Read The Ruling Iancu v. Brunetti
Read The Ruling Iancu v. Brunetti
Read The Ruling Iancu v. Brunetti
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
No. 18–302
_________________
II
This Court first considered a First Amendment chal-
lenge to a trademark registration restriction in Tam, just
two Terms ago. There, the Court declared unconstitutional
the Lanham Act’s ban on registering marks that “dispar-
age” any “person[ ], living or dead.” §1052(a). The eight-
Justice Court divided evenly between two opinions and
could not agree on the overall framework for deciding the
case. (In particular, no majority emerged to resolve
whether a Lanham Act bar is a condition on a government
benefit or a simple restriction on speech.) But all the
Justices agreed on two propositions. First, if a trademark
registration bar is viewpoint-based, it is unconstitutional.
See 582 U. S., at ___–___, ___–___ (opinion of ALITO, J.)
(slip op., at 1–2, 22–23); id., at ___–___, ___ (opinion of
Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 1–2, 5). And second, the dispar-
agement bar was viewpoint-based. See id., at ___–___,
___–___ (opinion of ALITO, J.) (slip op., at 1–2, 22–23); id.,
at ___–___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 2–5).
The Justices thus found common ground in a core postu-
late of free speech law: The government may not discrimi-
nate against speech based on the ideas or opinions it
conveys. See Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Va., 515 U. S. 819, 829–830 (1995) (explaining that view-
point discrimination is an “egregious form of content
discrimination” and is “presumptively unconstitutional”).
In Justice Kennedy’s explanation, the disparagement bar
allowed a trademark owner to register a mark if it was
“positive” about a person, but not if it was “derogatory.”
Tam, 582 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 2). That was the “es-
sence of viewpoint discrimination,” he continued, because
“[t]he law thus reflects the Government’s disapproval of a
subset of messages it finds offensive.” Id., at ___–___ (slip
op., at 2–3). JUSTICE ALITO emphasized that the statute
“denie[d] registration to any mark” whose disparaging
message was “offensive to a substantial percentage of the
Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019) 5
No. 18–302
_________________
No. 18–302
_________________
Opinion of BREYER, J.
No. 18–302
_________________
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of BREYER, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
No. 18–302
_________________
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
I
Trademark registration, as the majority notes, is not
required for using, owning, or suing others for infringing a
trademark. Rather, the trademark-registration system is
an ancillary system set up by the Government that confers
a small number of noncash benefits on trademark-holders
who register their marks. See ante, at 2.
The Government need not provide this largely commer-
cial benefit at all. Once the Government does provide the
benefit, however, it may not restrict access on the basis of
the viewpoint expressed by the relevant mark. See ante,
at 4–5. For that reason, the Court concluded in Matal v.
Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017), that §1052(a)’s provision direct-
ing the U. S. Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) to deny
registration to “disparag[ing]” trademarks was unconstitu-
tional. This case centers on a neighboring set of re-
strictions: §1052(a)’s provision barring registration of
marks featuring “immoral . . . or scandalous matter.”
The majority finds viewpoint discrimination here by
treating the terms “scandalous” and “immoral” as compris-
ing a unified standard that allows messages “aligned with
conventional moral standards” but forbids messages “hos-
tile to” such standards. See ante, at 6. While the major-
ity’s interpretation of the statute is a reasonable one, it is
not the only reasonable one.
A
As the majority notes, there are dictionary definitions
for both “immoral” and “scandalous” that do suggest a
viewpoint-discriminatory meaning. See ante, at 5–6. And
as for the word “immoral,” I agree with the majority that
there is no tenable way to read it that would ameliorate
the problem. The word clearly connotes a preference for
“rectitude and morality” over its opposite. See ante, at 5.
It is with regard to the word “scandalous” that I part
ways with the majority. Unquestionably, “scandalous” can
Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019) 3
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
fit this description as well. While Matal v. Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017),
removed a statutory basis to deny the registration of racial epithets in
general, the Government represented at oral argument that it is
8 IANCU v. BRUNETTI
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
B
A limiting construction like the one just discussed is
both appropriate in this context and consistent with past
precedent. First, while a limiting construction must al-
ways be at least reasonable, there are contexts in which
imposing such a construction is more appropriate than
others. The most obvious example of a setting where more
caution is required is in the realm of criminal statutes,
where considerations such as the prohibition against
vagueness and the rule of lenity come into play. See Reno
v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844, 872
(1997) (noting that “[t]he severity of criminal sanctions”
can increase First Amendment concerns); Board of Airport
Comm’rs of Los Angeles v. Jews for Jesus, Inc., 482 U. S.
569, 575–576 (1987) (declining to apply a limiting con-
struction to a provision that banned “ ‘First Amendment
activities’ ” from an airport and noting that the limiting
construction proposed would “ ‘confe[r] on police a virtually
unrestrained power to arrest and charge persons with a
violation,’ ” leading to “ ‘self-evident’ ” “ ‘opportunity for
abuse’ ”). Here, however, the question is only whether the
Government must be forced to provide the ancillary bene-
fit of trademark registration to pre-existing trademarks
that use even the most extreme obscenity, vulgarity, or
profanity. The stakes are far removed from a situation in
which, say, Brunetti was facing a threat to his liberty, or
even his right to use and enforce his trademark in
commerce.
Second, the Court has in the past accepted or applied
similarly narrow constructions to avoid constitutional
——————
holding in abeyance trademark applications that use that particular
epithet. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 61. As a result of today’s ruling, the
Government will now presumably be compelled to register marks
containing that epithet as well rather than treating it as a “scandalous”
form of profanity under §1052(a).
Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019) 9
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
save it, the Court should do so. See Stern v. Marshall, 564
U. S. 462, 477–478 (2011); NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin
Steel Corp., 301 U. S. 1, 30 (1937).
II
Adopting a narrow construction for the word “scandal-
ous”—interpreting it to regulate only obscenity, vulgarity,
and profanity—would save it from unconstitutionality.
Properly narrowed, “scandalous” is a viewpoint-neutral
form of content discrimination that is permissible in the
kind of discretionary governmental program or limited
forum typified by the trademark-registration system.
A
Content discrimination occurs whenever a government
regulates “particular speech because of the topic discussed
or the idea or message expressed.” Reed v. Town of Gil-
bert, 576 U. S. ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 6); see also Ward
v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 791 (1989) (“Gov-
ernment regulation of expressive activity is content neu-
tral so long as it is ‘justified without reference to the con-
tent of the regulated speech’ ”). Viewpoint discrimination
is “an egregious form of content discrimination” in which
“the government targets not subject matter, but particular
views taken by speakers on a subject.” Rosenberger v.
Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819, 829
(1995).
While the line between viewpoint-based and viewpoint-
neutral content discrimination can be “slippery,” see
Corbin, Mixed Speech: When Speech Is Both Private and
Governmental, 83 N. Y. U. L. Rev. 605, 651 (2008), it is in
any event clear that a regulation is not viewpoint discrim-
inatory (or even content discriminatory) simply because it
has an “incidental effect” on a certain subset of views.
Ward, 491 U. S., at 791. Some people, for example, may
have the viewpoint that society should be more sexually
Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019) 11
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
whether because not every such system invites expressive content like
trademarks or simply because other forms of registration may not be so
ancillary as to qualify solely as a “benefit.”
12 Though I do not address the constitutionality of provisions not be-
fore the Court, I note as well that the “scandalous” bar in §1052(a) is
hardly the only provision in §1052 that could be characterized as
content discriminatory. See, e.g., §1052(b) (no flags or insignias);
§1052(c) (no unapproved markers of deceased U. S. Presidents during
the lives of their spouses).
18 IANCU v. BRUNETTI
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
——————
Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S. 491, 504–507 (1985); see also Tam, 582 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 26) (striking down only the disparagement clause).
14 The majority adverts to details in the record that could call into