Popper Threeviews PDF
Popper Threeviews PDF
Popper Threeviews PDF
In Karl Popper
"Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge", Chapter 3,
London, Routledge, 1965, pp. 97-119.
2
2. THE ISSUE AT STAKE
All this looks like a great victory of philosophical critical thought over the ‘naïve
realism’ of the physicists. But I doubt whether this interpretation is right.
Few if any of the physicists who have now accepted the instrumentalist view of
Cardinal Bellarmino and Bishop Berkeley realize that they have accepted a
philosophical theory. Nor do they realize that they have broken with the Galilean
tradition. On the contrary, most of them think that they have kept clear of philosophy;
and most of them no longer care anyway. What they now care about, as physicists, is
(a) mastery of the mathematical formalism, i.e. of the instrument, and (b) its applications; and
they care for nothing else. And they think that by thus excluding everything else they
have finally got rid of all philosophical nonsense. This very attitude of being tough
and not standing any nonsense prevents them from considering seriously the
philosophical arguments for and against the Galilean view of science (though they will
no doubt have heard of Machvii). Thus the victory of the instrumentalist philosophy is
hardly due to the soundness of its arguments.
How then did it come about? As far as I can see, through the coincidence of two
factors, (a) difficulties in the interpretation of the formalism of the Quantum Theory,
and (b) the spectacular practical success of its applications.
(a) In 1927 Niels Bohr, one of the greatest thinkers in the field of atomic
physics, introduced the so-called principle of complementarity into atomic physics, which
amounted to a ‘renunciation’ of the attempt to interpret atomic theory as a description
of anything. Bohr pointed out that we could avoid certain contradictions (which
threatened to arise between the formalism and its various interpretations) only by
reminding ourselves that the formalism as such was self-consistent, and that each
single case of its application (or each kind of case) remained consistent with it. The
contradictions only arose through the attempt to comprise within one interpretation
the formalism together with more than one case, or kind of case, of its experimental
application. But, as Bohr pointed out, any two of these conflicting applications were
physically incapable of ever being combined in one experiment. Thus the result of
every single experiment was consistent with the theory, and unambiguously laid down
by it. This, he said, was all we could get. The claim to get more, and even the hope of
ever getting more, we must renounce; physics remains consistent only if we do not try
to interpret, or to understand, its theories beyond (a) mastering the formalism, and (b)
relating them to each of their actually realizable cases of application separately.viii
Thus the instrumentalist philosophy was used here ad hoc in order to provide an
escape for the theory from certain contradictions by which it was, threatened. It was
used in a defensive mood-to rescue the existing theory; and the principle or
complementarity has (I believe for this reason) remained completely sterile within
3
physics. In twenty-seven years it has produced nothing except some philosophical
discussions, and some arguments for the confounding or critics (especially Einstein).
I do not believe that physicists would have accepted such an ad hoc principle had
they understood that it was ad hoc, or that it was a philosophical principle-part or
Bellarmino's and Berkeley's instrumentalist philosophy of physics. But they
remembered Bohr's earlier and extremely fruitful ‘principle of correspondence’ and
hoped (in vain) for similar results.
(b) Instead or results due to the principle of complementarity other and more
practical results of atomic theory were obtained, some or them with a big bang. No
doubt physicists were perfectly right in interpreting these successful applications as
corroborating their theories. But strangely enough they took them as confirming the
instrumentalist creed.
Now this was an obvious mistake. The instrumentalist view asserts that theories
are nothing but instruments, while the Galilean view was that they are not only
instruments but also-and mainly-descriptions of the world, or of certain aspects or the
world. It is clear that in this disagreement even a proof showing that theories are
instruments (assuming it possible to ‘prove’ such a ting) could not seriously be
claimed to support either of the two parties to the debate, since both were agreed on
this point.
If I am right, or even roughly right, in my account of the situation, then
philosophers, even instrumentalist philosophers, have no reason to take pride in their
victory. On the contrary, they should examine their arguments again. For at least in
the eyes of those who like myself do not accept the instrumentalist view, there is
much at stake in this issue.
The issue, as I see it, is this.
One of the most important ingredients of our western civilization is what I may
call the ‘rationalist tradition’ which we have inherited from the Greeks. It is the
tradition of critical discussion-not for its own sake, but in the interests of the search
for truth. Greek science, like Greek philosophy, was one of the products of this
tradition, and of the urge to understand the world in which we live; and the tradition
founded by Galileo was its renaissance.
Within this rationalist tradition science is valued, admittedly, for its pratical
achievements; but it is even more highly valued for its informative content, and for its
ability to free our minds from old beliefs, old prejudices, and old certainties, and to
offer us in their stead new conjectures and daring hypotheses. Science is valued for its
liberalizing influence-as one of the greatest of the forces that make for human
freedom.
According to the view of science which I am trying to defend here, this is due to
the fact that scientists have dared (since Thales, Democritus, Plato's Timaeus, and
4
Aristarchus) to create myths, or conjectures, or theories, which are in striking contrast
to the everyday world of common experience, yet able to explain some aspects of this
world of common experience. Galileo pays homage to Aristarchus and Copernicus
precisely because they dared to go beyond this known world of our senses: ‘I cannot’,
he writes, ‘express strongly enough my unbounded admiration for the greatness of
mind of these men who conceived [the heliocentric system] and held it to be true . . .
,in violent opposition to the evidence of their own senses. . . .’ This is Galileo’s
testimony to the liberalizing force of science. Such theories would be important even
if they were no more than exercises for our imagination. But they are more than this,
as can be seen from the fact that we submit them to severe tests by trying to deduce
from them some of the regularities of the known world of common experience-i.e.
by trying to explain these regularities. And these attempts to explain the known by the
unknown (as I have described them elsewhere) have immeasurably extended the realm
of the known. They have added to the facts of our everyday world the invisible air, the
antipodes, the circulation of the blood, the worlds of the te1escope and the
microscope, of electricity, and of tracer atoms showing us in detail the movements of
matter within living bodies. All these things are far from being mere instruments: they
are witness to the intellectual conquest of our world by our minds.
But there is another way of looking at these matters. For some, science is still
nothing but glorified plumbing, glorified gadget-making-‘mechanics’; very useful, but
a danger to true culture, threatening us with the domination of the near-illiterate (of
Shakespeare’s ‘mechanicals’). It should never be mentioned in the same breath as
literature or the arts or philosophy. Its professed discoveries are mere mechanical
inventions, its theories are instruments-gadgets again, or perhaps super-gadgets. It
cannot and does not reveal to us new worlds behind our everyday world of
appearance; for the physical world is just surface: it has no depth. The world is just what
it appears to be. Only the scientific theories are not what they appear to be. A scientific theory
neither explains nor describes the world; it is nothing but an instrument.
I do not present this as a complete picture of modern instrumentalism, although
it is a fair sketch, I think, of part of its original philosophical background. Today a
much more important part of it is, I am well aware, the rise and self-assertion of the
modern ‘mechanic’ or engineer. Still, I believe that the issue should be seen to lie
between a critical and adventurous rationalism-the spirit of discovery-and a narrow
and defensive creed according to which we cannot and need not learn or understand
more about our world than we know already. A creed, moreover, which is
incompatible with the appreciation of science as one of the greatest achievements of
the human spirit.
Such are the reasons why I shall try, in this paper, to uphold at least part of the
Galilean view of science against the instrumentalist view. But I cannot uphold all of it.
There is a part of it which I believe the instrumentalists were right to attack. I mean
the view that in science we can aim at, and obtain, an ultimate explanation by essences. It is
5
in its opposition to this Aristotelian view (which I have called ‘essentialism’) that the
strength and the philosophical interest of instrumentalism lies. Thus I shall have to
discuss and criticize two views of human knowledge-essentialism and instrumentalism. And
I shall oppose to them what I shall call the third view-what remains of Galileo’s view
after the elimination of essentialism, or more precisely, after allowance has been made
for what was justified in the instrumentalist attack.
3. THE FIRST VIEW: ULTIMATE EXPLANATION BY ESSENCES
Essentialism, the first of the three views of scientific theory to be discussed, is part of
the Galilean philosophy of science. Within this philosophy three elements or
doctrines which concern us here may be distinguished. Essentialism (our ‘first view’)
is that part of the Galilean philosophy which I do not wish to uphold. It consists of a
combination of the doctrines (2) and (3). These are the three doctrines:
1. The scientist aims at finding a true theory or description of the world (and especially
of its regularities or ‘laws'), which shall also be an explanation of the observable
facts. (This means that a description of these facts must be deducible from
the theory in conjunction with certain statements, the so-called ‘initial
conditions’.)
This is a doctrine I wish to uphold. It is to form part of our ‘third view’.
2. The scientist can succeed in finally establishing the truth of such theories beyond all
reasonable doubt.
This second doctrine, I think, needs correction. All the scientist can do, in
my opinion, is to test his theories, and to eliminate all those that do not
stand up to the most severe tests he can design. But he can never be quite
sure whether new tests (or even a new theoretical discussion) may not lead
him to modify, or to discard, his theory. In this sense all theories are, and
remain hypotheses: they are conjecture (doxa) as opposed to indubitable
knowledge (episteme).
3. The best, the truly scientific theories, describe the ‘essences’ or the ‘essential natures’ of
things-the realities which lie behind the appearances. Such theories are neither in
need nor susceptible of further explanation: they are ultimate explanations, and
to find them is the ultimate aim of the scientist.
This third doctrine (in connection with the second) is the one I have called
‘essentialism’. I believe that like the second doctrine it is mistaken.
Now what the instrumentalist philosophers of science, from Berkeley to Mach,
Duhem, and Poincaré, have in common is this. They all assert that explanation is not
an aim of physical science, since physical science cannot discover ‘the hidden essences
of things’. The argument shows that what they have in mind is what I call ultimate
explanationix. Some of them, such as Mach and Berkeley, hold this view because they
do not believe that there is such a thing as an essence of anything physical: Mach,
6
because he does not believe in essences at all; Berkeley, because he believes only in
spiritual essences, and thinks that the only essential explanation of the world is Gad.
Duhem seems to think (on lines reminiscent of Kant15) that there are essences but that
they are undiscoverable by human science (though we may, somehow, move towards
them); like Berkeley he thinks that they can be revealed by religion. But all these
philosophers agree that (ultimate) scientific explanation is impossible. And from the
absence of a hidden essence which scientific theories could describe they conclude
that these theories (which clearly do not describe our ordinary world of common
experience) describe nothing at all. Thus they are mere instruments.16 And what may
appear as the growth of theoretical knowledge is merely the improvement of
instruments.
The instrumentalist philosophers therefore reject the third doctrine, i.e. the
doctrine of essences. (I reject it too, but for somewhat different reasons.) At the same
time they reject, and are bound to reject, the second doctrine; for if a theory is an
instrument, then it cannot be true (but only convenient, simple, economical,
powerful, etc.). They even frequently call the theories ‘hypotheses’; but they do not,
of course, mean by this what I mean: that a theory is conjectured to be true, that it is a
descriptive though possibly a false statement; although they do mean to say that
theories are uncertain: ‘And as to the usefulness of hypotheses’, Osiander writes (at
the end of his preface), ‘nobody should expect anything certain to emerge from
astronomy, for nothing of the kind can ever come out of it.’ Now I fully agree that
there is no certainty about theories (which may always be refuted); and I even agree
that they are instruments, although I do not agree that this is the reason why there can
be no certainty about theories. (The correct reason, I believe, is simply that our tests
can never be exhaustive.) There is thus a considerable amount of agreement between
my instrumentalist opponents and myse1f over the second and third doctrines. But
over the first doctrine there is complete disagreement.
To this disagreement I shall return later. In the present section I sha11 try to
criticize (3), the essentialist doctrine of science, on lines somewhat different from the
arguments of the instrumentalism which I cannot accept. For its argument that there
can be no ‘hidden essences’ is based upon its conviction that there can be nothing hidden
(or that if anything is hidden it can be only known by divine revelation). From what I
said in the last section it will be clear that I cannot accept an argument that leads to the
rejection of the claim of science to have discovered the rotation of the earth, or atomic
nuclei, or cosmic radiation, or the ‘radio stars’.
I therefore readily concede to essentialism that much is hidden from us, and,
that much of what is hidden may be discovered. (I disagree profoundly with the spirit
of Wittgenstein's dictum, ‘The riddle does not exist’.) And I do not even intend to
criticize those who try to understand the ‘essence of the world’. The essentialist
doctrine I am contesting is solely the doctrine that science aims at ultimate explanation; that
7
is to say, an explanation which (essentially, or by its very nature) cannot be further
explained, and which is in no need of any further explanation.
Thus my criticism or essentialism does not aim at establishing the non-existence
of essences; it merely aims at showing the obscurantist character of role played by the
idea of essences in the Galilean philosophy or science (down to Maxwell, who was
inclined to believe in them but whose work destroyed this belief). In other words my
criticism tries to show that whether essences exist or not the belief in them does not
help us in any way and indeed is likely to hamper us; so that there is no reason why
the scientist should assume their existence.
This, I think, can be best shown with the help of a simple example – the
Newtonian theory of gravity.
The essentialist interpretation of Newtonian theory is due to Roger Cotes.
According to him Newton discovered that every particle of matter was endowed with
gravity, i.e. with an inherent power or force to attract other matter. It was also endowed
with inertia – an inherent power to resist a change in its state of motion (or to retain
the direction and velocity of its motion). Since both gravity and inertia inhere in each
particle of matter it follows that both must be strictly proportional to the amount of
matter in a body, and therefore to each other; hence the law of proportionality of inert
and gravitating mass. Since gravity radiates from each particle we obtain the square
law of attraction. In other words, Newton's laws of motion simply describe in
mathematical language the state of affairs due to the inherent properties of matter:
they describe the essential nature of matter.
Since Newton's theory described in this way the essential nature of matter, he
could explain the behaviour of matter with its help, by mathematical deduction. But
Newton's theory, in its turn, is neither capable of, nor in need of, further explanation,
according to Cotes – at least not within physics. (The only possible further
explanation was that God has endowed matter with these essential properties.)
This essentialist view of Newton's theory was on the whole the accepted view
until the last decades of the nineteenth century. That it was obscurantist is clear: it
prevented fruitful questions from being raised, such as, ‘What is the cause of gravity?’ or
more fully, ‘Can we perhaps explain gravity by deducing Newton's theory, or a good
approximation of it, from a more general theory (which should be independently
testable)?’
Now it is illuminating to see that Newton himself had not considered gravity as
an essential property of matter (although he considered inertia to be essential, and also,
with Descartes, extension). It appears that he had taken over from Descartes the view
that the essence of a thing must be a true or absolute property of the thing (i.e. a
property which does not depend on the existence of other things) such as extension,
or the power to resist a change in its state of motion, and not a relational property, i.e.
a property which, like gravity, determines the relations (interactions in space) between
8
one body and other bodies. Accordingly, he strongly felt the incompleteness of this
theory, and the need to explain gravity. ‘That gravity’, he wrote, ‘should be innate,
inherent, and essential to matter, that one body may act upon another at a distance... is
to me so great an absurdity that I believe no man who has in philosophical matters a
competent faculty of thinking can ever fall into it.’
It is interesting to see that Newton condemned here, in anticipation, the bulk of
his followers. To them, one is tempted to remark, the properties of which they had
learned in school appeared to be essential (and even self-evident), although to
Newton, with his Cartesian background, the same properties had appeared to be in
need of explanation (and indeed to be almost paradoxical).
Yet Newton himself was an essentialist. He had tried hard to find an acceptable
ultimate explanation of gravity by trying to deduce the square law from the
assumption of a mechanical push-the only kind of causal action which Decartes had
permitted, since on1y push could be explained by the essential property of all bodies,
extension. But he failed. Had he succeeded we can be certain that he would have
thought that his problem was finally solved – that he found the ultimate explanation
of gravity. But here he would have been wrong, The question, ‘Why can bodies push
one another ?’ can be asked )as Leibniz first saw), and it is even an extremely fruitful
question. (We now believe that they push one another because of certain repulsive
electric forces.) But Cartesian and Newtonian essentialism, especially if Newton had
been successful in his attempted explanation of gravity, might have prevented this
question from ever being raised.
These examples, I think, make it clear that the belief in essences (whether true
or false) is liable to create obstacles to thought – to the posing of new and fruitful
problems. Moreover, it cannot be part of science (for even if we should, by a lucky
chance, hit upon a theory describing essences, we could never be sure of it), But a
creed which is likely to lead to obscurantism is certainly not one of those extra-
scientific beliefs (such as a faith in the power of critical discussion) which a scientist
need accept.
This concludes my criticism of essentialism.
9
The function of a theory may here be described as follows. a, b are phenomena;
A, B are the corresponding realities behind these appearances; and α, β the
descriptions or symbolic representations of these realities. E are the essential
properties of A, B, and ε is the theory describing E. Now from ε and α we can deduce
β; this means that we can explain, with the help of our theory, why a leads to, or is the
cause of, b.
A representation of instrumentalism can be obtained from this schema simply
by omitting (i), i.e. the universe of the realities behind the various appearances. α then
directly describes a, and β directly describes b; and ε describes nothing – it is merely
an instrument which helps us to deduce β from α. (This may be expressed by saying –
as Schlick did, following Wittgenstein – that a universal law or a theory is not a proper
statement but rather ‘a rule, or a set of instructions, for the derivation of singular
statements from other singular statements’).
This is the instrumentalist view. In order to understand it better we may again
take Newtonian dynamics as an example. a and b may be taken to be two positions of
two spots of light (or two positions of the planet Mars); α and β are the corresponding
formulae of the formalism; and ε is the theory strengthened by a general description
of the solar system (or by a ‘model’ of the solar system). Nothing corresponds to ε in
the world (in the universe ii): there simply are no such things as attractive forces, for
example. Newtonian forces are not entities which determine the acceleration of
bodies: they are nothing but mathematical tools whose function is to allow us to
deduce β from α.
No doubt we have here an attractive simplification, a radical application of
Ockham's razor. But although this simplicity has converted many to instrumentalism
(for example Mach) it is by no means the strongest argument in its favour.
Berkeley’s strongest argument for instrumentalism was based upon his
nominalistic philosophy of language. According to this philosophy the expression
‘force of attraction’ must be a meaningless expression, since forces of attraction can
never be observed. What can be observed are movements, not their hidden alleged
‘causes’. This is sufficient, on Berkeley’s view of language, to show that Newton's
theory cannot have any informative or descriptive content.
10
Now this argument of Berkeley’s may perhaps be criticized because of the
intolerably narrow theory of meaning which it implies. For if consistently applied it
amounts to the thesis that all dispositional words are without meaning. Not only
would Newtonian ‘attractive forces’ be without meaning, but also such ordinary
dispositional words and expressions as ‘breakable’ (as opposed to ‘broken’), or ‘capable
of conducting electricity’ (as opposed to ‘conducting electricity’). These are not names
of anything observable, and they would therefore have to be treated on a par with
Newtonian forces. But it would be awkward to classify all these expressions as
meaningless, and from the point of view of instrumentalism it is quite unnecessary to do
so: all that is needed is an analysis of the meaning of dispositional terms and
dispositional statements. This will reveal that they have meaning. But from the point
of view of instrumentalism they do not have a descriptive meaning (like non-
dispositional terms and statements). Their function is not to report events, or
occurrences, or ‘incidents’, in the world, or to describe facts. Rather, their meaning
exhausts itself in the permission or licence which they give us to draw inferences or to
argue from some matters of fact to other matters of fact. Non-dispositional statements
which describe observable matters of fact (‘this leg is broken’) have cash value, as it
were; dispositional statements, to which belong the laws of science, are not like cash,
but rather like legal ‘instruments’ creating rights to cash.
One need only proceed one step further in the same direction, it appears, in
order to arrive at an instrumentalist argument which it is extremely difficult, if not
impossible, to criticize; for our whole question-whether science is descriptive or
instrumental – is here exposed as a pseudo-problem.
The step in question consists, simply, in not only allowing meaning – an
instrumental meaning – to dispositional terms, but also a kind of descriptive meaning,
Dispositional words such as ‘breakable’, it may be said, certainly describe something;
for to say of a thing that it is breakable is to describe it as a thing that can be broken.
But to say of a thing that it is breakable, or soluble, is to describe it in a different way,
and by a different method, from saying that it is broken or dissolved; otherwise we
should not use the suffix 'able'. The difference is just this – that we describe, by using
dispositional words, what may happen to a thing (in certain circumstances).
Accordingly, dispositional descriptions are descriptions, but they have nevertheless a
purely instrumental function. In their case, knowledge is power (the power to
foresee). When Galileo said of the earth ‘and yet, it moves’, then he uttered, no doubt,
a descriptive statement. But the function or meaning of this statement turns out
nevertheless to be purely instrumental: it exhausts itself in the I help it renders in
deducing certain non-dispositional statements.
Thus the attempt to show that theories have a descriptive meaning besides their
instrumental meaning is misconceived, according to this argument; and the whole
problem-the issue between Galileo and the Church-turns out to be a pseudo-
problem.
11
In support of the view that Galileo suffered for the sake of a pseudo-problem it
has been asserted that in the light of a logically more advanced system of physics
Galileo’s problem has in fact dissolved into nothing. Einstein’s general principle, one
often hears, makes it quite clear that it is meaningless to speak of absolute motion,
even in the case of rotation; for we can freely choose whatever system we wish to be
(relatively) at rest. Thus Galileo’s problem vanishes. Moreover, it vanishes precisely
for the reasons given above. Astronomical knowledge can be nothing but knowledge
of how the stars behave; thus it cannot be anything but the power to describe and
predict our observations; and since these must be independent of our free choice of a
co-ordinate system, we now see more clearly why Galileo’s problem could not
possibly be real.
I shall not criticize instrumentalism in this section, or reply to its arguments,
except the very last one – the argument from general relativity. This argument is based
on a mistake. From the point of view of general relativity, there is very good sense-
even an absolute sense-in saying that the earth rotates: it rotates in precisely that sense in
which a bicycle wheel rotates. It rotates, that is to say, with respect to any chosen local
inertial system. Indeed relativity describes the solar system in such a way that from
this description we can deduce that any observer situated on any sufficiently distant
freely moving physical body (such as our moon, or another planet, or a star outside
the system) would see the earth rotating, and could deduce, from this observation,
that for its inhabitants there would be an apparent diurnal motion of the sun. But it is
clear that this is precisely the sense of the words ‘it moves’ which was at issue; for part
of the issue was whether the solar system was a system like that of Jupiter and his
moons, only bigger; and whether it would look like this system, if seen from outside.
On all these questions Einstein unambiguously supports Galileo.
My argument should not be interpreted as an admission that the whole question
can be reduced to one of observations, or of possible observations. Admittedly both
Galileo and Einstein intend, among other things, to deduce what an observer, or a
possible observer, would see. But this is not their main problem. Both investigate
physical systems and their movements. It is only the instrumentalist philosopher who
asserts that what they discussed, or , ‘really meant’ to discuss, were not physical
systems but only the results of possible observations; and that their so-called ‘physical
systems’, which appeared to be their objects of study, were in reality only instruments
for predicting observations.
12
section. I shall try, therefore, to force a clear decision on our problem by a different
approach – by way of an analysis of science rather than an analysis of language.
My proposed criticism of the instrumentalist view of scientific theories can be
summarized as follows.
Instrumentalism can be formulated as the thesis that scientific theories – the
theories of the so-called ‘pure’ sciences – are nothing but computation rules (or
inference rules); of the same character, fundamentally, as the computation rules of the
so-called ‘applied’ sciences. (One might even formulate it as the thesis that ‘pure’
science is a misnomer, and that all science is applied’.)
Now my reply to instrumentalism consists in showing that there are profound
differences between ‘pure’ theories and technological computation rules, and that
instrumentalism can give a perfect description of these rules but it is quite unable to
account for the difference between them and the theories. Thus instrumentalism
collapses.
The analysis of the many functional differences between computation rules (for
navigation, say) and scientific theories (such as Newton's) is a very interesting task,
but a short list of results must suffice here. The logical relations which may hold
between theories and computation rules are not symmetrical; and they are different
from those which may hold between various theories, and also from those which may
hold between various computation rules. The way in which computation rules are
tried out is different from the way in which theories are tested; and the skill which the
application of computation rules demands is quite different from that needed for their
(theoretical) discussion, and for the (theoretical) determination of the limits of their
applicability. These are only a few hints, but they may be enough to indicate the
direction and the force of the argument.
I am now going to explain one of these points a little more fully, because it gives
rise to an argument somewhat similar to the one I have used against essentialism.
What I wish to discuss is the fact that theories are tested by attempts to refute them
(attempts from which we learn a great deal), while there is nothing strict1y
corresponding to this in the case of technological rules of computation or calculation.
A theory is tested not merely by applying it, or by trying it out, but by applying it
to very special cases – cases for which it yields results different from those we should
have expected without that theory, or in the light of other theories. In other words we
try to select for our tests those crucial cases in which we should expect the theory to
fail if it is not true. Such cases are ‘crucial’ in Bacon’s sense; they indicate the cross-
roads between two (or more) theories. For to say that without the theory in question
we should have expected a different result implies that our expectation was the result
of some other (perhaps an older) theory, however dimly we may have been aware of
this fact. But while Bacon believed that a crucial experiment may establish or verify a
theory, we shall have to say that it can at most refute or falsify a theory. It is an attempt
13
to refute it; and if it does not succeed in refuting the theory in question – if, rather, the
theory is successful with its unexpected prediction – then we say that it is
corroborated by the experiment. (It is the better corroborated the less expected, or the
less probable, the result of the experiment has been.)
Against the view here developed one might be tempted to object (following
Duhem) that in every test it is not only the theory under investigation which is
involved, but also the whole system of our theories and assumptions – in fact, more or
less the whole of our knowledge – so that we can never be certain which of all these
assumptions is refuted. But this criticism overlooks the fact that if we take each of the
two theories (between which the crucial experiment is to decide) together with all this
background knowledge, as indeed we must, then we decide between two systems
which differ only over the two theories which are at stake. It further overlooks the fact
that we do not assert the refutation of the theory as such, but of the theory together
with that background knowledge; parts of which, if other crucial experiments can be
designed, may indeed one day be rejected as responsible for the failure. (Thus we may
even characterize a theory under investigation as that part of a vast system for which we
have, however vaguely, an alternative in mind, and for which we try to design crucial
tests.)
Now nothing sufficiently similar to such tests exists in the case of instruments
or rules of computation. An instrument may break down, to be sure, or it may
become outmoded. But it hardly makes sense to say that we submit an instrument to
the severest tests we can design in order to reject it if it does not stand up to them:
every air frame, for example, can be ‘tested to destruction’, but this severe test is
undertaken not in order to reject every frame when it is destroyed but to obtain
information about the frame (i.e. to test a theory about it), so that it may be used
within the limits of its applicability (or safety).
For instrumental purposes of practical application a theory may continue to be
used even after its refutation, within the limits of its applicability: an atronomer who
believes that Newton’s theory has turned out to be false will not hesitate to apply its
formalism within the limits of its applicability.
We may sometimes be disappointed to find that the range of applicability of an
instrument is smaller than we expected at first; but this does not make us discard the
instrument qua instrument – whether it is a theory or anything else. On the other
hand a disappointment of this kind means that we have obtained new information
through refuting a theory – that theory which implied that the instrument was
applicable over a wider range.
Instruments, even theories in so for as they are instruments, cannot be refuted, as we
have seen. The instrumentalist interpretation will therefore be unable to account for
real tests, which are attempted refutations, and will not get beyond the assertion that
different theories have different ranges of application. But then it cannot possibly account for
scientific progress. Instead of saying (as I should) that Newton’s theory was falsified
14
by crucial experiments which failed to falsify Einstein’s, and that Einstein’s theory is
therefore better than Newton’s, the consistent instrumentalist will have to say, with
reference to his ‘new’ point of view, like Heisenberg: ‘It follows that we do not say
longer: Newton’s mechanics is false. . . . Rather, we now use the following -
formulation: Classical mechanics ... is everywhere exactly “right” where its concepts
can be applied.’
Since ‘right’ here means ‘applicable’, this assertion merely amounts to saying,
‘Classical mechanics is applicable where its concepts can be applied’ – which is not
saying much. But be this as it may, the point is that by neglecting falsification, and stressing
application, instrumentalism proves to be as obscurantist philosophy as essentialism. For it is only
in searching for refutations that science can hope to learn and to advance. It is only in
considering how its various theories stand up to tests that it can distinguish between
better and worse theories and so find a criterion of progress.
Thus a mere instrument for prediction cannot be falsified. What may appear to
us at first as its falsification turns out to be no more than a rider cautioning us about
its limited applicability. This is why the instrumentalist view may be used ad hoc for
rescuing a physical theory which is threatened by contradictions, as was done by Bohr
(if I am right in my interpretation, given in section ii, of his principle of
complementarity). If theories are mere instruments of prediction we need not discard
any particular theory even though we believe that no consistent physical interpretation
of its formalism exists.
Summing up we may say that instrumentalism is unable to account for the
importance to pure science of testing severely even the most remote implications of
its theories, since it is unable to account for the pure scientist’s interest in truth and
falsity. In contrast to the highly critical attitude requisite in the pure scientist, the
attitude of instrumentalism (like that of applied science) is one of complacency at the
success of applications. Thus it may well be responsible for the recent stagnation in
quantum theory. (This was written before the refutation of parity.)
15
contributed more to the present vogue for instrumentalism than anything else; but he
later repented.
I trust that physicists will soon come to realize that the principle of
complementarity is ad hoc, and (what is more important) that its only function is to
avoid criticism and to prevent the discussion of physical interpretations; though
criticism and discussion are urgently needed for reforming any theory. They will then
no longer believe that instrumentalism is forced upon them by the structure of
contemporary physical theory.
Anyway, instrumentalism is, as I have tried to show, no more acceptable than
essentialism. Nor is there any need to accept either of them, for there is a third view.
This ‘third view’ is not very startling or even surprising, I think. It preserves the
Galilean doctrine that the scientist aims at a true description of the world, or of some
of its aspects, and at a flue explanation of observable facts; and it combines this
doctrine with the non-Galilean view that though this remains the aim of the scientist,
he can never know for certain whether his findings are true, although he may
sometimes establish with reasonable certainty that a theory is false.
One may formulate this ‘third view’ of scientific theories briefly by saying that
they are genuine conjectures – highly informative guesses about the world which although
not verifiable (i.e. capable of being shown to be true) can be submitted to severe
critical tests. They are serious attempts to discover the truth. In this respect scientific
hypotheses are exactly like Goldbach’s famous conjecture in the theory of numbers.
Goldbach thought that it might possibly bee true; and it may well be true in fact, even
though we do not know, and may perhaps never know, whether it is true or not.
I shall confine myself to mentioning only a few aspects of my ‘third view’, and
only such aspects as distinguish it from essentialism and instrumentalism; and I shall
take essentialism first.
Essentialism looks upon our ordinary world as mere appearance behind which it
discovers the real world. This view has to be discarded once we become conscious of
the fact that the world of each of our theories may be explained, in its turn, by further
worlds which are described by further theories – theories of a higher level of
abstraction, of universality, and of testability. The doctrine of an essential or ultimate
reality collapses together with that of ultimate explanation.
Since according to our third view the new scientific theories are, like the old
ones, genuine conjectures, they are genuine attempts to describe these further worlds.
Thus we are led to take all these worlds, including our ordinary world, as equally real;
or better, perhaps, as equally real aspects or layers of the real world. (If looking
through a microscope we change its magnification, then we may see various
completely different aspects or layers of the same thing, all equally real.) It is thus
mistaken to say that my piano, as I know it, us real, while its alleged molecules and
atoms are mere ‘logical constructions’ (or whatever else may be indicative of their
16
unreality); just as it is mistaken to say that atomic theory shows that the piano of my
everyday world is an appearance only – a doctrine which is clearly unsatisfactory once
we see that the atoms in their turn may perhaps be explained as disturbances, or
structures of disturbances, in a quantized field of forces (or perhaps of probabilities).
All these conjectures are equal in their claims to describe reality, although some of
them are more conjectural than others.
Thus we shall not, for example, describe only the so-called ‘primary qualities’ of
a body (such as its geometrical shape) as real, and contrast them as the essentialists
once did, with its unreal and mere1y apparent ‘secondary qualities’ (such as colour).
For the extension and even the shape of a body have since become objects of explanation
in terms of theories of a higher level; of theories describing a further and deeper layer
of reality – forces, and fields of forces – which are related to the primary qualities in
the same way as these were believed by the essentialists to be related to the secondary
ones; and the secondary qualities, such as colours, are just as real as the primary ones -
though our colour experiences have to be distinguished from the colour properties of
the physical things, exactly as our geometrical-shape-experiences have to be
distinguished from the geometrical-shape-properties of the physical things. From our
point of view both kinds of qualities are equally real – that is, conjectured to be real;
and so are forces, and fields or forces, in spite of their undoubted hypothetical or
conjectural character.
Although in one sense of the word ‘real’, all these various levels are equally real,
there is another yet closely related sense in which we might say that the higher and
more conjectural levels are the more real ones-in spite of the fact that they are more
conjectural. They are, according to our theories, more real (more stable in intention,
more permanent) in the sense in which a table, or a tree, or a star, is more real than
any of its aspects.
But is not just this conjectural or hypothetical character of our theories the
reason why we should not ascribe reality to the worlds described by them? Should we
not (even if we find Berkeley’s ‘to be is to be perceived’ too narrow) call only those
states of affairs ‘real’ which are described by true statements, rather than by conjectures which
may turn out to be false? With these questions we turn to the discussion of the
instrumentalist doctrine, which with its assertion that theories are mere instruments
intends to deny the claim that anything like a real world is described by them.
I accept the view (implicit in the classical or correspondence theory of truth)
that we should call a state of affairs ‘real’ if, and only if, the statement describing it is
true. But it would be a grave mistake to conclude from this that the uncertainty of a
theory, i.e. its hypothetical or conjectural character, diminishes in any way its implicit
claim to describe something real. For every statement s is equivalent to a statement
claiming that s is true. And as to s being a conjecture, we must remember that, first of
all, a conjecture may be true, and thus describe a real state of affairs. Secondly, if it is
false, then it contradicts some real state of affairs (described by its true negation).
17
Moreover, if we test our conjecture, and succeed in falsifying it, we see very clearly
that there was a reality – something with which it could clash.
Our falsifications thus indicate the points where we have touched reality, as it
were. And our latest and best theory is always an attempt to incorporate all the
falsifications ever found in the field, by explaining them in the simplest way; and this
means (as I have tried to show in The Logic of Scientific Discovery, sections 31 to 46) in
the most testable way.
Admittedly, if we do not know how to test a theory we may be doubtful whether
there is anything at all of the kind (or level) described by it; and if we positively know
that it cannot be tested, then our doubts will grow; we may suspect that it is a mere
myth, or a fairy-tale. But if a theory is testable, then it implies that events of a certain kind
cannot happen; and so it asserts something about reality. (This is why we demand that the
more conjectural a theory is, the higher should be its degree of testability.) Testable
conjectures or guesses, at any rate, are thus conjectures or guesses about reality; from
their uncertain or conjectural character it only follows that our knowledge concerning
the reality they describe is uncertain or conjectural. And although only that is certainly
real which can be known with certainty, it is a mistake to think that only that is real
which is known to be certainly real. We are not omniscient and, no doubt, much is
real that is unknown to us all. It is thus indeed the old Berkeleian mistake (in the form
‘to be is to be known’) which still underlies instrumentalism.
Theories are our own inventions, our own ideas; they are not forced upon us,
but are our self – made instruments of thought: this has been clearly seen by the
idealist. But some of these theories of ours can clash with reality; and when they do,
we know that there is a reality; that there is something to remind us of the fact that
our ideas may be mistaken. And this is why the realist is right.
Thus I agree with essentialism in its view that science is capable of real discoveries,
and even in its view that in discovering new worlds our intellect triumphs over our
sense experience. But I do not fall into the mistake of Parmenides – of denying reality
to all that is colourful, varied, individual, indeterminate, and indescribable in our
world.
Since I believe that science can make real discoveries I take my stand with
Galileo against instrumentalism. I admit that our discoveries are conjectural. But this
is even true of geographical explorations. Columbus’ conjectures as to what he had
discovered were in fact mistaken; and Peary could only conjecture – on the basis of
theories – that he had reached the Pole. But these elements of conjecture do not make
their discoveries less real, or less significant.
There is an important distinction which we can make between two kinds of
scientific prediction, and which instrumentalism cannot make; a distinction which is
connected with the problem of scientific discovery. I have in mind the distinction
between the prediction of events of a kind which is known, such as eclipses or
18
thunderstorms on the one hand and, on the other hand, the prediction of new kinds of
events (which the physicist calls ‘new effects’) such as the prediction which led to the
discovery of wireless waves, or of zero-point energy, or to the artificial building up of
new elements not previously found in nature.
It seems to me clear that instrumentalism can account only for the first kind of
prediction: if theories are instruments for prediction, then we must assume that their
purpose must be determined in advance, as with other instruments. Predictions of the
second kind can be fully understood only as discoveries.
It is my belief that our discoveries are guided by theory, in these as in most other
cases, rather than that theories are the result of discoveries ‘due to observation’; for
observation itself tends to be guided by theory. Even geographical discoveries
(Columbus, Franklin, the two Nordenskjölds, Nansen, Wegener, and Heyerdahl’s
Kon-Tiki expedition) are often undertaken with the aim of testing a theory. Not to be
content with offering predictions, but to create new situations for new kinds of tests:
this is a function of theories which instrumentalism can hardly explain without
surrendering its main tenets.
But perhaps the most interesting contrast between the ‘third view’ and
instrumentalism arises in connection with the latter’s denial of the descriptive
function of abstract words, and of disposition-words. This doctrine, by the way,
exhibits an essentialist strain within instrumentalism – the belief that events or
occurrences or ‘incidents’ (which are directly observable) must be, in a sense, more
real than dispositions (which are not).
The ‘third view’ of this matter is different. I hold that most observations are
more or less indirect, and that it is doubtful whether the distinction between directly
observable incidents and whatever is only indirectly observable leads us anywhere. I
cannot but think that it is a mistake to denounce Newtonian forces (the ‘causes of
acceleration’) as occult, and to try to discard them (as has been suggested) in favour of
accelerations. For accelerations cannot be observed any more directly than forces; and
they are just as dispositional: the statement that a body’s velocity is accelerated tells us
that the body’s velocity in the next second from now will exceed its present velocity.
In my opinion all universals are dispositional. If ‘breakable’ is dispositional, so is
‘broken’, considering for example how a doctor decides whether a bone is broken or
not. Nor should we call a glass ‘broken’ if the pieces would fuse the moment they
were put together: the criterion of being broken is behaviour under certain conditions.
Similar1y, ‘red’ is dispositional: a thing is red if it is able to reflect a certain kind of
light – if it ‘looks red’ in certain situations. But even ‘looking red’ is dispositional. It
describes the disposition of a thing to make onlookers agree that it looks red.
No doubt there are degrees of dispositional character: ‘able to conduct electricity’
is dispositional in a higher degree than ‘conducting electricity now’ which is still very
highly dispositional. These degrees correspond fairly closely to those of the
19
conjectural or hypothetical character of theories. But there is no point in denying
reality to dispositions, not even if we deny reality to all universals and to all states of
affairs, including incidents, and confine ourselves to using that sense of the word ‘real’
which, from the point of view of ordinary usage, is the narrowest and safest: to call
only physical bodies ‘real’, and only those which are neither too small nor too big nor
too distant to be easily seen and handled.
For even then we should realize that ‘every description uses… universals; every
statement has the character of a theory, a hypothesis. The statement, “Here is a glass of
water,” cannot be (completely) verified by any sense-experience, because the
universals which appear in it cannot be correlated with any particular sense-
experience. (An “immediate experience” is only once “immediately given”; it is unique.)
By the word “glass”, for example, we denote physical bodies which exhibit a certain
law-like behaviour; and the same holds of the world “water”.’
I do not think that a language without universals could ever work; and the use of
universals commits us to asserting, and thus (at least) to conjecturing, the reality of
dispositions – though not of ultimate and inexplicable ones, that or essences. We may
express all this by saying that the customary distinction between ‘observational terms’ (or
‘non-theoretical terms’) and theoretical terms is mistaken, since all terms are theoretical to
some degree, though some are more theoretical than others; just as we said that all
theories are conjectural, though some are more conjectural than others.
But if we are committed, or at least prepared, to conjecture the reality of forces,
and of fields of forces, then there is no reason why we should not conjecture that a die
has a definite propensity (or disposition) to fall on one or another of its sides; that this
propensity can be changed by loading it; that propensities of this kind may change
continuously; and that we may operate with fields of propensities, or of entities which
determine propensities. An interpretation of probability on these lines might allow us
to give a new physical interpretation to quantum theory – one which differs from
the purely statistical interpretation, due to Born, while agreeing with him that
probability statements can be tested only statistically.35 And this interpretation may,
perhaps, be of some little help in our efforts to resolve those grave and challenging
difficulties in quantum theory which today seem to imperil the Galilean tradition.
NOTES
i
I emphasize here the diurnal as opposed to the annual motion of the sun because it was the
theory of the diurnal motion which clashed with Joshua 10, 12.f., and because the explanation of
the diurnal motion of the sun by the motion of the earth will be one of my main examples in
what follows. (This explanation is, of course, much older than Copernicus even than
Aristarchus-and it has been repeatedly re-discovered; for example by Oresme.)
20
ii
‘. . . Galileo will act prudently’, wrote Cardinal BelIarmino (who had been one of the
inquisitors in the case against Giordano Bruno) ‘. . . if he will speak hypothetically, IX
suppositione ...: to say that we give a better account of the appearances by supposing the earth to
be moving, and the sun at rest, than we could if we used eccentrics and epicycles is to speak
properly; there is no danger in that, and it is all that the mathematician requires.’ Cf. H. Grisar,
Galileistudien, 1882, Appendix ix. (Although this passage makes Bellarmino one of the
founding fathers of the epistemology which Osiander had suggested some time before and
which I am going to call ‘instrumentalism’, Bellarmino-unlike Berkeley was by no means a
convinced instrumentalist himself, as other passages in this letter show., He merely saw in
instrumentalism one of the possible ways dealing with inconvenient scientific hypotheses. The
same might well be true of Osiander. See also note 6 below.)
iii
The quotation is from Bacon's criticism of Copernicus in the ovum Organum, II, 36. In the
next quotation (from De revoltitionibus) I have translated the term ‘verisimilis’ by ‘like the
truth’. It should certainly not be translated here by ‘probable’; for the whole point here is the
question whether Copernicus' system is, or is not, similar in structure to the world; that is,
whether it is similar to the truth, or truth like. The question of degrees of certainty or probability
does not arise. For the important problem of truthlikeness of verisimilitude, see also ch. 10
below, especially sections iii, x, and xiv; and Addendum6,
iv
See also ch. 6, below
v
The most important of them are Mach, Kirchhoff, Hertz, Duhem, Poincaré, Bridgman and
Eddington-all instrumentalists in various ways.
vi
Duhem, in his famous series of papers. ‘Sözein to phainómena’ (Ann.de philos. chrétienne,
anneé 79, tom 6, 1908, nos. 2 to 6), claimed for instrumentalism a much older and much more
ilIustrious ancestry than is justified by the evidence. For the postulate that, with a our causal
hypotheses, we ought to ‘explain the observed facts’, rather than ‘do violence to them by trying
to squeeze or fit them into our theories’ (Aristotle, De Caelo, 293a25;296b6; 297a4, b24ff; Met.
1073b37, 1074al) has little to do with the instrumentalist thesis that our theories cannot explain
the facts). Yet this postulate is essentially the same as that we ought to ‘preserve the
phenomena’ or ‘save’ them ([dia-]sõzein ta phainnmena). The phrase seems to be connected
with the astronomical branch of the Platonic School tradition. (See especially the most
interesting passage on Aristarchus in Plutarch’s De Faeie in Orbe Lunae, 923a; see also 933a
for the ‘confirmation of the cause’ by the phenomena, and Cherniss’ note a on p.168 of his
edition of this work of Plutarch’s; furthermore, Simplicius, commentaries on De Caelo where
the phrase occurs e.g. on pp. 497 1.21, 506 1.10, and 488 1.23 f, of Heiberg’s edition, in
commentaries on De Caelo 293a4 and 292b10.) We may well accept Simplicius' report that
Eudoxus, under Plato's influence, in order to account for the observable phenomena of planetary
motion, set himself the task of evolving an abstract geometrical system of rotating spheres to
which he did not attribute any physical reality. (There seems to be some resemblance between
this programme and that of the Epinomis, 990-1, where the study of abstract geometry-of the
21
theory of the irrationals, 990d-991 b-is described as a necessary preliminary to planetary theory;
another such preliminary is the study of number-i.e. the odd and the even, 990c.) Yet even this
would not mean that either Plato or Eudoxus accepted an instrumentalist epistemology: they
may have consciously (and wisely) confined themselves to a preliminary problem.
vii
But they seem to have forgotten that Mach was led by his instrumentalism to fight against
atomic theory-a typical example of the obscurantism of instrumentalism which is the topic of
section 5 below.
viii
I have explained Bohr’s ‘Principle of Complementarity’ as I understand it after many years of
effort. No doubt I shall be told that my formulation of it is unsatisfactory. But if so I am in good
company; for Einstein refers to it as ‘Bohr’s principle of complementarity, a sharp formulation
of which . . . I have been unable to attain despite much effort which I have expended on it.’
Cf. Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. by P. A. Schilpp, 1949, p. 674
ix
The issue has been confused at times by the fact that the instrumentalist criticism of(ultimate)
explanation was expressed by some with the help of the formula: the aim of science is
description rather than explanation. But what was here meant by ‘description’ was the
description of the ordinary empirical world; and what the formula expressed, indirectly, 1was
that those theories which do not describe in this sense do not explain either, but are nothing but
convenient instruments to help us in the description of ordinary phenomena.
22