Natural Fools and The Historiography of Renaissance Folly
Natural Fools and The Historiography of Renaissance Folly
Natural Fools and The Historiography of Renaissance Folly
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Renaissance
Studies
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Renaissance Studies Vol. 25 No. 2 DOI: 10.1111/j.l477-4658.2010.00674.x
Paromita Chakravarti
. . . after playing a minor role on the stage throughout the late Middle A
fool] steps forward at the height of the Renaissance to assume one of t
roles in life's drama ... he gives articulation to the doubts and uncerta
one of the great ideological upheavals in human history . . . [Walter K
1 Harry Levin (ed.), Selected Works of Ben Jonson (New York: Random House, 1938), 12.
2 Praisers of Folly (London: Victor Gollancz, 1964), 11.
3 Madness and Civilisation: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, abridged version trans. Richard Howard
(New York: Vintage Books, Random House, 1988, first pub. Random House, 1965), 7.
4 Erasmus' Praise of Folly sets the tone for the prolific literature of folly which includes works as diverse as
Nicholas de Cusa's Idiota, More's Utopia, Montaigne's essays, Rabelais' Gargantua and Pantagruel, Shakespeare's
portrayal of stage fools, Burton's Anatomy of Melancholy and Cervantes' Don Quixote. For the purposes of this
essay, these varied texts will be referred to generally as the 'praise of folly' genre.
Renaissance Studies © 2010 The Society for Renaissance Studies, Blackwell Publishing Ltd
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 209
lopsided historiography of Renaissance folly which tends to focus exclusively
on the philosophical and literary representations of the morosoph rather than
on the medical, legal, folkloric, anthropological and terratological accounts of
the natural fool.
5 With contradictory connotations in classical and Christian traditions, folly referred to unworldly wisdom in
Socratic philosophy (See The Apology of Socrates, Phaedrus, Ion) and Pauline Christianity, positing meanings very
different from madness as divine punishment for sin in Greek tragedy or the Old Testament (See M. A. Screech,
'Good Madness in Christendom', in Roy Porter et al. (eds.), The Anatomy of Madness, Essays in the History of
Psychiatry, 3 vols. (London: Tavistock, 1985-88), Vol. 3, 25-39).
6 The trope of universal madness has classical origins in the Stoic maxim, lInsaniunt omnes praeter sapientem ,
in Horace's lDoceo insanire omnis and Mantuan's first Eclogue, commonly quoted in the Renaissance, 'Id
commune malum; semel insanivimus omnes .
7 The Praise of Folly and Letter to Maarten Van Dorp 1515, trans. Betty Radice, with an introduction and notes by
A. H. T Levi (London: Penguin, 1971), 102.
8 Robert Burton, The Anatomy of Melancholy, 3 vols., (London: J. M. Dent and Sons, 1932), Vol.1, 39.
9 Bodleian Library, Oxford: Douce Portfolio 142.92. Reproduced in John Southworth, Fools and Jesters at the
English Court (Stroud: Sutton Publishing Ltd., 1998), 118.
10 See 1 Cor:l: 18-28; 2:18-20; 3:9-13. Authorised Version, 1616.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
210 Paromita Chakravarti
11 In the Preface, Erasmus bids 'learned More' to be 'a stout champion of your namesake Folly' [Praise of Folly,
Preface, 61].
12 See Thomas Stapleton, The Life and Illustrious Martyrdom of St Thomas More, trans. Philip E. Hallett,
(London: Burns Oates, 1928), 132-44.
13 See Noeline Hall, 'Henry Patenson - Sir Thomas More's Fool', Moreana XXVII, 101-02, May, 1990, 75-86.
14 'They [Utopians] have singular delite and pleasure in foles. And as it is a greate reproche to do annye of
them hurte or injury, so they prohibite not to take pleasure of foolyshnes.' [Thomas More, Utopia and the
Dialogue of Comfort (London: J. M. Dent, 1910, repr. 1935), 87].
15 Thomas More, The Apology, ed. J. B. Trapp, The Yale Edition of The Complete Works of Thomas More, Vol. 9 (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1979), 118.
16 While literary criticism of More emphasizes his valorization of fools and folly, histories of psychiatry mark
out the incident described in Apology as demonstrating the period's cruelty towards the mad and foolish. For D.
H. Tuke, in Chapters in the History of the Insane in the British Isles (London: Kegan Paul, 1882) the incident
'illustrates so graphically the whipping-post treatment of that day' (57). In Richard Hunter and Ida MacAlpine
(eds.), Three Hundred Years of Psychiatry (1535-1860) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961), the incident
exemplifies how 'pauper lunatics were generally classed with vagrants, beggars and disorderly persons and dealt
with in the same way, since madness meant socially intolerable behaviour' (5). George Rosen in Madness and
Society: Chapters in the Historical Sociology of Mental Illness (London: Routledge, 1968), 140-41, relates the incident
to demonstrate how the mad were flogged. These history of psychiatry accounts provides an alternative to the
prevalent historiography of folly which regards the Renaissance and particularly the humanists (like More) as
being peculiarly tolerant to fools.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 211
is the witty jester or the artificial fool with command over language and
culture who becomes the humanist spokesperson, rather than the natural fool
and his variants - the 'monster', savage, clown, wild man, bedlamite or native.
Rarely featured in Renaissance praises of folly, these figures remain outside
the pale of the educated, rational, male, European civic society which defines
the humanist understanding of the 'human'. It is the discourse of 'naturals',
often glossed over by historians of Renaissance folly (who tend to focus more
on the philosophical and literary representations of the wise fool) which
reveals how, despite celebrating the levelling effects of a symbolic, 'universal'
folly, Renaissance humanism remained exclusionist. Neither uniformly affir
mative nor unique, humanist attitudes to folly thus share the prejudices about
the foolish attributed to earlier and particularly, later times. Although histo
rians connect the discourse of folly with humanist emancipation from scho
lastic orthodoxies, the rupture was perhaps less absolute. Continuities also
existed between Renaissance and Enlightenment attitudes.
Much of the traditional scholarship on folly, as well as more recent work
characterize the Renaissance as a period of tolerance of and interest in
irrationality (see quotes above). Huizinga writes: 'The figure of Folly, of
gigantic size, looms large in the period of the Renaissance . . . People laughed
loudly and with unconcern at all that was foolish. . . ,'17 This laughter does not
ridicule but accepts foolish ridiculousness as well as risibility as an aspect of the
human condition: 'In the Renaissance, Christian laughter swept into promi
nence, aided by the conviction that man is a laughing animal.'18 Rosen
observes how folly pervades both Renaissance life and literature : 'Folly and
madness had become integral elements of the world of people and things. It
is certainly no coincidence that the literature of the late sixteenth and early
seventeenth centuries is so rich in the portrayal of distraught and insane
characters. Quixote, Lear, Ophelia . . ,'19
The Enlightenment however, is regarded as introducing the reign of secular
Reason which banishes the fool from the hospitable environment of the
earlier age, making him an outcast. Zijderveld remarks on the '. . . reforma
tion and Enlightenment - who won the definitive victory over traditional
folly.'20 In Kaiser's poetic formulation, 'As he goes to Arthur's bosom with the
chimes at midnight ringing for the last time', the quintessential Renaissance
fool, Falstaff, 'in a specific chronological sense, make(s) good his threat and
take(s) with him, if not all the world, at least his sixteenth century world.'21
17 Johann Huizinga, 'The Comedy of Life' in Kathleen Williams (ed.), Twentieth Century Interpretations of The
Praise of Folly (New Jersey: Prendce-Hall, 1969), 61-7, 66; repr. from Johann Huizinga, Erasmus, trans, by
F. Hopman (London: Phaidon Press, 1952).
18 M. A. Screech, Laughter at the Foot of the Cross (London: Penguin, 1997), 4.
19 Rosen, Madness and Society, 157.
20 A. C. Zijderveld, Reality in the Looking Glass, Rationality through an Analysis of Traditional Folly (London:
Routledge, 1982), 40.
21 Walter Kaiser, Praisers of Folly (London: Victor Gollancz, 1964), 277.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
212 Paromita Chakravarti
Oblivion falls upon the world navigated by the free slaves of the Ship of
. . . Behold it moored now, made fast among things and men. Retained
maintained. No longer a ship but a hospital.26
The transition however was not nearly as abrupt. The freedom that
bestows on the crazed mariners of the Ship of Fool is part of the r
zation of the Renaissance fool enabled by a wealth of literary mate
acterizing him as a metaphoric vestige of an older, stabler world orde
historians of Renaisance folly use humanist literature and contempora
as direct evidence of how fools were treated in real life: 'The presen
Bedlam and its inmates on the stage indicates the acceptance of
within a socially admissible framework. . . ,'27 But Midelfort warns u
this easy identification. He points out for instance, that empirical res
not yielded any records of real ships of fools mentioned by Foucault,
22 Barbara Swain, Fools and Folly During the Middle Ages and the Renaissance (New York: Columbia
Press, 1932), 184.
23 Enid Welsford, The Fool (New York: Anchor Books, 1961), 125.
24 Rosen, Madness and Society, 158.
25 William Willeford, The Fool and his Sceptre (London: Edward Arnold, 1969), Introduction, xx.
26 Madness and Civilisation, 35.
27 Rosen, Madness and Society, 158.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 213
28 H. C. Erik Midelfort, 'Madness and Civilisation in Early Modem Europe: A Reappaisal of Michel Foucault
in B. Malament (ed.), After the Reformation (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylavnia Press, 1980), 247-85, he
254.
29 H. C. Erik Midelfort, 'Reading and Believing, On the Reappraisal of Michel Foucault', in A. Still an
Velody (eds.), Rewriting the History of Madness (London: Routledge, 1992), 105-9, here 106.
30 Midelfort, 'Madness and Civilisation', 259.
31 Ibid.y 253-4, 255.
32 Critiquing Welsford's The Fool and Robert H. Goldsmith's Wise Fools in Shakespeare, both based heavily
literary representations of folly, Willeford shows how they oversimplify the fool in trying to extract 'mean
and attribute 'wisdom or sanctity' to him. So powerful is this humanist construction of the wise-fool that
impedes more complex modes of reading folly: 'This tendency provides a way of understanding the fo
meaning but impairs the mode of seeing him by which we gain access to his life. ... I do not assume that it
be reduced to the neat form of paradox or that it necessarily belongs to the ironic expression of wise truth.' (
Fool and his Sceptre Intro, xxi).
33 William Empson notes that the legal sense of the fool as imbecile emerged almost contemporaneously wi
its meaning as an affectionate dependant. See The Structure of Complex Words (Cambridge: Harvard Univer
Press, 1951; repr.1989), 115.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
214 Paromita Chakravarti
In The Tempest, the drunken Trinculo wonders about Caliban: ' "Lord" quoth
he? That a monster should be such a natural!'(3.2.30-1),35 playing on the idea
of the monster as an 'unnatural' creature, juxtaposing it with the colloquial
use of 'natural' to mean an idiot. Trinculo registers mock amazement at the
way Caliban combines these apparently opposed qualities of naturalness and
unnaturalness, idiocy and monstrosity. While his hybrid man-fish appearance
excludes Caliban from the natural realm, his natural folly connects him to it.
Although Trinculo's wordplay opposes folly and monstrosity, Renaissance
discourses of folly linked natural fools and monsters. Representing both fallen
mankind and the unnatural other, the natural fool was a bestial, half-human
creature, moving between the poles of comic inclusion in the pageant of
universal human folly and tragic alienation from human attributes.
The conceptualization of folly as a sign, not of difference, but of identity
with nature draws from the Christian view of it as an attribute, not exclusively
of the fool but of fallen nature. The irrational represent the universal post
lapsarian corruption of reason and are thus 'natural'. However, in other
semantic registers, 'natural' designates the non-rational natural world of
beasts and plants as distinguished from rational man.36 In his simultaneous
connection with and alienation from the human, the natural fool is both like
and unlike the unnatural monster. These conflicting views of folly as both
universal and natural condition as well as an inhuman and bestial one, stem
34 'Cogito and the History of Madness', Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Roudedge, 1978, first
pub. 1967, Editions du Seuill), 48.
35 The Norton Shakespeare, ed. Stephen Greenblatt, Walter Cohen, Jean E. Howard and Katherine Mauss (New
York: Norton, 1997).
36 C. S. Lewis, Studies in Words (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), 49.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 215
from competing Renaissance notions of the 'natural' and the 'human'. Ar
totelian ideas of nature as norm coexist with the Christian conception o
fallen and irrational nature. Greek definitions of the human as rational
coexist with Protestant scepticism about the limited, even damaged h
reason which makes man scarcely different from animals. With its tw
cies of classical philosophy and Christianity, humanism works with con
tory constructions of the 'human' and the 'natural'. Humanist discou
natural folly is allied to discourses of the monster, the wild man, th
World native and the child. These figures, like the natural fool, are
between the natural and unnatural, rational and irrational, primitive
infantile, both included and excluded in the 'human' category. Drawn
sometimes conflicting sources (medical, theological, legal, New W
debates and folklore) these allied discourses contribute to the humanist
ambivalence towards the natural fool.
37 Renaissance teratologist, Ambroise Parré, says: 'Wee call Monsters, what things soever are b
contrary to the common decree and order of nature. So wee terme that infant monstrous, which
one arme alone, or with two heads.' See The Workes of Ambroise Parey, trans. T.Johnson (Londo
38 Aristotle, The Generation of Animals, 4.4.770b; trans. A. L. Peck, Loeb Classical Library (Camb
University Press, 1963), 425.
39 See Keith Thomas, Man and the Natural World (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984), 32. Fools we
with beasts in the Renaissance art of Physiognomy. See Jonathan Andrews in 'Begging the Quest
the Definition and Socio-Cultural Meaning of Idiocy in Early Modern Britain: Part 2', History of P
1998, 179-200, here 182-95.
40 John Donne, 'The True Character of a Dunce', in The Complete Poetry and Selected Prose of
(Modern Library: New York, 1946), 293.
41 See Paul F. Cranefield and Walter Federn, 'The Begetting of Fools: An Annotated Translat
sus', De Generatione Stultorum , Bulletin of the History of Medicine, Vol. 41 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
63, 66.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
216 Paromita Chakravarti
. . . the head is sometimes misshapen; the tongue is huge and swollen; they are
dumb; the throat is often goitrous . . . they present an ugly sight. . . sitting in the
streets and looking into the sun . . . putting little sticks in between their fingers,
twisting their bodies in various ways, with their mouth agape . . ,43
In theological discourse the fool and monster were related through their
linking of the bestial and the human. Old Testament Proverbs connect fools
with animals: 'A whip for the horse, a bridle for the ass/and a rod for the back
of fools' (26:3).44 Despite the Pauline valorization of the spiritual fool, medi
eval and Renaissance Christianity underlined the ambiguity of the natural fool
and monster asking questions such as: Why were fools and monsters born? Did
such creatures have souls? Could they be saved? What was the function of such
mockeries of Creation? Christian writers usually explained their existence by
referring to the Fall. Although deviants in worldly terms, fools or monsters
represented postlapsarian man and were thus quintessentially human and
natural. Augustine writes:
42 Josias Simler, Vallesiae descriptio, libri duo (Tiguri: Froschouer, 1574) fols. 3b and 4a. Quoted in Paul F.
Cranefield, 'The Discovery of Cretinism', Bulletin of the History of Medicine, Vol.36, Nov-Dec 1962, 494.
43 Felix Platter, Praxeos, seu de cognoscendis, praedicendis, praevendis curandisque ajfectibus homini incommodantibus
tractatu s . . . (Basel, 1602-8), Vol.1, pp.95-6. Quoted in Cranefield, Ibid; 496.
44 See also Prov. 26:11 and 17:12. In 26:7, the fool is compared to the physically disabled.
45 Augustine, Contra Julianum Pelagianum, Lib.III, iv, 10 (Patrologia Latina, 44:707), trans. M. A Schumacher,
Saint Augustine Against Julian, in R.J. Deferrari et al. (eds.), The Fathers of the Church. A New Translation, Vol. 35
(New York: Fathers of the Church, inc., 1957), 115.
46 City of God, trans. Henry Bettenson with an introduction by David Knowles (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1972), 22: 19, 1061.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 217
Augustinian ideas. Paracelsus, the anti-Aristotelian physician influenced by
radical Protestantism universalizes and naturalizes folly and monstrosity by
tracing the genesis of fools and monsters to the postlapsarian moment:
. . . when they [Adam and Eve] came out of Paradise, they were . . . corruptible,
mortal, distressed . . . they saw . . . many deformations of their children. . . .
crooked children came into being, there blind ones, there deaf ones . . . there
fools, there monsters . . ,47
Paracelsus asserts that our 'wisdom is nothing before God ... all of us in our
wisdom are like the fools'48 and the fool is one of us.
Donne rationalizes the existence of monsters as a proof of the 'variety of
nature'49 implying that though anomalous, they were natural. This follows
Pliny's description of monsters as 'lusus naturae (sport of nature),50 who
provide entertainment as fools do. Clubbed together as recreational objects,
a dwarf, fool and madman provide a 'solazzo in Ariosto's Satire V; the her
maphrodite, dwarf and fool sing and dance in Jonson's Volpone. Natural
fools, like monsters, were considered freaks and 'folly' also meant a prodigy
or curiosity, commonly used for the fantastic seventeenth-century baroque
houses.51
Natural philosophy considered both fools and monsters as accidents of
nature who challenged the laws of heredity. Following Aristotle's definition of
monsters as offsprings not resembling parents, Juan Luis Huarte comments
on the birth of natural fools:
... of wise parents, are borne foolish children, and of foolish parents, children
very wise . .. And amongst children of one selfe father and mother, one
prooveth simple, and another wittie.52
Huarte suggests that fools, like monsters, were conceived through defects in
the maternal imagination which influenced the foetus so powerfully that the
father's seed, the legitimate and rational embryonic principle, was over
whelmed, giving rise to children defective in body and mind. Such creatures
bore no mark of the father but displayed the imprint of their foolish and
irrational mother's desires and experiences at the time of conception and
pregnancy. Thus fools and monsters are, in a certain sense, unfathered
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
218 Paromita Chakravarti
The conjunction of monstrosity and folly was most spectacularly noticed in the
figure of the 'wild man' who had both folkloric and Scriptural incarnations.
Associated with fertility like the ritual fool, this inarticulate, woodland crea
ture was a 'monster', more bestial than human.54 The 'wild man' was por
trayed in medieval literary descriptions as the 'salvage' or savage. The 'wild
man' myth was strengthened by scriptural accounts of Nebuchadnezzar's
bestial forest existence, punished for his folly by God55 as well as the positive
examples of Christian saints practicing asceticism in the wilderness (John of
Chrysostom, captured by hunters who took him for a beast or Francis of Assissi
living among wild animals).56 Contradictory ideas of Nebuchadnezzar's besti
ality and ungodly folly and the unworldliness of the wild 'fools of Christ'
constituted the complex blend of the irrationality and monstrosity of the wild
man. These figures were perhaps inspired by the actual practice of abandon
ing disabled or mentally challenged children in the woods.57 In the eighteenth
53 See C. F. Goodey in 'John Locke's idiots in the natural history of mind', History of Psychiatry V, 1994, 215-50,
here 227-34. See Paul F. Cranefield, 'The Discovery of Cretinism', 494-5, n. 15 for why the fool is colloquially
called a 'cuckoo' (or 'kookie'), a 'changeling' bird which substituted its eggs for those of another bird.
54 The club wielding Green Man dressed in vines, still seen on English pub signs, is a reminder of pagan
fertility rites. The Green Knight in Sir Gawain and the Green Knight is a variant of such a figure. See Welsford, The
Fool, 70-72 for the association of the fool with fertility rites. Legends of Welsh prophets like Lailoken, Merlin
and Irish gelts conflate Wild Men with pagan forest deities and magic-wielding fools. (Welsford, The Fool, 97,
103-5). The fool's connections with the wild man is preserved in the jester's and harlequin's use of animal skins,
foxtails and cockscombs (Willeford, Fool and his Sceptre, 18-19).
55 See Hayden White, 'The Forms of Wildness: Archaeology of an Idea', in Edward Dudley and M. E. Novak
(eds.), The Wild Man Within, An Image in Western Thought from the Renaissance to the Reformation (Pittsburgh:
Pittsburgh University Press, 1972), pp. 3-38, here 14; Penelope Doob, Nebuchadnezzar's Children: Conventions of
Madness in Middle English Literature (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974), 134^207.
56 Richard Bernheimer, Wild Men in the Middle Ages (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1952), Wild Men
in the Middle Ages, 17; John Saward, Perfect Fools (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 84.
57 For etymological connections between lunacy and the woods see Bernheimer, Wild Men in the Middle Ages,
12, 191 n.26, for Malory's use of the word 'wylde' as frenzied. Also the Anglo-Saxon word 'wode' means mad.
In A Midsummer Night's Dream, Demetrius describes his distraction in the forest as 'wood within this wood'
(2.1.192).
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 219
century, anthropological and philosophical interest was directed at these fera
children.
As civilization's banished other, the wild man shared the traits of another
'natural', the New World 'native' being 'discovered' by sixteenth-century
Europeans.58 Travellers' and colonists' accounts of the 'uncivilized' and 'mon
strous' people of the New World and theological, medical and philosophical
writings about natural fools converge significantly. Strategies of understand
ing known forms of deviance like folly, deformity and insanity were deployed
to explain the otherness of New World natives.59 Thus the discourse of Renais
sance folly must be situated in larger debates on nature and culture, civility
and savagery, folly and rationality, monstrosity and humanity which inform
discussions of the native. The fool must be studied alongside other outsiders
of European civilization, like the alien, the savage and the monster who
compelled a Eurocentric humanism to question its definition of the 'human'.
58 Both 'natural' and 'native' derive from Latin 'natus' or birth and refer to a state untouched by culture. For
connections between the Wild Man and native, see Stanley L. Robe, 'Wild Men and Spain's Brave New World',
Wild Man Within, 39-53.
59 Leslie Fiedler, The Stranger in Shakespeare (New York: Stein and Day, 1972), 199-253, shows how 'Old World'
travel narratives and Greek romances shaped descriptions of the New World. See John Pitcher, 'A Theatre of
the Future: The Aeneid and The Tempest', Essays in Criticism 34, 1984, 193-215.
60 Stephen Greenblatt, Marvellous Possessions: The Wonder of the New World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991),
135.
61 See J. B. Friedman, The Monstrous Races in Medieval Art and Thought (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1981), 178-96. Different standards were set for adjudging the humanity of these exotic races - Roman law
regarded the human form; Christian canonists, the soul; and Aristotelians, reason as the essence of mankind.
Other criteria of clothing, language, domesticating animals, religion, civil society and government were also
used.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
220 Paromita Chakravarti
62 Aristotle, Politics, Books I, 2-6. See Anthony Pagden, 'Dispossessing the Barbarian: the Language of
Spanish Thomism and the Debate over the Property Rights of American Indians', in A. Pagden (ed.), The
Language of Political Theory in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 79-98,
here 85.
63 However, missionaries' opinions differed. Many considered the natives incapable of Christianity. In 1517,
Cardinal de Cisneros wrote: 'they [Indians] are not capable of natural judgement or of receiving the faith . . .
and they need just as th e . . . beast does, to be . . . governed by Christians who treat them well and not cruelly'
[quoted in Lewis Hanke, All Mankind is One: A Study of the Disputation between Bartoleme de Las Casas and fuan Gines
de Sepulveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious Capacity of the American Indians (DeKalb: Northern Illinois
University Press, 1974), 11.] The Dominican, Tomas Ortiz, declared the natives incapable of learning before the
Council of Indies. Betanzos declared before the same council that Indians were incapable of reason and
Chrisdanity. Although he retracted his statement, doubts about the evangelical project continued.
64 Delndiis et deJuri Belli: Relectiones. Quoted in Lewis Hanke, Aristotle and the American Indians (London: Hollis
and Carter, 1959), 22-3.
65 See De bello contra insulanos. Quoted in Pagden, Political Theory, 93.
66 Quoted in Hanke, All Mankind is One, 20.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 221
'dumb brutes' and asserting that they were 'truly men'. But the controversy
about their intellectual capacities continued.
A national debate was held in Valladolid in 1550 to decide whether the
. . . vestiges of humanity, who not only possess no science but who also lack
letters.
. . . Neither do they have written laws but barbaric institutions and customs.68
By referring to the natives as 'little men' Sepülveda drew upon the tradition of
infantilizing the native going back to medieval characterizations of pygmies as
childish men representing an earlier stage of human development.69 This
description of natives as partially rational like the young, both men and not
men, helped to explain their simultaneous difference from and identity with
Europeans. This theory also offered a more Christian perspective. Domingo
de Betanzos described the Indians as immature and irrational like children;70
Vittoria called them 'unrational', with potential for reason, who could there
fore enjoy partial property rights.71 But for Sepülveda, the infantalization of
the native did not merely suggest a difference in degree of intelligence, but an
absolute difference of kind: 'In prudence, talent, virtue and humanity they are
as inferior to the Spaniards as children to adults, women to men . . . monkeys
to men.'72
Las Casas refuted Sepûlveda's claims in Apologia, using his opponent's
description of Indians but arguing that their childish status called for nurture
rather than assault.73 He also indicated the theological problems of supposing,
as Sepülveda and others did, that God would create a race of partially rational
creatures who 'should be called barbarians, savages, wild men and brutes.'74
They in fact had civil society and just governance comparable to the wisest
67 Ibid., 21.
68 Ibid., 85.
69 Friedman, Monstrous Races, 191.
70 Hanke, All Mankind is One, 19.
71 Pagden, Political Theory, 84-5.
72 Quoted in Hanke, All Mankind is One, 84.
73 Quoted in Hanke, Aristotle and the American Indians, 112.
74 Quoted in Hanke, All Mankind is One, 82.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
222 Paromita Chakravarti
Indians should not study because no benefit may be expected from their edu
cation. . . . Indians are not stable persons, to whom one should not entrust the
preaching of the Gospel.79
Those who had experience in teaching the natives refuted these charges.
Alonso de Zorita, described how liberal arts like music, reading and writing
flourished among Indians.80 Dominican Santo Tomas, compared the Peruvian
Indians' language to Latin. In his Preface to Grammatica (1560) he invoked
Aristotle's dictum, 'there is no better way to judge the genius of a man than in
the words and language that he uses' to prove that Peruvians had 'great
culture and order'.81 The humanist emphasis on linguistic ability as a marker
of humanity and civility informed discussions about the natives' capacities and
status. Zorita cannot see 'any reason for calling them barbarians' because they
have 'good Latinists and musicians'.82
Las Casas was reluctant to accept not only the Indians' 'barbarism' but the
existence of barbarians anywhere, since it would undermine the Christian
principles of man's perfectibility and the unity of species, implying that 'God
became careless in creating so immense a number of rational souls and let
human nature ... go astray'.83 It seemed like a frustration of the divine plan to
'find one whole nation . . . slow-witted, moronic, foolish or stupid' without
'sufficient natural knowledge and ability to rule and govern' itself.84 Even if
75 Ibid., 77.
76 Ibid., 76.
77 Ibid., 74.
78 Ibid., 11-12.
79 Ibid., 26.
80 M., 131.
81 126.
82 Ibid., 132.
83 Ibid., 77.
84 Ibid., 84.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 223
such races existed, war against them would still be unjust since, Las Casas
concludes, quoting John of Chrysostom:
The issues raised in the Spanish debates about the native recur in R
legal and medical discourses on the status of the natural fool. These
eighteenth-century constructions of folly, suggesting continuities
humanist and Enlightenment attitudes rather than the disjunction
by Foucault's thesis. Described as monsters, idiots (idiots; stulti),
(locos) New World natives shared traits of natural fools and monst
tions of property rights for fools, idiots and monsters revisit disp
natives' rights to dominium - are they human? Can they enjoy the sam
as others? These issues did not surface in the Enlightenment, but
histories of discrimination and segregation of the mad and foolis
thirteenth century, England passed statutes granting the king custody
belonging to congenital idiots or natural fools (fatuorum naturaliu
1540, the Court of Wards and Liveries took over the responsibility
istering the properties of idiots and lunatics. Intelligence tests were de
determine fitness for managing property. The Court would take
property of those
. . . who cannot count or number twenty, and tell who was his father or m
nor how old he is, so that may it appear that he hath no understanding or
what shall be for his profit, or what for his loss.87
85 Ibid., 96.
86 The king had custody of the lands for the fool's lifetime, 'taking their profits without waste,
their necessaries . .. and after their death must return them to the rightful heirs.' Quoted in Nigel
and Insanity in England, 2 vols. (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1968), Vol.1, 25.
87 A. Fitzherbert, Natura Brevium, (1652), 583; quoted in John Charles Bucknill and Dani
Manual of Psychological Medicine: Containing the History, Nosology, Description, Statistics, Diagnosis, P
Treatment of Insanity. With an Appendix of Cases (London: John Churchill, 1858), 94.
88 See Nigel Walker's discussion of the legal writing of Mathew Hale, Coke and Dalton on p
criminal laws for idiots in Crime and Insanity, Vol. 1,.35-51.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
224 Paromita Chakravarti
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 225
they were 'able enough for Mechanical Arts', others were 'only able to learn
what belongs to eating or the common means of living', and 'others merely
Dolts or drivelling Fools' unable to understand anything or 'do anything
knowingly'.98 The hierarchy of liberal and mechanical arts in assessing mental
capacities and rational abilities echo discussions of the Indians' educability.
Anticipating Willis, Zacchias, an earlier physician, also defines degrees of folly
according to learning abilities:
These persons .. . seem to exist below the condition of human nature with
respect to the use of reason. They are hardly taught to speak and are known to
be incapable ... by their very speech they make plain that they are fools (fatui),
because by talking (Jando) they show their imperfection . . ,100
Disputes about whether fools and monsters had rational souls, could be
baptized or saved revisit the theological controversies about the native
capacities for Christianity. Paracelsus' treatise on fools wonders about the
divine rationale of creating the mentally and physically disabled using argu
ments similar to Las Casas' speculations on why God would create barbaric
races. Thus Enlightenment medical and legal discourses are anticipated in
earlier discussions, not perhaps in the literature of humanist folly, but in other
debates of monsters, natives and naturals. This conflation of the fool, monster
and the native has important implications for Renaissance folly and its asso
ciations with cultural primitivism. The natural fool was not only outside civ
society but perhaps pre-dated society. Attitudes towards this anthropologize
version of folly were divided between alienation and acknowledgement. Fool
monsters and the exotic races were seen as trapped in some form of psych
logical and spiritual infancy which made them, like children, part of the
human species, yet dissimilar in their capacities and manners from other
Like the native, described as 'homunculus', the fool was frequently compar
98 Thomas Willis, De anima brutorum (Oxford, 1672), trans. S. Pordage, Two Discourses Concerning the Soul o
Brutes, which is that of the Vital and Sensitive of Man (London, 1683), 212.
99 Paulus Zacchias in Cranefield and Federn, 122.
100 Ibid., 126.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
226 Paromita Chakravarti
It might be very well expected, that innate Principles should be perfectly known
to Naturals. . . . But alas, among Children, Ideots, Savages and the grossly illi
terate, what general Maxims are to be found? What universal Principles of
Knowledge?105
Devoid oi Innate ideas and sense impressions, possessing little memory and
rudimentary verbal abilities, the idiot occupied the threshold between nature
and civilization, providing a living example of the individual and collective
childhood of man, demonstrating the processes of memory and language
learning and their role in defining the 'human'.106 He was, consequently, at
the heart of the Enlightenment project of constructing a speculative natural
history, which would explain the origins of institutions like the State and trace
human progress from primitivism to civilization. Conjectural histories of the
development of polity from a hypothetical 'State of Nature' by Locke, Rous
seau, and Hobbes, and attempts to trace the origins of language and culture
101 Leah S. Marcus, Childhood and Cultural Despair (Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, 1978), 11-12.
102 Willis, Concerning the Soul of Brutes, 213.
103 Zacchias, 126. The fool's interest in trifles is discussed in connection with the infantalization of natives.
Zorita however argued that Indians' childish interest in acquiring trifles in exchange for gold was comparable
to the Spaniards equally childish hunger for gold (Hanke, Aristotle and the American Indians, 50). In More's
Utopia, children play with pearls and gems, since these were considered worthless in Utopia. When the
Anemolian ambassadors visit, dressed in expensive clothes and jewellery, a Utopian child wonders why adults
should be dressed in children's trinkets like a 'great lubbor'. His mother suggests that the ostentatiously dressed
man was the king's fool. ( Utopia and the Dialogue of Comfort, pp.68-70).
104 John Brydall, Non Compos mentis: or the Law relating to Natural Fools, Mad-Folks and Lunatick Persons (London,
1700), facs. repr. Of 1st edn. (New York: Garland, 1979), 9.
105 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1975), Book I, Ch. 2, 64. Also Book I, Ch.2, 49.
106 See Goodey, John Locke's Idiots', 215-50.
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The historiography of Renaissance folly 227
by Adam Smith and Condillac contemplate human beginnings which seem
be embodied and preserved in the idiot. Narratives of feral children, conflated
with the scrutiny of the idiot were useful in understanding the pre-verb
pre-civil, savage existence of our ancestors and the connections between t
natural and the human.107 Although identified with the Enlightenment, these
discussions had earlier incarnations in the Renaissance discourse of naturals.
Jadavpur University
This content downloaded from 170.173.0.22 on Sun, 17 Nov 2019 14:09:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms