YOUNG, J. Nietzsche's Philosophy of Art
YOUNG, J. Nietzsche's Philosophy of Art
YOUNG, J. Nietzsche's Philosophy of Art
P H I L O S O P H Y OF ART
JULIAN YOUNG
Department of Philosophy,
University of Auckland
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Acknowledgments page xi
List of abbreviations xiii
Introduction
1 Schopenhauer 5
2 The Birth of Tragedy 25
3 Human, All-too-human 58
4 The Gay Science 92
5 Twilight of the Idols "7
Epilogue 148
Notes 153
Texts and translations 166
Index 167
IX
Acknowledgments
XI
Abbreviations
A The Anti-Christ
BGE Beyond Good and Evil
BT The Birth of Tragedy
CIV The Case of Wagner
D Dawn {Daybreak)
EH Ecce Homo
GM On the Genealogy of Morals
GS The Gay Science
HHi Human, All-too-human
HH ii a Assorted Opinions and Maxims
HH lib The Wanderer and his Shadow
NCW Nietzsche Contra Wagner
TI Twilight of the Idols
WB Richard Wagner at Bayreuth
WP The Will to Power
Z Thus Spoke Zarathustra
KG Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, ed. G.Colli and M.
Montinari in 30 vols.
xin
Introduction
Schopenhauer
5
6 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
in this regard. In The Gay Science, for instance, he refers to
Schopenhauer's "immortal doctrine" of the "instrumental [i.e.
practical] character" of human thought and perception [GSgc)]).
Notice that the biological route to idealism modifies the character
of Kantian, strictly "transcendental," idealism. For, according to
Kant, it is not merely the world of common sense but, more
comprehensively, " n a t u r e , " the entire world of space and time, that
is ideal. Yet an argument to the ideality of the common-sense image
of the world that is grounded in an appeal to proto-Darwinian facts
concerning the biological function of the brain seems to presuppose
that a scientific, and hence natural, image of the world presents it as
it really, in itself, is. The non-natural an sich of Kant's metaphysics
is transposed into a natural, albeit esoteric, domain. 2
species and hence, if its form is such as to express that Idea clearly,
it is beautiful. In general, however, art is more beautiful than nature
since the artist's control over form is greater than that of nature. He
is able to provide a " purer repetition" {WR n y p . 407) of nature's
forms and hence to "express clearly what nature only stammers"
( W Ä i , p . 222).
The impetus behind this account of aesthetic representation is the
rejection of naturalism. Art does not mirror nature, Schopenhauer
insists, but rather eliminates, obscures or deemphasizes everything in
an object or action that is not to its purpose. That purpose - a
purpose, he holds, which art shares with philosophy - is the
revelation of ultimate and universal truth; " t h e true nature of
things, of life and of existence" {WR 1, p. 406). It is the emphasis of
this purpose, not the introduction of Plato's ontology, which, I
believe, provides the rationale for Schopenhauer's use of Plato's
terminology. Plato, that is, pursuing " t h e ancient quarrel between
philosophy and poetry," condemns art for seducing the mind away
from the quest for truth with a play of sensuous surfaces.
Schopenhauer's aim is to rebut Plato's critique of art, " o n e of the
greatest errors... of that great m a n " {WR 1, p. 212), by redescribing
art in precisely the terms which Plato reserved for philosophy. Art
does not baffle but rather, in its own way, prosecutes the quest for
ultimate knowledge.
its antagonist. But this by no means requires that the lyric poet,
say Archilochus, "should see nothing of the phenomenon of the
man Archilochus." For Archilochus qua lyric " g e n i u s " is distinct
from Archilocus qua "non-genius," qua "passionately inflamed,
loving and hating m a n . " This is so because, through a "mystical
self-abnegation," he has become " t h e only truly existent and eternal
self resting at the basis of things." From that perspective he may
retain objectivity but still express his "primordial [i.e. universal]
pain symbolically in the symbol of the man Archilochus" (ibid.).
(Notice that Nietzsche offers here precisely the reconciliation of
objectivity and expressiveness which, in section 8, I argued to be
implicit in Schopenhauer's general theory of art.)
also the effect of this development upon the mind of the hero, an
effect which culminates in a moment of metaphysical, world-
transcending insight. Schopenhauer cites Bellini's Norma in this
connection (WR i, p. 436), but one might think al§o of the film of
Marcel PagnoPs, so it seems to me, deeply Schopenhauerian Manon
des Sources: of the harvest of catastrophe reaped by Papet from his
narrow, greedy willing and of his sudden transformation into a
metaphysical figure of resignation and dignity as he learns that the
man his rapaciousness has destroyed is, in fact, his own yearned-for
son.
i Nietzsche's first book, The Birth of Tragedy > was published in 1872,
the same year as that in which the foundation stone was laid for the
Festival Theater in Bayreuth. Politically and emotionally it is, like
his next substantial discussion of art, Richard Wagner at Bayreuth
(1876), dominated by the figure of Richard Wagner. The work is not
only dedicated to Wagner (to whom, at this period, Nietzsche was
accustomed to refer as Meister) but is conceived as, above all, a work
of propaganda on behalf of the Wagnerian cause. (If one attempted
to summarize the essence of its complex argument the following
might be offered: we stand in need of a "solution" to the suffering
and absurdity of life. The Greeks found such a solution in the art of
their great tragedians. Our only hope for a solution - given the
untenability of Christianity in the modern age - lies in the rebirth of
such art in the music-dramas of Richard Wagner.) Nietzsche was
dedicated to Wagner's cause and made proposals, both before and
after the publication of The Birth, to abandon his professorship at
Basle in order to work exclusively for the realization of the theater at
Bayreuth.
Philosophically, however, the figure of greatest importance for the
work is Arthur Schopenhauer. This is in no way inconsistent with its
Wagnerianism, for the Wagner Nietzsche came to know (they first
met at the end of 1868), the Wagner who had completed his whole
musico-dramatic ceuvre save for Götterdämmerung (1874) and Parsifal
(1882), had been, since his discovery of Schopenhauer in 1854,
himself dominated by the philosophy of the great pessimist.
Nietzsche himself discovered Schopenhauer in 1865 and became
an immediate disciple. In letters of the following year he spoke of
"my Schopenhauer" and described himself and Schopenhauer as
"often the same thing." This passion, it is clear, is what first
attracted him to Wagner: " I have found a m a n , " he wrote of
25
26 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
5 What is The Birth about? Nietzsche gave the book two alternative
titles: The Birth of Tragedy (in the first edition, The Birth of Tragedy
out of the Spirit of Music) and Hellenism and Pessimism. These indicate
its two central theses in the statement of each of which the celebrated
(but elusive) distinction between the "Apollonian" and the
"Dionysian" plays a crucial role. As a first approximation, these
theses may be stated as follows. The first, " t h e birth-of-tragedy
thesis" I shall call it, asserts that Greek tragedy came into being
through the union of Apollonian and Dionysian elements. It " d i e d "
through the elimination of the Dionysian from Greek drama at the
hands of Euripides acting under the baleful influence of Socrates.
The second thesis, which I shall call " t h e Hellenism-and-pessimism
thesis," asserts that although vividly sensitive (BT<$, 6) to the " terror
and horror of existence" (BT 3) the Greeks were nevertheless able
to survive and even thrive, psychologically speaking, through the
effect of their art - through, more specifically, the effects of their two
types of art, Apollonian and Dionysian art.
Stated in this way, the argument of The Birth has the air of thin-
blooded scholarly detachment that one would expect from an author
who was still Professor of Greek at Basle. Actually, however, the
book is far removed from any such spirit for, in reality, it is engaged,
evaluative, prescriptive, short on footnotes (Kaufmann's generous
supply rather spoils this effect), long on fancy, fanciful to the point
of falsification. The reason for this is that its primary concern is not
The Birth of Tragedy 3*
to provide an historically accurate account of the Greeks and their
culture at all. Its concern lies, rather, with us and our culture,
Nietzsche's speculative account of the rise and fall of Greek art and
culture having importance only as a "polished mirror'' (HH na,
218) in which we can see aspects of our own culture reflected and
clarified: The task of the classicist, he wrote in section 7 of the
unpublished " W e Philologists," is that of "understanding his own age
better by means of the classical world. This demotion of classical
scholarship, by a supposed professional in the field, from an end in
itself into a means for understanding modern life and culture - his
demand that it be " r e l e v a n t " - goes a considerable distance towards
explaining the scholarly fury with which the work was first received. 3
In reality, it seems to me, Nietzsche's first thesis is not, in its most
fundamental intention, a genetic thesis about Greek tragedy at all
but rather an analytic and evaluative thesis about great art in
general. The highest form of art, that is art which, seen in the
"perspective of life" (BT 2, 5), is of the greatest service (as with
classical scholarship and all forms of theoretical activity, Nietzsche
always insists that art has value only to the degree that helps us in
the practical task of living life), is a "fraternal u n i o n " in which,
though " t h e Dionysian predominates," "Dionysus speaks the
language of Apollo and Apollo speaks the language of Dionysus."
When this happens " t h e highest goal of tragedy and of all art is
attained" (BT 21, 24; my emphasis). Greek tragedy, Nietzsche
holds, provides a paradigm example of such art and for this reason
it merits close study. The fundamental purpose of The Birth,
however, is to argue not the greatness of Greek tragedy but rather
that we have, finally, another instance of the pattern of greatness
first exemplified in the works of Sophocles and Aeschylus - the
music-drama of Richard Wagner. Hence, Nietzsche holds, though
our culture is "Socratic," devoid of the Dionysian, we can yet hope
for its regeneration through the music which is to sound from
Bayreuth.
With regard to the Hellenism-and-pessimism thesis the important
point is that it is not just the Greeks but we, 4 too, who confront the
pain and absurdity (BT 7) of existence. Hence the Greek art-
solutions to pessimism were not only of interest to them but are of
vital concern to us. Fundamentally, that is, the Hellenism-and-
pessimism thesis is a recommendation as to how we should overcome
pessimism.
32 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
The remainder of this chapter falls into five main parts: in the first
(sees. 6-7) I attempt to understand the Apollonian-Dionysian
dichotomy; in the second (sees. 8-9) the birth-of-tragedy thesis; in
the third (sees. 10-13) the Hellenism-and-pessimism thesis; in the
fourth (sees. 14-18) I attempt to establish my thesis concerning the
Schopenhauerian, that is pessimistic, character of the work; I
conclude (sees. 19-21) with some remarks concerning Richard Wagner
at Bayreuth, a work that can be seen as something of a postscript to The
Birth.
enjoyment of the magnificence of its sweep and style one must avoid
empathy, avoid identification with the suffering of its victims. This,
Nietzsche holds, is what happens in the Apollonian outlook: the
"mirror of appearance" (Schein), he says, prevents the Apollonian
artist from "becoming one and fused with his figures" (ibid.). We
are, as it were, so dazzled by the beauty of the Homeric figures that
we cannot see the inner reality of their suffering. The Apollonian
outlook is characterized by an externality, a profound superficiality. 14
(Schopenhauer makes a similar observation about the Homeric
world: objects and events are portrayed, he says, with a unique
"objectivity," are untouched, that is, by human feelings and moods
[PPn, p. 444]-)
Playing with Life - The facility and frivolity of the Homeric fantasy was
necessary for soothing the immoderately passionate disposition and over-
subtle intellect of the Greeks and temporarily banishing them. When their
intellect speaks, how cruel and bitter life appears! They do not deceive
themselves, but they deliberately and playfully embellish life with lies.
Simonides advised his compatriots to take life as a game, they were only too
familiar with its painful seriousness (for the misery of mankind is among the
favourite themes for song among the gods), and they knew that even misery
could become a source of enjoyment solely through art. As a punishment for
this insight, however, they were so plagued by a delight in telling stories
that it was hard for them to desist from lies and deception in the course of
everyday life -just as all poetical people take a delight in lying, a delight
that is moreover quite innocent. The neighbouring nations were no doubt
sometimes reduced to despair by it. [HH i, 154].)
The Birth of Tragedy 45
13 The Apollonian " veiling" of the horrors of life strikes one as a
somewhat fragile prophylactic against pessimism. Though it may
seduce one into a general valuing of life, its "superficiality" appears
to leaves one unprotected against suffering that thrusts itself upon
one in a personal and unavoidable way. But Nietzsche does not
represent it as an ideal. The solution he favors is the Dionysian
solution, the solution offered by Greek tragedy. This, he says,
belongs to a higher stage of Greek culture and offers a " m o r e
profound" world-view than that offered by Apollonian art (BT 10).
What then is the Dionysian solution? Nietzsche says that whereas
Apollonian art tries to convince us of the joy of existence by a
glorification of phenomenal reality, Dionysian art "teaches us that
we are to seek this joy not in phenomena but behind t h e m " (BT 17).
It brings us, that is to say, a certain "metaphysical comfort" for the
"terrors of individual existence" (ibid.). How does it do this? This
question is the question of Nietzsche's account of the "tragic effect,"
the question of why, paradoxically, we derive pleasure from,
voluntarily subject ourselves to, confrontations with, indeed in a
certain sense, experiences of, the painful and catastrophic in life.
The general character of Nietzsche's answer to this question is
clear. In Dionysian art, in Greek tragedy in particular, the
destruction of the tragic hero is presented in a way that is exulting:
though forced to witness the tragic catastrophe " w e are not to
become rigid with fear: a metaphysical comfort tears us momentarily
from the bustle of changing figures. We really are, for a brief
moment, the primodial being itself" (ibid.).
It seems to me clear, in spite of attempts by the later Nietzsche and
others to suggest that his account of the tragic effect is entirely
original (BT, "Attempt at a Self-Criticism," 6), that this is a version
of Schopenhauer's account of the tragic effect as our highest
experience of the "feeling of the sublime" - as indeed, in The Birth,
Nietzsche admits: the "artistic taming of the horrible" is, he says,
"the sublime" (BT 7). Our tragic joy consists in an at least
momentary escape from the terror of individual human existence, in
an intimation of our "higher," suprahuman destiny: tragedy " i n the
person of the tragic hero... knows how to redeem us from the greedy
thirst for this existence, and with an admonishing gesture... reminds
us of another existence and a higher pleasure for which the tragic
hero prepares himself by means of his destruction not by means of his
triumphs" (BT 21).
Unlike Schopenhauer, however, who reports the sublime effect
46 Nietzsche's philosophy offurt
but never really attempts an explanation of how it occurs (see ch. i,
sec. 13 above), Nietzsche attempts such an explanation, at least with
respect to Greek tragedy. Some of its details are obscure, but it is
clear that the crucial idea is that the Greek audience, though (as in
Schopenhauer's account of the experience of the sublime) partially
identifying with the individual threatened by tragic destruction - it
"shudders at the sufferings which will befall the h e r o " (BT 22) -
has, as its primary identification, the chorus.
Nietzsche suggests that the singing of the chorus (the original
prototype of tragedy, the drama being, as it were, born out of it at
a later date [BT 7]) "nullifies" the principium individuationis (ibid.),
draws the hitherto soberly Apollonian spectator into the Dionysian
world. From this perspective he experiences w i t h j ^ the annihilation
of the tragic hero. As, that is, the barbarians celebrated their ecstatic
absorption into the primal oneness in acts of real violence performed
on real individuals, so the Greek audience performed the same act
symbolically (the first "artistic jubilee" of the Dionysian impulse
[see sec. 7 above]). Tragedy offers, as it were, a symbolic sacrifice to
Dionysus. A joy which appears to rest on cruelty, appears to be
Schadenfreude, is in reality, an exuberant affirmation of one's supra-
individual identity that resembles the burning of banknotes as an
expression of sudden accession to great wealth.
Nietzsche says that tragedy offers us " a profound and [note this
word] pessimistic view of the world. It offers " t h e conception of
individuation as the primal cause of evil" but also " the joyous hope
that the spell of individuation may be broken in augury of a restored
oneness" (BT 10). And he speaks in apocalyptic terms of the
yearning of the Dionysian initiates for a " rebirth of Dionysus, which
we must now dimly conceive as the end of individuation" (ibid.). But
if this is the character of the tragic effects, why did the Greeks not
lapse into Schopenhauerian " resignationism " (BT, " Attempt at a
Self-Criticism," 6), a pessimistic nausea, and " Buddhistic negation
of the will"? Social organization, action, in particular political
action, that is, demands the world of Apollonian individuation: a
distinction between actor and that which is acted upon, a distinction,
in the case of the defense of the state, between us and them. But
Dionysian man knows both the futility of action - that it can change
nothing " i n the eternal nature of things" - and the joy of a higher,
non-Apollonian state. It surely follows, then, that "from [Dionysian]
orgies a people can take one path only, the path to Indian
The Birth of Tragedy 47
Buddhism" (BT21). And yet the Greeks acted: among things, they
defeated the Persians. How was this possible?
Nietzsche answers by saying that situated between the Indian
culture of actionless contemplation on the one side and the Roman
culture of action and assertion on the other, the Greeks "exhausted
themselves neither in ecstatic brooding nor in a consuming chase
after worldly power and worldly h o n o u r " but succeeded, at least
during the short period of their high tragedies, in producing a
synthesis of Indian passivity and Roman assertiveness, a third form
of culture both "fiery and contemplative" (BT 21). Through
tragedy, that is, we are brought tidings of a "higher existence," a
"metaphysical comfort" which "stimulates, purifies and dis-
charges" our feelings of nausea at our habitation of the world of
individuals (ibid.). Now, however, the Apollonian part of tragedy
must be brought into play. Through it we are subject to the "noble
deception " (ibid.) that the meaning of the play concerns only the fate
of an individual in a world of individuality: the tragic hero as it were
"relieves us of the b u r d e n " of Dionysian insight (ibid.). Even the
author, as we have seen, cannot properly understand the meaning of
his work (BT 17).
The same is true of Wagner's Tristan. No completely musical soul
would be able to experience the third act as absolute music with
"expiring in a spasmodic unharnessing of all the wings of the soul"
(BT 21). 15 Fortunately, however, the Apollonian drama exists to
restore " t h e almost shattered individual with the healing balm of
illusion" (BT 17). Tristan wakes up from metaphysico-sexual
reverie and so do we, unable to understand the metaphysical
meaning of our musical experience. The effectiveness of Dionysian
art, therefore, is that while on the one hand affirming to us our
ultimate deliverance from the pain and anxiety of individuality, on
the other ^ as if recognizing that "action requires the veil of
illusion" (BT 7) - it acts like a fairy godmother and draws a veil of
forgetfulness over what we have experienced. In this way we are
returned to the world strangely comforted but yet able to act.
we individuals are not the creator of the world but "merely images
and artistic projections for the true author, and that we have our
highest dignity in our significance as [his] works of a r t " (BT 5). We
resemble soldiers painted on a canvas of a battle scene (ibid.). O u r
protest that the world should have been kinder to us is as laughable
as their protest would be.
As aesthetic phenomenon, then, the world is an object of pleasure;
beautiful, "justified," affirmable. But to whom is it justified? Not,
clearly, to individual human beings, but rather to the world creator.
There is no suggestion here at all that humans find or can find their
life to be pleasurable or justified. To suggest otherwise would be to
suggest that because a concentration camp "justifies" itself to its
sadistic (or perhaps merely playfully mad) commandant as a
pleasurable " e n t e r t a i n m e n t " (BT6), so too must the inmates find
it justified. If Nietzsche's account of the tragic effect is right, human
beings can, with luck, be transported briefly out of the role of
protagonist in the tragedy of life and into that of its "sole author and
spectator" (ibid.). But this does nothing to justify the life of an
inmate to an inmate. And such a justification indeed - Nietzsche is
quite explicit - is not offered. The world, he says, evincing an artist's
megalomania of truly Wagnerian proportions, was not created "for
our betterment or education" (BT 5). Consequently, justification
from our perspective is something we have no right to demand.
It is possible that we have misunderstood Nietzsche's Dionysi-
anism by taking the discussion too literally, too metaphysically?
Should we not perhaps 2 0 take metaphysics as metaphor and
understand The Birth to take the Dionysian to be not really a
metaphysical, but rather a,psychological, state? On this interpretation,
the "end of individuation" is not a matter of absorption into a
higher metaphysical domain but rather the achievement of a state of
love for and security with one's fellow human beings - Schopen-
hauerian Gemeinschaß (see ch. sec. 5), in other words. On this
view Nietzsche's Dionysianism would not be an escape from, denial
of, the human self and life, but rather an affirmation of the higher
potentialities of that life and self.
The answer is that while it is possible to reconstruct Nietzsche in this
way, to derive from The Birth inspiration for a Nietzschtfarc (or, more
correctly, Schopenhauerian) ethics of altruism, it is not possible
correctly to interpret The Birth in this way. For two reasons. First,
because, as we will see in the next chapter, the later Nietzsche's
The Birth of Tragedy 53
critique of the postulation, intimation of, or yearning for, a
" metaphysical world," whether it be in religion, art, or philosophy,
a critique begun in his " positivistic " years, is very clearly a self-
critique: he describes the metaphysical interpretation of life with an
authenticity and intimacy that only a former inhabitant of that
interpretation could achieve. Indeed, he tells us this in the already-
quoted (n. 19 above) passage in £arathustra, a passage that can refer
only to The Birth: " A t one time Zarathustra too cast his delusion
beyond man, like all the afterworldly. The work of a suffering and
tortured god. The world then seemed to m e . . . " (£1, 3). T o view The
Birth's metaphysics as mere metaphor deprives Nietzsche of an object
for this self-critique. The second reason is that, as Schopenhauer
realized - and as Nietzsche, given his close acquaintance with
Schopenhauer cannot have failed to realize too - altruistic ide-
ntification with the totality of human lives does not solve the problem
of pessimism. If I identify - empathize, that is - with humanity in
general then, though the quality of my suffering may change, given
that the wisdom of Silenus was a problem to start with, it remains a
problem: if human life is in general a confrontation with horror and
absurdity, then it remains so notwithstanding my solidarity with the
numerous other individuals who find themselves in the same
predicament. (One is not the less likely to drown just because there
are others in the lifeboat.) Indeed, if Schopenhauer is right,
identification with others increases one's awareness of the horror of life
(see ch. 1, sec. 5). Since, therefore, overcoming pessimism is the
problem for The Birth, it is important to resist the temptation to read
Nietzsche's Dionysian solution as a matter of identifying with other
human beings. Rather, one identifies with a wonhuman being, the
primal unity, or "will-to-live" which celebrates, says yes to, not the
inexhaustibility of human life but rather "its own inexhaustibility"
(see sec'. 16 above; my emphasis), the wanton pleasure of its own
eternally boyish existence as the creator-spectator of the fate of the
human flies (see A 48).
Human, All-too-human
58
Human, All-too-human 59
i) and gone too, as we will see, is Schopenhauer's pessimism.
Stylistically, the book marks a liberation from the nineteenth
century. Gone are the long, heavy, humorless passages of overripe
prose that marked The Birth of Tragedy. In the short, dry, witty
aphorisms that replace them we escape and breathe, in fact, for the
first time, the air of the modern world.
8 How does art fall within the scope of this spiritual spring-cleaning
that is to produce the self-love of the "free spirit"? Why, that is, does
art invite and perpetuate the metaphysical interpretation of
existence ?
As has already been intimated,
Art raises its head when the religions relax their hold. It takes over a host
of moods and feelings engendered by religion, lays them to its heart and
itself grows more profound and soulful, so that it is now capable of
communicating exultation and enthusiasm as it formerly could not. The
wealth of religious feelings, swollen to a torrent, breaks forth again and
again and seeks to conquer new regions; but the growth of the
Enlightenment, undermined the dogmas of religion, and inspired a
fundamental distrust of them; so that the feelings expelled from the sphere
of religion by the Enlightenment throw themselves into art... Wherever we
perceive... higher, gloomier colouring, we can assume that dread of spirits,
the odour of incense and shadows of churches are still adhering to them.
( / / / / I , 150)
(Note the stark contrast between this and the demand in The Birth
for the "desecularization" of society [BT 23; cf. ch. 2, sec. 14],) Art,
in other words, enables us to enjoy religious sentiment without the
need to subscribe to any conceptual content (see HHi, 131) - a point
not only admitted but emphasized as constituting its central value
by, in particular, Kant. Art in a secular age provides, as it were, a
catacomb in which the religious habit of mind can continue to exist.
For what it offers is religious feeling without cognitive responsibility.
We have, says Nietzsche, in a penetrating and surely self-analytical
remark about the romantic imagination, a tendency to ontologize
the intentional objects of " d e e p " and serious feelings, to assume, as
66 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
does astrology, that what we have "essentially at h e a r t " must
constitute also " t h e essence and heart of things" (HH i, 4). But the
objects of the quasi-religious feelings engendered by art are so
intangible and vague that they constitute no challenge to the
accepted verities of a secular age.
Above all, music provides a home for the continued existence of the
religious feeling. (It comes as no surprise, given that in The Birth it
was viewed as the metaphysical art, that it is now viewed with
particular distrust.) " A r t , " says Nietzsche,
makes the thinker's heart heavy. - How strong the metaphysical need is, and
how hard nature makes it to bid it in a final farewell, can be seen from the
fact that even when the free spirit has divested himself of everything
metaphysical the highest effects of art can easily set the metaphysical
strings, which have long been silent or indeed snapped apart, vibrating in
sympathy; so it can happen, for example, that a passage in Beethoven's
Ninth Symphony will make him feel he is hovering above the earth in a
dome of stars with the dream of immortality in the heart: all the stars seem
to glitter around him and the earth seems to sink further and further away.
- If he becomes aware of being in this condition he feels a profound stab in
the heart and sighs for the man who will lead him back to his lost love
whether she be called religion or metaphysics. It is in such moments that
his intellectual probity is put to the test. (HH 1, 153)
ideals out of the mass of material presented by past and present life
we are discussing the "transfiguration" of reality - the activity
which defines Apollonian art. Notice, however, that though
signposting art employs the familiar Apollonian techniques of
selecting, "concealing and reinterpreting" ( / / / / i i a , 174) and so on,
its old associations of " l i e " and "illusion" have been discarded.
Apollonian art has become " h o n e s t " because it has ceased to make
truth-claims. In The Birth, that is, the Apollonian artist, as it were,
held up a distorting mirror to nature and said (mendaciously) " the
world is thus." Now, however, she holds up the same mirror but
says: " m a k e yourself t h u s ! " (In terms of a Wittgensteinian
distinction: the "sentence-radical" is the same but the mood-
indicator has changed.)
17 What kind of art signposts the future? Not, we have seen, the art
of other-worlds. Only this-worldly art can construct the future of this
world. (Not musical art either, so, at least some of the time, it seems.
Since according to section 171 music is always backward-looking -
"all truly meaningful music is a swan-song" - it seems to be
excluded from future-oriented activity.) And not the art (about
which more will be said shortly) which consists in " t h e barbaric if
enthralling spluttering out of hot and motley things from a chaotic,
unruly soul." For the image of the "great and beautiful soul" can be
embodied only in forms that are "harmonious and well-pro-
portioned." The poems, therefore, of artists who signpost the future
An excuse for many a fault- The ceaseless desire to create on the part of the
artist, together with his ceaseless observaton of the world outside him
prevents him becoming better and more beautiful as a person, that is to say,
from creating himself ...he possesses only a fixed quantitfy of strength: that
of it which he expends upon himself- how could he at the same time expend
it on his work? - and the reverse.
And in section 174 he emphasizes that " a r t is above and before all
Human, All-too-human 83
supposed to beautify life, thus making us ourselves endurable, if
possible pleasing to others."
Is it possible to reconcile these two themes? Section 174 attempts
to do so by making it clear that Nietzsche stands not for the abolition
of art, but is concerned, rather, to oppose the deification of " t h e art
of works of art," to set it in its proper place as an " a p p e n d a g e " to
the art of living. A man or society, he says, who possesses an "excess"
of beautifying power, will, in the end, "discharge" it in works of art
as well as in life. The mistake, however, is to believe that " t h e art of
works of art is the true art out of which life is to be improved and
transformed." Life, rather, is to be transformed by applying artistic
powers to it directly. Art is the "dessert," not the main course.
Nietzsche's position here seems to rest on the Schopenhauerian
perception of the artistic genius as someone endowed with
exceptional energy (see WR 11, p. 377). It seems that, in spite of the
suggestion in section 102 that everyone has only a limited quantity
of energy, the exceptional person has in fact energy enough to create
herself as a work of art (this is a notion we shall explore in detail in
the next chapter) and also to create artworks in the literal sense. So
the overall position seems to be that the true artist legitimately
engages in the production of artworks and these will have value as
"signposts" to the future. Ordinary people, on the other hand, are
required to devote their limited creative energies to their lives and
are not to delude themselves that either by producing minor
artworks or by having elevated experiences in art galleries are they
doing anything of life-transforming significance.
But this attempt to present a consistent position is a failure. For if
the providing of "signposts" to the future is really an important,
artwork-justifying function, then regardless of the question of whether
or not their production involves the diversion of energy from the
beautification of life, the artist, surely, is legitimately employed in
their production. Many people have taken the view that, often at
least, the price of great art is a deficient or diseased personality. If
that is so then the price of art is lack of " b e a u t y " in the artist's life.
But that, surely, if art has the function of creating ideals or values for
the future, is a price that may be worth paying. The run of
humanity, that is, in the endeavor to beautify, to give shape and
coherence to their lives stand in need of archetypes that only the
exceptional person, the artist, can provide. This, in a fine passage in
The Gay Science, Nietzsche came later to understand. The "con-
84 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
templative" type, the "poet," he says, sadly fancies that he is a mere
"spectator and listener who has been placed before the great visual
and acoustic spectacle that is life." But this is a "delusion." For it is
really the poet who keeps creating this life. Of course, he is different from the
actor of this drama, the so-called active type; but he is even less like a mere
spectator and festive guest in front of the stage. As a poet he certainly has
vis contemplativa and the ability to look back upon his work but at the same
time also and above all vis creativa which the active human being lacks,
whatever visual appearances and the faith of all the world may say. We
who think and feel at the same time are those who really continually fashion
something that had not been there before: the whole eternally growing
world of valuations, colours, accents, perspectives, scales, affirmations and
negations. This poem that we have invented is continually studied by so-
called practical human beings (our actors) who translate everything into
flesh and actuality, into the everyday. (GS 301)
22 The conclusion to be drawn from the reflections of the previous
section is that in Opinions contrary impulses are at work. On the one
hand, continuous in this respect with the debunking of the romantic
vision of art and the artist in Human, there is disposition to debunk
everything connected with " h i g h " art, with concert halls, art
galleries, and the like. (The examples he gives in section 174 of the
beautification of life through the direct application of the aesthetic
impulse - the creation of "social forms," "rules of decency,
cleanliness, politeness, of speaking and staying silent at the proper
t i m e " - have a humble, almost William Morris flavor to them.) On
the other hand, the theme of the artist as prophetic regenerator of
culture reappears in the work in a way that restores to the artist a
pedestal not that much lower than the one so recently removed.
Opinions is, with respect to art, an unresolved work.
With every Greek artist, poet and writer one has to ask: what is the new
constraint he has imposed upon himself and through which he charms his
contemporaries (so that he finds imitators) ? For that which we call
" i n v e n t i o n " (in metrics, for example) is always such a self-imposed fetter.
" D a n c i n g in chains," making things difficult for oneself and then spreading
over it the illusion of ease and facility - that is the artifice they want to
demonstrate to us. Already in Homer we can perceive an abundance of
inherited formulae and epic narrative rules within which he had to dance:
and he himself created additional new conventions for those who came after
him. This was the school in which the Greek poets were raised: firstly to
allow a multiplicity of constraints to be imposed upon one; then to devise
an additional new constraint, impose it upon oneself and conquer it with
charm and grace: so that both the constraint and its conquest are noticed
and admired, (ibid.)
27 In The Birth, we saw, the value of art lay in its capacity to bring
us "comfort" for (or else to disguise) the horror and terror of
existence. In Human Nietzsche loses (temporarily) the Schopen-
hauerian sense of life as a tormenting " r i d d l e " the idea that there
is a philosophical problem of pessimism is reduced to ashes by the
heat of scientific optimism. Yet there remains, of course, the
undeniable phenomenon of depression "distress of the soul" (D
269) as an individual phenomenon has to be acknowledged. The
difference is that it has lost its epistemological validation. It is no
longer a deep, truth-perceiving, philosophically justified state of
mind, but is, rather, a mere neurosis. With this Nietzsche is now
brisk, militaristic, and (as in Wanderer [see HH 11b, 1, 84])
physiological. He recommends "change of diet and hard physical
l a b o u r " (D 269). (This crudely physical approach contrasts sharply
with the, as it were, "talking c u r e " for depression that he discovers,
as we will see, in The Gay Science.)
Unfortunately, however, he continues, people resort to "means of
intoxication: to art, for example" as a cure for their distress (ibid.).
This, though perhaps alleviating the problem for a short time, in the
long term only exacerbates it. For as is the habit of drugs, it produces
both serious side-effects and dependency. One begins to identify
one's real life and self with one's intoxicated state and to view one's
ordinary existence as a drab impediment to access to one's real self.
In this way addicts (such as, for example, the " u n t i m e l y " author of
The Birth of Tragedy - the passage is unmistakably self-referential [see
BT, "Attempt at a Self-Criticism," 7]) qome to " h a r b o u r feelings of
revengefulness towards their environment, their age, their entire
w o r l d " (D 50).
In spite of the mark of deadly truth with which this passage,
Human, All-too-human 89
considered as phenomenology of a certain species of afflicted
consciousness, is stamped, it is time to enter a protest against the
general truth of the assertion which constitutes its heart; the assertion,
in Schopenhauerian language, that affirmation of a metaphysical
world always and inevitably entails denial of this one; in Nietzschean
language, the assertion that such affirmation is always and inevitably
"romantic."
In tone and content, the volume deserves its title. After having struggled
through a period of some years of intellectual crisis, its author has attained
a new philosophical and spiritual health, of the sort he describes at the fifth
book's end (382). He has become profoundly and joyfully affirmative of life
and the world and has discovered that "all the daring of the lover of
knowledge is permitted again" (343). He is in love with knowledge and
with life and the world, and with the humanity emerging out of them; for,
having earlier become hard and disillusioned by them, he has now become
newly appreciative of them. Thus he cheerfully and confidently sets out to
explore them as they stand revealed in the "new dawn" that has broken
in the aftermath of "the news that 'the old god is dead' " (343)x
92
The Gay Science 93
These two parts of the work thus bracket £arathustra (parts I - I I
appeared in 1883, part 111 in 1884, part iv in 1885) and Beyond Good
and Evil (1886).
The reason I make The Gay Science the center of this unity is that
all of the major ideas touching upon the topic of art which appear
in the works of this period are found first in it: in fact, in its first four
books. (The one exception to this, the critique of the K a n t -
Schopenhauer notion that aesthetic perception is "disinterested," I
shall reserve for discussion in chapter 5.) All the other works may be
regarded as commentaries on, elucidations of The Gay Science, It is
true that Nietzsche himself suggested that the latter could be
regarded as commentary on the yet-to-be-written ^arathustra2 but
the truth, so it seems at least to me, is if anything the reverse,
Thoughts which first appear in The Gay Science and, because it stands
so close to their creation, are expressed in difficult and unclear ways,
not uncommonly appear with much greater clarity and simplicity in
Zarathustra. Wissenschaftliche prose, strangely, finds its elucidation in
poetic fiction.
3 Let us begin at the beginning; with the title of the work. Why
should anyone entitle a book The Gay Science? Why should anyone
subtitle it la gaya scienza, a phrase of Provencal that refers to the
culture and poetry of the medieval troubadours; to their, as
Nietzsche describes it, gay, free, exuberant, childish, mocking,
dancing, light, floating spirit? Why insist- and insist, as Nietzsche
does, so repeatedly - on how infused and permeated by that spirit is
the book? Why preface and conclude the work with a set of poems
- as if in fear that someone might fail to get the point that in it the
spirit of the troubadours is reborn? A prudent reader, it seems to me
(a "philologist" or "psychologist" in Nietzsche's sense), ought to
suspect that someone who displays, parades their alleged gaiety so
insistently - and in the end tediously - is closely acquainted with
suffering and despair.
In the Preface (on which, since it was written last and therefore
constitutes Nietzsche's last word in the work, I shall place
considerable weight) Nietzsche admits to a past acquaintance with
suffering. The book is, he says, " nothing but a bit of merry-making
after a long privation," filled with the " intoxication of con-
valescence" (GS, Preface, 1) of one who has endured a "long slow
p a i n " (GS, Preface, 3). What we have to decide is how correctly this
pain is consigned to the past.
94 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
4 But let us first do away with metaphor. What is the "long slow
p a i n " to which Nietzsche refers? It is, in a word, the death of God,
an event which, though formally announced for the first time only
in section 125 of The Gay Science, was in fact acutely present to
Nietzsche from the very outset of his philosophical career. The pain
is the pain of confronting the "terror and horror," the "heart-
breaking and cruel character" of existence - " w h a t I desire most,"
he wrote to Heinrich von Stein in December 1882, "is a high point
from which I can see the tragic problem lying beneath me. I would
like to take away from human existence some of its heartbreaking
and cruel character" - without the "metaphysical comfort"
brought to us by theistic belief. The problem is suffering and our
vulnerability to it: not all suffering (not the pain of dentistry, for
example) but rather suffering for which we can discover no
redeeming purpose or justification, suffering that disposes us to view
life as "nauseating." Without God life appears to be " a b s u r d " and
(save for extinction) there appears to be no deliverance from it.
In The Birth of Tragedy, as we saw, Nietzsche discovered a
substitute for God in art. In experiencing tragic art we receive the
"metaphysical comfort" of becoming aware of our supraindividual
identity, our oneness with the "primal unity" that is the
metaphysical reality beneath the illusory world of individuality. In
Human, All-too-human, however, the idea of art as a substitute for
religion, the idea of a "metaphysical world" in both its overt and
covert manifestations, is exposed to ridicule and is demolished. The
world, as Nietzsche confronts it at the beginning of The Gay Science is
completely "naturalized," fully "dedeified" (GS 109). There is no
metaphysical redemption from its horrors.
9 But will the balloon fly for very long? The essence, after all, of
Nietzsche's solution to the riddle is self-deception, acting, role-
playing. Becoming an appearance to oneself, deplored in Wagner at
Bayreuth (WB 5), is now, it seems, just what is proposed. Repression,
the denial of desires and character traits, the pretense that traumatic
events of the past never happened, is seen now as a vital, life-saving
activity. But does this not lend a brittle, desperate, doomed quality
to Nietzsche's gaya scienza? Truth, as poor, silly Wilde's tragedy
exemplifies, cannot easily be kept at bay. And even if, for a time, it
can, the price exacted by such repression in terms of neurotic
symptoms is (if we believe Freud at all) a high one.
Another question to ask, however, is whether the advocacy of
profound superficiality really constitutes Nietzsche's last word by way
of a solution to the riddle. What gives force to this question - and
makes The Gay Science 3, very puzzling text to decipher - is that
although the Preface is dominated by the perceived need at all costs
to fly from, eradicate, the will to truth, the body of the work is
dominated by the attachment of tremendous value to "honesty," to
the "intellectual conscience" (GS 2, 335), to the avoidance ofthat
"suicide of reason" for which, in Beyond Good and Evil (229), he
condemns Pascal. Moreover, and most importantly, The Gay Science
is the place where the doctrine that being able to will the eternal
recurrence is the mark of the ideal stance towards the world receives
its first enunciation [GS 341). And the point of this doctrine, as we
The Gay Science IOI
will shortly see, is that ideally one should be able to accept, love, will
to recur all of the truth about the world, down to the very last detail.
II What does the Dionysian solution look like? In Beyond Good and
Evil Nietzsche couples the life of la gaya scienza with the Christian
interpretation of existence, as both species of profound superficiality.
Both the transcendentalization of existence by ''homines religiosi" and
the "impassioned and exaggerated worship o f ' p u r e forms' among
both philosophers and artists" illustrate, he says, " h o w much
wisdom there lies in the superficiality of men. The instinct that
preserves "these ["burnt children"] teaches them to be flighty, light
and false." (Notice that this coupling provides, given Nietzsche's
well-known antipathy to homo religiosus, a further reason for doubting
that la gaya scienza constitutes Nietzsche's final response to the
riddle.) Both, he continues, are products of artistry, artistry inspired
by "fear of truth," fear of an "incurable pessimism" that would
result were one to "get hold of a truth too soon." But he mentions,
too, another, nonsuperficial, truth-embracing approach to existence
that one could take were one "strong enough, hard enough, artist
io2 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
enough" (BGE 59). This indicates, firstly, that the Dionysian
solution will abandon the Apollonian " falsification " of the image of
life (ibid.), that it will be in some way "honest," and, secondly, that
it, too, will somehow involve artistry. As in The Birth of Tragedy,
therefore, we are provided with two ^-solutions to the riddle.
For the new year Today everybody permits himself the expression of his
wish and his dearest thought; hence I, too, shall say what it is that I wish
from myself today I want to learn more and more to see as beautiful what
is necessary in things beautiful. Amorfati: let that be my love henceforth!
I do not want to wage war against what is ugly. I do not want to accuse;
I do not even want to accuse those who accuse. Looking away [after the
fashion of the profoundly superficial] shall be my only negation. And in its
totality and greatness [alles in allem und grossen]: some day I wish to be only
a yes-sayer. (GS 276)
15 How can one possibly come to love, will the recurrence of,
everything that has happened? Section 276 of The Gay Science (quoted
in sec. 14 above) starts to tell us: one is " t o see as beautiful what is
necessary in things." The following section continues the thought.
Though there is no divine providence in the world we are to seek to
put in its place the vision of a "wonderful harmony," a "personal
providence." We are
to see how palpably always everything that happens to us turns out for the
best. Every day and every hour, life seems to have no other wish than to
prove this proposition again and again. Whatever it is, bad weather or
good, the loss of a friend, sickness, slander, the failure of some letter to
arrive, the spraining of an ankle, a glance into a shop, a counter-argument,
The Gay Science 105
the " artistic p l a n " ofthat nature as a whole. Neither can I view, let
us say, the mental damage that terminated my career as a
mathematical logician and turned me to the life of philosophy nor
the "counterargument" that turned me from a philosopher into a
peace activist as a benefit unless I have decided that being a
philosopher or a peace activist is what, fundamentally, I want to be.
To decide that some past event was a benefit presupposes and
commits me to certain views as to who I am, what my dominant
desires and goals are now. Thus the process of coming to love fate,
coming to will the eternal recurrence, demands, and incorporates
the construction of the self- the construction of an authentic, truth-
embracing self: becoming, in other words, who one is.
Notice that the process of creating this self is an artistic process, 13
a task of ordering the events in one's life that in some respects is
analogous to the writing of a Bildungsroman,14 a story of the growth
of personality from naivety to maturity, and in other respects is
analogous to the task of constructing a character that will engage the
esteem and attention of the reader. And notice, too, that in a clear
sense the creation of this self is more artistic (see sec. 11 above), more
of an artistic tour deforce than the creation of an inauthentic self. For
as we think of one scientific theory as better than another if it
comprehends a greater range of observational " d a t a " it makes sense
to think of art as more or less consummate according to the richness
of the " d a t a " that it accommodates.
Of course, the construction of a self such that all its past deeds and
experiences add up to the life of an attractive, fortunate self- a self
we can "esteem," "desire," view with " p l e a s u r e " (GS 78), " a t t a i n
satisfaction" with (GS 290), a self we like, indeed love being - is not
the only self one could construct. One could construct out of the
same set of facts an equally clear coherent and honest self that is the
victim of misfortune. ( " T h e world of the happy person is a different
one from the world of the unhappy person," writes Wittgenstein. But
it is not the "facts" that are different only the " l i m i t s " [Tractatus,
6.43].) T h a t way, however, lies the path to "nausea and suicide."
The construction of a self that we love to be is the one we need
because in it we find the solution to the problem of the riddle.
This life as you now live it and have lived it, you will have to live once more
and innumerable times more; and there will be nothing new in it, but every
pain and every joy and every thought and sigh and everything unutterably
small and great will have to return to you, all in the same succession and
sequence - even this spider and this moonlight between the trees.
Notice that the spider and the moonlight are treated here as, like my
pains and joys, parts of my biography. This can only be a shorthand
way of saying that the experience of the spider and of the moonlight
is part of my biography. If, then, I am to will the recurrence of not
just my life but of my exact life, I must will the recurrence of all of my
knowledge of world history. But if there are any world-historical
events I cannot will to recur then I cannot will the recurrence of my
knowledge of them. To will, then, the recurrence of my exact life I
must be able to will the recurrence of all those events in world history
I know about. The thought of the recurrence of my life and of the
world as seen from my perspective are equivalent. It follows that
bringing oneself to will the recurrence of one's exact life requires the
The Gay Science 109
19 What has health or its lack got to do with coming to a view of the
world in which the questionable is redeemed, the appearance that
I 10 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
life is a pit of reasonless pain dispelled? What, in other words, does
the Übermensch have that we lack?
Nietzsche's answer is: "energy." A "fullness," an "over-fullness of
life" an "overflowing energy that is pregnant with future." It is this
which brings it about that " T h e Dionysian god or man, cannot only
afford the sight of the terrible and questionable but even the terrible
deed and any luxury of destruction, decomposition, and negation. In
his case what is evil, absurd and ugly seems, as it were, permissible,
owing to an excess of procreating, fertilizing energies that can still
turn any desert into lush farmland" (GS 370). We, however, suffer,
to one degree or another, from "impoverishment of life" (ibid.). In the
Geneaology of Morals this is said to be a physiological state associated
with a coolness of the "affects," a slowness in the " t e m p o of life,"
and the absence of "certainty of life and of the future" (GM m, 25).
Why should energy be the key to willing the eternal recurrence?
And why should it be connected in some important way with the
future? What Nietzsche is confronting here, I believe, are the limits
to any redemption of the past which does not embrace the future.
There are, I think he is prepared to concede, atrocious events that
can be redeemed by nothing that is discoverable in past or present
experience. And for ordinary mortals that is the end of the matter:
the future is dark, and while it is not, perhaps, inconceivable that some
pattern in future history might present materials for the redemption
of those events, that is something of which we lack all "certainty."
Dionysian man, however, is different: he possesses such certainty.
What has this certainty, or its lack, to do with energy levels?
Nietzsche is pointing out, it seems to me, that with regard to certain
beliefs about the future it is inappropriate to regard them as based
on evidence or to demand that they should be thus based. Rather,
they are to be treated as aspects of a general orientation towards the
world that is a symptom of one's level of psychic energy. If, that is,
one's energy level is high one will feel not merely equal to whatever
exigencies may be thrown at one by fate but possessed of a surplus
of energy with which to master fate, mold it to one's will. One will
then be likely to subscribe to a set of beliefs expressing confidence in
a congruence between one's future and one's will. And by an
extension of confidence one will be likely to subscribe to a set of
more-or-less ungrounded beliefs concerning events over which, in
the normal sense, one has no personal control. A highly ebullient
Russian, for example, might (at least at the time of writing) be
The Gay Science
expected to be confident of both an orderly transition to liberal
democracy and of the continued integrity of the Soviet Union.
Those of low psychic energy, on the other hand, will feel unequal
to what fate is liable to throw at them and their vision of the future
will be (equally groundlessly) full of foreboding. Since they expect
no consolation in the future for present ills they will turn instead, in
one form or another, to other worlds. They will become " r o m a n t i c "
rather than "Dionysian" pessimists and will seek "rest, stillness,
calm seas, redemption ... through art... or intoxication, convulsions,
anesthesia and madness" (GS 370). 17 Or else, we might add, through
profound superficiality,
The Übermensch is an extreme case of the person of high energy. So
" overflowing " is she with energy that she is certain of the redemption
of presently unredeemed evils. Though she cannot always see what
these redemptions are, she has absolute faith that they will occur, an
absolute faith that enables her to " a t last cry [using Goethe's line]:
'life however it may be is g o o d ! ' " (HH1, 222). We, however, have
lived under the shadow of God for so long that we possess still a
theological cringe (see GS 285), a culturally transmitted taint of
" g u i l t " and "depression" (HH 1, 133). We lack a sense of our own
worth and power, we lack "self-love" and "self-valuation" (HH 1,
134), and cannot therefore believe in the future redemption of, as
yet, unredeemed events: because of our guilt we feel that there
cannot be redemption, that existence must be eternal " p u n i s h m e n t "
(£11, 20). As "convalescents," therefore, the only recourse for us is
profound superficiality, the remedy for convalescents. Only that can
rescue us from the riddle.
The focus of the passage is thus not metaphysics but the concept
of joy. If, Nietzsche is saying, you stand in the ideal relationship to
the world then you perceive all things to be interconnected not
because they are, of metaphysical necessity, so interconnected but
rather because standing in that relationship is a matter of accepting
the totality of things as constituting a beautiful, "perfect" (ibid.)
whole of which everything is an organic part and in which
problematic events stand in redemptive relationships to ones which
are not problematic. If, Nietzsche is saying, you ever "say Yes" to
anything you must "say Yes" to everything - not on account of the
metaphysical interconnectedness of all things but simply because if you
do not "say Yes" to everything then it is not, in Nietzsche's sense, " Y e s "
that you say. " J o y , " he writes, "wants everything eternally the
s a m e " (ibid.). If that is not what one wants then one's " Y e s " to life
(the cautious, qualified discerning " Y e s " of, as Nietzsche would be
likely to say, the scholar) is not the joyful " Y e s " that Nietzsche seeks.
The search for such a " Y e s " is manifested not just in the
dithyrambic ^arathustra but in The Gay Science too. Most people, he
complains in section 288, do not believe in "elevated moods" (hohe
Stimmungen). At best they believe in their lasting for a few moments,
" a t most a quarter of an hour." T o be " a human being with one
elevated feeling - to be a single great mood incarnate" has up to
now been considered " a mere dream and delightful possibility." Yet
might not history, Nietzsche speculates, one day give rise to such
beings, beings whose perpetual state is, as it were, " a continual
ascent as on stairs and at the same time a sense of resting on clouds"?
T o achieve, then, the status of Übermensch is to achieve and sustain
a condition of ecstasy (Rausch) - to be, as we used to say in the 1960s,
on a "permanent [and apparently ever-ascending] high." Now it
seems to me that Nietzsche is quite right that ecstasy is, by definition,
unqualified and unconditional. If one affirms something ecstatically,
if one loves someone or something ecstatically, then one does not love
it in spite of but rather because of its faults. Its faults, that is, to the
extent that one is aware of them, are seen as part of what one loves
about it - which is to say that they are not really faults at all but
necessary contributors to the "desirability" (WP 1041) of the whole.
The reason, therefore, that Nietzsche demands the willing of the
recurrence of everything about the world is that it alone expresses the
condition of ecstasy; and ecstasy is what he regards as the ideal relationship
to reality.2Q
The Gay Science JI
5
22 It may be noticed, en passant, that it is on account of this ideal
that, given that we are unable to achieve the Dionysian solution to
the riddle, the only alternative considered by Nietzsche is the
Apollonian. The stance of profound superficiality, that is, also yields
an ecstatic state. (As we observed earlier, Nietzsche describes not
merely Dionysian joy but also his own convalescent gaiety as a state
of "intoxication" [GS, Preface, i].) For qua inhabitant of the
condition of profound superficiality, one affirms, like Dionysian
man, everything in one's world; one loves one's fate. T h e only
difference between this and the Dionysian state is that what one
loves is a fake fate. Nietzsche's valuation of ecstasy is thus so high
that, so he believes, if one is unable to affirm everything, the only
viable response is to eliminate the irremediably unlovable from one's
world. La gay a scienza is a kind of parody of willing the eternal
recurrence.
117
n8 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
we want to be poets of our lives" [GS 299]) is present in the works
of 1888. Instead art, literal art, is seen as the "great stimulus to life"
( 7 7 ix, 24) and a cause of health (CW 3), while the "psychology of
the artist" is seen as the epitome of healthy life-affirmation ( 7 7 i x ,
8-9, x, 4-5).*That artists are by our standards typically "sick" is
viewed, in The Will to Power, as a criticism not of the artist but of our
criteria of health (812).
The fact is that in 1888 art and its creators are restored to their
former glory: the glory they possessed in The Birth of Tragedy. It
seems to me completely wrong to suggest, as does Michael Tanner, 2
that Nietzsche spent the rest of his life regretting his characterization
of art in The Birth of Tragedy as " t h e highest task and truly
metaphysical activity of this life" or to suggest, as does Richard
Shacht, that "Nietzsche's enthusiasm for art in The Birth of Tragedy
was so great that further reflection could only have tempered it - as
it in fact did." 3 After The Birth Nietzsche did indeed have, as Schacht
suggests "second thoughts about a r t " (ibid.). But he also had third
and fourth thoughts, and the fourth ones return, in their esteem for
art, to the first. To be sure, it is no longer Wagner who sits upon the
throne of art. But the throne remains, occupied now by the likes of
Hafiz, Raphael, Rubens, Goethe, Bizet, and, once again, the Greek
tragedians.
The second and connected contrast is that the "Dionysian"
attitude to life, regarded in The Gay Science as beyond the power of
ordinary mortals, is viewed in 1888 as achievable, indeed achieved,
by at least the artist ( 7 7 i x , 8, x, 5). The sense of The Gay Science that
we are all "convalescents" disappears in Nietzsche's final year. (In
fact, however, this apparently optimistic turn in Nietzsche's thought
is an illusion; for, so I shall argue, the only reason the Dionysian
condition is viewed as achievable is that, without Nietzsche properly
noticing it, the concept of what constitutes it has altered.)
been persuaded that " t o look at life without desire and not, like a
dog, with one's tongue hanging o u t " is best; but not their "entrails."
They are, therefore, "sentimental hypocrites... lechers" who lack
"innocence" in their desire for immaculate perception, their desire
to be "nothing but a mirror." This surely, is another presentation of
the psychoanalysis of Schopenhauer (see n. 5 above), the theory that
his "interest" in disinterested is in using it "like lupulin 7 or
c a m p h o r " [GM m, 6) as an antidote to the "vile urgency" of sexual
desire.
Nietzsche's second claim is that pure perceivers are barren. It is
not as "creators," not as the sun but rather as the moon, that they
"love the earth": they will never "give birth." T o think that their
ernasculated leer constitutes the experience of the beautiful,
continues Nietzsche, is a travesty. Where really is beauty? "Where
I must will with all my will: where I must love and perish that an
image may not remain a mere image." A similar connecting of the
beautiful with sex and reproduction occurs in Twilight of the Idols:
" b e a u t y , " he says there, "incites procreation" ( 7 7 i x , 22).
Nietzsche's objection to the disinterestedness theory is, itiseems to
me, a simple one: disinterested, will-less contemplation is ncit a state
out of which anything is created. Yet art, the state which produces
it, essentially is creative. Hence "objectivity, mirroring, suspended
will" are "inartistic states" (WP 812). Art, in short, is not
contemplation but action. Nietzsche's activist vocabulary for talking
about artists - he refers to them as creators, makers, doers, violators and
as rapists ( 7 7 ix, 8) - continually emphasizes this. And it is this
perspective on the artist that provides the basis for the inclusion
of conquerors and builders of states and empires among the ranks of
" a r t i s t s " : men possessed of the artist's "terrible...egoism," artists
of "violence" (GM 11, 17).
one lends to things, out forces them to accept from us, one violates them -
this process is called idealising. Let us get rid of a prejudice here: idealising
does not consist, as is commonly held, in subtracting or discounting the petty
and inconsequential. What is decisive is rather a tremendous drive to bring
out the main features so that the others disappear in the process. (77 ix, 8)
The point here, in the last two sentences, is the rejection of the notion
that the experience of the beautiful can be divided up into (1) a
phase of pure receptivity and (2) a will-governed phase in which one
subtracts, erases, that which obscures or is irrelevant to " t h e main
features." If, as both Nietzsche and Schopenhauer agree, ex-
periencing the beautiful is experiencing "significant form," then
being significantly structured is how one's experience is from the
start. If, to employ an analogy, one sees one's lover across a crowded
room one does not observe first a sea of faces and then attach the
predicate "nonlover" to all but one. Rather one sees the lover and
simultaneously all the other faces simply disappear from con-
sciousness. The lover becomes in Wittgenstein's phrase (Notebooks
igi4~i6, p. 83) the whole of " m y world."
Nietzsche is certainly right that " m i r r o r i n g " in the sense of pure
passivity is an "inartistic state." Conceived as pure passivity the
aesthetic state is a fiction. In fact, as Kant pointed out, there is no
consciousness of any kind with respect to which the mind is a tabula
rasa. The subject of aesthetic experience, whether it be the creator of
art Or the spectator (who must also, though perhaps with help from
the artwork, impose a construction upon the object of experience),
must always " d o " things to, " a c t " upon the object.
124 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
And again:
one question remains: art also makes apparent much that is ugly, hard and
questionable in life: does it not thereby spoil life for us? And indeed there
have been philosophers who attributed this sense to it: "liberation from the
will" was what Schopenhauer taught as the overall end of art; and with
admiration he found the great utility of tragedy in "evoking resignation."
But this, as I have already suggested, is the pessimists' perspective and "evil
eye." (77ix, 24)
With what eyes do you think Homer made his gods look down upon the
destinies of men? What was the ultimate meaning of the Trojan Wars and
other such tragic errors? There can be no doubt whatever: they were
intended as festival plays for the gods; and insofar as the poet in these matters
was of a more "godlike" disposition than other men, no doubt also as
festival plays for the poets. (GM 11, 7)
Thus Homer and now, Nietzsche claims, Zola too. Zola's joy in
creation is the joy of his surrogate satisfaction of the impulse to cause
and witness pain. And of such a character, too, is the satisfaction we
derive from reading Zola.
Therefore, if art, good art, is to be of " service to life" - the one view
Nietzsche always holds - it follows that it cannot be more or less overt
propaganda on behalf of socialist reform. And Zola was a good artist.
So let us not be "childish" about this. Zola was a good artist:
consequently Zola was no socialist.
The antithesis of a real and apparent world is lacking... there is only one
world and it is false, cruel, contradictory, seductive without meaning - A
world thus constituted is the real world. We have need of lies in order to
conquer this reality "Life ought to inspire confidence": the task thus
imposed is tremendous. To solve it man must be a liar by nature, he must
be above all an artist... Art and nothing but art! It is the great means of
making life possible, the great seduction to life, the great stimulant of life.
(WP853)n
16 The second apparent difficulty for the thesis that art affirms life
acknowledged by Nietzsche is provided by the case of tragedy. It is,
I think, of considerable significance that tragic art, the starting-point
of Nietzsche's philosophy but absent from his thought ever since its
dismissal as a serious phenomenon in Human, All-too-human ("the
realm of inescapable, implacable destiny is growing narrower and
narrower," a " b a d lookout for writers of tragedy" [HH 1, 108]),
reappears at its terminus. (Tragedy does make a brief appearance in
The Gay Science, but because it suits Nietzsche's theoretical purposes
of the moment is represented, quite scandalously misrepresented, as
a species of Apollonian art. The Athenian went to the theater,
Nietzsche there claims, not to experience strong sentiments but "in
order to hear beautiful speeches. And beautiful speeches were what
concerned Sophocles: pardon this heresy!" [GS 580]. Certainly not,
one wishes to respond.)
Does the tragic artist's display of the " u g l y " "spoil life" for us?
There have indeed been philosophers, writes Nietzsche, who thought
so:
"liberation from the will" was what Schopenhauer taught as the overall
end of art; and with admiration he found the great utility of tragedy in its
"evoking resignation." But this...is the pessimist's perspective and "evil
eye." We must appeal to the artists themselves. What does the tragic artist
communicate of himself? Is it not precisely that state without fear in the face
of the fearful and questionable that he is showing? This state itself is a great
desideratum; whoever knows honours it with the greatest honours. He
communicates it - must communicate it, provided he is an artist, a genius of
communication. Courage and freedom of feeling before a powerful enemy,
before a sublime calamity, before a problem that arouses dread - this
136 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
triumphant state is what the tragic artist chooses, what he glorifies. (77ix,
24)
17 At the end of the section from Twilight of the Idols that we have
been discussing, Nietzsche seems to indicate that he perceives some
connection between the experience of tragic feeling and willing the
eternal recurrence ("I, the last disciple of the philosopher Dionysus,
I, the teacher, of eternal recurrence"). The preceding section
explains the connection he believes to obtain. Goethe, he claims,
excluded the orgiastic from his understanding of the Greek soul:
Consequently Goethe did not understand the Greeks.12, For it is only in the
Dionysian mysteries, in the psychology of the Dionysian state, that the basic
fact of the Hellenic instinct finds expression - its "will to life." What was it
that the Hellene guaranteed himself by means of these mysteries? Eternal
life, the eternal return of life; the future promisee! and hallowed in the past;
the triumphant Yes to life beyond all death and change: true life as the over-
all continuation of life through procreation, through the mysteries of
sexuality. For the Greeks the sexual symbol was the venerable symbol par
excellence, the real profundity in the whole ancient piety. Every single
element in the act of procreation, of pregnancy, and of birth aroused the
highest and most solemn feelings. In the doctrine of the mysteries pain is
pronounced holy: the pangs of the woman giving birth hallow all pain: all
becoming and growing - all that guarantees a future - involves pain. That
there may be the eternal joy of creating, that the will to life may eternally
affirm itself, the agony of the woman giving birth must also be there
eternally.
All this is meant by the word Dionysus: I know no higher symbolism
than this Greek symbolism of the Dionysian festivals. Here the most
profound instinct of life, that diverted towards the future of life, the eternity
of life, is experienced religiously - and the way to life, procreation, as the
holy way. (77 x, 4)
Notice that the confessional use of the pronoun in this passage has
the effect of adding Nietzsche's own name to the roll-call of German
greats.) By the time of The Gay Science Nietzsche realizes that he
himself is vulnerable to the charge of psychological romanticism and
warns himself to guard against it: the higher type, he says, must
overcome his time, its thoughts and values, but " n o t only his time
but also his prior aversion and contradiction against this time, his
suffering from this time, his untimeliness, his romanticism" [GS 380).
Comparisons between present and past, to the detriment of the
former do not, of course, necessarily constitute romanticism. For the
romantic is alienated not from the present but from life, from its
present and future. Hellenism, therefore, the idealization of classical
antiquity, can constitute a nonromantic stance: it does so if the way
back is genuinely conceived as the way forward. Nietzsche often likes
to portray himself as a constructive Hellenist of this kind. But at the
end this is not part of his philosophy. He is ultimately and
fundamentally, as I shall shortly emphasize, himself a romantic - as
he confesses on occasion, a "decadent."
148
Epilogue 149
his pessimism while Nietzsche fights to avoid it, or at least to disguise
its truth from both himself and others, the truth about human
existence is, in the end, as " u g l y " for Nietzsche as it is for
Schopenhauer.
With regard, however, to their responses, their solutions to
pessimism, the two philosophers do diverge. Nietzsche's Apollonian
solution, first of all, the idea of "overcoming" Silenus' truth through
the redemptive power of the beautiful illusion, is something of which
there is no hint in Schopenhauer's philosophy. In a way, this is
strange since no philosopher has emphasized more than Schopen-
hauer the role of illusion in human life. We have already observed
his emphasis upon the idea that our conception of the outer world is
constructed in the interests of the practical will rather than those of
truth (ch. 1, sees. 1 and 6). And when it comes to the inner world,
Schopenhauer again is deeply alive to the role of illusion, of
repression and self-deception, in the normal functioning of the human
psyche. Ignoble motives and desires, he says (in a passage
acknowledged by Freud to anticipate his central postulations of
repression and the unconscious), we quite typically deny admission
to "clear consciousness" since " t h e good opinion we have of
ourselves would inevitably suffer." In their place we substitute
fictions, as we do, too, with respect to the gaps created in memory by
the repression of past experiences too painful to be acknowledged
(WR 11, pp. 209-10, 399-402; WR 1, pp. 192, 296).
But while recording the role of illusion in human life with
unprecedented thoroughness, Schopenhauer's stance towards it is
always Platonic - contemptuous. The cause of this is his philoso-
pher's morality, his care for truth - the fact that, as Nietzsche would
put it, possessing an "unconditional will to t r u t h " he is "still pious"
(GS 344). This prevents him from entertaining the distinctively
Nietzschean idea that illusion, " a r t , " is " ' m o r e divine' than truth,"
prevents him making the inference that since " w e have need of lies
in order to live," well then, let there then be lies (WP 853).
Nietzsche's Dionysian solution, too, is something not offered to us
by Schopenhauer. Not that he did not, in effect, consider it. " O n l y
small, trivial minds," he writes, "fear death as annihilation" (WR 11,
p. 475). And he speaks of the fact that the species survives the
destruction of the individual as "nature's great doctrine of
immortality" (WR 11, p. 475), her intuitive proof of the "inde-
structibility of our inner n a t u r e " by death (WR 11, p. 463). If, that is,
150 Nietzsche's philosophy of art
Schopenhauer suggests, one identifies oneself not with the suffering
and mortal individual but with the metaphysical will-to-live, then
" h e would willingly give up his individuality, smile at the tenacity
of his attachment thereto, and say: what does the loss [or pain] of
this individuality matter to me? for I carry within myself the
possibility of innumerable individualities" {WR n, 491). The idea
that we can escape the horror and terror of individual existence by
achieving a state of sublimity, a sense of a supraphenomenal
existence, is strongly present in Schopenhauer. Such a state is indeed
achieved by the Schopenhauerian altruist: she escapes the anxious care
for the individual self by identifying with the will that manifests itself
in all individuals (see ch. 1, seic. 5).
What takes Schopenhauer, however, beyond this position is once
again morality. The " transition from virtue [altruism] to as-
ceticism" (see ch. , sec. 5) is brought about by the altruist's coming
to share in Schopenhauer's moral revulsion against the will which,
as the ground of the world's sufferings, comes to be perceived as evil.
Schopenhauer, because he is unable to adopt the Nietzschean stance
beyond good and evil, looks, ultimately, for redemption in
identification not with the will but with some still more fundamental
entity " beyond the will."
What sets Schopenhauer apart from both Nietzsche's solutions
(and what, one might well feel, makes him ultimately a more
human, more attractive figure) is his morality. On the other hand,
what is common to both Schopenhauer and Nietzsche is ro-
manticism, "romantic pessimism" (GS 370). Both Schopenhauer
and, at the end, Nietzsche, is caused by his "great dissatisfaction"
with life, to "look away...from himself and from his world" (WP
844), to yearn for some better mode of being.
INTRODUCTION
Bernd Magnus "Nietzsche's philosophy in 1888: The Will to Power and
the ' Übermensch?" Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (January 1986),
PP- 79-99-
SCHOPENHAUER
I have discussed Schopenhauer's biological route to idealism in detail in
chapter 1, section 3, of my book Willing and Unwilling a Study in the
Philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer (Dordrecht: Nijhoff, 1987).
2 In Willing and Unwilling (see especially ch. in) I have argued that
Schopenhauer is most coherently read as not so much abandoning
Kant's dualism between an ideal nature and a non-natural thing in
itself but as, rather, dividing up the natural side of the duality into (1)
the world as conceived in the common-sense image and (2) the world
as conceived in an image constructed out of philosophical reflection
upon the foundations of natural science. T h e result is a Jnpartite
structure composed of the common-sense world, a deeper world of
" w i l l " , and the non-natural world in itself: the second, though often
called the thing in itself is, I suggest, ultimately distinct from it.
Nietzsche, however, most often reads Schopenhauer as implicitly
naturalizing the Kantian thing in itself, as offering a dichotomy
between the ideal world of common sense and an an sich that is to be
conceived in terms of the equivalent notions of "force," energy, or
"will." In what follows, I shall present Schopenhauer in Nietzsche's
rather than my own way.
3 Schopenhauer's argument for this (see ch. 4, sec. 2) is, in a nutshell, that
since (1) the most ultimate entities posited by any scientific theory must
possess causal powers in order to have explanatory value and (2)
atomism is committed to grounding any power or disposition in atomic
structure, it follows that the atomistic view is infinitely regressive, that
it can never consistently claim to possess an account of ultimate reality.
In chapter iv, section 3, of Willing and Unwilling I have shown that
Schopenhauer's dynamism places him in a tradition that goes back via
K a n t to Joseph Priestley and ultimately to the eighteenth-century Jesuit
153
154 Notes to pages 6-23
nightmares: "perhaps many will, like myself, recall how amid the
dangers and terrors of dreams they have said to themselves in self-
encouragement and not without success: ' I t is a dream! I will dream
o n ' " (BT 1). Many people, for example Descartes, are not lucid
dreamers. It is important for our attempt to understand the Apollonian
solution to pessimism (sees. 11-12 below) to remember that it is the lucid
dream, the dream one, as it were, spectates rather than lives, to which
aesthetically Apollonian consciousness is compared.
10 Notice here the early appearance of a theme much in evidence in
Nietzsche's later philosophy. Living well - which implies at least living
a civilized life - depends, we have seen, upon the existence of the " l a w s "
and " b a r r i e r s " erected between one individual and another by the
(metaphysically) Apollonian mind. These are to preserve us from the
crudities and cruelties of barbaric Dionysianism. But these barbaric
impulses are not to be eradicated (as Christianity would like) but rather
sublimated or, as Nietzsche puts it, "spiritualized," transmuted into, for
example, art. "Evil," the later Nietzsche insists, is something we need,
is inseparable from "greatness."
The quotations, from Wagner's Opera and Drama are given in Carl
Dahinaus' fine essay " T h e two-fold truth in Wagner's aesthetics," the
second essay in his book Between Romanticism and Modernism, tr. M.
Whittall (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980). Notice the
harmony between the musical theory of the younger Wagner and the
opera-friendly version of Schopenhauer's theory.
12 There is a temptation to insist that since music cannot be formless
content, the Apollonian must be present even in absolute music. There
are two comments to be made here. First, that which is demanded by
form is a contribution from, as I have called it, the metaphysically
Apollonian mind, the ordering, organizing " r a t i o n a l " mind which
gives us the world of the principium individuationis. The birth-of-tragedy
thesis, however, holds that great art must contain, as a component,
Apollonian art, must, that is, be in part a product of the aesthetically
Apollonian mind. Second, during the period of The Birth Nietzsche did
not admit the claim that music must possess form, taking as paradigms
of musical "composition" the rhapsodic emissions of the Dionysian
reveler and the conceptually unintelligible choral hymns to Dionysus
that punctuate Greek tragedy. Later, Nietzsche saw that art must
communicate and that communication demands (conventionally under-
stood) form (see ch. 3, sec. 24); but communication is not demanded of
music in his early period. In the unpublished fragment " O n music and
w o r d s " reproduced in a Kaufmann translation in Dahinaus' book (see
n. 11 above) he writes, in a discussion of song, that
the individual who is in a state of Dionysian excitement has no listeners to whom
he has anything to communicate any more than does an orgiastic crowd,
[though] the epic narrator and, more generally, the Apollonian artist, does
presuppose such a listener. It is of the essence of Dionysian art it does not know
Notes to pages 40-51 157
any consideration for a listener; the enthusiastic servant of Dionysus
understood only by his peers, (p. 114)
13 Nietzsche is, of course, the famous philosopher of the circle. But
Schopenhauer preceded him in the use of the circle as an image for time
(see WR 1, pp. 380, 280).
14 The borrowing of his paradoxical conjunction from The Gay Science
(Preface, 4) is apposite here for it captures Nietzsche's insistence in The
Birth that the "cheerfulness" of the Greeks was the solution to a problem,
was achieved in the face of a deep sensitivity to the horrors of life and was
not, as the dominant nineteenth-century conception had it, due to a
blithe ignorance of such horrors (see n. 4 above).
15 This extraordinary evocation of musical experience might be seen as
constituting an answer to the criticism made in section 9 above that
Nietzsche seems mistaken in demanding an Apollonian aspect of all
great art given the undeniable greatness of many works of purely
instrumental music. As an answer, however, this would only be effective
were we really willing to grant to absolute music the power to threaten
permanent psychological dislocation.
16 This is the reason that the famous assertion that only as aesthetic
phenomenon is life and existence justified (see sec. 15 below), an
assertion which would appear to be a natural bedfellow for the idea of the
Apollonian triumph of beauty over suffering, is, in fact, associated only
with Dionysian, never Apollonian art. The world is not justified by the
Apollonian outlook but only seems so to its inhabitants. In a later
echoing of the famous sentence that is connected with Apollonian art
Nietzsche is careful to eliminate the notion of justification; " a s an
aesthetic phenomenon," he says, "existence is still bearable for u s " (GS
107; Nietzsche's emphasis).
17 Nietzsche's condemnation of modern culture parallels his condemnation
of the culture of the " n e w Attic C o m e d y " that succeeded the age of
Greek tragedy as a culture that takes "womanish flight from seriousness
and terror" into the "craven satisfaction and easy enjoyment" of " t h e
passing m o m e n t " (BT 11).
18 See Nietzsche's comments on Heraclitus in "Philosophy in the tragic
age of the Greeks," in The Complete Works of Frederick Nietzsche, ed. O.
Levy (London: Foulds, 1911)5 vol. 11, pp. 106-11.
19 Notice that the artist-god with whom we identify is an Apollonian artist
i> (sculpture, remember, e.g. sand-sculpture, is a paradigm of Apollonian
art), someone the object of whose consciousness is the principium
individuationis raised to a state of beauty. Occasionally, Nietzsche makes
the resemblance to the human Apollonian artist even closer by
suggesting that the demiurge's motive for creation is to find an escape
from the reality of its own " p a i n and contradiction" (BT 5). He refers
back to this conception in ^arathustra:
At one time Zarathustra too cast his delusion beyond man, like all the
i58 Notes to pages 52-74.
afterworldly. The work of a suffering and tortured god, the world then seemed
to me. A dream the world then seemed to me, and the fiction of a god: coloured
smoke before the eyes of a dissatisfied deity. Good and evil and joy and pain and
I and you - coloured smoke they seemed to me before creative eyes. The creator
wanted to look away from himself: so he created the world. (£ 1, 3)
This notion seems to me (1) inconsistent with the dominant conception
of the demiurge as a joyfully playful child whose existence is "powerful
and pleasurable," " h a p p y " (BT 17), and (2) inconsistent with the idea
that identification with the primal unity constitutes a solution to the
pain of human existence. If the primal unity's mode of existence is a
copy of our own then identification with it is a transition, merely, from
the frying-pan into the fire. These inconsistencies come about, I think,
because Nietzsche wants to use the idea of the artist-god to perform two
functions: (1) to contribute an answer to the cosmological question of
why the world came into being; and (2) to figure in the Dionysian
solution to pessimism. The kind of answer he gives to (1) determines a
characterization of the demiurge inconsistent with that demanded by
(2).
20 As Petra von Morstein has suggested to me.
21 In Ecce Homo Nietzsche suggests that in Wagner at Bayreuth he uses
Wagner as Plato used Socrates " a s a sign language for P l a t o " {EH v,
3).
3 HUMAN, ALL-TOO-HUMAN
Since Nietzsche wants to reduce matter to force, "motions," it would be
incorrect to treat "materialism" as a synonym for the " n a t u r a l i s m " to
which he subscribes. In section 5 he rejects mind-body dualism as a
primitive superstition. It seems, therefore, that Nietzsche's particular
form of naturalism is best described as "neutral monism."
2 See G. J. Stack's Lange and Nietzsche (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1983),
pp. 226-7.
3 Mozart's " J u p i t e r " Symphony was, I believe, so called because it seems
to possess the effortless perfection of a god.
4 This conjunction between (Apollonian) art and the unconditional willing
of life seems to anticipate the theme of The Gay Science that (as we will
see in chapter 4) art helps us will the eternal recurrence.
5 O n one occasion, Nietzsche acknowledges a cognitive value in art: in
Wagner at Bayreuth he suggests that art can provide a simplification of the
multiplicity of phenomena that reveals to us the "laws of life"
knowledge of which is essential to the adoption of a " s p i r i t u a l - m o r a l "
attitude towards it (WB, p. 213). But never again does he acknowledge
that it has this value. This is the most consistent deficiency in his
thought about art. Schopenhauer, in this respect, had a much better
understanding.
6 This picture of science as a value-neutral activity seems to me a myth.
M a n y values - truth, beauty, simplicity, interpersonal harmony, for
Notes to pages j6-86 J
59
example - are written into the activity of science. The scientist qua
scientist is committed to these values and does not need any outside
agency to determine them for her.
7 This distinction between " s p i r i t " and " s o u l " is an allusion, surely, to
Plato's division between the "spirited " part of the psyche and " reason."
In the Republic "justice" in the soul is defined as harmony between its
various parts, under the leadership of "reason," There are various
forms of "injustice" one of which, the " t i m o c r a t i c " soul, consists in the
dominance of the rational soul by aggressive, ambitious, militaristic
"spirit." This is what Nietzsche here seems to be rejecting.
8 Quoted in E. M. Butler The Tyranny of Greece over Germany (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1935), p. 46.
9 See M. S. Silk and J . P . S t e r n , Nietzsche on Tragedy (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1981), ch. 1, sec. 2.
10 In Nietzsche's mature philosophy, above all in £arathustra, there is, of
course, a very powerful anti-ant theme. T h e "great and beautiful soul"
is conceived as a rare and isolated individual standing out from and in
opposition to the multitude or " h e r d . " But in Opinions there is no hint
of this. Indeed the logic of the discussion precludes it, for if artists are
to construct " i m p r o v i n g " archetypes then, by definition, their audience
or target is the multitude. The great individual who stands out against
the herd must, of necessity (a theme which will become prominent in ch.
4), be a self-creator rather than a follower of other-determined
archetypes.
Notice that Nietzsche's distinction between the classical and " b a r o q u e "
is reminiscent of the Kant-Schopenhauerian distinction between the
beautiful and the sublime and, of course, his own between the
Apollonian and Dionysian.
12 In The Birth " A s i a " is the home of " b a r b a r i s m " that threatens always
to engulf Greek (i.e. classical) civilization.
13 In Opera and Drama Wagner accuses Berlioz of by "purely mechanical
m e a n s " creating " a n unprecedented variety of... the most marvellous
effects" the content of which, however, is "inartistic rubbish" (quoted
in Carl Dahlhaus, " T h e two-fold truth in Wagner's aesthetics," in his
Between Romanticism and Modernism, tr. M. Whittall [Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1980], p. 9). Nietzsche's critique of Wagner is not
intended to be novel. The intention is rather, I think, to hoist him with
<. his own petard.
14 It seems appropriate to enter a protest against the implicit demand here
that an artist should conquer the formal constraints of his art with an
"illusion of ease and validity." Not only is this a highly subjective, and
not particularly attractive, valuation, it also sits most uncomfortably
with the suggestion in Human, that we should not be taken in by the
artist's attempt to make his work seem the "casual improvisation of a
g o d " (see sec. 10 above). Does Nietzsche wish to be ravished by the
artist or does he not?
i6o Notes to pages 8y-g6
15 This is the first published appearance of" romantic " used, in Nietzsche's
characteristic manner, as a pejorative expression.
16 Though Nietzsche would sometimes like to represent Wagner's
" b a r o q u e " art as both of these things (see HH na, 144) they cannot
possibly be simultaneously coinstantiated.
17 Another conception of the romantic would conceive of him as someone
alienated from the given world not by incapacity to deal with the
present and fear of the future but by the demand for more than is
yielded by the present and impatience to realize it in the future.
According to Nietzsche's (arbitrary) terminology, however, that person
is not " r o m a n t i c " but "Dionysian" ( " Z a r a t h u s t r i a n " or "Nietz-
schean") (see GS 370).
18 If this comparison is correct Nietzsche's relation to the Gorgias is a
peculiar one. His moral philosophy, it is clear, is deeply indebted to
Callicles, the ablest defender of the rhetoricians' way of life. Indeed
Callicles' distinction between master and slave morality, his defense of
the former and postulation of resentment as the source of the latter so
closely anticipates Nietzsche's own Genealogy of Morals as to place the
latter in some danger of sustaining a charge of plagiarism. On the other
hand, if I am right, Nietzsche's objections to Wagner are influenced by
Socrates' objections to rhetoric. Nietzsche, it seems, borrows from both
sides in the debate which is the Gorgias.
4 THE GA T SCIENCE
"Nietzsche's Gay Science, or, how to naturalize cheerfully," in R.
Solomon and K. Higgins (eds.), Reading Nietzsche (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1988), p. 69.
2 In a letter to Franze Overbeck of 1884. See Selected Letters of Friedrich
Nietzsche, ed. C. Middleton (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1969), p. 223.
3 And have been thus interpreted by Alexander Nehamas in Nietzsche:
Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985),
ch. 2. One of the major pieces of evidence cited by Nehamas in favor of
his interpretation is the fact that at GS 354 Nietzsche disassociates the
affirmation of perspectivism from the "opposition of'thing in itself and
appearance." This, together with section iv of Twilight of the Idols
("How the 'true world' finally became a fable"), he sees as establishing
that the mature Nietzsche abandoned the metaphysical contrast
between thing in itself and appearance. I agree that he did. But to deny
that a thing in itself lies behind our interpretations of the world is not at
all the same as holding that nothing does. Two comments are in order
here. First, Nietzsche typically uses "thing in itself" when he wants to
evoke specifically Kantian overtones, so that to be a " t h i n g in itself"
something has to be a non-natural item of the kind demanded by religion,
presupposed by morality, and intimated by art (see ch. 3, sec. 4, above).
Notes to pages g6-8 161
9 Remember the Nietzschean axiom that the state which produces is the
same as that produced by art.
10 See also section 12 below.
11 This passage of uncertain date is actually presented as a summary of the
outlook of The Birth of Tragedy. It seems to me, however, that while in
some respects seriously inaccurate as an account of The Birth ( " T h e
antithesis of a real and apparent world is lacking"!), it accurately
expresses one of the two art solutions to the riddle of life offered by
Nietzsche in his final year.
12 Goethe, for most of Nietzsche's life, was one of his supreme heroes. But
in 1888 he seems to have turned against him. In addition to the above
remark, consider: " I have no words, only a look for those who dare say
the word Faust in the presence of [Byron's] Manfred. The Germans are
incapable of any conception of greatness" (EH 11, 4).
13 The case of Rubens is symptomatic of a deeper tension. For if, as
Nietzsche's metaphysics holds, reality is "flux," "becoming," from
which all " b e i n g " is absent, and if, moreover, as Nietzsche sometimes
holds, " h o n e s t y " in one's perception of the world is a value, then art too
should be honest and should reflect the flux-ridden character of the
world. But this means that art must be rco/zclassical since classical art is
dedicated to the deification of reposeful being (see GS 370).
f4 The Importance of Nietzsche (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988),
p. 166.
EPILOGUE
1 W. Kaufmann in his translation of Ecce Homo (EH, p. 258, fn.).
<ß R. Hollingdale, Nietzsche (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973),
P- 157-
Texts and translations
For Nietzsche's texts I have used Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, ed. G. Colli
and M. Montinari, 30 vols. (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1967-78) and Werke in drei
Banden, ed. K. Schlechta, 3rd edn. (Munich: Carl Hanser, 1965). For
Schopenhauer's texts, the Zürcher Ausgabe, 10 vols. (Zurich: Diogenes,
1977). This is a paperback version of the Sämtliche Werke, ed. A. Hubscher
(Wiesbaden: Brockhaus, 1946-50). T h e translations on which I have
generally depended (significant emendations are accompanied by the
German original) are the following:
The Antichrist, tr. W. Kaufmann, in The Portable Nietzsche, ed. W
Kaufmann (New York: Viking Press, 1954).
Beyond Good and Evil, tr. W Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Press, 1966).
The Birth of Tragedy, tr. W. Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Press, 1966).
This volume contains also The Case of Wagner, tr. W. Kaufmann.
Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, tr. R. Hollingdale (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).
On the Genealogy of Morals, tr. W Kaufmann and R. Hollingdale (New
York: Vintage Press, 1968). This volume contains also Ecce Homo, tr. W
Kaufmann.
The Gay Science, tr. W Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Press, 1974).
Human, All-too-human, tr. R. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1986). This volume contains also Assorted Opinions and
Maxims, tr. R. Hollingdale, and The Wanderer and his Shadow, tr. R.
Hollingdale.
Nietzsche Contra Wagner, tr. W Kaufmann, in The Portable Nietzsche, which
contains also Twilight of the Idols, tr. W Kaufmann.
Richard Wagner at Bayreuth, the fourth of the Untimely Meditations, R.
Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
The Will to Power, tr. W Kaufmann and R. Hollingdale (New York:
Vintage Press, 1968).
Thus Spoke ^arathustra, tr. W Kaufmann, in The Portable Nietzsche.
166
Index
67
168 Index
Ecce Homo, 2, 28, 29, 49, 58, 102, 105, idealizing process, 123-6, 129, 130-1
136, 150, 151-2, 158 idealism: biological, 5-6, 60; K a n t i a n , 5-6,
ecstasy, see Rausch 41, 153; rejection of, 64, 6 6 - 8
egoism, 8-9, 121 illusion, 6 1 - 2 , 101, 139-40, 148; in
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 105, 109 Apollonian art, 4 2 - 5 ; redemptive power
emotion: and art, 13-15; and music, 22-3 of, 135; veil of, 42, 47
energy, 8 1 , 83, 1 0 9 - n , 115-16, 141; "in-itself," 7
sexual, 128-30 individuation, 39, 46, 52
Engels, Friedrich, 132 Ingres, J e a n Auguste Dominique, 140, 142
Enlightenment, 65 instrumentalism, 5-6, 11
Erasmus, Desiderius, interpretations, 2, 96, 161
errors, 5, 95-7 intoxication, see Rausch
eternal recurrence, 1, 100-1, 103-4, 107-9,
136, 137-9, 151; problem of, 112-13, joy, concept of, 113-14
115-16 justification of life, aesthetic, 28, 5 1 - 3 ,
Euripides, 30 54-5, 157
evil, as something we need, 156
K a n t , Immanuel, 5, 12, 14-15, 65, 118,
force, 6, 154 119-20, 123, 144; Critique of Judgment,
form, beauty in significant, 15-16, 43, 14-15; Critique of Pure Reason, 5
122-3 Kaufmann, Walter, 27-9, 44, 125, 161
free spirit, 58, 64-6, 74 knowledge: and action, 4 2 ; as reward for
frenzy, see Rausch altruism, 9-10
Freud, Sigmund, 100, 129-30, 149
Lange, F A., History of Materialism, 6 2 - 3
Gay Science, The, 6, 28, 81, 82, 83-4, 88, Langer, Suzanne K., Feeling and Form, 22-3
92-116, 118, 135, 138, 139, 142-3, 144 Laocoon, 77
Genealogy of Morals, On the, 110, 119, 126, Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 20, 144
132 liberation, 58, 6 6 - 8 , 135
genetic fallacy, 145 lies, 4 2 - 5 , 149
genius, artist as, 10, 37, 58, 66, 68-9, 83 life-affirmation, 27, 29, 118
G e r m a n : character, 50; nationalism, 55 Locke, J o h n , 6
Gibbon, Edward, 40 Lutheranism, 49
Goethe, J o h a n n Wolfgang von, 77, 137, lyric poetry, Schopenhauer on, 18-19
165; Mignon, 17
Goldmark, Carl, 140 M c C a h o n , Colin, 75
Greek tragedy, 30-2, 45-7 M a r x , Karl, 132
Greeks, 27, 28, 137; Homeric, 42-5 mass, compared with opera, 21-2
Index 169
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 3-4, 5-24, 33, 34, Thus Spoke £arathustra, 53, 75, 92, 93, 101,
118-19, H 0 ' 144; as antipode to 103, 105, 113, 119, 120-1, 137, 138, 139,
Nietzsche's philosophy, 3, 26-7, 148; 157-8
influence on Nietzsche, 25-6, 58-60 Tönnies, Ferdinand, 9
Schopenhauerian character of Birth of tragedy, 19-20, 131, 135-7
Tragedy, The, 25-6, 27-8, 48-55 " t r a g i c effect,", 19-20, 45-7, 51
science, 6 0 - 3 ; foundations of natural, 6; Twilight of the Idols, 117-47, 126, 127,
and rationality, 41 129-30
scientific optimism, 4 0 - 1 , 59-63, 71-2,
73-4, 9 4 - 5 , 97 Übermenschlichkeit, 75, 109-11, 114, 137,
secularization, 49-50, 65 139, 146, 151
self, artistic creation of, 99, 102-3, I 0 5 - 7> ugly, the, 127, 131-2, 134
162 Upanishads, 9
self-deception, 44, 48, 100
sexual origin of art, 126-30 von Gersdorff, Karl, 26
sexuality, 137, 138
sickness, 3, 26-7, 101 Wagner, Richard, 21, 23, 24, 25-6, 31,
skepticism, classical, 122 55-7, 58, 80, 105, 140; Götterdämmerung,
socialism, 132-4 25; Opera and Drama, 36; Parsifal, 25, 5 5 ;
Socrates, 27, 30, 49, 158, 160 Ring, 56; Tristan, 47, 56
Socratism, 4 0 - 1 , 56 Wagnerian art, critique of, 88-91
solipsism, metaphysical, 9, 34 Wanderer and his Shadow, The, 58, 84-7
song, 126, 156 " W e Philologists, 31
Sophocles, 31 Weimar classicism, 77
spiritual health, 115-16 western culture, 50
Stalinism, 79, 82 Wilde, Oscar, 100
state, 8, 46, 103 will: Buddhistic negation of the, 39, 4 2 ;
Stein, Heinrich von, 94 denial of the, 9-10, 119; music as
Stendhal, 120, 126 expression of the inner, 2 0 - 1 , 2 3 ; the
style for a character, 105, 162 world as, 5-7, 34
subjectivity, Schopenhauer on, 11-13 will to life, 5 0 - 3 , 136-8
sublimation thesis, 126-30 will to power, 1, 154
sublime, the, 14-15, 18, 19, 45, 137, 139, Will to Power, The, 4/^28, 117, 118, 120,
126, 127, 129, 131, 136, 143
suffering, solutions to, 25, 5 4 - 5 , 98-116, will to truth, 9 8 - 9 , 149
also Apollonianism, Dionysian solution Willing and Unwilling (Young), 15, 153
suicide, 39, 97 Winckelmann, J o h a n n J o a c h i m , 77, 142
superficiality, profound, 44, 99-100, 101, Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 11, 107, 109, 123,
i n , 112, 115, 116, 139, 151 163
world-affirmation, aesthetic criteria and,
T a n n e r , Michael, 118 5"-3> 54-5
Taylor, Charles Sen, 155 World as Will and Representation, The
theater, 17; see also tragedy (Schopenhauer), 5
" t h i n g in itself," 60, 160; music and, 2 0 - 1 ,
23 Zola, Emile, 131, 132-4