child's reliance on the
mother militated against the propriety of capital punishment. In sum, the judge
in each case found (or created) some type of factual, legal, or moral doubt-
sometimes in combination-that called criminal culpability into question.
These various types of doubt provided the basis for avoiding criminal
punishment in each case.
Read together, these early cases represented judicial practices that
resonated in juristic circles as normative, even if they were not as airtight as
arguments based on text. For the later jurists considering these early cases, the
outcomes pointed to an overall tendency of early Muslim judges and founding
figures to avoid punishment through heightened procedural and other
requirements, even where there were solid indications that some crime had
taken place. Having distilled this understanding from early judicial practices,
the jurists expressed it frequently in 5the
0
form of the doubt canon: avoid
criminal punishments in cases of doubt.'
actually happened, I argue that the case reports indicate ideas that the later generations of scholars came
to associate with Islam's earliest period. In a related context, Roy Mottahedeh has used sources from the
Biiyid dynasty in the late 'Abbgsid era to uncover the symbolic importance and practice of taking oaths
in processes through which local rulers gained political legitimacy. See ROY P. MOTTAHEDEH,
LOYALTY AND LEADERSHIP IN AN EARLY ISLAMIC SOCIETY passim (1980).
149. E.g., QUDORI, supranote 50, at 5949-50.
150. See, e.g., MUAMMAD AMIN AL-ASTARABADT, AL-FAWA'ID AL-MADANIYYA 326
(Mu'assasat al-Nashr al-Islrni 2003); 9 SuLAYMAN B. KHALAF AL-BAJI, MUNTAQA 168-71, 175-76,
232 (Maktabat al-Thaqdfa al-Diniyya 2004); 6 ABO HAMID AL-GHAzALT, AL-WAsIT 443-46 (Dr al-
Salem 1997); 2 IBN AL-'ARAB!, supra note 58, at 604; 2 IBN 'ABD AL-BARR, KAFl 1069-73 (Maktabat
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
Once the jurists had expressed the doctrine of doubt in the form of an oft-
repeated canon located in early judicial practices, the jurists' next move was to
turn the canon into a text. My claim is that the jurists literally asserted that the
divine lawgiver had laid down the rule through the Prophet himself. They did
not do so based on any one text or at any one identifiable moment. Rather, they
did so based on their interpretations of the early .hadTth literature alongside
judicial practices that seemed to consistently pursue a policy of punishment
avoidance in cases of doubt, including the Case of M 'iz and other early cases.
By the end of the tenth and eleventh centuries, interpreting these cases in the
aggregate, virtually all Muslim jurists came to conceive of the doubt canon as a
foundational text issued by the Prophet himself.152 This move represented a
radical change from the early conceptions of the doubt doctrine as judicial
practice;this later conception of doubt had been transformed into a rule of text.
A study of the legal literature from the first three centuries of Islam's
advent reveals that no jurist understood direct statements about doubt to have
been prophetic in origin. To be sure, they knew of the doubt canon expressed
through its standard formulation: "avoid criminal punishments in cases of
doubt." Yet, they regarded it as statement of judicial53 practice, not as a prophetic
haaith. It simply was not a foundational legal text.
In this vein, the founders of Islam's multiple legal schools tended to cite
the doubt doctrine in their treatments of criminal law without claiming it to be a
prophetic directive. Abu Hanifa's circle in Iraq expounded the doubt doctrine
early on in the form that has been popularized amongst most subsequent jurists:
al-Riydl al-Hadithah 1980); 2 IBN RUSHD AL-HAFID, BIDAYAT AL-MUJTAHID 632 (Dar al-Kutub al-
'Ilmiyya, 1996); 16 IBN RUSHID AL-JADD, BAYAN 324 (Dar al-Gharb al-islamI 1988); 9 ABC BAKR B.
MAS'OD AL-KAsANI, BAD,' AL-SANAI' 4150 (Zakariyy Yfisuf 1968); MAWARDI, supra note 50,
'Alli
at 207-15; 9 SHAMS AL-A'IMMA AL-SARAKHsT, MABSOT 66 (AbOi 'Abd Allah Muhammad Hasan
Ism5't1 al-Shdfi'i ed., Dar al-Kutub al-'Ilmiyya 2001); ABC ZAYD AL-DABOSI, KITAB AL-ASRAR, in
Salim Ozer, Debbusi'nin "El-Esrarfi'l-UsulveT-Furu "' Adli Eserinin Tahkik ve Tahlili 151, 1229
(1997) (unpublished Ph.D. thesis, Erciyes Oniversitesi) (on file with author).
151. For approaches to early Islamic history and historiography in other contexts, see generally
FRED M. DONNER, NARRATIVES OF ISLAMIC ORIGINS: THE BEGINNINGS OF ISLAMIC HISTORICAL
WRITING (1998), which argues that early Islamic sources present a "kernel" of historical truth; TAYEB
EL-HIBRI, REINTERPRETING ISLAMIC HISTORIOGRAPHY: HARON AL-RASHID AND THE NARRATIVE OF
THE 'ABBASID CALIPHATE (1999), which identifies early Arab historical writing as moralizing rather
than presenting a register of facts; R. STEPHEN HUMPHREYS, ISLAMIC HISTORY: A FRAMEWORK FOR
INQUIRY (1991), which surveys major contemporary approaches to the field; and CHASE F. ROBINSON,
ISLAMIC HISTORIOGRAPHY 118-23 (2003), which notes that political patronage colored historical
narratives and, where independence was lacking, often presented facts best suited to legitimate the
sponsoring regime.
152. Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims, supra note 17, at 100-06.
153. For a more in-depth survey, see id.at 5.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
154. One of Abo Hanlfa's two most prominent students, Shaybani, attributed instances of the
doubt canon's application to his teacher, who in turn drew on opinions of the seventh-century jurist
Ibrihtm al-Nakha'. See MUJAMMAD B. HASAN AL-SHAYBANI, KITAB AL-A/THtAR 136 (Khadlja
Mubammad Kamil ed., Idarat al-Qur'fln wa'l-'Ulum al-Islamiyya 1998).
155. AbO Yasuf included discussions of the doubt canon in his treatise on taxation, which
contains sections on criminal and other areas of public law. See ABID YOsur, KrrAB AL-KHARAr 303-05
(Mubammad Ibr-ahim al-BannV' ed., Ddr al-Ildh 1981).
156. E.g., 7 'ABD AL-RAZZAQ, AL-MUSANNAF F! 'L-IIADITH 210 (Iab-h al-A'Zam! ed., al-
Maktab al-IslmT 1972) (reporting on avoidance practices in Medina of the Umayyad caliph 'Umar b.
'Abd al-'Aziz (r. 717-720) for alleged sex crimes); WArd', supra note 91, at 617 (reporting cases in
which the Syrian Umayyad judge Fadldla b. 'Ubayd al-Anffri avoided punishment).
157. See 2 MALIK B. ANAS, AL-MUWATTA' 393 (Bashshar 'Awwad Ma'rf ed., Dk al-Gharb
al-Isldin 1996) (holding, for example, that judges were not to punish in a case where a man permitted
his slavewoman to have sex with another man, even though giving the permission and the act were
illegal).
158. See 16 SAI3NON, supranote 137, at 236 (noting Mdlik's position that judges should avoid
punishment for adultery in a case of alleged infidelity where there were disputes about whether the
marriage was consummated, and thus completed legally).
159. See generally SHAFt'l, supra note 12 (elaborating a jurisprudence based on his call for
authentic foundational texts as the most authoritative bases for law).
160. SHArFI', supra note 50, at 52-53 (invoking the doubt canon to avoid corporal punishment
in cases of theft, though requiring the thief to pay afine in such cases).
161. See QuMM!, supranote 140, at 253-54.
162. See IBN SHU'BA, TULTIAF AL-'UQOL 126, 128 ('Ali Akbar al-Ghaffar! ed., Maktabat al-
Sadfiq 1376). This source is dubious, and the doubt canon does not appear in the version of the letter
recorded in RAVI, supra note 90. Yet this version indicates a certain regard for the doubt canon in the
ShVI communities that Ibn Shu'ba frequented in the tenth or eleventh century, during a period when the
canon was growing in importance.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40:41
It was not inevitable that the doubt canon would come to dominate
criminal law. Jurists and caliphs alike could have just as well used the divine
legislative supremacy ideal to emphasize their subordination to the law and its
dictates of criminal law enforcement-as had the Prophet in the Case of the
MakhzamT Thief 166 Likewise, the Case of Md'iz could have been read to
emphasize the validity of capital punishment and the imperative of law
enforcement, despite the harsh consequences and what might have been the
163. For a more detailed survey, see Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims, supra note 17, at 69-77,
which suggests that these developments reflected a shift in early understandings of legal validity in
Islamic law, from reliance on practice to authoritativeness of text.
164. The earliest reliable juristic attribution of the doubt canon to the Prophet is that of the
.Hanafi jurist Jas5$, 3 supra note 22, at 330. Such attributions increased in the eleventh century.
165. See supra note 150; see also Rabb, Islamic Legal Maxims, supra note 17, at 100-06.
166. See supra note 59 and accompanying text.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
The early cases, by requiring more procedure, had put on display some of
the moral concems of the early juristic community as they were systematizing
Islamic law. That is, the jurists responsible for articulating the law used doubt
to express concerns about draconian punishments in the political sphere that
percolated in the background of, and were subject to, the developing norms of
Islamic law. The local rulers who seized control in the central Muslim lands of
the eleventh century (and in the later 'Abbasid period) asserted power primarily
through military force and punishment as a means of social control. 167 As I
argue here, their excesses prompted the jurists to constrain the caliphal reach
over Islamic criminal law. That is, as jurists began to systematize the law, they
did so against this early legacy of political violence and arbitrariness, which
continued-and indeed increased-after the 'Abbasid grip on absolute power
began to loosen.
To be sure, previous regimes were known for excess. Mu'dwiya's use of
military force to depose 'AI and establish the Umayyad dynasty became
standard practice for dynastic regime change in the premodem Muslim world.
The dynasty following his, that of the 'Abbasids, rose to power on the heels of
an army that marched from the East to take control from the Umayyads in
750.168 The Umayyad and 'Abbasid dynasties both indulged in disparate and
excessive applications of punishment. 169 Their excesses prompted the jurists
167. See generally LANGE, supra note 126 (detailing the particularly violent Seljdiq use of
punishment for social control).
168. See generally MOSHE SHARON, BLACK BANNERS FROM THE EAST: THE ESTABLISHMENT
OF THE 'ABBASID STATE-INCUBATION OF A REVOLT (1983) (examining the revolt that brought the fall
of the Umayyads and rise of the 'Abbfsids); MOSHE SHARON, REVOLT: THE SOCIAL AND MILITARY
ASPECTS OF THE 'ABBASID REVOLUTION: BLACK BANNERS FROM THE EAST 1 (1990) (same).
169. See JONATHAN P. BERKEY, THE FORMATION OF ISLAM: RELIGION AND SOCIETY IN THE
NEAR EAST, 600-1800, at 84-85 (2003) (noting that while some of the opposition came from a stance
championing Arab ascendancy, most of the opposition was religious, as diverse pockets of scholars and
other members of the elite became increasingly distressed at reported caliphal divergences from
Qur'anic and prophetic principles ofjustice).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
not only to distinguish themselves from the caliph, but to form a "pious
opposition" against him, seeking 70to restrict as much as possible the caliphal
reach over Islamic law writ large. 1
Major developments in the eleventh-century political center of the
Muslim empire led to significant changes in the administration of criminal
justice and juristic responses to it. Namely, break-off local dynasties wrested
ever more control from the central 'Abbdsid caliph. Notable amongst them
were the Seljulqs, a group of Central Asian warriors who assumed power over
Iraq and greater Persia in 1055.171
Under the Seljiiqs, violence became more excessive and public.
Executions were especially rampant, accompanied by floggings, public
shaming parades, and imprisonment.172 The term that Mdwardi had devised for
"political governance" (siyrsa)to demarcate the jurisdiction of the caliph from
that of the jurists had transformed. By the Seljiiq period, this term for "political
governance" had come to mean "punishment" or "execution., 173 A prominent
jurist of the time remarked that the "sultans of today rely on punishment
[siydsat] and awe,' 174 that is, the type of awe75 surrounding kings, induced by the
threat or application of severe punishment.'
The sultan-appointed and jurist-advised judges played a significant role in
the administration of criminal justice. Some scholars have suggested that the
political officials were able to skirt the jurist-advised ordinary courts and
transfer criminal justice administration to officials who fell solely under the
authority of the caliph. 176 Moreover, they have suggested that the caliph had
free jurisdiction over crimes that carried discretionary penalties. In particular,
these scholars have pointed to the "extraordinary" courts of equity over which
the caliphal officials presided, as well as to law enforcement officials who
sometimes presided over discretionary penalties. 177 But more likely, as
Mdwardi had intimated, there were spheres of shared jurisdiction between the
ordinary courts on the one hand and the extraordinary, political institutions on
the other, a scheme wherein even caliphal officials' exercises 178
of discretion
were supposed to be subject to juristic articulations of law.
One example of this type of shared jurisdiction was the police role in
criminal prosecution and law enforcement. 179 The police were an arm of the
caliphal power whose main job was to secure public safety, prosecute crime,
and enforce criminal punishments upon conviction in ordinary courts. 180 To be
sure, the police did not always bring their charges through the courts, and they
often imposed outsized punishments. For example, when a man of one
neighborhood in Baghdad killed 181
his sister and her lover, the police rode out and
destroyed the entire quarter.
But as exemplified in the articulation of the doubt canon during this time,
episodes like these fueled, rather than quashed, juristic opposition to excessive
and illegitimate punishment. Such incidents provided a powerful public symbol
of excessive punishment, which jurists could highlight as illegitimate executive
overreach in a way likely to garner the sympathies of the populace. Such
instances also pushed the jurists to make clearer statements of criminal law and
procedure to which the caliph and police force would have done well to adhere,
at least in part, in order not to compromise their legitimacy.
In this vein, the other official who played a role in criminal law
enforcement-the market-inspector (muhtasib)-"declined in people's
estimation when rulers neglected [the office] and conferred it on men of no
repute, whose goal was to make profit and get bribes. ' 82 As the name would
suggest, the inspector monitored the quality of goods and guarded against
price-fixing in the marketplace. Alongside the police, the inspector also had
punitive authority, usually over non-capital crimes. The inspector sought to
curb "undesirable" social practices like open alcohol consumption and singing
through punishments such as detention, flogging, and public humiliation (by
parading offenders around town).1 83 Like the judges-who sometimes rotated
to the position of muhtasib-the inspectors were formally limited by the
THE MIDDLE EAST: ORIGIN AND DEVELOPMENT OF ISLAMIC LAW 259 (Majid Khadduri & Herbert J.
Liebesny ed., Lawbook Exchange 2008) (1955) (same).
178. MAwARDT, supranote 118, at 250.
179. See 1 MUjAMMAD 'ABDALLAH AL-BATALYAWSI, AL-IQTI)AB FTSHARII AL-KUTrAB 159
(Mu tafa al-Saqqd & Hamid 'Abd al-Majid eds., al-Hay'a al-Misriyya al-'Ham li'l-Kit~b 1961); 12 IBN
AL-JAWZT, AL- MUNTAZAM FTTA'RIKH AL-UMAM WA-L-MULOK 124 (Muhammad 'Abd aI-Qfdir 'At'
& Mu~tafai 'Abd al-Qadir 'AtA' eds., 1992); 13 id.at 316; HUGH KENNEDY, THE ARMIES OF THE
CALIPHS: MILITARY AND SOCIETY IN THE EARLY ISLAMIC STATE 13-14 (2001).
180. See Intisar A. Rabb, Police, in THE PRINCETON ENCYCLOPEDIA OF ISLAMIC POLITICAL
THOUGHT 427, 427-28 (Gerhard B6wering et al. eds., 2012); see also LANGE, supra note 126, at 48-51
(detailing the role of the police under Seljiiq rule).
181. 17 IBN AL-JAWZI, supranote 179, at 99; see also LANGE, supra note 126, at 52.
182. MAWART, supra note 118, at 258; cf Henry F. Amedroz, The Hisba Jurisdiction in the
Ahkam Sultaniyya ofMtwarda, J. ROYAL ASIATIC SOC'Y 77 (1916).
183. See LANGE, supra note 126, at 56 (describing bisba activity under the Seljoqs); cf.
KRISTEN STILT, ISLAMIC LAW IN ACTION: AUTHORrrY, DISCRETION, AND EVERYDAY EXPERIENCES IN
MAMLUK EGYPT (2011) (describing hisba activity in Mamlak Egypt).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
jurists' articulation of Islamic law. 184 That is, for maximum legitimacy, the
jurist-defined Islamic criminal laws provided the upper limits of the
discretionary
1 85
punishments that the inspector possessed the authority to
enforce.
Punishment on the part of the political rulers implicated questions about
the legitimacy of the caliphs' rule. Even if the jurists were not in agreement
with the severity of punishment-and they were not-"[t]he overwhelming
persuasive power of public punishment" left no question about the rulers'
authority.186 The difficulty lay in the rulers' claim to legitimacy, attacks against
which were the only real arrow in the jurist's quiver. At the same time, Muslim
jurists knew that they relied on the new rulers' enforcement power for the rule
of law. They therefore did not seek to completely delegitimize Seljfiq rule, but
to constrain it. 87 This explains why they needed to convert the doubt doctrine
into a textual rule.
The jurists' appeal to the newly textual authority of the doubt canon
reflected moral anxieties stemming from the ongoing political culture of
violence combined with the factual uncertainty of criminal culpability in many
cases, both of which were exacerbated by the breakup of the empire in the
eleventh century. That is, the clear and present danger of death in the quick-to-
punish political context planted serious anxieties among many of the jurists,
who worried about frequent executions of dubious justification at precisely the
moment when they were trying to better articulate and systematize Islamic law.
Still, why should the jurists have understood doubt to include heightened
criminal procedures when the burdens of proof in Islamic criminal law were
already so high? The answer has to do with the nature of the punishments that
were of most concern. If jurists could deploy doubt doctrines to require
procedures that tended to avoid capital punishment rather than authorize it, they
could ameliorate any anxieties over authorizing execution on dubious grounds.
Conceivably, they could also thereby restrict the rates of capital punishment. In
184. E.g., MU'AYYAD AL-DAWLA, 'ATABAT AL-KATABA 52 (Muhammad Qazvlni & 'Abbds
Iqb5l eds., 2005) (reproducing an appointment diploma of hisbajurisdiction for ajudge).
185. See, e.g., LANGE, supranote 126, at 58 (citing 'ABD AL-RAIJMAN B. NA$R AL-SHAYZARI,
NIHAYAT AL-RUTBA FTTALAB AL-IjISBA 9 (Matba'at Lajnat al-Ta'lif wa'l-Tarjama wa'l-Nashr, 1946));
'ABD AL-RAHMAN B. NA$R AL-SHAYZARI, THE BOOK OF THE ISLAMIC MARKET INSPECTOR (Ronald P.
Buckley trans., 1999). Of course, adhering to this upper-limit was not always followed in practice. See,
e.g., STILT, supra note 183, at 89-106; TYAN, supra note 176, at 649 (relating a number of examples
from historical sources from other periods of muhtasibs exceeding the extent of punishments prescribed
by the hadd penalties).
186. LANGE, supra note 126, at 43 (arguing further that such coercive power left "no doubt"
about the ruler's legitimacy). While the author is correct to note that the authority was left virtually
unquestionable, my reading of the sources suggests that the legitimacy, by contrast, was questionable-
for which the jurists responded with a doctrine of doubt.
187. As Christian Lange has observed, Muslims much preferred the draconian criminal justice
system of the Seljitk dynasty to the utter chaos that reigned when those authorities lost power in
Khuras~n for some time beginning in 1153 until the Mongol invasion a century later. See LANGE, supra
note 126, at 244-46.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
other words, where the stakes were life or death, using the doubt canon to
assure more procedure was the juristic attempt at alleviating their own
anxieties and ameliorating widespread practices of capital punishment.
188
1. MoralAnxieties Revealed: Death Is Different
Muslim jurists historically had been skittish about any involvement with
political authorities, which they deemed unseemly and corrupting for people of
moral conscience. The Muslim jurists' general skittishness toward judging, I
suggest, was exacerbated in capital contexts, which principally explained the
rise of the doubt doctrine in Islamic law.
Though some jurists certainly served as state-appointed judges and
assumed other government posts, they were a distinct minority. Many who
were nominated for official judgeships or other positions stubbornly refused to
serve, preferring to remain independent of the political apparatus.'89 The
sources are replete with instances of their recoil at being nominated to judge.
Famously, Abu Han1fa was said to have endured torture for his refusals."tg The
main chronicle for the early history of judges opens with prophetic cautions
against judging. 191 This inclination against judging represented just some of the
moral anxieties surrounding judging in accordance with God's law, and the
consequences of not getting it right. When it came to the death penalty, Muslim
jurists feared answering in the afterlife for wrongful deaths occasioned by their
allowance of punishment that was not in fact warranted. 192 Moreover, against
188. The American experience with the death penalty-from which I draw the title of this
section-well articulates the "difference" of death. When placing a moratorium on the death penalty in
1972, the Supreme Court cited the need for procedure, in light of the fundamentally different nature of
the death penalty, and the need to avoid executions that were so arbitrary as to be "wanton and freakish"
in nature. Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 295 (1972) (Brennan, J., concurring) (imposing what was to
become a four-year moratorium on the death penalty). In his concurrence, Justice Brennan explained
that this outcome had to do with the fact that "[d]eath is a unique punishment, . . . in a class by itself."
Id. at 286-89 (Brennan, J., concurring); see also id.at 306 (Stewart, J., concurring) ("The penalty of
death differs from all other forms of criminal punishment, not in degree but in kind."). When capital
punishment was reinstated in the 1970s, the Court subjected it to heightened procedures above that of
ordinary crimes. See Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 188 (1976) (joint opinion of Stewart, Powell, and
Stevens, JJ.) ("[The] penalty of death is different in kind from any other punishment" and "unique.");
Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280, 305 (1976) (joint opinion of Stewart, Powell, and Stevens,
JJ.) ("[The] penalty of death is qualitatively different from a sentence of imprisonment, however long.").
For an analysis of the consequences of America's constitutional and procedural regulation rather than
abolition of the death penalty, see Carol S. Steiker & Jordan M. Steiker, Entrenchment andor
Destabilization? Reflections on (Another) Two Decades of Constitutional Regulation of Capital
Punishment,30 LAW & INEQ. 211 (2012).
189. See, e.g., ABO 'ABD ALLH AMMAD B. AL-HARITH AL-KHUSHANT, QUIAT QURTUBA
kMUH.
79-93 (Yhsir Salama Ab5 Ta'ma ed., Ddr al-SamT'i 2008) (listing instances of ten judges who refused
the judgeship); WAKI', supra note 91, at 24-25.
190. For a discussion of this and his extreme antipathy toward the ruling authorities and
censure ofjudges like his rival Ibn Abi LaylI who "colluded" with them, see MUi .AMMAD ABO ZAHRA,
ABO HANIFA: HAYATUH WA-'A$RUH, ARA'UH WA-FIQHUH 37-48 (Dhr al-Fikr al-'Arabi, 2d ed. 1965).
191. See WAKI', supra note 91, at 19 (introducing biographical reports on judges with the
"[section] mentioning [hadith and other] reports announcing the gravity of assuming a judicial post over
people and that whoever assumes [such a post] has been [metaphorically] slaughtered without a knife").
192. See Baber Johansen, Vom Wort- zum Indizienbeweis: Die Anerkennung der richterlichen
Folter in islamischen Rechtsdaktrinen des 13. und 14. Jahrhunderts[From Proof by Word to Proof by
Indicia: The Recognition of Judicial Torture in Islamic Legal Doctrines of the Thirteenth and Fourteenth
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
Centuries], 28 IUS COMMUNE 2, 11-12 (2001) (noting medieval Muslim jurists' fears of the legal and
physical consequences of punishment for false convictions, namely, the doctrine that the judge
responsible would suffer the same punishment in the afterlife that he had falsely inflicted in this life); cf.
LANGE, supra note 126, at 101-15 (noting the connection between this-worldly sins and fear of other-
worldly punishment).
193. 2 ABO AL-HASAN AL-MAWARD!, ADAB AL-QAQT 14-16 (Ri'asat Diwn al-Awqdf 1972).
194. For the four-witness requirement for sex crimes, see THE QUR'AN 4:15, and for the
related four-oath procedure of mutual imprecation (plus a fifth invoking God's wrath if found to be
lying) for spousal accusations of zinil, called li &n, see id. 24:7, 9. Another procedure contained in the
.hadth corpus, but not in the Qur'dn, was the elaborate process of swearing multiple oaths to assign
liability for homicide where the evidence proving a crime was inconclusive. On the fifty-oath procedure
called qasama (after which, capital punishment could not apply), see Rudolph Peters, Murder in
Khaybar: Some Thoughts on the Origins of the Qasdma Procedure in Islamic Law, 9 J. ISLAMIC L. &
Soc'Y 132 (2002).
195. See supra Section II.A.
196. See supra notes 131-163 and accompanying text.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
197. See 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *358 ("[1]t is better that ten guilty persons
escape than that one innocent suffer.").
198. 10 'ABD AL-RAZZAQ, supra note 156, at 66; BAYHAQI, supra note 59, at 413; 4
D.RAQUTNT, SuNAN 62-63 (Mu'assasat al-Risala 2004); IBN ABI SHAYBA, supra note 46, at 360; 5
TIRMIDH, SuNAN 112-13 (al-Maktaba al-Salafiya 1965).
199. BAYHAQI, supranote 59, at 414; cf 1aN ABT SHAYBA, supranote 46, at 359.
200. Notably, although medieval Muslim jurists used the doctrine of doubt to express their
discomfort with the arbitrariness of capital punishment, they were careful to note that they were not
attempting to vitiate criminal punishment altogether. Instead, these jurists took criminal law prohibitions
to be justified-Bentham style-as rules aiming to deter crime. See, e.g., MAwARDI, supra note 50, at
99 (".Hudud are punishments by which God deters (zajara bihd) people from committing prohibited
[acts] and encourages them to follow [His] commands."). They also acknowledged a retributive
justification for criminal sanctions for defendants like M5'iz, who requested criminal punishment
believing it to provide this-worldly divine retribution that would expiate his sins and result in
forgiveness. Id. at 100. For an analogous meditation on contemporary criminal law responses to mass
atrocities, see MARTHA MINoW, BETWEEN VENGEANCE AND FORGIVENESS 9-24 (1998).
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
These types of moral concerns about judging and doubt were not unique
to medieval Muslim jurists and judges. Their Christian counterparts in England
and continental Europe were themselves morally anxious when it came to
dealing with doubt, and likewise created procedures designed to allay those
concerns. Shared across these disparate contexts, morality-based responses to
doubt were clearly regular features of criminal law in medieval religious
communities, even when their precise motives and means markedly differed.
As comparative legal historian James Whitman has argued, the
reasonable doubt doctrine that eventually emerged out of medieval Christian
contexts was "designed [not] to make it more difficult for jurors to convict, [but
to make it] easier, by assuring jurors [as well as witnesses and judges] that
their souls were safe if they voted to condemn the accused., 20 2 In the modem
scheme, finding facts particular to criminal elements became the equivalent of
establishing guilt "beyond a reasonable doubt," without special regard for truth
or moral concern about the soul of the one responsible for convicting a
defendant.203 This observation is significant inasmuch as it radically differs
from modem understandings of reasonable doubt as a safeguard for defendants'
rights. It is also significant in the extent to which it sheds light on the differing
trajectories of doubt rooted in the medieval Islamic and Christian worlds.
Despite the historical, institutional, and contextual differences between
the two legal systems, medieval European and English approaches to doubt
display significant parallels to the Islamic jurisprudence of doubt. For example,
medieval European and English judges and jurors initially declined to punish in
the face of doubt out of concern for their own souls. They feared-in addition
to the legal and physical consequences that sometimes obtained from
demonstrably false verdicts-the spiritual consequences of unjust verdicts,
201. I use this title to express the continuing death-is-different theme articulated in modem
American law, to refer to the extra procedures derived by medieval Christian and Islamic legal actors in
cases of capital punishment. See Schriro v. Summerlin, 542 U.S. 348, 363 (2004) (Breyer, J., dissenting)
(emphasizing that capital punishment requires extra procedural cautions not just because death is
different, but because of the "dramatically different nature of death").
202. WHITMAN, supra note 8, at 4, 11; id. at 194 ("The underlying concern was not with
protecting the defendant at all. It was with protecting the jurors."); cf Charles Donahue Jr., Proofby
Witnesses in the Church Courts of Medieval England: An Imperfect Reception of the LearnedLaw, in
ON THE LAWS AND CUSTOMS OF ENGLAND: ESSAYS tN HONOR OF SAMUEL E. THORNE 127, 132-34
(Morris S. Amold et al. eds., 1981).
203. For more on the somewhat contrasting notions that modem American liberalism relies on
constitutional due process values to align questions of reasonable doubt with defendants' rights, but that
the reasonable doubt doctrine emphasizes fact-based inquiries that sometimes obscure truth within the
context of procedural norms such as the exclusionary rule that may otherwise prejudice defendants, see
WHITMAN, supranote 8, at 203, 207, 334-36.
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
204. See I JAMES FITZJAMES STEPHEN, A HISTORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF ENGLAND 573
(Routledge 1996) (1883) ("[Medieval judges often dreaded] the responsibility-which to many men
would appear intolerably heavy and painful-of deciding . . . upon the guilt or innocence of a
prisoner.").
205. See WHITMAN, supra note 8, at 11 (noting the work of "anthropologists and historians of
religion [demonstrating that] . . . anyone in the premodern world involved in the killing of another
person subjected himself to the risk of bad luck, bad karma, bad fate, or some kind of vengeful divine
retribution") (citations omitted).
206. Id. at 11, 192-93, 198-99.
207. Id. at 90.
208. Id. at 94, 105.
209. Id. at 138.
210. Id. at 161-63.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
For example, witnesses often refused to testify, and judges found strategies to
avoid findings of guilt in ordinary crimes that they did not feel warranted
capital punishment. 211 Juries also expanded the scope of the old "benefit of
clergy" doctrine, allowing first-time offenders in fourteenth-century
ecclesiastical courts to receive lighter sentences in formulations available to
literate members of the Church.212 Moreover, prosecutors frequently
"downcharged" crimes or "downgraded" the value of stolen goods to arrive at
more lenient sentences than the statute would ordinarily require.213 And judges
regularly barred criminal convictions or construed criminal laws narrowly
when they had doubt about the relationship between the evidence2 14
and criminal
culpability or fairness of punishment for an alleged crime.
Taken together, the procedural manifestations of doubt took on multiple
forms that persist in modem American criminal law: the criminal law void-for-
vagueness doctrine and its "junior version," the rule of lenity; 215 the
presumption of innocence; 216 the principle of legality; 2 17 the rule against federal
2 19
common law crimes; 218 doctrines of mistake to absolve criminal liability;
and of course heightened standards and burdens of proof-including
reasonable doubt. Possessed of only a general awareness of the roots of
reasonable doubt and lenity, Justice John Marshall famously stated in his
nineteenth-century invocation of the American rule of lenity: "The rule that
penal laws are to be construed strictly is perhaps not much less old than
220
construction itself.,
211. JEROME HALL, THEFT, LAW AND SOCIETY 92-96 (1935) (noting that judges used to
"invent technicalities in order to avoid infliction of the capital penalty").
212. See LEONA CHRISTINE GABEL, BENEFIT OF CLERGY IN ENGLAND IN THE LATER MIDDLE
AGES (Octagon Books 1969) (1929); see also JOHN HAMILTON BAKER, AN INTRODUCTION TO ENGLISH
LEGAL HISTORY 513-15 (4th ed. 2002) (1971) (overview); J.M. BEATTIE, CRIME AND THE COURTS IN
ENGLAND 1660-1800, at 141-45 (1986) (examples); John Langbein, Shaping the Eighteenth-Century
CriminalTrial: A View from the Ryder Sources, 50 U. CHI. L. REV. 1, 37-41 (1983) (further examples).
213. LANGBEIN, supra note 8, at 334-35 (citing, inter alia, BLACKSTONE, supra note 197, at
239); see also LEON RADZINOWICZ, A HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW AND ITS ADMINISTRATION FROM
1750, at 83-106, 138-64 (1948).
214. For the development of these reasonable doubt practices in English common law and in
continental European law, see WHITMAN, supra note 8, at 334-36. As for the development of lenity
practices, there is debate about when lenity became prevalent, but agreement that it was in full force by
the eighteenth century. See LANGBEIN, supra note 8, at 335 (noting that the rule predated the eighteenth
century but did not become prevalent until then); WHITMAN, supra note 8, at 185-200; Livingston Hall,
Strict or Liberal Construction of Penal Statutes, 48 HARv. L. REV. 748, 750 nn.12-13 (1935) (tracing
the consistent use of the rule of lenity back to mid-seventeenth-century England).
215. See HERBERT PACKER, THE LIMITS OF CRIMINAL SANCTION 95 (1977). For recent
applications, see supra note 11.
216. See Taylor v. Kentucky, 436 U.S. 478 (1978) (labeling the term the "assumption of
innocence"); Coffin v. United States, 157 U.S. 432 (1895) (tracing the concept back to Roman law,
canon law, and early common law); Cummings v. Missouri, 71 U.S. 277 (1866).
217. See McBoyle v. United States, 283 U.S. 25, 27 (1931) (stipulating that the criminal law
texts and punishments must be clear before a criminal defendant may be punished for violating the law).
218. United States v. Hudson & Goodwin, 11 U.S. (7 Cranch) 32, 34 (1812). For further
analysis, see Dan M. Kahan, Lenity andFederal Common Law Crimes, SuP. CT. REV. 345 (1994).
219. See DRESSLER, supra note 3, at 153-65 (mistakes of fact); id. at 167-80 (mistakes of law).
220. United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 95 (1820). On the reasonable doubt
doctrine, see In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 362-63 (1970) ("[P]roof of a criminal charge beyond a
reasonable doubt is constitutionally required .... The standard provides concrete substance for the
2015] "Reasonable Doubt" in Islamic Law
presumption of innocence-that bedrock 'axiomatic and elementary' principle whose 'enforcement lies
at the foundation of the administration of our criminal law."' (quoting Coffin v. United States, 156 U.S.
432, 454 (1895))).
221. WHITMAN, supra note 8, at 131 ("[T]he kings of England were involved in political
conflicts both with the church and with a recalcitrant, and sometimes rebellious, feudal nobility. In the
early days of the development of English law, those conflicts expressed themselves largely as conflicts
over jurisdiction.").
222. The modem situation is quite different. It was only much later that the breakdown of
traditional moral and institutional structures would lead to the wholesale dismissal of doubt in most
modem Islamic criminal law contexts-a fact underscored by this examination of its otherwise forgotten
history. For further discussion see RABB, supra note 25, at 320-21.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
questions of fact and law to issues of the propriety of punishment and mercy.
223. QARAFT, supranote 25 (labeling this type of difference "doubt in interpretive approach").
224. They systematically articulated these doctrines in new works dedicated to legal maxims
under the Mamlik dynasty in Egypt and Syria, which rose with the complete collapse of the 'Abbasid
caliphate. For example, the Sh~fi'i jurist Suyaiti identifies three additional types of doubt: mistake-of-
law, mistake-of-fact, and interpretive difference. SUYOTI, supra note 25, at 237. Compare the M5liki
jurist, Shih~b al-Din al-Qarffi, who identified those three categories of doubt. QARAFI, supra note 25, at
1307-09. Notably, the concepts had existed before in thefiqh treatises of the late 'Abbasid era. See, e.g.,
GHAZALT, supra note 150, at 443-44 (identifying mistake of fact, mistake of law, and "doubt in the
interpretive approach to permissibility"); 7 YAI.YA B. SHARAF AL-NAWAWI, RAWIDA 306-12 (al-Maktab
al-IslAmT 1991) (identifying interpretive doubt as "doubt in the juristic perspective or interpretive
approach"); see also 11 'ABD AL-KARTM AL-RAFI'!, AL-'AzTz 145-47 (Dar al-Kutub al-'llmiyya 1997)
(same).
225. See, e.g., RABB,supra note 25 (describing these notions as elaborated in Shil' contexts).
226. See JACKSON, supra note 108, at 142 (quoting the definition of legal pluralism advanced
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
by distinguished Egyptian jurist Shihab al-Din al-Qaraft during his tenure as a judge in the multiple
legal school-jurisdictions of thirteenth-century Mamliik Egypt).
227. For medieval Muslim jurists' definitions of textual ambiguity, see, for example, 4
MUSTAFA MUHAQQIQ DAMAD, QAVA'ID-I FIQH 54 (Sazimdni Mut~li'-i va Tadvin-i Kutub-i 'Ulcim-i
InsdnT-i Ddnishgihhd 2001), which defines textual ambiguity as uncertainty as to whether a legal text
covers a new set of facts because of silence concerning the new facts, generality in the import of a
statement, or conflicts between the legal text at issue and another equally authoritative legal text; and 2
IBN 'ABD AL-SALAM, AL-QAWA'ID AL-KUBRA 279-80 (Nazlh Kam~l Hammdd &'Uthmgn Jumu'a
Dumayriyya eds., 2007), which describes textual ambiguity as texts that suggest both prohibition and
permissibility.
228. There is evidence that temporary marriages continued well into the first century of Islam
in the Meccan school of Ibn 'Abbas and in the proto-ShIFl circles in Medina and Kufa. This rule
continues as a valid form of marriage in Shi'! law today, perhaps drawing from the Meccan school. See
Wilferd Madelung, 'Abd Allah b. 'Abbcs and Shrite Law, in LAW, CHRISTIANITY, AND MODERNISM IN
ISLAMIC SOCIETY: PROCEEDINGS OF THE EIGHTEENTH CONGRESS OF THE UNION EUROPEtENNE DES
ARABISANTS ET ISLAMISANTS 13, 15-16 (Urbain Vermeulen & J.M.F. van Reeth eds., 1998).
229. For a discussion of first-century temporary marriage rulings and reports of 'Umar's
prohibition, see MOTZKI, supra note 104, at 142-46. For the settled Sunni position of prohibition, see,
for example, II MAwARDI, supranote 50, at 449.
THE YALE JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 40: 41
230. See, e.g., QARAFI, supra note 25, at 1309 (noting that "only astute jurists can discern
[many debatable Islamic legal] rules" and that even they often disagree).
231. See Sherman A. Jackson, Fiction and Formalism: Toward a FunctionalAnalysis of Usul
Al-Fiqh, in STUDIES IN ISLAMIC LEGAL THEORY, supranote 54, at 178.
232. See supranote 17. These discussions are elaborated in RABB, supranote 25.
2015] "ReasonableDoubt" in Islamic Law
CONCLUSION