Kant On Empiricism and Rationalism-Published PDF
Kant On Empiricism and Rationalism-Published PDF
Kant On Empiricism and Rationalism-Published PDF
KANT ON EMPIRICISM
AND RATIONALISM
Alberto Vanzo
53
54 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
It is often alleged that Kant introduced the three biases that plague
much post-Kantian historiography. As for the classificatory bias, Kant
is said to have “argued, in the Critique of Pure Reason, that empiri-
cism and rationalism represent two comprehensive options, and that
the philosophers of his day were drawn respectively to one or other
of them.”16 “[T]his was the easiest way to describe the development of
philosophy in the two centuries prior to Kant in the light of his own
problem:”17 namely, an epistemological problem. Kant allegedly had
the epistemological bias because he reduced “the history of modern
philosophy to an epistemological clash between rationalism and em-
piricism.”18 He did this to “argue for a third option, his own, which
incorporated, as he saw it, what was true in both [empiricism and
rationalism], while avoiding their errors.”19 He exhibited the Kan-
tian bias by recommending his own philosophy as the “‘true middle
course’ between the self-revealing one-sidedness of empiricism and
rationalism.”20
This paper provides an alternative account of Kant’s contribution to
the development of the standard narrative. The paper argues for the
following claims:
1. Kant is not directly responsible for the three biases of the stan-
dard historiography. In fact, Kant did not have any of the three
biases. He did not regard most or all early modern philosophers
as empiricists or rationalists. He did not regard his own philoso-
phy as an alternative to empiricism and rationalism as such but,
rather, as a form of rationalism. And he did not interpret most
or all of the main philosophical doctrines, developments, and
disputes of the early modern period in the light of philosophers’
commitment to empiricism or rationalism.
2. However, Kant made three indirect contributions to the develop-
ment of the standard narrative:
(a) He formulated the notions of empiricism and rationalism that
are at the basis of the standard narrative, and he employed
them in his sketches of the history of modern philosophy.
(b) He outlined, most notably in the antinomies, a dialectical
pattern of argument that would inform the standard narra-
tive.
(c) He promoted a way of writing histories of philosophy that,
once combined with (a) and (b), would give rise to the biases
of the standard narrative.
56 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
By arguing for these claims, the paper provides a first step toward a
comprehensive reconstruction of the history of the standard narrative
of early modern philosophy.
The paper is divided into seven sections. Section 1 outlines Kant’s
notions of empiricism and its rivals. Section 2 examines the role of the
RED in Kant’s sketches of the history of philosophy. Sections 3 to 5 ar-
gue that Kant did not have the three biases. Section 6 highlights Kant’s
indirect contributions to the development of the standard narrative.
Some conclusions are drawn in Section 7.
Ancient philosophers
Practical philosophers Theoretical philosophers
Dogmatists Sceptics
Empiricists [Rationalists] Mystics
Empiricists Rationalists
Locke Leibniz
Hume Kant
There are good reasons to hold that Kant regards other early modern
philosophers as rationalists or empiricists, as summarized in Table 2
below.
1. The Metaphysik Mrongovius (29:761) associates Christian Au-
gust Crusius with Plato and Leibniz. This suggests that Kant
takes Crusius to be a rationalist.
2. By combining two passages from the second Critique (5:40,
70–71), one can infer that Kant regards Michel de Mon-
taigne, Bernard Mandeville, and Francis Hutcheson as
moral empiricists, Christian Wolff and Crusius as moral
rationalists. Moral rationalists establish whether an action
is morally good on the basis of its conformity to an a priori
law. Moral empiricists establish whether an action is mor-
ally good on the basis of its consequences, namely, whether
it promotes one’s happiness.
3. By combining two passages from the third Critique (5:277–78,
346–51), one can infer that Kant would call Edmund Burke
an empiricist about beauty. Aesthetic empiricists claim that
judgments of taste can be based only on empirical principles.
Aesthetic rationalists claim that whether an object is beautiful
depends on its conformity with an a priori principle.
4. Kant does not mention any aesthetic rationalists in the third
Critique. However, he criticizes a form of aesthetic rationalism
that assimilates beauty to perfection.32 It is not difficult to iden-
tify this view with those of Wolff, Alexander Baumgarten, and
Georg Friedrich Meier, all authors whom Kant knew well.
Empiricists Rationalists
In general Crusius
In ethics Montaigne Wolff
Mandeville Crusius
Hutcheson
In aesthetics Burke Wolff
Baumgarten
Meier
Admittedly, the most explicit indications that Kant took his philoso-
phy to be a form of rationalism can be found in lecture notes, which are
far less reliable than Kant’s own works and must be used with care.
However, the passages at stake are from three different transcripts. The
approximate datings of the lectures on which the transcripts are based
are uncontroversial and can be traced back to a time span of only five
years (1790–95),42 all well within the Critical period. The meaning of
each passage taken individually is rather clear, and the passages are
consistent with one another. They are also consistent with the doctrine
of the original acquisition that is sketched in several texts from 1770 to
the 1790s and with statements in the first Critique, the Prolegomena,
and the Progress of Metaphysics. As we saw above, some of those other
statements also suggest that Kant took his theoretical philosophy to be
a form of rationalism. This is in line with Kant’s explicit categorization
of his ethics and aesthetics as rationalist. For all these reasons, we can
rely on the collective evidence provided by the lecture transcripts and
the other texts to conclude that Kant did take his philosophy to be a
form of rationalism.
Of course, Kant took his philosophy to be more than just another
form of rationalism. He regarded it as the only true rationalism. As
we saw in Section 2, he criticized earlier forms of rationalism as much
as earlier forms of empiricism. At the same time, he accepted tenets of
earlier empiricists and rationalists. For instance, he combined Locke’s
emphasis on the necessity of sensory input for knowledge acquisition
with Leibniz’s admission of substantive a priori knowledge. Neverthe-
less, Kant did not see his combination of the views of earlier empiricists
and rationalists as an alternative to empiricism and rationalism as such
but, rather, as a higher form of rationalism.
One may question whether Kant was right in viewing his philosophy
in that way. Few scholars ever claimed that Kant was indeed a rational-
ist, with the notable exceptions of some of his first readers and Erich
Adickes.43 Most regarded Kant’s philosophy as a via media between
empiricism and rationalism that is neither empiricist nor rationalist.
Others, like Wayne Waxman, take Kant’s project to be steeped in Locke’s,
Berkeley’s, and Hume’s philosophical tradition.44
However things may be, whether Kant had the Kantian bias does
not depend on whether his philosophy actually is a form of rationalism,
empiricism, or neither. One has the Kantian bias if one holds that Kant’s
Critical philosophy is a superior alternative to empiricism and rational-
ism as such, regardless of whether one is correct in holding this. This
applies to Kant, too. The evidence assembled in this section establishes
that he did not take his own philosophy to be an alternative to empiri-
KANT ON EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM 67
Although Kant did not have the classificatory, Kantian, and epistemo-
logical biases that characterize the standard narrative of early modern
philosophy, he promoted a way of writing histories of philosophy from
which those biases would naturally flow. He did so by endorsing four
tenets.
(a) The history of philosophy is a philosophical discipline. Kant took
the section of the first Critique on the history of pure reason to
designate “a place that is left open in the system” of philosophy
(A852/B880). This provides “a secure touchstone for appraising
the philosophical content of old and new works in this specialty”
(B27). Historians should assess past philosophies from a Kantian
point of view.
(b) Historians of philosophy should reconstruct the “natural train
of thought through which philosophy had to progressively de-
velop from human reason” (Briefwechsel, 12:36). The “temporal
sequence” of dogmatism, skepticism, and Criticism “is founded
in the nature of man’s cognitive capacity” (Fort., 20:264). Given
the nature of human psychology, humans have an inclination to
embrace dogmatism, discover its flaws, move on to skepticism,
be dissatisfied by it, and keep searching until they reach the safe
haven of Criticism. Historians of philosophy should show how the
temporal sequence of specific systems exemplifies this natural
psychological development of the human mind.
(c) Given the nature of human psychology, it is unavoidable that
humans go through the three stages of dogmatism, skepticism,
and Criticism. Historians should make the unavoidability of this
process apparent. They should show how the “opinions which
have chanced to arise here and there” instantiate “what should
have happened,” how reason must necessarily develop “himself
from concepts” (Fort., 20:343).
(d) In line with his tendency to endorse intermediate views between
two extremes, as discussed above, Kant regards his Critical
philosophy as a middle way between the extremes of dogmatism
and skepticism. It combines the dogmatists’ claim that we can
know the external world with the skeptics’ claim that we can-
not know mind-independent objects. Historians of philosophy
should describe this historical movement from the two extremes
of dogmatism and skepticism to their higher synthesis in Kant’s
Critical philosophy.
70 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
7. Conclusion
In this paper, I have argued that Kant did not have the three biases,
although he indirectly contributed to the development of the standard
narrative. The first historians who developed accounts of early modern
philosophy that revolve around the RED and display the three biases
did this by employing Kantian notions and embracing Kantian views
on the historiography of philosophy.
According to the Kantian historian par excellence, Wilhelm Gottlieb
Tennemann, “[t]he Critical inquiries of the philosopher from Königsberg
had the most beneficial consequences not only for philosophy itself, but
also for the history of philosophy.”50 Nowadays, few would agree that the
consequences of Kant’s views on the historiography of philosophy were
the most beneficial. Nevertheless, Kant’s views had a remarkable influ-
ence on how many philosophers have understood their early modern
predecessors. It is important to recognize the extent to which their un-
derstanding was shaped by Kantian views on the nature of philosophical
historiography. This should alert us to the wide-ranging consequences
that historians’ assumptions on the nature and method of philosophical
historiography can have for the way they reconstruct their philosophical
past. To be aware of this is especially important now, when the limits of
the traditional historiography of early modern philosophy have become
apparent and many are looking for new, enhanced narratives.51
University of Warwick
KANT ON EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM 71
NOTES
Bracken, Berkeley (New York: St Martin’s Press, 1974), 15–17, 259 on Berkeley’s
rationalism.
12. See, e.g., R. A. Watson, “Shadow History in Philosophy,” Journal of
the History of Philosophy 31 (1993): 95–109, at 97; D. Garber, “Descartes and
Experiment in the Discourse and Essays,” in Essays on the Philosophy and Sci-
ence of René Descartes, ed. S. Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993),
288–310, at 306.
13. Loeb 1981, 13–14.
14. For example, Descartes’s influence on Locke (ibid., 36–62) and Leibniz’s
influence on Hume (Engfer 1996, 329–32).
15. See, e.g., H. Ishiguro, “Pre-established Harmony versus Constant
Conjunction: A Reconsideration of the Distinction between Rationalism and
Empiricism,” in Rationalism, Empiricism, and Idealism: British Academy
Lectures on the History of Philosophy, ed. A. Kenny (Oxford: Clarendon, 1996),
61–85.
16. R. Scruton, Modern Philosophy: An Introduction and Survey (London:
Sinclair-Stevenson, 1994), 30. See M. Gentile, Se e come è possibile la storia
della filosofia (Padua: Liviana, 1966), 60; Gaukroger 2010, 156.
17. Gentile 1966, 60. See R. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 148.
18. Haakonssen 2006, 18. See A. Waldow, “Empiricism and Its Roots in the
Ancient Medical Tradition,” in The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge:
Embodied Empiricism in Early Modern Science, ed. C. T. Wolfe and O. Gal
(Dordrecht: Springer, 2010), 287–308, at 307.
19. Scruton 1994, 30. See S. Schmauke, Wohlthätigste Verirrung: Kants
kosmologische Antinomien (Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2002), 106;
H. Holzhey and V. Mudroch, Historical Dictionary of Kant and Kantianism
(Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2005), 111–12.
20. Engfer 1996, 357, see 411; E. Papadimitriou, “Zu den philosophie
geschichtlichen Voraussetzungen der Kantischen Kritik der reinen Vernunft,” in
Akten des 4. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, ed. G. Funke (Berlin: de Gruyter,
1981), vol. I.1, 39–47, at 39, 41; I. Hunter, “The History of Philosophy and the
Persona of the Philosopher,” Modern Intellectual History 4 (2007): 572–600, at
592–94.
21. See Bxxxv.
22. I focus on only the first two antinomies for the sake of brevity.
23. Welches sind die wirklichen Fortschritte, die die Metaphysik seit Leibni-
zens und Wolf’s Zeiten in Deutschland gemacht hat? (henceforth Fort.), 20:275.
24. To reconstruct Kant’s views, we must rely to a significant extent on ma-
terials that Kant never intended to be published, especially manuscript notes
(Reflexionen) and lecture transcripts. These materials must be used with caution
(see E. Conrad, Kants Logikvorlesungen als neuer Schlüssel zur Architektonik
KANT ON EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM 73