Foley (1999) (1997) 150-166
Foley (1999) (1997) 150-166
Foley (1999) (1997) 150-166
Linguistics
An Introduction
William A. Foley
University of Sydney
CEtmollE INVESTIGACIONES
YESTUDIOS SUPE~IORES EN
ANTROPOLOG/A ¡OCW.
aIBL.HDTi¡CA
13 BLACI<WEU
Publishers
·n0670(ff'
7
Color
U ndoubtedly the most influential and possibly the most robust elaims of
uni versal innate constraints 00 the semantic strucrure of certain cognitive
dornaios have beeo marle in the area of color terminology, starting with the
landmark study of Berlin and Kay (1969) and extended with subsequent
work by them and associates (Berlin and Berlin 1975; Kay 1975; Kay,
Berlin, and Merrifield 1991; Kay and McDaniel 1978; MacLaury 1987,
1991, 1992). The erosslinguistie study of color terminologies has beeome
something of the paradigm case for demonstrating the effeets of universal
innate biological cons traints 00 human categorizations of th e world. Color
has long beco a favored semantic dornaio in which to investigare issues of
the relationship between language and thought (Brown and Lenneberg
1954; Lantz and Stefflre 1964; Lenneberg 1953; Lenneberg and Roberts
1956; Stefflre, Castillo Vales, and Morley 1966). This is a tradition that
Berlin and Kay (1969) build on, but erueially they are attempting to show
universal constraints in this dornaio, rather than relativistic effects linked to
language differenees, as is the aim of the earlier work. The whole thrust
of work in color terminologies stemming from Berlin and Kay (1969) is to
demonstrate thar universal design [eatures of the human visual perceptual
system strongly eonstrain the systems of color terminologies found in the
world's languages to a very small and largely predietable subset of the very
large set of theoretieally possible, but aetuall)' unattested, types:
basic color categorics can be derived directly from the ncural response pat-
terns that underlie the perception of color . (Kay and McDaniel 1978:130)
predicting the composite color categories ofthe \Vorld's languages from prop-
erties of color vis ion that are independent of culture and of langua ge, biolog-
¡cal properties which are in fact independent ol' human experience per se being
widespread in genera other than Horno. (Kay, Herhn, and Merrifield 1991:18)
Color \51
Color Categorization
underpinnings to all the colors subsumed by the eleven basic color teTms of
English can be modelled. Seeond, universal panerns of eolor-naming sys-
tems emerge across languages. No language, for example, has a word for
"grecn," unless it also has a word for "red." T he maximum number ofbasic
color terms seems fixed at around a dozen, but a language may have much
less. If so, a given color term will be a composite category, covering a range
of stirnulus colors, for example, the native Trobriand color terminology has
four terms (Senft 1987); one of these digadegila eovers the speetrum range
of yellow-green-blue, although its prototypieal foeus seems to be "yellow"
(Senft 1987:329). The patterns of sueh eomposite eategories seems largely,
but not eompletely, predictable on neurophysiologieal grounds.
the basic dimension of contras! for the t\Vo BUfara basic color rerms, gUl1galtja
and gUlIgulldja. Gll1lgaltja refers to light, bright colors, like white, pastels,
and red. Its focal prototype is reflective aluminum foil, certainly suggesting
high brightness as its basic feature. AU other colors are covered by gltllgttlldja.
The BUfara system, then , is a more transparent brightness-based two-term
system [han the mixed brightness-hue system of Dani. In fact, MacLaury
(1992) suggests two paraUel paths of development of basic color terms, one
based on hue and ane on brightness, with crossover relations between them.
Burara is probably the most likely example of a basic color system grounded
in brightness contrasts, Dani exemplifying the more common crossovcr
between the t\VD dimensions.
When a language has thrce basic color rerms, the warm colors red-
orange--yeUow split from LIGHT /W ARM to form the foUowing three-
way contrast: LIGHT, WARM, and DARK/COOL. A true hue contrast
now definitely emerges. The focal hue for LIGHT is white, and for WARM,
red but DARK/COOL continues to have variable foci in black, pure blue,
or pure grecn. Watam is a good example of this type of language, with
wawar LIGHT: white, greyish, 1Ilbllk1llbllk DARK/COOL: black, dark
brown, green, blue, andyallp WARM: red, orange, yeUow, red-brown . This
early emergence of RED fits weU with Sahlin's (1976) claim of its psycho-
¡agical salience and emotional attractiveness.
With four basic color rerms, the possibilities now become quite complex,
with no less than five-attested sysCems (Kay, Berlin, and Merrifield 1991).
The two most common of these were uncovered as early as Berlin and Kay
(1969). In one, the WARM category, previously covering from red through
yeUow, but focused on red, splits into two distinct terms: RED and YEL-
LOW. This system is found in traditional, pre-Spanish Bisayan of the
Philippines (Berlin and Kay 1969:68): mabosas LIGHT / WHITE, maitu1Il
DARK/ BLACK, mapllla RED, and madurag YELLOW. In such systems
orange is divided between RED and YELLOW.
The other commonly attested four-term system separates the cool colors,
grecn and blue, [rom the DARK/COOL category, resulting in DARK/
BLACK and GRUE, a composite category made up of green and blue. In
such systems the focal hue for GRUE is either blue or green or bifocal in
both) never turquoise) i.c. the secondary "mixed" hue composed of these
two primaries. T his again is said to vindicate Kay and McDaniel's (1978)
universal neurophysiological account for basic color terminologies. Ibibio of
Nigeria is one such four-term system: afíá DARK/BLACK ébúbít LIGHT /
WHITE, Mdíddt WARM, awawa GRUE/focus in green (Berlin and Kay
1969:64).
The other three systems are more problema tic. In one, GRUE separates
from DARK/COOL and RED emerges as a distinct category from W ARM,
but "yellow" rejoins the LIGHT category. A neurophysiological account
156 Universalism: Innate COl1straints on Mind
for this is no! apparent, nor is a diachronic mechanism which would yie1d
this four-term system from the previous three-term one ofDARK/COOL,
LIGHT, and WARM. Most problematic ofall are systems which have as a
basic color term a YELLOW /GREEN composite category, in which YEL-
LOW again splits from WARM, but this time merges with GRUE. How
can YELLOW be simultaneously LIGHT/WARM and DARK/COOU
Once previously thought to be rare, YELLOW /GREEN is now attested
on four continents: Asia (Hanunoo), Australia and Oceania (Gugu-Yalanji,
Trobriand), North America (Salish, Wakashan, Creek, Natchez, Karok),
and South America (Chacobo). There are two types of such systems. One
has a YELLOW- GRUE category and is exemplified by the traditional
Trobriand color terminology (Senft 1987): pupwakau LIGHT /WHITE,
bwabwau DARK/BLACK, bweyani RED, and digadegila YELLOW /GRUE.
Other languages with this system inc1ude Karok (Bright 1952) and Gugu-
Yalanji (Berlin and Kay 1969:70; Rivers 1901). This grouping of YEL-
LOW /GRUE poses formidable problems for Kay and McDaniel's grounding
of generalities of basic color terms in ¡nnate perceptual properties of rhe
human color vision system, specifically, the subsystems based on opposing
colors. Yellow and blue (member of the composite GRUE) are opposing
poles of the same subsystem and if these subsystems based on oppositions
are rhe universal grounding for human color categorizations, ir is .hard to see
how yellow and blue could be conflated in a single named category. This
serious problem is c1early seen by MacLaury (1992), who tries to solve it by
claiming this category is actually informed by a brightness dimension, flot
one of hue, these co10rs occupying a range of middle brightness. This is in
keeping with his postulation of the pivotal role of a brightness dimension in
the sequence of development of basic color terms, but it rather does con-
travene the strict Kay and McDaniel universalist interpretation in terms of
hue, and poses the question what favors the mediation of the brightness
dimension in addition to hue in certain color terminologies. Culture?
The other four-term system involving YELLOW /GREEN actually di-
vides GRUE into BLUE and GREEN, merging the former with BLACK
and the latter with YELLOW. Hanunoo of the Philippines (Conklin 1964)
is one such system: bi:ru DARK/BLACK/BLUE, lagtiq LIGHT /WHITE,
raraq RED, latuy YELLOW /GREEN. Other languages with this system
are Creek (Kay, Berlin and Merrifield 1991) and Shuswap (MacLaury 1987).
Given that these languages assign yellow and blue to different named cat-
egories, they do not pose the quite same problems for the universal neurophy-
siological basis of basic color terms in color oppositions like yellow-blue;
they do, however, pose problems of their own, such as how would they arise
from a previous three-term system ofDARK/COOL, LIGHT, and WARM?
Again the role of yellow is pivotal; it must migrate out of the WARM cat-
egory to join with the green focus of GRUE, a composite category already
Color 157
1
separate from DARK/COOL. Thus, the ancestor of four-term systems
with YELLOW /GREEN may be the common type with the four terms
LIGHT/WHITE, DARK/BLACK, WARM and GRUE, as in Ibibio.
MacLaury (1987) proposes something like this for the history of the color
terminology of Shuswap, a Salish language of Canada in which the WARM
term extended to the green focus of GRUE (due to an operative brightness
dimension?) and simultaneously retracted fram red. Blue rhen merges wit~
DARK/BLACK. Halkomelem, another Salish language (MacLaury and
Galloway 1988), shows the opposite trajectory: GRUE is extended to the
yellow focus of WAR¡v¡, isolating red and simultaneously retracting from
blue, which again merges with DARK/BLACK. While not ruled out on a
neurophysiological account of opposing color hues, yellow- blue and red-
grecn, such an account cerra¡nly provides no straightforward explanarian
of such migrations of yellow or green. MacLaury's (1992) theory of a co-
emergent brightness dimension, with YELLOW /GREEN a category of
medium brightness, seems ro offer the only avenue of explanarian here.
Languages with five basic color rerms exhibir fewer possibilities rhan
those with four, there being three-attested types. The most common arise
from rhe [\VD most \Videl)' attested four-rerm systems, eirher by splitting
WARM into RED and YELLOW or by dividing DARK/COOL into
DARK/BLACK and GRUE, again with variable focus of GRUE in either
blue or green, or bifocal in both. AIl such languages ha ve DARK/BLACK,
LIGHT /WHITE, RED, YELLOW, and GRUE and are illustrated by
Tzeltal, a Mayan language ofMexico (Berlin and Kay 1969:82); 7ink' DARK/
BLACK, salk LIGHT /WHITE, cah RED, k'an YELLOW, andyafGRUE.
Uncommon, but attested, systems inc\ude those in which only GREEN is
separated from DARK/COOL, leaving blue to remain in the latter along
with black: DARK/BLACK/BLUE, LIGHT /WHITE, RED, YELLOW,
and GREEN. Chinook Jargon, a pidgin previously spoken in the Pacific
north-west of the United States and Cana da, is an example of this five-term
system (Berlin and Kay 1969:75): 1/7et DARK/BLACK/BLUE, Ik 71lp
LIGHT /WHITE, p,1 RED, ptcJh GREEN, and kawakawak YELLOW
(with pale greens). And there is at least one reported language (Kay, Berlin,
and Merrifield 1991) in which green migrates from GRUE to merge with
yellow to form a YELLOW /GREEN composite category, isolating BLUE
as a new uniquely named color category: DARK/BLACK, LIGHT /
WHITE, RED, YELLOW/GREEN, and BLUE. Kwak'wala (Saunders
1992), a Wakashan language of Canada, may also illustrate this last sys-
temo zulla DARK/BLACK, lIlela LIGHT /WHITE, tlakwa RED, ¡henza
YELLOW /GREEN, and zasa BLUE. .
The possibilities for systems of basic color terms from the minimum of
t\VD members up to five can be secn in 7.1.
Beyond tive basic color terms, there appears to be far less arder. Berlin
158 Universalism: lnnale ConstrainlS on Mind
I 1-+ tcnns
DARK/ COOL: G, Hu , Bl DARK/ B1
R GRUE: G , Bu
y WAR.!\oI: R, y
L1GHT/ W LlGHT / W
1
DARK/ COOL: Bu, BI DARK/ BI DARK/ B!
R GRUE: G, Bu y IGRUE: G, Bu
Y/ G R R
UGHT/ W LlGI-IT/ W / Y L1GHT/ \V
I I
DARK/ BI
GRUE: G, Bu
R 5 tcrms
y
LlGHT/ W
and Kay (1969) in their early phase of the theory proposed the strong con-
straint that GRUE necessarily splits into GREEN and BLUE, followed by
the addition of BROWN, and then lhe emergence of PURPLE, GREY,
PINK and ORANGE in any order, but later research has shown this to be
false. Evidence above shows that GREEN and BLUE may already emerge as
distinct in a five-term system. It is also now weJl established that, contrary
to Berlin and Kay (1969), GREY, BROWN, and PURPLE appear as basic
color terros in no fixed order. Indeecl, GRUE may persist undissolved into
GREEN and BLUE well after GREY, BROWN, or PURPLE have been
labelled wilh their o\Vn basic color terms (Kay, Berlin, and Merrifield 1991).
It is important to note that MacLaury (199 1,1992) has found that prior
to their emergence as basic color terros both purple and brown show con-
flicting categorizations in different languages. Thus, in a typical five-term
system, purple may be assigned complete1y to the GRUE category or to the ~
boundary between GRUE and RED. Similarly, brown can be included in the
YELLOW or DARK/BLACK category. Variable categorizations like these
Color 159
may be the souree of the largely unpredietable panern for their emergenee
as basie color terms. PI K and ORANGE do generally appear to be dis-
tinetly late, though see Saunders (1992:151) for a claim that ORANGE is a
basic color term in Kwak'wala, otherwise a language with a five-tcrm sys-
tem, as mentioned aboye. Finally, sorne languages may have mOfe (han one
basic color rerm corresponding to a single ane in English: for example,
Russian has two basie color terms for BLUE, gO/IIboj for LIGHT -BLUE
(i.e. "sky-blue") and sinij for OARK-BLUE, and Hungarian has two words
for RED, piros LIGHT-RED and voros OARK-REO (Wierzbieka 1990).
Inserting a category of ye/low- green- blue ioro the sequence cas[s daubt upon
[he presumed conncerion betwcen panhuman visual physiology and the widely
observed regularities of color categorization; ir calls into question the vcry
notioo of color- category univcrsals.
Since the yellow-greell- bluc category represents the extreme, dropping it
into the universal sequence concedes the debate to the relativists .
So what is the relativist response to this imposing body of work and how
do they account for the universal constraints on basic color terminologies
already mentioned? It is perhaps best articulated in Sahlins (1976), but
see also Lucy (1996), Saunders (1992), and Tornay (1978). The basic point,
of course, is that cultural practices are a crucial mediating force in color
naming and the systems of basic color terms. They argue that culture must
be the crucial autonomous intermediary between any innate and hence
universal neurological perception of co lor stimuli and the cognitive under-
standing of these. This point is echoed linguistically by Wierzbicka (1990)
who notes that the meaning of a color term in a language cannot possibly be
a neural response to a color chip, but rather the cognitive understanding the
Native speaker of the language has of that term: "language reflects what
happens in the mind, not what happens in the brain" (Wierzbicka 1990: 163).
The basic thrust of the relativist critique of the Berlin and Kay (1969)
inspired tradition is to invert its determinism: "it is not, then, that color
terms have their meaning imposed by the constraints of human and physica1
natures; it is that they take on such constraints in so far as they are mean-
ingful" (Sahlins 1976:3), i.e. meaningful in a culrurally constructed sym-
bolic system; symbols for practical public action, as in Geertz (1973). Herein
lies the rub; Berlin and Kay (1969) and associates regard a particular color
as a label given in response to a controlled stimulus, a Munsell color chip,
an act of naming an objective sensible difference. The language of color,
thus, is reduced to a nomenclature of objective pure color referents in a
controlled sensible world . The basic color terms in a language are separated
Color 161
First, there is the opposition between light and dark, obvious in the con-
trasted ranges of meaning of lagtiq and b'::ru. Second (here is an opposition
between dryness or desiccation and wetness or freshness (succulence) in visible
components of the natural environment which are reflected in the terms raraq
and latuy respectively. This distinction is of particular significance in terms
162 Ul1iversalism: hmate C01lStraints 011 Mind
of plant life. Almost al! living plant types possess sorne fresh , succulent, and
ofren " grecnish" parts. Tu cat any kind of raw, uncooked [Dod, particularly
fresh fruits Of vegetables, is known as pag-laty-ulI «latuy). A shiny, \Ver,
brown-colored section of newly-cur bamboo is maiatuy (llot mararaq). Dried-
out 0 1' matured plant material such as certain kinds of ycllo\Vcd bamboo or
hardened kernels of marure Of parched com are mararaq. Tu hecome desic-
cated, ro lose a1l moisrure, is koown as mamoraq «paraq " desiccation" ... )
... A rhird opposition, dividing (he [\VD already suggested , is rhar of deep,
unfading, indelible, and hence ofrcn more desired material as against pale,
weak, faded, bleached or "colorless" substance, a distinction contrasting mabi:m
and mararaq with malagtiq and malatuy. This opposition holds for manufac-
tured items and trade goods as well as for sorne natural products (e.g. red and
white trade beads, red being more valuable by Hanunóo standards; indig(}-
d yed corton sarongs, the most prized being those d yed most oftcn and hence
of the deepest indigo color - som etimes obscuring completely the designs
fonned originally by white warp yarns; etc.).
ReJativists like Luey (1996) and Saundcrs (1992) eharge that Berlin and
Kay, and subsequent workers, only get the results they do by bracketing out
such rich cultural information about the mcanings of the basic color terms
and by foeusing solely on the ehromatie information they denote. Luey notes
that adcquate Native knowledge (the goal of any truly cognitive anthropo-
logy) of ¡he Hanunoo system eould never be aehieved by eodifying labelling
responses in the Hanunoo language to color stímuli provided by Munsell
chips. The thrust of the relativist critique ís to daim that basie color terms
stand in meaningful relationships to each other not only according to chro-
matic contrasts, but many other culturally defined dimensions, and, further,
they individually and as a group may enter into relations with many olher
tenns and semantic domains, as part and parcd of the wider meaningful
practices which make up the culture. Colors as perceptual structures are
merely raw materials of cultural production, the handmaiden of meaningful
practices: virginal white versus promiscuous red. Colors, too, are good to
think with. Saunders (1992:219) summarizes lhis view nieely:
[ha! which most fuIly characterises rhe mental (or psychological). Instead
of cvolutionarily ernerging neuro-based epistemological primitives (funda-
mental ncural responses / basic color rerms) 1 propose to Jocate a quality like
Kwak'wala Ihmxa [YELLOW /GREEN] ... in "intenrional spacc" and char-
actcrise it in terros wcdded to ao intentional view of [he wodd, ¡.c. in purposivc,
indexical, and interactional rerms. Then lIun.m ... have rneaning only in [he
normativc setting of [he customs, regular beliefs and desires, and appropriate
behaviour of a Kwakiutl ... community [i.c. embodied practices], as COffi-
ponents of vistas on ly discernible from thcir intenrional points of vicw. Cat-
cgorisation in terms of"colour" or whatevcr, would then be inextricably bound
up wÍth having states of rnind which cannot be understood exccpt by those
who enjoy the appropriate kind of intentional liaison with the world [i.e.
structural coupling), that ¡s, by people who have the skills to use terrns like
Ihenxa . .. mauve, or Pmssian h/ue in the appropriate contcxts - an intentional
liaison only secured when one is part of(or becornes part of) a cornrnunity for
which il is utterly natura.! to idcntify fcatures of the world with these notions.
No less than any other code, a system of color meanings must be grounded
in a corresponding set of distinctive perccptual properties. Hence, the natural
corTeJa tes of color words: they comprise the rninimal distinctions on the
ohjcct plane ~ of lightness/darkness, hue/ neutrality, uniqueness/admixture,
and the like - by which differences in meaning are signalled.
Sununary
The systems of color terminologies among the languages of the world present
a promising case for the establishment of universals in human categoriza-
tion, due to the pan human neurophysiology of human visiono The thrust
of work in the tradition stemming from Berlin and Kay (1969) has becn to
prove exactly this claim, locating established universals in the systems of
basic color terminologies in the mechanisms of human color vision and
arguing further that cultural interests and practices play no role. They have
determined a typology of basic color terminologies varying from a min-
¡mum of two terms up to a maximum of eleven, with the actually attested
systems restricted to a very smaU and mainly predictable subset of the very
large set of theoreticaUy possible, but actuaUy unattested, types, a finding
strongly in support of universal constraints in this dornain. Further, the
focal hue of a basic color term like "red," for instance, remains the sarne
across languages, regardless of whether it comes from a three-term system,
where the term covers the range from red through yellow, or an eleven-
term one, more evidence that universal perceptual biologically based con-
straints are operative. Relativists respond by claiming that this research
tradition gets the results it does almost by definition, by bracketing out a1l
Color 165
the cultural information in the meaning of color terms, so that only the non-
cultural perceptual components can reveal themselves. They argue that Ihe
meaning of a color term is not a labelling response 10 a color stimulus, but
the full culturally defined relations it engagcs in and activates, its role in the
ongoing social coupling of a people.
Further Readillg
Color has also been much wrinen about. Davidoff (1991), Hardin (1988), Lamb and
Bourriau (1995), and Ottoson and Zeki (1985) are good introductions to the field,
but see Thompson (1995) and Thompson, Palacios, and Varela (1992) for an altern-
arive. There is a large amount of literature in the Berlín and Kay tradition, bu! the
basic saurces are Berlín and Kay (1969), Kay and McDaniel (1978), Kay, Berlin and
Merrificld (1991), and MacLaury (1992). Important relativist responses are Lucy
(1996) and Sahlins (1976).