Soeteman Legal Logic or Can We Do Without PDF
Soeteman Legal Logic or Can We Do Without PDF
Soeteman Legal Logic or Can We Do Without PDF
197
2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
AREND SOETEMAN
Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam, The Netherlands
E-mail: [email protected]
Abstract. In this paper the thesis is argued that there is no need for a special legal logic to deal with
the defeasibility of legal arguments. An important argument for this thesis is that legal judgements
ask for a complete justification and that such a complete justification requires a deductively valid
argument.
1. Introduction
Df: 1 Pp ¼ O p;
Df: 2 Fp ¼ O p:
Standard axioms are:
Ax: 1 O(p & q) Op & Oq;
Ax: 2 (Op & O p),
Ax: 3 O(p v p).2
As a formal system, however, this deontic system is only a game of symbols.
As long as we are within the formal system, the reference to the deontic
operators may be put between parentheses. We do not need to know that O
refers to obligation for the deduction of O(pvq) from Op.
198 AREND SOETEMAN
3. Non-formal logic
audience, including me, should accept the conclusion, given the arguments
presented.
Jaap Hage recently has formulated my argument against a merely
informal analysis of legal argument as follows: ‘‘Either such an argument
can be made formally valid by adding an acceptable premise to it, or it
cannot. If it can be made valid, the best thing to do is to add this acceptable
premise and remain satisfied with the resulting validity according to formal
logic. If the argument cannot be made formally valid by adding an
acceptable premise, it should be discarded as an invalid argument’’ (Hage
2001). I would never say that one (who?) should add an acceptable premise,
but only that it should be taken into consideration if one wants to study the
logical validity of the argument. But apart from this minor point Hage’s
summary is correct.
Hage is kind enough to qualify my argument as powerful. But he goes on
to say that my argument presupposes a distinction between form and
content, which with respect to arguments in ordinary language is much less
clear than is suggested (Hage 2001, p. 355). ‘‘Logical form is not something
that is given with an argument … On beforehand there is no objection against
taking elements from the legal domain and incorporating them in a special
legal logic, which recognises more logical form than, for instance, predicate
logic’’ (Hage 2001, p. 356).
I completely agree with Hage’s remarks on form and content. There is no
sharp and given distinction. Content can be formalised whenever we want to
do so. But I fail to see why this possibility of formal analysis would be an
argument against my objections to a merely informal analysis.
As far as Hage wants to say that formal logical systems can be developed
which have as their intended field of application legal arguments, he also is
right. It could be possible, e.g., to develop some formal characteristics of legal
concepts, as tort or property or agreement and to construct formal systems
elaborating these concepts. Whether one wants to name such a system a legal
logic is a matter of terminology. As one can never exclude the possibility that
the system, as a formal system, can appear to have other applications then the
intended one, this terminology could give a wrong suggestion. But I have to
admit that comparable considerations do not prevent us from calling the logic
which analyses deontic operators a deontic logic.
Hage also objects that my argument against informal logic can be adduced
against predicate logic as well. Take the example (from Hage):
(1) All thieves are punishable,
John is a thief,
Therefore: John is punishable.
This is not a valid argument according to propositional logic: P, Q, therefore
R is not a valid scheme. It is, however, valid according to predicate logic:
202 AREND SOETEMAN
In almost every introduction to logic one can read that logic is about the
study of valid argument. The traditional logical interpretation of validity is as
follows. An argument is valid if and only if the conclusion necessarily follows
from its premises, i.e., if and only if a world where the premises are true and
the conclusion is false is not possible. From ‘all human beings are mortal’ it
follows that ‘the human being Socrates is mortal’ if it is not possible that in
some world as a matter of fact all human beings are mortal, but not the
human being Socrates.
This logical validity is monotonic: if we add new premises to a valid
argument, the argument remains valid. This is necessarily the case. The class
of all worlds in which all the original premises and the added premises are
true is a subclass of (or equal to) the class of all worlds in which all the
original premises are true. If the conclusion is true in all the worlds of the
bigger class, it is also true in all worlds of its subclass.
204 AREND SOETEMAN
6. Defeasible beliefs
It is clear that all our knowledge, including knowledge about positive law and
about facts which are relevant for law application, is defeasible. Beliefs may
be justified, but nevertheless turn out to be wrong. Let us take the example of
my plane from London to Amsterdam. When my wife first thought that I
could be home about 10 p.m. she was wrong. Added information about the
diversion of my plane to Brussels exposed the mistake. The argument was:
Many rules are open to exceptions. There are general exceptions like force
majeure and self-defence. And there may be special exceptions to special
rules. It is also usual that in positive law many exceptions are not formulated
in the rules themselves (as part of ‘p’ in (4)), but in some other statute or in
another provision of the same statute. The condition of normality implies
206 AREND SOETEMAN
(6) If the marriage ends then both partners (or their heirs) should have
half of the matrimonial property.
This marriage between me and my wife Juliet has ended (by my
killing of Juliet).
Therefore: I, Romeo, should have half of the matrimonial property.
There are a number of reasons to interpret the legal rule involved rather
strict: the prevention of endless fights about the settlement of the joint
property, legal certainty (also for other parties who may be involved), and so
on. As far as I know there was no exception to the rule before this case arose.
But there are also reasons to make an exception in this particular case. The
most important reason might be that the judge should not cooperate in the
murderer carrying off his prize.
We can interpret the rule in two different ways. First, we can interpret it in
a prima facie way, meaning that until we find in some case compelling
reasons to the contrary, the property should be divided by half. In this
interpretation (6) is only a valid argument if we add the logical minimum,
which means if we add the normality thesis.
Second, we can interpret the rule in an all-things-considered way, meaning
that in all situations which should be subsumed under its antecedent the
consequent gives the valid legal consequence and that (6) is a valid argument.
Now, suppose we agree with the Dutch courts that an exception should be
made in this case. In the first interpretation we can only make this exception
by challenging the normality thesis, which was one of the premises. In the
second interpretation, we challenge the legal rule in the first premise: we
change it into a rule with an exception.
The story about non-monotonic logic is the same as with defeasible
beliefs. If we interpret the rule in (6) in the all-things-considered way we do
not need any non-monotonic logic. We argue monotonically, which does
not imply that our conclusions are undefeasible, but only that the
conclusions can only be defeated if one of the premises is defeated. A
proponent of non-monotonic logic might argue, however, that, as legal
systems are open, it is very implausible to give any legal rule a monotonic,
all-things-considered interpretation. If we agree with this argument,13 we
208 AREND SOETEMAN
should interpret the rule in (6) in a prima facie way. It is clear that, given
this interpretation of the rule, (6) is not deductively valid. At most we can
say that the conclusion is made plausible. But how do we know that the
conclusion is plausible? The answer is: because the conclusion follows in
normal circumstances and we have no reason to suppose that in the case at
hand the circumstances are not normal. Again: addition of the normality
hypothesis to (6) makes it a valid deductive argument. Even if we add the
normality hypothesis by default.
We can say (as I suggested Hage did), that plausibility is all we have in
law. Legal argument is as a matter of fact defeasible. Let me accept this
observation, at least for the sake of argument. The practice of legal argument
is a practice where limited knowledge results in plausible, but defeasible
conclusions. Then we have reason to try to develop formal schemes of
argument, reconstructing this legal reasoning. If we want to instruct
computers, e.g., we need such formal schemes.
However, these non-monotonic schemes are no alternative for monotonic,
deductive schemes. Just as Perelman’s and Toulmin’s informal analysis of
(legal) argument could not replace formal analysis, so non-monotonic analysis
cannot replace monotonic analysis. One way to express this fact is to say that
non-monotonic logic is about the context of discovery, monotonic logic about
the context of justification. However, adherents of non-monotonic logic
usually don’t agree with this characterisation. They claim that non-monotonic
logic also is about justification: not about deductive but about defeasible
justification. Non-monotonic logic justifies that a conclusion is plausible. But
as far as this claim is true, the plausibility-claim presupposes a normality
hypothesis. If (as is common) this normality hypothesis remains implicit, it is
still there, nevertheless. Without it, the argument is completely unconvinc-
ing.14 From the point of view of deductive, monotonic analysis, defeasibility of
conclusions always means that premises are defeasible. Such a monotonic
analysis remains very useful, for complete justification, without hindering the
relevancy of non-monotonic analysis.
As a conclusion, I suggest that my ‘powerful argument’ also stands in
relation to non-monotonic logic. We might use non-monotonic logic, which
could be constructed especially for legal reasoning. But in the end, the study
of the justification of a conclusion requires traditional, monotonic formal
logic, which is not specifically legal.
Notes
*
This paper is based on Soeteman (2003) a paper which I wrote to honour Ake Frändberg.
1
In 1951 Von Wright’s Deontic Logic was published. This paper is generally recognized as the
beginning of modern deontic logic. But the study of logical relations between normative concepts is
older. For a short historical overview, see Kalinowski (1972, pp. 31–78).
LEGAL LOGIC? OR CAN WE DO WITHOUT? 209
2
These definitions use the standard connectives of propositional logic: is the negation (not), &
is the conjunction (and), v is the disjunction (or), is the equivalance(if and only if). Another
standard connective is for the implication (if… then).
3
In propositional logic the connectives (see footnote 2), in predicate logic ‘all’ and ‘some’, in
deontic logic the deontic operators.
4
Sometimes legal interpretation or judicial decision making are called legal logic. I have, of
course, no objections against the study of these topics.
5
A. Soeteman, Logic in Law, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1989 (revised English
edition).
6
The capitals here are propositional constants, they do not represent arbitrary propositions, but
just and only the propositions which are expressed in (1).
7
In his paper Law and Defeasibility, published in this issue, Hage argues from the supposition
that my ‘complete justification’ of a conclusion means that the conclusion is beyond any doubt. But
that is a misunderstanding, possibly caused by my incomplete formulations. Complete justification
refers to a relation between premises of an argument and the conclusion: it is the relation which
exists if, whenever the premises are accepted (as true or as legally valid), the conclusion has to be
accepted. Thus I am not striving for ‘impeccable legal conclusions’ which are ‘absolutely justified’.
I am striving for conclusions which are completely, that is deductively, justified by the premises of
the argument. The point of this is not to make conclusions more certain or stronger, the point is to
locate possible reasons for uncertainty in the premises of the argument. If someone challengs the
conclusion then, in my model, he has not to challenge some rather unspecified relation between
premises but, as is argued in this paper, he has to challenge at least one specific premise. My point
is not ontological, it is argumentational, or pragmatic.
8
For more details, see Soeteman (1995).
9
The Dutch High Court had to decide this case in December 1990: HR 7-12-1990, NJ 1991, 593.
The court judged that the husband’s demands conflicted with the requirements of reasonability and
equity to such a degree, not to say that they were shocking to the sense of justice, that compliance
of these demands should be completely denied to him. I analysed the case in Soeteman (1995).
10
Cf. Prakken (1997, p. 256), who argues that his system formalises Toulmin’s ideas on the
structure of argument.
11
Cf. Prakken (1997, p. 34 and 35).
12
See Prakken (1997), who also gives some examples.
13
Legal positivists are inclined to deny that legal rules are defeasible in such a degree as proponents
of non-monotonic logic believe. See, for instance, Bay on (2001), who argues that the consequence of
the view that all legal rules are defeasible is that the law is pervasively indeterminate.
14
It is indifferent for my analysis whether the often implicit defeasibility of a conclusion is made
explicit in one of the premises (e.g., in a normality hypothesis which is accepted by default, as long as
we have no reason not to accept it) or in the conclusion, which can be reconstructed as: it is plausible
that Oq. In the last case the normality hypothesis is part of the prima facie meaning of ‘if p then Oq’.
References
Bayón, J. C. (2001). Why is Legal Reasoning Defeasible? In Soeteman, A. (ed.), Pluralism in Law,
327–346. Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht.
Hage, J. C. (2001). Legal Logic, Its Existence, Nature and Use. In Soeteman, A. (ed.), Pluralism in
Law, 347–374. Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht.
Hofstadter, D. R. (1980). G€ odel, Escher, Bach, an Eternal Golden Braid. Vintage Books: New
York.
Kalinowski, G. (1972). La Logique des Normes. Presse Universitaire de France : Paris.
210 AREND SOETEMAN