Rogue Neoliberalism Liturgical Power and PDF
Rogue Neoliberalism Liturgical Power and PDF
Rogue Neoliberalism Liturgical Power and PDF
upon a well of deep theological resources. In its wake, it has unmoored its
own various Center-Left, cosmopolitan, and globalist manifestations. It can
reside both in the authoritarian resacralization of the market and national
economy and the purification of the nation itself from foreign, ethnic, and
racial contaminants, and also in the libertarian “lifestyle politics” that claims
to oppose it, and the pieties of the “rule of law” liberalism that seeks to keep
it in check. In terms of cultural diagnostic and imagery, the Weberian “soul-
nessness” of the Fordist industrial welfare state has been replaced by a low-
level confessional civil war between progressivist and fundamentalist neo-
liberalisms, from which the political Left has largely absented itself. At the
same time, a surplus of both political acclamation and capital accumulation
is produced by social media companies, leading to a new kind of liturgical
power that can be acted on, manipulated, and controlled with the same ruth-
lessness that an earlier generation of spin doctors sought to act on the public
opinion produced in the mass media. The manufacture of contempt has
replaced the manufacture of consent.1
diversity, that offered support to the emerging minority groups who sought
to maximize autonomy in their own self-definition and self-creation and
resist the subjection of the welfare state and human sciences.
This is not to say that Foucault saw no dangers in neoliberalism, chief
among them the manipulation of choice by environmental interventions,
but these should be weighed against the considerable potentials he found in
it. However, in expressing the view that the Left would have to draw on liber-
alism to constitute an art of government, and that there was no equivalent in
the socialist political canon, Foucault set the course for what might be called
the search for a left governmentality. At the same time, the most famous
names of the neoliberal thought collective were enunciating the principles of
neoliberalism’s relation to authoritarianism in the context of their involve-
ment in the Pinochet regime. Friedrich Hayek (1981) seemed to surprise
himself in an interview in Santiago when he found himself preferring a “lib-
eral dictator” to a “democracy lacking liberalism,” and arguing that some-
times “democracy needs the broom of strong government.” More concisely,
for neoliberals such as Hayek and Milton Friedman, liberalism and democ-
racy were not the same thing; the opposite of liberalism was not authoritari-
anism but totalitarianism, and authoritarianism could thereby serve true
liberalism. In contrast to the supposition of a recent authoritarian turn, in
this period neoliberalism as an intellectual and political project was already
prepared to sacrifice, at least temporarily, democratic procedures and rights
for an authoritarian state willing to implement the conditions for a “free
market.” In this respect, it had learned the lessons of a “commissarial dicta-
torship” that Carl Schmitt (2014) had identified just after World War I.
ular ways, learning to plan their own lives, combating the ill effects of their
risk of welfare dependence, undertaking training and retraining as required,
undergoing therapy and being case-managed, and learning to act more and
more like an enterprise. Key themes would include the telos of an “active soci-
ety,” with flexible and agile populations, able to grasp the changing opportu-
nities of the market, now projected onto a global scale rather than remaining
at a national one, made competitive by the investments in human capital and
the enterprise of the individuals that composed it (Dean 1995). As Foucault
foreshadowed, the individual, having been through a series of tests and
ordeals, would experience the pleasures of life as an enterprise.
While Foucault would look to Greco-Roman antiquity for an autono-
mous practice of the care of the self, other theorists of left governmentality
would find an easier route through the sociological supposition of changing
forms of subjectivity. While not using such an expression, sociological theo-
rists such as Ulrich Beck (1992) and Anthony Giddens (1991) would argue
that under conditions of late modernity, the individual would no longer be
bound by the ascribed characteristics of class, race and ethnicity, and gender
and sexuality that had been transmitted by traditional, patriarchal, familial,
and religious forms of socialization. Rather, individuals were capable of
remaking themselves, with or without the help of the armies of therapists
and self-help experts; of examining the contents of their given identities,
including those of class; of challenging them and making new choices for
themselves. Individuals would be capable of narrating and renarrating their
own lives, choosing their own personal and sexual identity, and entering into
intimate relations on a new ground of equality rather than conventional patri-
archal and traditional hierarchical relations, including those of class. This
“reflexive project of the self” would at best lead to a new “cosmopolitan” iden-
tity that would be capable of understanding and empathizing with the trajec-
tory of other very diverse pathways to this reflexive identity. As class identi-
ties and solidarities loosened and lost their defining significance for identity,
the presence and impact of a class politics of mass labor parties and trade
unions would diminish and eventually disappear. The reflexive, self-making
individuals would identify with different communities and forms of political
associations around these new identifications. The importance of the auton-
omy, vibrancy, and vitality of civil society or community would be rediscov-
ered. Civil society would be the place of the experimentations made possible
by these new diverse collective identifications and would also become the
means by which the fiscal problems and bureaucratic sclerosis of the welfare
state would be attenuated, if not fully solved, and on a global scale; problems
of war, poverty, and the environment would be addressed.
The diagnostic moment for such social theory comes when we turn to
public policy. Because the truth of the subject was changing, and the poten-
tial of a new self-making or reflexive individual was emerging in a “second
modernity,” it was no longer possible to provide governmental programs and
politics around the old solidarities of class and family. Rather than being the
recipient of a right, the individual had to become a certain type of subject,
with the help of a range of experts, but no longer under their tutelage and as
a full and equal partner; the vertical relations of state, authority, and exper-
tise were to be replaced by horizontal and reciprocal ones that enlist the sub-
ject’s own capacities, lifestyle, and forms of freedom in the process. Life had
become a “planning project.” As Giddens (1998: 36–37) put it, “We have to
make our lives in a more active way than was true of previous generations,
and we need more actively to accept responsibility for the consequences of
what we do and the life habits we adopt.” Or, even more bluntly, this from
Ulrich Beck (1992: 135): “In the individualised society, the individual must
learn, on pain of permanent disadvantage, to conceive of himself or herself
as the centre of activity, as the planning office with respect to his or her own
biography, abilities, orientations, relationships and so on.” Such was the uni-
versal lesson of this new modernity for rich and poor, for S&M-experiment-
ing philosophers and dope-smoking unemployed youth, for Cambridge
white male academics and black teenage moms alike: no longer Cuius regio,
eius religio (whose realm, his religion), but Cuius societas, eius forma vitae
(whose society, his form of life).
There is then a direct link between sociological theories of the self and
the individualization processes of late modernity and the programs of gov-
ernment that seek to elicit such self-transformational capacities from the
individual. This is the key lesson of the Third Way politics in which
Anthony—later Lord—Giddens would play the crown theorist to Tony Blair’s
New Labour. But the aporias of turning a general sociological theory of the
subject into a normative governmental one soon would multiply, with devas-
tating consequences for those who would meet the newly privatized, mar-
ketized, and individualized service provision amid the ruins of the welfare
state. One can note that the categorization of individuals according to such
individualizing capacities leads to a particular hierarchy in terms of the
degree of capability of exercising autonomy, and the emergence of multiple
categories of those “at high risk of welfare dependency,” who should be sub-
ject to a range of educational, training, and therapeutic practices to assist in
the gaining of such capabilities. Because they do not have or have yet to
develop such capacities, they need to be encouraged, enticed, and even forced
into such: hence the long deliberation on and experimentation with the rela-
tionship between libertarianism and paternalism, first with the New Pater-
nalism and later with the advocacy of a libertarian paternalism and nudge
theory. If neoliberal policy prescriptions had been revealed to be entirely com-
patible with the authoritarian and dictatorial regimes at national levels during
the 1970s and, in many instances, required them, by the 1990s it was becom-
ing clear that the neoliberal prescriptions for the shaping of choice and free-
dom were necessarily connected to the instantiation of systems of obligation
and coupled with more or less disciplinary, coercive, and sovereign instru-
ments. Among the coercive ones would be the widespread use of workfare
programs (Peck 1998), that is, make-work programs that simulated employ-
ment for social welfare beneficiaries and made participation in them condi-
tional for receiving benefits. The limits of the governmentality of the welfare
recipient are revealed by the increasing use of the removal of benefits from
the individual for failing to participate in said programs or to make enough
job applications, and the mandating of what benefits can be spent on. The net
effect of this conditionality is the deterrence of the use of social welfare by
large sections of the population, leaving them to the vagaries of the precari-
ous and minimum-wage employment market, “zero-hour” contracts, the “gig
economy,” the support of their families and friends, the empty promises of
entrepreneurship and start-ups, or, worse still, grifting and less socially
acceptable ways of eking out a living. There is little choice between the ordeals
required to remake oneself as an enterprise and the quotidian ordeals of a
deconstructed labor market. The neoliberal celebration of identity and
self-making is mired in the authoritarian practices it generates (Dean 2002).
political and policy agenda is being implemented by that which it posits as its
opposite. Rather than two opposed ideologies and contrasting worldviews,
such as the Cold War binary between communism and capitalism, progres-
sive, financial neoliberalism finds a distorted version of itself in its Other. The
nativist expulsion from the body of the nation of undesirable populations is
tightly coupled with the expulsion from the market of unnecessary regula-
tion. Populism clings like mud shaped by neoliberalism’s antistatist and anti-
bureaucracy tire tracks: from the “drain the swamp” variety in the United
States to Matteo Salvini’s characterization of his prime ministerial designate
as an “expert in simplification and de-bureaucratization” (Horowitz 2018).
So what has happened? Neoliberalism as a thought collective and path
dependency has largely succeeded in the economic “neutralization” of the
political. The failure of the search for a left governmentality, or the adoption
by Center-Left parties of neoliberal technologies of government, together
with a widespread intellectual antistatism and rejection of formal politics, has
deprived or at least undermined labor and social-democratic parties’ organic
concerns with the conditions of the working and precarious populations, leav-
ing little effective voice of discontent other than antiglobalist appeals to a
“walled sovereignty” (Brown 2010). Instead, as exemplified by the Hillary
Clinton campaign in 2016, the Center Left becomes—or at least can be read-
ily portrayed by its opponents as—the party of diversity disconnected from
fundamental concerns around economic exploitation, widening inequality,
and narrowing life chances for a sizable segment of its traditional constitu-
ents. This means that there is an opportunity to articulate economic griev-
ance and disappointment with an attack on the cultural as well as economic
“elites” of contemporary capitalism. It is also possible to articulate a possible
identity politics for those left out of it. Thus, groups that include many who
would be conventionally defined through ascribed characteristics as white,
male, and working class demand to be heard not in terms of their class posi-
tion but as yet another identity group with specific interests, needs, and
rights. Isn’t gun owning simply another lifestyle for people in rural areas? In
an age where sexual minorities are encouraged to assert their rights, what
about the ordeals of involuntarily celibate men, as the “incels” violently assert?
At the same time, the kind of developments that undermined the
Fordist system of industrial production and the welfare state have utterly
transformed the previous hegemony of the capitalist media corporations and
the form of public sphere and public narratives they sustained. Social media,
and the forms of participation it has engendered, not only multiply sources
of knowledge and opinion and increased opportunities for political participa-
tion and identification, but they also unravel the regimes of truth character-
istic of the mass media (Dean 2017). The “objective” voice of the narration
formed through the mass media is displaced by the more volatile swings of
the public mood registered and almost immediately legible on social media,
and the tribal truths of those who make specific identifications through
social media. The latter, of course, becomes a new domain of political manip-
ulation and control, much to the surprise of the peddlers of liberal teleolo-
gies of the progressive expansion of civil society. Yet the relations of power
and possibilities of manipulation run much deeper than the surveillance
society with its increased digital panopticism and even algorithmic govern-
mentality can allow. While there is much talk of a “politics of untruth” or of
“post-truth politics,” we can say that the mass media, like science, has lost its
monopoly on truth. Indeed, the demand for regulation of social media in the
name of individual privacy, and the protests in the defense of science, can be
understood as belated and parallel attempts by the mass media and institu-
tionalized science to reclaim their monopolies on certain manifestations of
truth. What is paradoxical is that those who once might have criticized the
first as purveyors of ideology and the other as reductionist and positivist can
now find themselves aligned with both.
When the alt-Right emerged as an actor in the 2016 US election, it may
have appeared as little more than white supremacism mixed with wounded
masculine aggression (Green 2017). However, at least publicly, it succeeded in
representing itself as a conjunction of social media savvy with the appropria-
tion of identity politics on behalf of the “forgotten” populations laid to waste
by global capitalist competition and the deconstructed welfare state. It demon-
strates the capacity to extend the political manipulation of the public sphere
from the dispositive of public opinion associated with the mass media to the
dispositive of the “public mood” formed through social media (Dean 2017).
While it is easy, and somewhat facile, to regard this latter shift as a seismic
catastrophe for liberal democracy, one could argue that it was founded on an
extension of one of the oldest elements of direct forms of democracy: accla-
mation, the shouts and cries accompanied by hand gestures and flag waving,
that were at the core of both the liturgical power (Heron 2018) of the Chris-
tian church and the mass identifications of authoritarian and direct democra-
cies. The acclamations of the public assembly, which had been displaced by
the kind of acclamation produced by the corporate mass media, was now
renewed, not least by the Trump campaign itself, in tandem with the likes,
posts, and “friending” of social media. The latter, which had been the basis of
the business model of social media platforms in their use of “digital market-
ing,” found its way into the marketing of political candidates. Insofar as both
populist politics and social media posts are versions of acclamatory will and
The present moment is crucial for the humanities and social sciences,
undergoing their own transformations that have reconstructed the univer-
sity space of research and teaching as one of competition and performance.
They have the tools, the methods, the heritage, and the historical sense to
make the present intelligible. However, they are hampered by inherited and
now quite dominant critical traditions following poststructuralism and the
immanent turn that have, among other things, reduced the political to a
debate over forms of governance, displayed and encouraged an analytical
antistatism, and absolutely neglected the problem of the formation of publics
through the acclamations, ceremonies, protocols, and liturgies of politics and
political communication. One of the ways out of these analytical shortcom-
ings has, for the past few years at least, required the radical problematizations
made available by first a political, and then an economic theology (Dean
2018b). In the latter, we find the broadest and most compelling attempt to
rethink, using the history of not only discourses of civil government but also
those of divine government, the relationship between the mundane gover-
nance and economic management of life and the sovereign power that is
constituted as its foundation and source of authority.
Notes
As is clear from the text, the title of this essay is indebted to the theoretical work, of very
different kinds, conducted by Nicholas Heron and Daniel Zamora.
1. I owe the former phrase to a personal communication I had with Ian Hunter.
References
Beck, Ulrich. 1992. Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. Translated by Mark Ritter. Lon-
don: Sage.
Boland, Tom, and Ray Griffin. 2017. “The Purgatorial Ethic and the Spirit of Welfare.” Journal
of Classical Sociology 18, no. 2: 87–103.
Brenner, Neil, Jamie Peck, and Nik Theodore. 2010. “Variegated Neoliberalization: Geographies,
Modalities, Pathways.” Global Networks 10, no. 2: 182–222.
Brown, Wendy. 2010. Walled Sovereignty, Waning States. New York: Zone Books.
Chozick, Amy. 2016 “Hillary Clinton Calls Many Trump Backers ‘Deplorables,’ and G.O.P.
Pounces.” New York Times, September 10.
Dean, Mitchell. 1995. “Governing the Unemployed Self in an Active Society.” Economy and
Society 24, no. 4: 559–83.
Dean, Mitchell. 2002. “Liberal Government and Authoritarianism.” Economy and Society 31,
no. 1: 37–61.
Dean, Mitchell. 2017. “Three Forms of Democratic Political Acclamation.” Telos, no. 197: 9–32.
Dean, Mitchell. 2018a. “The Dark Arts Reach the Internet.” TELOSscope, March 27. www.telos
press.com/the-dark-arts-reach-the-internet/.