Islamic Law and Legal Positivism
Islamic Law and Legal Positivism
Islamic Law and Legal Positivism
Islamic Law
Raja Bahlul
Doha Institute for Graduate Studies
Doha, Qatar
[email protected]
[email protected]
2
Islamic Law
1. Introduction
By its own lights, Islamic law is of divine origin. Owing to its divinity, it may be
rules, conventions, and norms, ‘posited’ and enforced by human beings, with no
Yet it is our intention in this paper to look at Islamic law in terms of Legal
Positivism. This does not mean that the present study is based on contesting, or
denying the claim of Islamic law to being divine. A theological stand of this kind
would be out of place here, for our goal is purely analytical and descriptive. There is
needs to be said that Islamic law has been studied by historians and legal scholars
was applied for a time (however long or short) and to some extent (however wide or
narrow); and it was elaborated (and developed) by jurisprudents who came to belong
No system of law is independent of what the people who apply it, interpret it, and
theorize about it in the context of a legal tradition take themselves to be doing. Hence
3
in our examination we shall not only be concerned with the content and form of
Islamic law, but also with what Muslim theorists had to say about it. Thus we have a
two-fold thesis to explain and defend. (1) Islamic law can be comprehended by
Among competing views of Muslim theorists, the one that was destined to
In section 2, we firstly explain what we take Legal Positivism to stand for -- its
main tenets, and some of its important concepts. Then we proceed to employ these to
look at Islamic law -- its origins, some of its structural features, and statements of
theorists who discussed and debated about obligation and proscription in the context
of divine law.
Legal Positivism has been subjected to in modern times. Secondly, we discuss the
debate that took place between Ash‘arism and Mu‘tazilism about morality and
obligation in relation to divine commands. A comparison between the ideas and lines
of thought followed by the Mu‘tazilites and critics of Legal Positivism shows that the
the disagreement between legal positivists and their critics (both Islamic and modern)
Speaking of the notions of ‘legal right’ and ‘legal obligation’ Dworkin says that our
understanding of these notions is “remarkably fragile”. The same could be said of the
notion of “law” itself, for, as Dworkin goes on to say, “We are used to summing up
our troubles in the classic question of jurisprudence: What is 'the law'?” (Dworkin
1978, 14) In answer to this question Legal Positivism (henceforth ‘LP’) provides a
general theory of what the law is -- “general in the sense that it is not tied to any
particular legal system or legal culture, but seeks to give an explanatory and clarifying
What does Legal Positivism have to say about the law, then? To go by the
characterization given by Dworkin, LP asserts, firstly, that laws are rules, backed by
the use of public force, that are used by a community of people, to regulate their
affairs in the various areas of social life. But more interestingly, “These … rules can
be identified and distinguished by specific criteria, by tests having to do not with their
content but with their pedigree or the manner in which they were adopted or
developed.” (Dworkin 1978, 17) “[E]very legal system has a fundamental test for law
Secondly, “[t]he set of these valid legal rules is exhaustive of ‘the law’, so that if
someone's case is not clearly covered by such a rule … then that case cannot be
decided by ‘applying the law’. It must be decided by some official, like a judge,
exercising his discretion, which means “reaching beyond the law for some other
Thirdly, “[t]o say that someone has a ‘legal obligation’ is to say that his case falls
under a valid legal rule that requires him to do or to forbear from doing something.
5
…In the absence of such a valid legal rule there is no legal obligation;…” (Dworkin
1978, 17)
With this brief explanation of what Legal Positivism has to say about the law, we
can proceed to look at Islamic law and legal tradition. It is commonly known that
Islamic jurisprudence recognizes four “sources of law”: the Qur’an (which is literally
the very words of the Divine Legislator), the recorded sayings and practices of the
Prophet Muhammad (the Sunna), consensus of the Muslim community (or at least that
of its jurisprudents), and, finally, the use of Analogy, a reasoning method employed to
extend legislation to cases not covered by laws derived from the first three sources.
Laws which are explicitly and directly based on the Qur’an and the Sayings of
the Prophet were from the start recognized as having greater authority than the third
and fourth sources. For consensus proved to be a debatable concept, whose practicality was
challenged by Averroes (1198), himself a jurist of great repute. (Gracia 1996, 243-50). As to
the method of Analogy, it was denied the status of being a source of law by the Zahirite jurist,
Ibn Hazm. (Hourani 1985, 186). For these reasons it may be appropriate for us to focus
initially on the Qur’an itself (and the Sunna) for purposes of examining the character
of Islamic law.
In the Qur’an we finds a sizable number of verses that formulate rules (the so-
called ‘Ayat al-Ahkam’) that are designed to govern the life of the Muslim community
under the leadership of the Prophet. These verses, which have been variously
estimated to number between 500 and 1000 (Anzi 2004, 8-9), were divided according
to subject matter by early jurists. There are as many as 30 different subject matters on
some counts. The subjects are not neatly separated from each other1, but putting aside
1
On the matter of distinction between subject matters, Joseph Schacht had this to say: “One important
criterion of the sociology of law is the degree to which the legal subject-matters are distinguished and
differentiated from one another. There is no such distinction in Islamic law”. (Schacht 1964, 206).
6
rules of ritual and worship, one finds that areas subject to divine legislation include:
alms-tax, war, sale (and interest), contract, testimony, (manumission of) slaves, spoils
marriage and personal status, inheritance, safe conduct, and administrative regulation
among others.2
Whatever booty you take, the fifth of it is God's, and the Messenger's, and the
near kinsman's, and the orphans', and for the needy, and the traveler. (8:40) 3
And the thief, male and female: cut off the hands of both, as a recompense for
what they have earned, and a punishment exemplary from God. (5:40)
[When contracting a debt:] And call in to witness two witnesses, men; or if the
two be not men, then one man and two women, such witnesses as you approve
of. (2:80)
These verses and others like them are not examples of familiar kinds of laws
which legal theory commonly deals with, namely, natural law, customary law,
statutory law, common law, or plain man-made positive law. Viewing such verses by
their own lights, there is nothing for us to call them but “divine laws”. But this may
not the most accurate description that we can offer. For there are uses of ‘divine law’
where it is said that rational human knowledge of the dictates of morality and natural
Geach,
2
A more thorough enumeration of subjects of legislation can be found in Nicolas Starkovsky (2004,
381-459).
3
All translations are from Arthur J. Arberry, The Koran Interpreted (Arberry 1964).
7
Yet “laws” such as “All human beings are equal”, or “All humans have a right to
live in peace and freedom”, which we can (let us assume) know by Reason, are not of
the type which our examples are meant to illustrate. A more accurate description of
the divine laws we have mentioned would be to call them “divine positive laws”, for
they bear many of the marks that are commonly taken to characterize positive law, as
normally understood. These marks include deliberate enactment (being “laid down”,
positive law and what we may now call ‘human positive law’ from both customary
law and natural law (Murphy 2005, 3; 18). Furthermore, divine positive law
resembles human positive law in terms of specificity to legal systems. For each
human legal system may be said to have its specific laws, while (we suppose) all such
systems may share the same natural law precepts. In a similar fashion, Islamic law
To every one of you We have appointed a right way (shir‘a) and an open road.
If God had willed, He would have made you one nation; but that He may try
you in what has come to you. (5:48).
Finally, divine positive law, like the legal rules of human positive law, but unlike
natural and/or moral law, is able to “provide more specific guidance to human conduct
than do moral precepts”. This is important, and also relevant to our being able to call
In choosing to think about Islamic law in terms of divine positive law, we follow
the practice of St. Thomas Aquinas who distinguished, within Mosaic Law, between
Christians and others) and ritual, or ceremonial commands which he called “positive
8
law” (Murphy 2005, 20). But we do not assimilate the positivity of Islamic law its
ceremonial or ritualistic features, for Islamic laws of ritual constitute only a small part
With these considerations in mind, let us proceed to discuss how Islamic law can
be comprehended in legal positivist terms. The first tenet of LP which says that
“[E]very legal system has a fundamental test for law in the form of a rule of
the rule of recognition is simply inclusion in the Book of God, or counting among the
canonical sayings of the Prophet. We can, following the terminology of The Concept
of Law, refer to the legal rules based on the Qur’an, (such as “Contracts must be
witnessed by two men, or one man and two women”) as primary rules. But the rule
(or rules) which “validate” such primary rules (allow them to be considered part of
Let us now see how Islamic law stands with regard to the second tenet of LP,
which requires that the cases where the law is not clearly applicable must be decided
by a judge, using discretion, and “reaching beyond the law for some other sort of
to be encountered in legal practice sooner or later. In the case of Islamic law the
possibility arose during the life-time of the Prophet, and afterwards, as Muslim armies
brought more and more peoples and territories under Islamic rule (and law). A well
known tradition relates the story of a conversation which took place between the
Prophet and the Companion Mu‘ath ibn Jabal, who was to be sent to Yemen. The
Prophet asks Mu‘ath about the method he intends to follow in judging between
9
disputants. Mu‘ath answers by saying that he would judge by what is in the Book of
God, the Qur’an. “What if the Qur’an does not give an answer?” the Prophet asks.
Mu‘ath would then have recourse to the Sayings of the Prophet. But what if the
Sayings of the Prophet do not provide an answer either? “I will exercise my judgment
without fail,” says the Companion. Upon hearing this, the tradition relates, the
Prophet thanked God and expressed pleasure at the Companion’s plan. (Abu Dawud
1997, #3592).
After the death of the Prophet, one of earliest school of jurisprudence to arise was
that of Hanafism, whose eponym, Abu Hanifah (767), was famous for his advocacy of
the ra’y, or exercise of personal judgment. (Arrabi 1999, 58-62) But the many
differences of opinions and disagreements between jurists, amid concerns about the
method for deriving “new” legal rules. This method, which came to be known as “the
use of Analogy” was added to the sources of Islamic law by Imam al-Shafi‘i (820),
and became accepted afterwards by other schools. This method depends on finding
relevant similarities between a novel situation requiring a legal decision, and the
drink (never mentioned in the Qur’an, of course) on the basis of the prohibition of one
To all intents and purposes, the role Analogy is not very dissimilar to the role of
‘discretion’ in the second tenet of LP. For Analogy functioned as a kind of “controlled
discretion”, on account of its being a limited way of using one’s reason within the
bounds of existing rules. The question of how analogy is to be used raised (and
To complete this account of how Islamic law can be understood within the
conceptual framework provided by LP, we turn now to third tenet, according to which
rules, in whose absence no claim of obligation can be made. (Dworkin 1978, 17)
In some ways the treatment of the concept of the obligatory, the forbidden,
proscribed, and other concepts that lie between these, is the most definitive mark
which suggests that Islamic legal philosophy may be viewed as a kind of legal
The central feature that makes Islamic religious law what it is, that guarantees
its unity in all its diversity, is the assessing of all human acts and relationships,
including those which we call legal, from the point of view of the concepts
obligatory/ recommended/ indifferent/ reprehensible/ forbidden. (Schacht
1964, 200)
function, because a legal system by its nature aspires to be encompassing and unified.
What is remarkable is the range of notions that were brought to bear on the semantics
If we are to go by what Kevin Reinhart says, it seems that as early as the late first
century of Islam, reflective Muslims were asking questions about the status of actions
which people engaged in before the advent of Revelation, that is, before God revealed
His judgment (hukm). Were actions such as lying, thanking a benefactor, killing,
According to Reinhart “We see this question as inchoate before the development of
11
the science of principles of jurisprudence (usul al-fiqh) in its classic form.” (Reinhart
1995, 14). Those who followed the “Permitted” position said that “in the absence of
revelational knowledge to the contrary, useful acts are permitted.” (Reinhart 2005, 38)
Those who followed the Proscribed position said they were forbidden. There were
also those who chose to say that “No Assessment” was possible .
implies that the assignment of value is a function of revelation itself. This is not the
God”. But it certainly paves the way for this claim, for what changes with the advent
say that useful acts are permitted in the absence of revelation implies that unaided
human reason is able to pass value judgments on actions with regard to their
“permissibility” of lack thereof. And while this does not imply that obligation is to
During the formative period of Islamic jurisprudence there was much intellectual
fluidity and diversity in the positions of the different schools. The “Permitted”
position had many adherents among Shafi‘ites, even the Hanbalites, not to mention
the Mu‘tazilites (who seem to have had some “Proscribers” of their own). But
gradually, as orthodoxy began to set in, the Shafi‘ites and Hanbalites and others chose
(Reinhart 2005, 2006). In this way, jurisprudence settled for itself the question of what
role, if any, reason could play in the assignment of value to action. It could be at best
12
subsidiary, the major role being reserved for canonical texts of the Qur’an and
But it remained for al-Ash‘ari (935) and his spiritual heirs to formulate and
implicit in the “No Assessment” position. In essence, the Ash‘arite idea was that God,
who rules over the universe, is King and Owner of everything. He lays down rules for
what to do and what not to do. These laws define what is obligatory and what is
forbidden. This can be best illustrated by reference to the writings of Juwaini (1085),
because his explanation of the notion of obligation is clear and to the point. According
to him:
which one is not allowed to transgress. This is what Juwaini’s teacher Al-Ash‘ari
law is found in the idea that there are no obligations which God has to fulfill.
God is not subject to obligation…. We ask one who disagrees with us, what
does it mean for there to be obligation on God to do something? If you mean a
command is directed at God, this is impossible. For He is the Commander, and
there is no commander above Him. If you mean that He obliged to do on
account of wanting avoiding harm, then this, too, is impossible. Finally, if you
mean that an action is made obligatory on account of its inherent goodness,
and the evil of its omission, then this is false too, because good and evil are
not intrinsic qualities. (Juwaini 1950, 272)
In defining obligation and other moral notions in these terms, it seems that al
Ash‘ari and his heirs, who came to stand for Muslim orthodoxy, do no more than
draw the logical conclusions implicit in the ideas of the previous generations of
From all of this it is possible to conclude that the type of legal philosophy which
al-Ash‘ari and his heirs subscribed to was a kind of legal positivism, an Islamic Legal
Positivism, if you will. For al-Ash‘ari’s explanation of the notion of the obligatory is
not at all different from that of LP, as we have just explained. And, of course, he
cannot pose any objection to the idea that legality, or the validity of rules is
recognized by reference to the accepted authority of the Qur’an and the Sayings of the
Prophet. As for the tenet of discretion, he could not have denied this, having accepted
a role for consensus and the use of Analogy in his philosophy of law.
The aim of the preceding section was to justify the twin claims that (1) Islamic Law
can be comprehended in terms of LP, and (2) Islamic legal philosophy, as theorized by
14
Neither LP, nor the Islamic version of it, has been without its critics. It will be argued
in the present section that similar lines of criticism can, and have been, be pursued in
these two areas. This stands to provide additional support for the idea that this way of
Dworkin begins his criticism by reflection on the “hard cases” of the law, that is,
cases which may appear to fall under the jurisdiction of a clear legal rule, but which
are “hard” in that lawyers, judges, and even ordinary people, may judge that the rule
should not be applied. Under regular circumstances, a son who is named in his
father’s will has a right to inherit in accordance with the will. But what is the law to
say in “the hard case” where the son kills his further in order to hasten the prospect of
inheriting? When we argue about such cases, says Dworkin, we find ourselves
appealing to principles, policies and standards that are not legal rules in any ordinary
sense of the term (Dworkin 1978, 23). In the present example we may invoke a
maxim such as “No one shall be permitted to profit by his own fraud, or to take
advantage of his own wrong, or to found any claim upon his own iniquity, or to
acquire property by his own crime.” (23) This maxim is not similar to a law which
defines and prescribes a punishment for exceeding a precisely defined speed limit.
Positivism were to include them in the law, then the rule of recognition tenet goes by
the board, for there is no rule of recognition that can be associated with these non-
15
rules. At the same time we cannot say that judges have unlimited discretion to apply
these principle or not. For we are inclined to take such principles as binding, in the
sense that a judge who fails to apply them is thought of as failing in his duty. Thus the
Tenet 3 does not fair any better. For if there are principles that are not the same as
the regular “primary” rules of the legal system, and if they may be viewed as
reference to falling under the purview of legal rules. According to this line of thought,
the murderer does not have a right to inherit by his father’s will. Had the possession
of such a right depended on merely falling within the purview of the legal rule, an
obligation would have existed for him to inherit. But as no such obligation exists, it
follows that obligation is not a matter of falling under a legal rule. Tenet 3 has to be
abandoned. (44)
highlights the relevance of morality to the law by saying that obligation, rights, and
duties cannot be reduced to an outcome of the application of legal rules. This is stated
clearly in Dworkin’s reply to his critics—he now asserts that “no ultimate distinction
can be made between legal and moral standards, as positivism insists.” (Dworkin
1978, 47)
The idea then is that moral principles must be considered when thinking about
what the law is. The existence of rules and their enforcement by sanction creates a
where obligations, rather than obligings obtain. The idea that force is not the same as
right nor capable of creating one is an old idea, of course. Hart recognizes it, and a
main objective of his Concept of Law is to accommodate this idea within a legal
16
“accepted social practice.” (Hart 1978, 79-88) But this difficulty may not be solved
even if we were to stipulate that the rules are willingly accepted and complied with, in
the absence of force and social pressure. As Dworkin argues, at one time a generally
accepted rule required men to pay certain courtesies to women. If that meant the
existence of obligations on the part of men to (for example) take off their hats when
greeting women, then what could it possibly have meant for someone back then to
deny the existence of such an obligation on the ground that it was an insulting kind of
social rules to be as real as the social rules themselves. But whereas the existence of
the rules could not be denied, the obligation could (and has been, in fact) denied (cf.
How are we to understand the obligatoriness of the law, then? According to Priel,
the content (substance) of the law must be considered, not just its formal feature of
being a law:
Much the same idea, stated in less radical terms, is behind the claim of the
relevance of natural law to legal rules. By ‘positive law’ Cotta understands “an Ought
that has a factual existence,” but “it is exactly to this positive (i.e. factually enacted)
form that natural law is opposed (or proposed) as indicating what the former ought to
17
be.” (Cotta 1983, 267) Were we to specify what positive law ought to be, we would
According to Fazlur Rahman, Ash‘arism “came to claim for itself the exalted function
of being the ‘defender of the bases of Islamic law’.” (Rahman 1982, 26) This is
undoubtedly related to the position of eminence which Ash‘arism attained in the field
of legal thinking in Islam. Given this, it stands to reason to think that a look at the
extended criticism of Ash‘arism by the Mu‘tazilah may expose some of the problems
cases” where our ideas about obligation are tested. Here is one. In the Qur’an it is
stated: “And the thief, male and female: cut off the hands of both, as a recompense for
what they have earned, and a punishment exemplary from God.” (5:40) But a few
years after the death of the Prophet, Muslim lands were afflicted with famine, which
led to many cases of theft. Under these circumstances, the Caliph ‘Umar I was led to
Other hard cases can be imagined in connection with the legal rule that requires
that a man’s testimony carry more weight than that of a woman. According to
Rahman, “to say that, no matter how much women may develop intellectually, their
evidence must on principle carry less value than that of a man is an outrageous affront
If we think about such “hard cases”, real or imagined, and the way they can be
dealt under Islamic law, we will inevitably be led to consider the place of principles,
18
policies and standards in such a system. But at this point it will be asked: aren’t these
principles, policies and standards to be found in the sources of Islamic law itself,
namely (and mainly), the Qur’an and the Sayings of the Prophet? It may be true, as
Rahman himself says, that the Qur’an mostly deals with concrete situations and offers
practical solutions, but it also “provides, either explicitly or implicitly, the rationales
behind these solutions and rulings, from which one can deduce general principles.
(Rahman, 1982, 20) Moreover, according to the same author, the Qur’an has a basic
moral message:
The basic élan of the Qur’an--the stress on socioeconomic justice and essential
human egalitarianism--is quite clear from its very early passages. Now all that
follows by way of Qur’anic legislation in the field of private and public life,
…., has social justice and the building of an egalitarian community as its end.
(Rahman 1982, 19)
Many Qur’anic verses can be cited which express judgment on matters that fall
within the realm of the moral, such as privacy, freedom of religion, individual
responsibility, equality, honesty, and elements of the virtuous life generally, as noted
his Caliphate and Kingship (Mawdudi 1975). One can also find legal precepts and
allowances that ought to govern legal proceedings, such as the Saying attributed to the
Prophet, which enjoins judges to “ward off the fixed punishments …on the strength of
shubhat [doubts about the truth] as much as you can.” (Peters 2005, 25)
If these considerations can be accepted, then it would appear that Islamic Legal
Positivism differs from the kind of legal positivism which Dworkin criticizes. As far
“principles, policies and standards”, because they are included in the system of law
itself.
19
Despite the availability of moral principles for use in the elaboration of divine
law, it can be said that Islamic jurisprudence, historically speaking, was for the most
part rule-driven, rather than morality-driven. It is an historical fact that at no point was
it considered possible to strike any legal rule off the book, on the strength of changed
with the value of woman’s testimony. This is not hard to understand in view of the
fact that legal rules of Islamic law are taken to be statements of Divine commands that
Without denying the existence of morals principles, policies and standard in the
Qur’an, one can still wonder about the influence they were destined to exert on the
The opposite tendency, taking material facts into account, diverging from the
formally correct decision for reasons of fairness or appropriateness, is not
unknown in Islamic law; it appears in istihsan [consideration of goodness] and
istislah [consideration of utility]. But this principle, both in theory and in its
actual application, occupies too subordinate a position for it to be able to
influence positive law to any considerable degree. (Schacht 1964, 204)
What this suggests is that general moral principles tended to carry less weight
than the clear-cut rules which we refer to as “divine positive law”. Despite the efforts
of the Mu‘tazilites and other rationalists, no doctrine of natural law ever took root in
surrounding jurisprudence.4
4
Patricia Crone denies the existence of a natural law doctrine in Islam (Crone 2004, 263-24). Avner
Emon (2010) disagrees, attributing a “soft” natural law doctrine to those who accepted a subordinate
role for reason. Undoubtedly, the use of analogy, and the invocation of maslaha (utility) in legislation
all require the use of reason, even belief in objective standards on some level. The question will always
be one of what impact moral considerations based on natural law and morality had in practice, and how
much official recognition they received.
20
The tendency towards seeing the law in terms of divine positive laws, rather than
in terms of moral concepts and principles is part and parcel of how the dominant view
came to understand moral discourse in general. According to Ash‘arism, not only are
commands and prohibitions (as we saw in the last section), the same applies to the
A thing is evil on our part only because we transgress the limit and boundary
set for us and do what we have no right to do. …Lying is evil because God has
made it evil [by proscribing it]. Had he commanded it, it would not have been
objectionable. (Al-Ash‘ari 1955, 117)
good and evil on the one hand, and divine command on the other:
Thus moral principles, standards and policies are themselves the product of
divine decision. This creates a difficulty. We are inclined to assume that ‘Umar I
right for people to starve to death, when they could save their lives by a little stealing.
e.g., the one that says “You ought not to take your own life” (2: 195) But according to
the Ash‘arite view, God was under no obligation to command this; He could have just
as easily commanded the opposite, in which case ‘Umar I would have been under an
principles. This does not set well with our firm intuition that, e.g., lying cannot be
prescribed.
To the Mu‘tazilites, who offered the most sustained and carefully worked out
criticism of Ash‘arism over many centuries, all of this ran counter to commonsense,
and made mockery of the idea of an all-good God. The Mu‘tazilites, at least as we
know them through the Mughni of Qadi ‘Abd- al-Jabbar, presented many arguments
against the Ash‘arite position.5 Here we shall consider only the ideas that are closely
The Mu‘tazilite criticism of the Ash‘arite concept of obligation turns out to be not
vastly different from criticisms of contemporary LP. In both cases what is found
morality. In particular, they thought that commands and prohibitions (divine or other)
could not be the ground of obligation. A fortiori, a command that was not in
accordance with what is morally required could not ground any obligation
but without creating, or constituting it in any way. In the words of cAbd al-Jabbar:
Revelation only uncovers in the character of these acts aspects whose evilness
or goodness we should recognize if we knew them by reason; for if we had
known by reason that prayer is of great benefit to us, …, and that we will be
rewarded for in the afterlife, we should have known its obligatory character
[also] by reason. Therefore we say that revelation does not necessitate (la
yujib) the evilness or goodness of anything, it only uncovers the character of
the act by way of indication. (cAbd al-Jabbar 1958-65, 64)
prayer. The Ash‘arites, of course, will say that what makes prayer obligatory is divine
command, and nothing else. But ‘Abd al-Jabbar claims that what makes prayer
obligatory is the goodness of its consequence in this life and the next. Had we been
5
For an overview of the Mu‘tazilite arguments, see Mariam al-Attar (2010).
22
able to know these consequences by reason, “we should have known its obligatory
command.
Now if the Mu‘tazilites in fact equated good with utility, and evil with harm, then
we can replace the phrase “entails benefit” in the above definition with the phrase
“entails good”, and the phrase “entails harm” with the phrase “entails evil”. But it is
not universally accepted that the Mu‘tazilites were utilitarian. According to Hourani:
[T]he Mu‘tazilites chose to define the main terms of ethics in ways which
avoid teleology. Mu‘tazilite ethics is deontological, because it explains wajib
[obligatory] hasan [good] and qabih [bad] not entirely by relations to ends, but
sometimes at least as characters of acts themselves. (Hourani 1985, 153)
This seems to be Richard M. Frank’s view too, for although, according to him,
nevertheless,
That we ought to do so, however, that is, to fulfill the moral obligation to seek
one's own good and to avoid grave or irremediable harm, is absolute and
irreducible. (Frank 1983, 207)
23
Perhaps what Hourani and Frank are saying can be illustrated by ‘Abd al-Jabbar’s
treatment of the case of someone who gives directions to the lost traveler.
We know by experience that one will sometimes give directions to one who
has lost his way …without there being any benefit for him personally—no
reward for commission or punishment for omission,…no expectation of
thanks, fear of blame or desire for praise…. nor because he is soft-hearted
(otherwise most everybody in the world would be soft-hearted). (cAbd-al-
Jabbar 1958-65, 223, 224, 225)
We can infer from this is that providing guidance for the lost is good (hasan), and
that its goodness is sufficient to motivate action. By itself, this does not prove that
goodness bears no relation to consequences. What it shows is that some of our actions
can be other-regarding, that we do not always act for self-regarding reasons. But it
remains true to say that the goodness of the action is not independent of the
consequences for the person whose good we have in view. Acting with no end in view
(personal or other) is the same acting purposelessly, something which Mu‘tazilites are
Be the case as it may with regard to the Mu‘tazilite stand on utilitarianism and
deontology, what matters essentially is fact that their critique of the legal positivism of
Ash‘arite doctrine was based on the idea that obligation cannot be divorced from the
moral considerations of goodness, and that the law is answerable to the standards of
spirit, their criticism was not really different from that of Dworkin, according to
whom “no ultimate distinction can be made between legal and moral standards as
From a certain perspective, it is to the credit of the Mu‘tazilites that they were
able to maintain a distinction between divine commands and moral grounds, between
24
the obligatory and the good. But as we shall see in the next section, the Ash‘arite
position may have had a logic of its own, a logic embedded in the concrete life of a
community of Faith, where no distinction was made between leading a good life and
The claim which Dworkin makes of there being no ultimate distinction between legal
rules and moral standards is precisely what John Austin denies in these famous words:
The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be
or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed
standard, is a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law, though
we happen to dislike it, or though it may vary from the text by which we
regulate our approbation and disapprobation. (Austin 1995, 157)
In the remainder of this paper an attempt will be made to determine whether there
is a way to make sense of the positivist view of obligation after due allowance is make
for the moral considerations which critics adduce. This will pave the way for looking
The following examples may serve to illustrate how consonant it is with ordinary
obligations on the on the one hand, and the law as such on the other. Suppose
someone makes a lie in the presence of other people, so there is no doubt about its
being a lie. We can say: “he ought not to have lied”, or “he had a moral obligation not
to lie”. In many cases, this is the end of the matter. But suppose, on the other hand
that the same lie was made under oath, in a court of law. The lie is the same, but the
situation is vastly different. Here the person clearly acts under a legal obligation to
25
tell the truth. Lying is called “perjury” and it is subject to sanction. By comparison,
telling the truth, outside of a law-governed context, seems more like something which
Kantians, of “the moral law within,” and our obligation to obey “the moral law”. But
this “moral law” does not have the reality, the bite, which legal obligation has.
The same applies to breaking promises. You promise someone you will sell him
your car; later, you change your mind, and break your promise. This is morally wrong,
we say. You may or may not be able to find an explanation for what you did, and your
explanation may or may not be convincing to this or that person. As long as the matter
remains in the realm of the moral, no definite decision may be reached. On the other
hand, had your promise been legally witnessed, signed and attested, your obligation to
sell the car assumes a different shape. Now it is a legal obligation, whose breaking
person, reflecting on life in ancient Greece may say the following: “In ancient Greece,
people owned slaves, and had a right to buy and sell as many slaves as they wanted. A
slave, on the other hand, did not have a right to leave the service of his master.” Some
may say that we must not talk like this; that we should place the words “rights” and
“obligations” between scare-quotes to indicate that, in reality, the slave owners did
not have a right to sell slaves, and that the slaves did not have an obligation to obey
their masters. But then we may as well place scare-quote around “owned”, because,
after all, what does ownership mean, if it does not mean that you have right to sell
But clearly, there is no call for us to sprinkle a historical discourse about ancient
Greece with scare quotes in order to reveal our moral standpoint on slavery. Talk of
slave ownership, and the rights and obligations that go with owning slaves is perfectly
objections to the laws, but to think that we are not dealing with rights and obligations
According to G.E.M. Anscombe’s famous essay of 1958, the idea of there being
immoral, was once , and for a long time, at home within the framework a divine law
Christianity. But, of course, one must add Islam. The law conception of ethics was
evident in the Ash‘arites’ willingness, nay, their anxiety, one may say, to put good and
evil, the right and wrong, the forbidden and the obligatory, all in one basket: the
basket of divine law. They did this by one simple move: they said that all these
notions are definable by reference to divine law. In plainer, less theological (therefore
less contentious) language they could have said: “to live a good life, where one
always does right, and fulfills one’s obligations is simply to live in accordance with
divine law.”
By saying that divine law obliges “as rules oblige in a game”, Anscombe does not
imply that the rules of divine law are the same as the rules of a game. Divine rules and
moral laws differ from the rules of a game (such as chess) in that they are
This, of course, cannot be said for the laws of a game, such as chess. It cannot be
said that an enormous amount of human good hangs on it. So it does not attain the
status of being a moral rule. But insofar as it is a rule, the chess rule which says “You
cannot make two moves in a row” is not different from the rule which says “You
cannot kill innocent persons”. A command, rule, or law, be it of the religious- divine
type, or the game type, has meaning precisely because it can be complied with. The
cynical saying that “laws are made to be broken” has a grain of truth in it, precisely
because it is also true to say that rules are made to be obeyed. If no obeying ever took
divine/legal rules on the one hand, and those of chess, on the other. In all these cases,
final answers to a certain type of question can be given. To the question of why I, a
driver, had an obligation to stop I can say: “because the traffic light was red, and the
law says to stop at a red light”. To the question of why I had to move a chess piece, I
can say: “my King was in check, and the rule says to move or resign”. To the question
28
of why I had to reject this drink I, a Muslim, can say: “it is an intoxicating drink, and
divine law prohibit this”. In all these cases justification comes to an end by reference
to a rule. In many cases of this type, this is a perfectly acceptable stopping-point and
explanation of obligation.
In many cases, yes, but the “conversations” of the last paragraph can be
continued. One can be challenged to say why one ought to obey the (divine) law. But
to see what is at stake in such a challenge consider a similar challenge to say why one
should obey the laws of chess. A question such as this last one can only mean “what
good is to be found in this activity of obeying chess laws?” Perhaps one should not
can then be construed as a call for abandoning the game of chess altogether. Or
perhaps the challenger could be satisfied with an answer such as: “because chess
The important thing to realize is that what is stake in the “ought” involved in
these challenges is not the same as the “ought” involved in “You ought to move your
King”, or “Thou shalt not kill”. Rather, it is the same as the “ought” we employ in
ought to be exercising more”. Here the “ought” refers to what is needed for the good
of the plant and the athlete to be achieved – watering in one case, exercising in the
reference to Aristotle’s definition of the necessary as that “without which the good
obligation which the Ash‘arites and legal positivists are interested in.
the question of what is obligatory and what is forbidden. As said before, they
29
ultimately define the obligatory act as one whose omission leads to corruption or
harm. On the other hand, the tradition to which the Mu‘tazilites were opposed was at
no point prepared to think about the divine law in term of Aristotelian necessity. For
in defining the obligatory and the forbidden, as well as good and evil in terms of
divine law, it ruled out the possibility of there being any notion that could be used to
pass value judgment on laws and legal norms. Human reason, which could be counted
on to know something about good and evil, was rendered useless, at least as far as
were simple-minded in comparison with the Ash‘arites. At one point ‘Abd al-Jabbar
The divine prohibition of something in effect says: “such and such is evil.” In
reality, there is no distinction between someone saying “this is evil” and
saying “Do not do this.” (‘Abd al-Jabbar 1958-65, 105)
But to think that a (divine) command such as e.g. “Thou shalt not kill” is
category of “rule”, or “law” altogether. For saying that killing is evil may be no more
than a moral truth, or a report of moral fact. In no way can it play the role which it is
the nature of laws and rules to play: to make it possible for there to be acts of
obedience, (compliance) and disobedience. The Ash‘arites, for their part, were aware
of this. For there to be such thing as obligation, there has to be “obliger”, and an
“obligee”, and something which one is obliged to do. This holds regardless of the
The Ash‘arites were not willing (or able) to think philosophically about the
prescribed content of divine law. What figured prominently in their thinking was the
30
existence of rules that were laid down by the recognized authority of the All-mighty
God. Pressed to say why one should not lie, they could say: “because God says not
to,” which is a good answer in the framework of a way of life that accepts Divine
“because the laws of chess say to.” What the Ashcarites omitted to do is raise the
question of why it was worth one’s while to engage in the whole practice of obeying
divine law. The Mu‘tazilites implicitly raised the question and answered by saying, in
effect, “because it is good (objectively good) to do so.”6 But then we must remember
that this questioning attitude of the Mu‘tazilites behooves people who choose to
follow the path of Reason rather than Faith. The latter may lump the notion of the
good with the obligatory, and thus fail, as the Ash‘arites apparently did, to distinguish
Implicit in what we have said in this section is a suggestion that that the
Mu‘tazilites and the Ash‘arites are not opposed to each other in the way it has hitherto
been supposed. If we are right, then it would appear the former were on the whole
preoccupied with a rule-theoretic notion of what one “must” do: there are rules, and
rules must be obeyed. As to the latter, it would then appear that they were mostly
preoccupied with goodness-theoretic notion of what one “must” do: one must do that
(not mere moral advice) is needed, but we would like the law to serve what is good
and what is right. Perhaps something along these lines can be developed in order to
6
It would not make a difference if the Mu‘tazilites were to be taken as saying that keeping promises,
returning deposits, etc. are good in themselves, and not because of their consequences. For the notion
of “Aristotelian necessity” makes no reference to the nature of the good, i.e. whether it defined in a
consequentialist-utilitarian or a deontological manner.
31
reconcile Legal Positivism and Natural Law Theory. But this undertaking is beyond
References
Abu Dawud. (1997). Sunan Abi Dawud, ed. ‘Izzat Da‘as. Beirut: Dar Ibn Hazm.
Anscombe, Elizabeth. (1981). “On Promising and its Justice, and Whether it Need be
Respected in Foro Interno”. In Ethics, Religion, and Politics: Collected
Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell, and Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Anzi, S.A. (2004). Fathu al-‘Ullam fi Tartib Ayat al-Ahkam. Kuwait: Ministry of
Islamic Affairs.
Arberry, Arthur J. (1964). The Koran Interpreted. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aristotle (1984). Metaphysics. In: The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan
Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Arrabi, Usama. (1999). Early Muslim Legal Philosophy. Los Angeles: G.E. von
Grunebaum Center for Near Eastern Studies.
32
Cotta, Sergio (1983). “Positive Law and Natural Law”. Review of Metaphysics, 37,
365-285.
Crone, Patricia. (2004). God’s Rule: Government and Islam: Six Centuries of
Medieval Islamic Political Thought. New York: Columbia University Press.
Emon, Avner M. (2010). Islamic Natural Law Theories. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Geach, P. T. (1969). “Moral Law and the Law of God”. In God and the Soul. London:
Kegan and Paul.
Gracia, Jorge J. (1996). “The Philosopher and the Understanding of the Law”, in
Mourad Wahba and Mona Abousenna (eds.), Averroes and the Enlightenment, New
York: Prometheus Books.
Hourani, George F. (1985). “Divine Justice and Human Reason in Mu‘tazilite Ethical
Theology”, in Ethics in Islam, ed. R. Hovannisian . Malibu, CA: Undena Publications
33
Al-Mawdudi, Abu al-A‘la. (1987). Caliphate and Kingship. Kuwait: Dar al-Qalam
Murphy, J. B. (2005). The Philosophy of Positive Law. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Rahman, Fazlur. (1982). Islam and Modernity. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Reihnart, A. Kevin. (1995). The Boundaries of Muslim Moral Thought. Albany: State
University of New York.
Lubnan.
University Press.