Brinton Nietzsche
Brinton Nietzsche
Brinton Nietzsche
NIETZSCHE
LONDON : GEOFFREY CUMBERLEGE
OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
NIETZSCHE
BY
CRANE BRINTON
McLean Professor of Ancient and Modern History,
Harvard University
CAMBRIDGE · MASSACHUSETTS
H A R V A R D U N I V E R S I T Y PRESS
1948
COPYRIGHT, I94I
Second Printing
I. THE STUDENT 3
PROPHET 232
BIBLIOGRAPHY 247
INDEX 263
ILLUSTRATIONS
NIETZSCHE IN H I S L A S T Y E A R OF L I F E frontispiece
Thanks to photography, we have as good a record of Nietzsche's ap-
pearance as one might expect of a member of a German middle-class
family in the late nineteenth century. He did not, however, become a
subject for artists until the decade of his great fame, the 1890's, by
which time he was insane and bedridden. Elizabeth allowed several
artists to have access to her brother at Jena and Weimar. In 1899 one
of these, Dr. Hans Olde, made this now familiar drawing, showing the
sick Nietzsche gazing sightlessly at the setting sun. There arc several
better-known engravings from this drawing, in which only Nietzsche's
head or head and shoulders are shown.
NIETZSCHE AT SIXTEEN 22
This is the familiar photograph which all good German families have
taken of the son at his confirmation.
RICHARD AND COSIMA W A G N E R 46
The famous couple posed at about the period when Nietzsche first
made their acquaintance — an acquaintance which very rapidly became
friendship.
ELIZABETH NIETZSCHE 112
This is Elizabeth on the edge of middle age, just before she married
Bernhard Förster. She did not assume the name by which she is known
to students of Nietzsche, Frau Förster-Nietzsche, until the 1890'$, when
her husband was dead and her brother famous.
NIETZSCHE IN UNIFORM 170
This photograph was taken in the fall of 1868, about the time of
Nietzsche's appointment to the professorship at Basle.
H I T L E R AT THE NIETZSCHE-ARCHIV IN W E I M A R 208
Elizabeth did all she could to associate both Hitler and Mussolini with
the memory of her brother. The photographer has here, perhaps sym-
bolically, cut Nietzsche's bust in half. The fuehrer is there in full.
INTRODUCTION
*Mr. Peter Viereck first brought to the attention of Americans the Nazi
canonization of Wagner as a thinner and prophet. His articles in Common
Sense for November and December, 1939, are being expanded into a book to
be published shortly.
INTRODUCTION xvii
most unhappy — unless there is in Valhalla also a Sils-Maria.
For Nietzsche, living, got on very badly with flesh-and-blood
Germans. He loved to badger them, to attack their most as-
sured superiorities.
I shall never admit that a German can understand what music is.
Those musicians who are called German, the greatest and most famous
foremost, are all foreigners, either Slavs, Croats, Italians, Dutchmen —
or Jews: or else, like Heinrich Schütz, Bach and Händel, they are Ger-
mans of a strong race which is now extinct.2
The boy grew up as Fritz to his family and friends; and since,
as a grown man and a philosopher, he came to feel an ordinary
king of Prussia rather far beneath him, he did not customarily
use the royal name, but signed himself simply Friedrich
Nietzsche.
About Nietzsche's heredity biographers have indulged them-
selves in the fine free speculation customary in such matters.
Nietzsche himself set them an example. The Slavic family
1
E . Förster-Nietzsche, The Life of Nietzsche, English translation (1912),
I, 12.
4 NIETZSCHE
name, and some tales of his grandmother, gave his imagina-
tion a few facts to work on, out of which, perhaps with the help
of his always admiring young sister Elizabeth, he spun out a
romantic tale of decent from a family of refugee Polish nobles
named Nicki or Nietzky.
My ancestors were Polish noblemen: it is owing to them that I have
so much race instinct in my blood — who knows? perhaps even the
liberum veto. When I think of the number of times in my travels that
I have been accosted as a Pole, even by Poles themselves, and how seldom
I have been taken for a German, it seems to me as if I belonged to those
only who have a sprinkling of German in them.2
II
At fourteen, the adolescent boy was at last separated from
his adoring womenfolk, and entered on a scholarship at the
boys' school in Pforta, five miles away from Naumburg on the
river Saale. Schulpforta has always had an admirable intellec-
tual tradition, and many writers and scholars have gone from
there to the universities. Lutheran pastors and teachers had
taken over the place from mediaeval monks, and maintained
some of the strictness, sobriety, and devotion to a classical edu-
cational discipline of the mediaeval school. The boys worked
hard at Pforta. But the school did not put its pupils through
the essentially unintellectual social conditioning such nurseries
of a ruling class as Eton or the Prussian cadet schools im-
pose. Nietzsche was probably already at fifteen as proof
against this sort of conditioning as was, at the same age,
the lad Shelley. But Shelley had to undergo Eton and Ox-
ford. Nietzsche never came quite so close to this harsh
world.
Pforta was not of course entirely a cloister, a prison, or a
library. It was filled with adolescent boys who played, strolled
in the garden, swam in the river, joked, and on Sundays and
holidays drank wine from the school's own vineyards. Yet this
kind of play was pleasantly anarchic, with nothing to gall —
or restrain — a lad already precociously intellectual. Fritz had
at first some trouble adapting himself to the routine of early
rising, communal meals, and ordered studying, but he was still
young enough to bend slightly. A fragmentary diary, preserved
as usual by Elizabeth's care, gives an interesting account of the
daily life of this most German school, so different from any-
THE STUDENT iz
thing young Americans and young Englishmen have ever been
put through. 10
As the boy grows up his letters, journals, and essays — for he
was always writing — begin to lose their straightforward
clarity. With adolescence, the appropriate emotional crisis
seems to come over Fritz, and gets expressed in ways which
are still appropriately conventional. "Vorbei, vorbei! Herz,
willst du zerspringen?" Roses, and the world, must die. He
writes poetry, pages and pages of it, lyric and dramatic. At his
height, in "The Conspiracy of Philotas," he achieves thirty-six
exclamation points in twenty-seven lines, which is rather bet-
ter than his father had done. 11 A new and somewhat less
solemn tone comes into the letters from Pforta. He writes long
letters to his old friends Krug and Pinder, and to a new one,
Granier, letters full of self-conscious and literary jesting, wag-
gish and lively as though they came from a perpetually young
American college professor of English:
The plan for my contrarious novel — Lord! you've already forgotten
it — never mind! — I threw overboard in annoyance as soon as I had
finished the first chapter. I'm sending you the monstrous manuscript
to use for . . . well, what you will. . . . Yours till we meet again soon
F W ν Nietzky (alias Muck)
homme étudié en lettres
{votre ami sans lettres) 12
III
In October, 1864, at the age of twenty, Friedrich Nietzsche
matriculated in theology and philosophy at the University of
" E . Förster-Nietzsche, Das heben Friedrich Nietzsches (1895), I, 80. There
is also a song of his printed in the same volume, p. 224. The "Hymn to Life,"
words by Lou Salomé, music by Friedrich Nietzsche, can be found at the end
of the English translation of Ecce Homo and the poems.
"Förster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, I, 119-121.
14 NIETZSCHE
Bonn. The next few months are a crisis in his life, which will
probably remain obscure, and therefore a constant temptation
to his biographers. Nietzsche himself used afterwards to refer
to his "lost year" at Bonn, and to the whole experience as an
almost inexplicable straying from the path of his destiny. His
sympathetic biographers, such as Charles Andler, have regarded
the year at Bonn as an essential part of their hero's Calvary, his
ennobling exposure to the test of withstanding German student-
life in its full comic-opera vulgarity.
Here a simpler explanation may be hazarded. Nietzsche was
making a final and determined effort to be one of the boys.
After his coddled childhood, his cloistral adolescence, after the
long domination of his womenfolk, of the Naumburg proprie-
ties, of all sorts of high seriousness, the young man was ready
for revolt. And his revolt was still, characteristically, very con-
ventional. He was going to sow his wild oats, in our complex
modern society one of the ritual forms through which the
adolescent becomes a man. Nietzsche was still one of the tribe,
still most eager for the applause of the tribe. He would go
through a brave and boisterous initiation.
Such ceremonies, varying in form from tribe to tribe, seem
always a bit ludicrous to an outsider. The current American
form, especially as caricatured in Hollywood moving pictures
of "collegiate" life, may seem ludicrous even to an insider.
Certainly German "student life" of the mid-nineteenth century
takes on today an absurdity mellowed into something roman-
tically enduring. Beer, metaphysics, song and buxom young
love, the manly touch of the duel, the sweetness of a not un-
conquerable nostalgia — this is surely one of the world's great
patterns for ritual, and one likely to survive a number of
THE STUDENT 15
totalitarian dictatorships. Sowing one's wild oats, never a pur-
suit to give the subtle artistic sensibility much scope for inde-
pendent variation, was in nineteenth-century Germany limited
by the national genius for organization, which seems as apt —
if as unlovely — at organizing youthful jollity as at organizing
a military campaign.
Nietzsche tried his best. He joined a student corps, the Fran-
conia, which was composed mostly of Pforta men. H e drank
beer — a drink for which he later expressed the greatest con-
t e m p t — at noisy student gatherings, took long walks, always
with groups, and even made a pathetic attempt to fight a duel.
For this latter purpose, he challenged a man of whom he was
very fond; perhaps the ironist was already at work within him.
T h e duel produced no scars. H e must also have been appropri-
ately in love, or at least given his fellows some evidence that in
this most important human activity he was what a good Ger-
man ought to be in his student days. H e may merely have
talked about women, which if done at all skillfully, will qualify
the talker among men. H e may have had a go with a prostitute,
and thus unfortunately caught the syphilis which ended his
career twenty-five years later. 16 Nietzsche's actual relations with
women remain a puzzle for most of his life. In spite of the
pathetic efforts of his sister Elizabeth to bring in concrete in-
stances of his puppy loves and his adolescent flames, in spite of
the insistence with which she repeats that her Fritz was in this
as in all matters a sound, normal German lad, the impression
I write this the first thing in the morning after having just torn myself
from bed, thus flatly disproving the notion that I may have a thick head.
Maybe the expression "thick head" conveys nothing to your mind. Yes-
terday we had a great drinking bout and sang the solemn Landesvater,
and there were endless torrents of punch; guests from Heidelberg and
Göttingen, . . . We numbered over forty men; the public-house was
beautifully decorated. . . . The festival was of a very splendid and
elevating nature. On such evenings, believe me, there is a general spirit
of enthusiasm which has little in common with the mere conviviality
of the beer-table. This afternoon we are all going to march through the
High Street in parade garb, and there will be a good deal of shouting
and singing. Then we go by steamer to Rolandseck, where we have a big
dinner in the Hotel Croyen. . . . The bout began on the evening of
the day before yesterday; we drank until two o'clock in the morning,
assembled yesterday at n a.m. for a morning pint, and then went on a
spree in the market-place, and had lunch and coffee together at Kley's.18
Perhaps this letter still sounds a bit priggish, even from Fried-
rich Nietzsche.
Bonn had become unbearable. Well before he composed the
"Förster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, I, 146.
w
Briefe, II, 12. Oct. 20, 1865. English translation in Förster-Nietzsche,
Nietzsche, I, 147.
ι8 NIETZSCHE
a Briefe,
Briefe, II, 45. April 7, 1866. To Carl von Gersdorfi.
Werke, IV, 126.
THE STUDENT 19
Yet it is dear from these notes seen as a whole that Nietzsche
was a careful and a curious worker, that he kept asking himself
questions about his Greeks that went far beyond mere cata-
loguing. His most finished work in the field, De Laertii Di-
ogenis fontibus, was printed in the Rheinisches Museum für
Philologie in 1868 and 1869, and gave the twenty-four year old
scholar a European reputation among professional philologists.
More important in the long run for Nietzsche's career was his
discovery of Schopenhauer's philosophy. In one of his numer-
ous autobiographical fragments he has described how, rum-
maging in a Leipzig bookshop during the lonely days after he
had broken with Bonn and the Franconia, he came across
Schopenhauer's The World as Will and Idea, took the book
home, and devoured it with increasing excitement. This was
something less than what had happened to St. Paul on the road
to Damascus or to Rousseau on the road to Vincennes, but it
too was a great conversion. Schopenhauer's slightly Bieder-
meier stoicism, though it could not for long satisfy the emo-
tional needs of a man as God-ridcten as Nietzsche, solved in this
crisis and for a moment the problem of the universe. "Here
each line," he wrote a few years later of his first reading of
Schopenhauer, "cried out renunciation, denial, resignation;
here I saw a mirror in which the world, life, my own mind
were reflected in fearful grandeur. Here the wholly disinter-
ested and heavenly eye of art looked at me, here I saw illness
and salvation, banishment and refuge, hell and heaven."28
The world makes no sense intellectually; Kant and the eight-
eenth-century philosophes were no more than whistlers in the
dark. Will, the blind striving of millions of organisms, is what
" Wer\e, III, 298. "Rückblick auf meine zwei Leipziger Jahre."
20 NIETZSCHE
IV
Hero-worship has produced flattering descriptions of the
young Nietzsche. W e have some help from photographs, and
notably from one his sister gives us, taken at his confirmation
at the age of sixteen. The portentous Polish cavalryman's
mustache of his maturity is not yet there. The lad's rather large
mouth is set firmly. His eyes look dark and for so young a boy,
surprisingly deep-sunken. His face is round and full, yet sensi-
tive. He is certainly no Nordic, but he might be almost any-
thing else.
He appears at Bonn "a picture of health and strength, broad-
shouldered, brown, with rather thick fair hair, and of exactly
the same height as Goethe." 25 Goethe, of course, is for Ger-
mans strength and beauty made flesh, and to associate him ever
so tenuously with Nietzsche is to make Nietzsche share some-
thing of Olympian health. Elizabeth reports that her brother
swam, skated, and rode horseback, and that only his short-
sightedness prevented his being still more athletic. Later ob-
servers were not struck with any such evidence of physical
prowess. They are, indeed, usually reporting after Nietzsche
had become famous — which was only after he had become
" One of the most plausible of these descriptions is that made by a French-
man, Edouard Schuré, who saw Nietzsche in Bayreuth in the 1870's, and re-
ported in the 1890*5. It is given in Salter, Nietzsche, 476.
NIETZSCHE AT SIXTEEN
From a photograph, 1861
THE STUDENT 23
hearty, sane Germanic health. Such is the account Frau
Förster-Nietzsche gives us.27
T h e medical problems of Nietzsche's life are puzzling enough
to the physician. They are quite insoluble to the layman. One
can only note that Elizabeth herself was no physician, and that
she could not bear to think of her brother as in any way abnor-
mal. H e was, she is quite willing to admit, a genius. But
"genius" is a very nice word, and "abnormal" is not. Later in
Nietzsche's career his behavior was clearly that of an extreme
neurotic; and though "neurotic" is also a word of pejorative
overtones, and though it has somewhat different meanings for
physician and for layman, most of us know neurotic behavior
when we see it — and sometimes, even when we indulge in it.
Whatever name we give this behavior of Nietzsche's, it is
evident enough, in milder forms, in what we know of the
school and university student. The young Nietzsche, swim
and skate though he did, seems always to have been awkward
in the use of his body. Sensitive and self-conscious, he did not
like to appear awkward. If you prefer, you may say that he was
a perfectionist, and that he would do nothing he could not
from the first do pretty well. Or you may say that he was proud,
or vain, and that he hated to seem ridiculous. Whatever the
reason, save for a tempestuous facility with the piano, he had
no bodily skills. Bodily energy he had, or at least a kind of
nervous restlessness for which he found an outlet in long walks.
little vacation trips together, she writes, for instance, that they
ran up a huge bill at Constance because Fritz would not eat in
the table d'hote. He called such meals "the browsing of herds,"
and on this occasion had all their meals served privately. As he
paid the bill, he remarked sadly, "Lizzie, one always has to pay
dearly for grazing away from the herd." 3 One more instance,
close to neurosis. Piccard, a colleague, tells how he advised
Nietzsche to see the cathedral at Lausanne, and how carefully
he described the best way to see the sights of the whole city.
Nietzsche got lost, walked around aimlessly for hours, and
came back to the railway station without having seen anything
of the city itself, let alone the cathedral. "But why didn't you
ask some one the way?" said Piccard. And Nietzsche replied,
"You know, Piccard, they might have laughed at m e ! " 4 .
Nietzsche, then, had a kind of neurotic dislike for mingling
with his fellows, a dislike which the professional psychologist
could no doubt break down into its complex parts. Fear of
ridicule was certainly one of the most important of these.
Nietzsche himself was sure that this feeling of discomfort in
crowds was a most aristocratic trait. His admiring biographers
have repeated the word "aristocratic" in constant admiration of
their hero's behavior. Though this comforting adjective has
not infrequently been given such an application, especially
since the rise of the middle classes, in the general course of
European history aristocratic folk have not behaved like Nie-
is the best single collection of Nietzsche's letters. It has six volumes (volume V
in two parts).
'Förster-Nietzsche, Lije, I, 314.
1 C . A. Bernoulli, Overbec\ und Nietzsche, II, 169. In Lausanne, Nietzsche
would probably have had to use French, a language which he read easily,
but did not speak well.
30 NIETZSCHE
tzsche. There is something insecure, timid, and defeated about
the over-sensitive young professor that in no way seems aristo-
cratic. Aristocrats have to be fairly insensitive in some ways or
they cease to stay up where aristocrats belong. They must not
be afraid of crowds, nor even of vulgarity — least of all in
themselves. Nietzsche was, in simple fact, a middle-clàss in-
tellectual in revolt against most of the ways of his class. "F. W.
von Nietzky," the would-be descendant of Polish noblemen,
was hardly more of an aristocrat than was Keats. Both, no
doubt, belong with the eternal aristocracy of the spirit; but
Nietzsche, one suspects, would have been willing to compro-
mise on some more earthly and more immediate distinction,
which he was never quite to obtain.
Whatever its roots, whatever its explanation, Nietzsche's
inability to lead a conventional social life has important conse-
quences in any estimate of his work. In spite of the many
insights he achieved, in spite of the intensity of his search for
a good way of life for men on this earth, at bottom Nietzsche's
study of man as a social and political animal — and this is most
of his work — suffers from the fact that he knew so little, at
first hand, of other human beings. To a sufficiently transcen-
dental critic, this is of course hardly a serious deficiency. But
Nietzsche himself tried hard not to set up as a transcendentalist,
directed indeed some of his sharpest barbs at innocent old Kant
and other dwellers in the untrodden ways of pure spirit. On
Nietzsche's own grounds, his withdrawal from this world was
a limitation and a weakness.
It was a weakness reflected rather in his attempts at practical
judgments, in his sense of what is possible, than in the actual
materials, in the facts and observations he worked with. Nie-
THE PROFESSOR 31
have had to the end the greatest admiration and love for
Nietzsche, whom he held to be a genius, an unquestioned mem-
b e r — though certainly not the greatest — of the small group
of supremely great German men of letters. But Overbeck
thought he was justified from intimate experience of Nietzsche's
daily life in noting that his friend was also selfish, absurdly
sensitive, a neurotic invalid given to self-doctoring, an awkward
figure in society, a thinker impatient of criticism, assured and
intolerant. For all that, and indeed because of it, Overbeck to
the end cherished towards Nietzsche an affection he himself
called "unclouded." 6 It was, in part, no doubt, the affection
the competent in this narrow world often have for the incom-
petent, an affection that grows on irritation. Nietzsche may
well have been a great man; he was certainly not a competent
one.
Nietzsche's great sensibility was perhaps unduly concentrated
on his few friends. He had no great abstract loyalties to take
up his energies and his vanity, no routine administrative duties,
no hobby, no gift at all for idleness, for doing nothing. Even
the Franco-Prussian War proved for him a confused and un-
profitable interlude. He had had to become a naturalized
Swiss citizen, and so could not join the German armies. A t the
first news, he was proudly cosmopolitan and superior. But soon
the itch to take part in this marvellous redemption of the
Teutonic race from Latin vices and Latin rationalism grew too
strong. He enlisted in the German ambulance service, and
after a short period of training was sent out to the battlefields,
where he promptly took very ill with dysentery and diphtheria,
and had to be invalided out of the service. Elizabeth regards
'Bernoulli, Overbed^ und Nietzsche, I, 63.
34 NIETZSCHE
II
Of all the men and women who touched Nietzsche's life,
Richard Wagner is perhaps the most important, as he is cer-
tainly the most striking. The brief and intense friendship
between the two men takes up most of the early years of
Nietzsche's professorate; its long disintegration filled the rest
of his conscious life. Just before his final madness Nietzsche
printed a series of violent attacks on the now-dead Wagner.
The problems of the relationship, complicated by the fact that
Nietzsche was in some senses in love with Wagner's mistress
and wife, Cosima, have tempted all sorts of writers, and there
is already a large Wagner-Nietzsche literature.9 Both Masters
have their disciples and their defenders, though Wagner, whose
charms are perhaps a little more obvious, has here the numeri-
cal advantage.
Nietzsche had met Wagner briefly at Leipzig, but in the rush
of a mere social occasion had had no chance to impress himself
upon the composer. Now he learned that Wagner, having been
forced into the open in his relations with Cosima, the wife of
Wagner's friend von Biilow, had left the scandal behind him,
and had retreated with Cosima and his Art to the peace of the
near-by Swiss village of Triebschen. Admiration and ambition
aiding, Nietzsche so far overcame his natural diffidence as to
call on the great man. He was politely, and then cordially,
received. He was young, eager, admiring, a professor and
hence perhaps not without some influence on public opinion.
Wagner, who had not yet entirely conquered public opinion,
even in Germany, welcomed a new disciple. Soon Nietzsche
* For a brief discussion of it. see the bibliography, p. 255.
36 NIETZSCHE
was spending as much of his spare time as possible in Trieb-
schen, listening to Wagner's music, discussing the supreme
synthesis of human culture Wagner was preparing — had in-
deed practically achieved — talking, eating, strolling by the
lake, running errands for the household.
Triebschen is removed from us by an awkward interval of
time and its idyll necessarily seems to us to fall short of classic
finish. The setting is wrong: a Swiss villa of the 1870's will do
at best for comic opera. The characters lack serenity and no-
bility. They seem to come from a slightly depressing novel, or
from real — too real — life. Wagner, high-priest even to him-
self, living each moment and each act in a supreme, intense,
and wearing dedication; Frau Cosima, nursing, protecting,
flattering and cajoling this man who had brought her fame,
if he had not quite made her Isolde; the four children of Cosima
and von Bülow, with the fifth, little Siegfried, child of Cosima
and Wagner, all of them lively, and, in such a household, rela-
tively uninhibited; the awkward young professor and philolo-
gist, protective cavalryman's mustache just grown, listening,
admiring, and when opportunity presented — and when Wag-
ner allowed someone else to talk — breaking into long periods
of eloquence in which the Master saved the clean soul of animal
man from the corruptness of Socrates and Christ.
Time has made almost everything about Triebschen slightly
ludicrous. The villa itself, furnished "in accordance with the
style of a Paris furniture company, who had been somewhat
lavish in their use of pink satin and little Cupids," seems no fit
birthplace for a pure Teutonic Siegfried. Then there is Frau
Cosima strolling by the lake, "dressed in a pink cashmere
gown with broad revers of real lace, on her arm a large Tuscan
T H E PROFESSOR 37
And therefore:
When the Dionysian powers rise with such strength as we are experi-
encing at present, there can be no doubt that, wrapped in a cloud, Apollo
has already descended to us. . . · 1 3
Ill
Nietzsche almost from the first seems to have regarded his
duties at the University as an unpleasant interruption of the
serious work of his life. He took maximum advantages of
vacations and holidays; he was ill with increasing frequency,
and in one way or another managed to pare down his actual
teaching to a minimum. The publication of The Birth of
Tragedy and its effect on his reputation further diminished his
teaching load. Serious students began to avoid him. The little
book was hailed favorably by the Wagnerites, neglected by the
general public, and damned almost unanimously by Nietzsche's
professional colleagues in the study of philology. Had Nie-
11 The Birth of Tragedy, chap. xxv.
42 NIETZSCHE
IV
One series of gestures Nietzsche did make, in the middle
seventies, towards reconciling his sense of mission — mission
to do something great, mission to reform the universe — with
his position as a university professor. He projected first as lec-
tures, then as essays, a series of discussions on all the great
issues which, as editorial writers like to put it, confront man-
kind. Of these, four longish essays were actually written, and
published between 1873 and 1876 under a title officially trans-
lated in the English edition of Nietzsche's works as Thoughts
out of Season: the untranslatable German original, Unzeit-
gemässe Betrachtungen, may be roughly given as Considera-
tions contrary to the Spirit of the Age. In these essays praising
Schopenhauer as an educator, damning the philistine and com-
placent rationalism of the famous Strauss of The Life of Jesus,
worrying about the deadening effect of our modern interest in
history on our energies and originality, praising Wagner in
Bayreuth, Nietzsche conscientiously carries out the promise of
his title. Everything is wrong in the nineteenth century. The
age is materialistic, vulgar, corrupt, leveling all distinction of
mind or spirit in a democratic tyranny, doomed to extinction
— and so on in a vein familiar nowadays to everyone. Nie-
tzsche's tone is very much assured, very superior, very earnest
and omniscient. It is a tone recognizable enough for twentieth-
century Americans, among whom it is rather oddly known as
"liberal."
These thoughts were apparently a little too far out of season.
They were not appreciated save by the now narrowing circle
of Nietzsche's own friends. The philologists no longer even
φ NIETZSCHE
bothered to attack the young professor. The Germans, after
1870, felt pretty much in tune with the times. They didn't even
listen to Nietzsche as he urged them to gather behind him and
go somewhere Bismarck couldn't possibly lead. But not only
was Thoughts out of Season a failure. The one great corporate
effort into which the young man had put the devouring en-
thusiasm of his ambition was turning out badly. Wagner was
going wrong; he was succeeding.
The composer had long wanted to build a center wherein his
music-dramas could receive the complete and reverent per-
formance impossible in theatres built for the limited operas of
Gluck and Mozart. It was not fitting, indeed it was hardly
possible, to present Götterdämmerung in a setting meant for
Così fan tutte. In the 1870's, he set seriously to work on what
finally became the shrine of Bayreuth. The money essential to
the undertaking — ultimately supplied by the mad King of
Bavaria — Wagner at first tried to raise by an appeal to his
devotees, an appeal conducted with a very modern apparatus
of publicity, meetings, committees, a "campaign," in short.
Nietzsche, high in the esteem of the Master, was given an
important place in the campaign. His essay on "Richard Wag-
ner in Bayreuth," included in Thoughts out of Season, was
originally campaign literature, though in the three years or so
it was being put together, it lost a bit of its early freshness.
Nietzsche was chosen to write a particularly important piece
of publicity, a direct appeal for funds. His draft was severely
criticized by his co-workers, who found it better philosophy
than advertising. It was cast aside as much too high-falutin',
and Nietzsche received another of the innumerable wounds he
collected all his life — with profit, if not with pleasure.
RICHARD AND COSIMA WAGNER
From a photograph, ι8γο
THE PROFESSOR 47
More and more people kept discovering Wagner. They were
rich, noble, snobbish, vulgar, worldly. They did not seem to
find Wagner at all superior to the Spirit of the Age. They did
not, unless they had happened to glance at The Birth of Trag-
edy, think of him as Dionysos. They did not, in fact, often
notice Herr Nietzsche. They took up most of Wagner's time.
The Master not only did not mind them: he seemed to like
them. They were helping him build Bayreuth.
Bayreuth was built, and in 1876 the first of the festivals
opened with performances of the whole Ring of the Nibelungen.
Nietzsche could hardly refuse the invitation to be an honored
guest. He came, and was lost in the press of visitors. Bayreuth
was no Heavenly City: it was already no more than a summer
resort, a watering-place.17 Nietzsche took ill, and went off to
the quiet woods of near-by Klingenbrunn to get strength to
face the dress rehearsals and formal performances of the four
operas. He returned to Bayreuth but could not go through
with it. The dress rehearsals were enough. He had been look-
ing for some supreme, unearthly experience, some touch of
eternity. He found himself looking at Grand Opera.
M y blunder was this. I travelled to Bayreuth with an ideal in my
breast, and was thus doomed to experience the bitterest disappointment.
The preponderance of ugliness, grotesqueness and strong pepper thor-
oughly repelled me. 1 8
II
There is not much use trying to follow Nietzsche in the
detail of his wanderings during this decade, nor in trying to
trace the ups and downs of his health and his friendships.8 But
there is one phase of his relations to his fellows so characteristic
of the man, and so illuminating, that it is worth dwelling upon.
As at Triebschen, it is a triangular relation, and as at Triebschen,
it is a tragi-comic idyll. The figures were Nietzsche, Paul Ree,
and a young and very intellectual Jewish girl, Russian — or
rather, Finnish — by nationality, Mile. Lou Salome. The three
met first in the circle of Mathilda von Meysenbug. Lou was a
precocious girl, with literary and philosophical aspirations, and
most probably also with a few more ordinary, if not more
specifically feminine, aspirations. She was chaperoned — the
word is a bit strong — by a not too clearly designing mother.
The interplay of emotion among the three is most complicated
and confused, and has not been cleared up very satisfactorily
by the letters, confessions, and memoirs of the participants,
and the debates of Nietzsche's biographers and hagiographers.®
Nietzsche certainly saw in Lou a prospective disciple, a
tender, respectful disciple, ewig weibliche. When, writes And-
ler "she confided to him her intention of sacrificing her life to
Truth, he recognized in her a predestined companion." 10 At
any rate, he made her a formal proposal of marriage, to be
delivered through Rèe. Whether Ree delivered it or not is
uncertain. That Lou was also interested in Ree, whom she must
have found rather easier to get along with than Nietzsche, is
Adler and Jung and Freud are hardly necessary here: almost
any kind of life is clinical experience enough to give an under-
standing of such a case. Even Nietzsche himself could have
understood it — in another.
Ill
This is the decade when Nietzsche's best known books were
written — though "written" is a modest, routine word for what
Nietzsche himself regarded as a cosmic process. He composed
them in all sorts of places and in all sorts of conditions —
sitting on the sea-shore near Genoa, strolling the back-ways of
Nice, striding in ecstasy by Lake Silvaplana, hunched near-
sightedly over a table in a dozen rooming-houses. His habit
was to think out the matter occupying his mind while he was
walking; in times of great excitement he could walk for hours
at a rate apparently quite inconsistent with his invalidism.
Back in his room, he would put his thoughts together in a series
of aphoristic passages, or in a short chapter. A few days, at most
a few weeks, of these erratic efforts would exhaust his strength.
" Forster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, II, 181.
THE PROPHET 59
Headaches, sleeplessness, and chloral would follow, until calm
returned, and inspiration began again its wearing course.
The books he wrote under these conditions were naturally
not systematic, orderly treatises. They were collections of great
and lesser thoughts, beaded together on the string of Nietzsche's
temperament. Critics have inevitably found a higher unity,
indeed, several higher unities, in his work. But on the surface
— and surfaces are important — a book of Nietzsche's lacks
form and continuity. He is always a bit out of breath. And,
except in small doses, he is likely to weary readers short on
devotion.14 He repeats himself perhaps more often — perhaps
only more obviously — than is usual among more formal
philosophers.
We shall have to return to this problem of how far Nietzsche's
work holds together. Here we are concerned with the cata-
logue of his books. They were not, by a publisher's no doubt
confined standards, successful books. His Birth of Tragedy and
Thoughts out of Season had been published by E. W. Fritsch
of Leipzig, Wagner's own publisher, to whom he had been
recommended as one of the inner circle of Wagnerites. Human,
All Too Human was not the kind of book Fritsch dealt in.
Nietzsche transferred his patronage to Schmeitzner of Chem-
nitz, who continued to publish for him down to 1884. When
Fritsch, after Wagner's death, consolidated his list and took
back Nietzsche's books, there were still "62 hundredweight"
of these earlier writings unsold.15 Nietzsche was hard on pub-
lishers, nagging them over details of printing, always unsatis-
" Overbeck himself notes the limitations of the "books of aphorisms" his
friend wrote. Bernoulli, Overbeck und Nietzsche, I, 228.
"Förster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, II, 267.
6o NIETZSCHE
fied with sales and promotion, convinced that publishers were
natural slaves and herd-men who owed their unnatural power
over authors to the perverse structure of nineteenth-century
society. In 1884, after years of wrangling with his publishers
— and after finding it very hard if not impossible to get a new
one — he decided to have Part IV of Zarathustra printed and
published at his own expense. Beyond Good and Evil was so
published in 1886, and all the rest of his works to the end of his
sane life. The great man was reduced to the expedient of buy-
ing his way into print. The swinish public wouldn't even root
among his pearls.
Human, All Too Human, published in 1878, inaugurates a
series of books which clearly belong together. All are frankly
aphoristic, modeled as to form on the great French aphorists
like La Rochefoucauld. They are collections of thoughts on
men and morals, at once chaotic and encyclopaedic. They vary
somewhat in tone, but they are all expressions of what Nietzsche
called "the free spirit" — anti-intellectual, but also anti-roman-
tic, contemptuous of the plush civilization of Bismarck's Ger-
many, sure that most men are fools, but still unsure as to just
who are wise. They are part of the field of belles lettres', had
Nietzsche never written anything more, he would certainly not
be known as a philosopher, but at most as a German imitator
of the French aphorists.
Human, All Too Human was followed in 1881 by The Dawn
of Day and in 1882 by The Joyful Wisdom. These are the books
that celebrate Nietzsche's emancipation from teaching and his
discovery of Italy — sunny, classic, smiling Italy, free of damp,
beer, corsetry, Protestantism, and Wagner's music. The Joyful
Wisdom is — or aspires to be — the Provençal gai saber, the
THE PROPHET 6l
flashing southern wit, never morose, never befuddled with
metaphysics, but capable of tragic depth and penetration. Both
books are more cheerful than Human, All Too Human, less
bitterly critical of life as ordinary people live it, less closely
modeled on French patterns. They are Nietzsche's best-tem-
pered books.
While they were being written, Nietzsche was meditating
much grander things. He was not going to content himself
with being a German Montaigne, resigned to writing wisely
and skeptically about a world he could not change. He was
still the Nietzsche who, in Thoughts out of Season, had really
hoped to change the German season. After all, there were a lot
of clever writers in the world, even in the i88o's, and the world
wasn't very clearly the better for their being in it. What was
wanted was someone of the stamp of the great religious leaders,
Buddha, Zoroaster, Jesus, Mohammed, but someone who could
do the job much better than they had done.
Nietzsche set himself up as prophet in Thus Spa\e Zara-
thustra: A Boo\ for All and None, published in four short parts
between 1883 and 1885. The book is in form no more unified
than all his other books after The Birth of Tragedy. It is a
collection of parables, sermons, and reflections, written in what
is, no doubt justly, called poetic prose, and giving an account of
the mission of Zarathustra to pave the way for the coming of
the Superman. Zarathustra has no more than the name in
common with his historical original, Zoroaster, and is as much
nineteenth-century Nietzsche as the Persians, Hottentots, or
Hurons of eighteenth-century letters were Montesquieu, Vol-
taire, or Diderot. The style throughout is exceedingly elevated;
Zarathustra would be lost without his "saith," and "thou" and
62 NIETZSCHE
"ye," helpless without his exclamation points. In English
translation he sounds very pseudo-biblical, like the King James
version gone wrong, and almost inevitably suggests the literary
style of the angel Moroni, as transcribed by another and less
highly educated prophet, Joseph Smith. Indeed, Thus Spa\e
Zarathustra has become, for a certain type of half-educated in-
tellectual throughout the world, a kind of Enchiridion.
This is, of course, the report of an unbeliever. For the
Nietzscheans, Thus Spa\e Zarathustra is an undoubted master-
piece, a sacred writing inferior in depth and dignity to none.
Nietzsche himself was of this opinion. "Whenever I dip into
my Zarathustra," he said, "I walk up and down my room for
half-an-hour, unable to repress my sobs." And his sister con-
tinues, "The figure of Zarathustra is the poet's highest creation,
it is a type of eternal beauty, of a divine transfiguration of the
world — it is the Superman himself." 16
Whatever its depth and beauties — probably, since the world
of the flesh is so limited, because of its depth and beauties —
Thus Spa\e Zarathustra is an enigmatic work. Nietzsche seems
pretty clearly to have set himself next the deliberate task of
bringing it down to earth, of expounding analytically and in
plain prose the elevated obscurities that give the book its first
hold on the seeker. After the Word, comes exegesis. The
result was two books which, to many limited intellects outside
the circles of convinced Nietzscheans, are his masterpieces:
Beyond Good and Evil, published in 1886, and The Genealogy
of Morals, published in 1887, and written, Elizabeth claims, in
twenty days.17
, ™ Förster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, II, 234.
"Förster-Nietzsche, Nietzsche, II, 277.
T H E PROPHET 63
But Goethe also wrote poems like Ueber allen Gipfeln and
Nietzsche did not.
IV
Nietzsche's last few years were spent in loneliness: hotel-
keepers, servants, fellow-guests, a very few casual acquaintances
made the sum of his relations with his fellow-men. It was, if
you are a Nietzschean, the loneliness of a brooding Titan left
alone by ungrateful little men; if you are not a Nietzschean, it
was the loneliness of a man who had quarreled with all his
friends and relatives. Peter Gast remained, and from time to
time stayed with Nietzsche, and helped him with his manu-
scripts. The rest were all gone — Wagner and Cosima long
ago. Ree and Lou Salome, Fräulein von Meysenbug, all the
arty and talkative little folk of her circle had broken with
Nietzsche, or left him to himself. Frau Overbeck had mixed
in the affair of Lou, Elizabeth had replied indignantly, and
though there was no formal break between Nietzsche and Over-
beck, there was a coolness, and a lessening of letter-writing.
Rohde was one of the last to go. But in the spring of 1886
Nietzsche had stayed for a while in Leipzig, and misunder-
standings between the two had come to the surface. To his
sister he wrote from Leipzig:
Neither Rohde nor Overbeck have the slightest idea of what I am
about, let alone a feeling of obligation towards me. In this university
atmosphere the best men decay; I feel it continually in the background
and as an ultimate determinant, even with such men as Rohde and
Overbeck, this damned general indifference and total lack of belief.28
him too, and her leaving had in some ways been a worse blow
than the defection of Lou. Nietzsche had come to regard
Elizabeth as his; she was proof that he, too, owned a woman.
And now, at almost forty, she married Bernhard Förster, an
anti-semitic agitator who had founded a Germanic racial colony
in Paraguay, and was taking her off there to the ends of the
earth. Nietzsche had opposed the engagement, but, as usual
when he attempted to get something done, he behaved very
unskillfully. Elizabeth took literally his sour and self-pitying
assertions that he could get along by himself and married
Förster in 1885. Nietzsche wrote an extraordinary letter to the
bridegroom.
Love is leading the Lama — apologies, but I have called her that up
to now — into many dangers, it seems, far from home, into a life full
of temptations. Some things will go well, others badly: on the whole,
she has a heroic future before her. So have I: it seems that this is char-
acteristic of our stock. A n d if love leads her in a less abstract form
than it leads me, perhaps she has a better taste, and has chosen the better
part: namely Herr Bernhard Förster. In such matters, women are
shrewder than men. W e men run after truth, and similar pallid beauties.
. . . This, to conclude from letters and other psychological documents
has not been my sister's fate.
debts — to you, for instance. Right now I'm having all the
anti-Semites shot — Dionysos." It was this letter, and a longer
one to Burckhardt which the historian had brought at once to
Overbeck, that sent Overbeck to Turin.
The whole sheaf is no doubt revealing to the professional
psychiatrist, and tempting to the amateur psychiatrist that
lurks, not sufficiently unsuspecting, in almost everyone who
writes today. The illusions of grandeur, the assumption of the
rôle of Napoleon-Caesar, are obvious enough. Dionysos and
the Crucified One are echoes of Nietzsche's own intellectual
history. But the strangest, most revealing, in some ways most
obvious of the letters was a scrawled line to the widowed
«
struck him in Turin, held his whole right side, and prevented,
one can only say fortunately, his writing. He would lie for
hours, looking fixedly out of the window. Music stirred him
to the end, and to the end he could listen to Peter Gast, who
had followed the Master to Weimar. On August 25, 1900 he
died quietly.
Nietzsche's illnesses were many and varied. It is unlikely
that, even with the full information we have about his daily
life, a trained physician could from such documentary informa-
tion alone make a satisfactory diagnosis of his trouble. Cer-
tainly, it would be rash for a mere historian to attempt such a
diagnosis. But one thing seems fairly clear. He did have
syphilis, and the paresis with which his life ended followed on
a syphilitic infection.28 Some natural and presumably very
useful sentiments, strong even among intellectuals, tend to
focus a disproportionate attention on the fact that a great man
had a venereal disease. With Nietzsche, especially, that atten-
tion is perhaps rather cruelly sharpened by the workings of the
comic spirit. For syphilis is not a philosopher's disease. Even
after we cease in our minds to associate it with sin, it cannot
be dissociated from indignities.
You cannot, however, explain Nietzsche by the spirochetes.
His trouble — and his genius — are not so simple as that. And
even after psychiatrist, psychologist, physician, and biographer
have got through with the man, his printed words remain.
28 T h e explanation of syphilis was first ably and completely put forward
in P. G. Möbius, Ueber das Pathologische bei Nietzsche (1902), and put be-
yond reasonable doubt by Podach's Nietzsches Zusammenbruch, based on an
examination of the papers recording the clinical examination of Nietzsche at
Jena. It has been bitterly denied, even in the face of this evidence, by most
Nietzscheans, or slurred over in silence.
THE PROPHET 73
They now are Nietzsche. They now are part of what we call
Western culture. And more: they have been incorporated into
the body of beliefs to which the German National Socialists
subscribe. They have, then, become a part of something many
men fear as the mortal enemy of Western culture. Nietzsche's
personal history fades into unimportance compared with the
history of his ideas. We may here leave the nicer disputes over
Nietzsche's life and personality to others, and attempt the
difficult task of analyzing and classifying his ideas.29
29O£ the books which attempt at some length the process of linking
Nietzsche's life and character with his work, I find best among the older
ones C. A . Bernoulli, Overbec\ und Nietzsche, and among the newer ones
K . Jaspers, Nietzsche: Einfuhrung in das Verständnis seines Philosophieren
(1936). Professor Jaspers is certainly not guilty of over-simplification. Neither
of these books is available in English.
CHAPTER IV
W H A T NIETZSCHE H A T E D
Fancy judging the Greeks in the German style, from their philoso-
phers; fancy using the suburban respectability of the Socratic schools as
a key to what is fundamentally Hellenic! The philosophers are of course
the decadents of Hellas, the counter-movement directed against the old
and noble tribe (against the agonal instinct, against the polis, against
the value of the race, against the authority of tradition). 6
But in his younger days these two were his Masters. They
taught him to distrust the comforts of logic and common-sense,
to seek refuge in something endless, indefinable, and indescrib-
able, which he was to spend his life trying to limit, define, and
describe. They did not make him a romantic, but they con-
firmed his romanticism. He tried to shake off Schopenhauer's
pessimism, but succeeded only in calling it optimism. His
concrete debt to Schopenhauer — his ideas on women, for in-
stance — remained very great. He tried to shake off Wagner's
confused bumbling by going to those masters of clarity, the
French moralistes.
Nietzsche learned much from the French. He did not need to
learn to write, for even as a schoolboy he could write a clear, im-
patient German. But he learned to write better, to mould a
sharper phrase, to twist suddenly into irony, to condense and
to shade. His was still, however, a German style, full of striv-
ing and parentheses, and hitched to all the heavens. He went
to La Rochefoucauld and Beyle for an antidote to German
Gemütlichkeit and idealism, of which he never had much any-
way, just as he went to Bizet for an antidote to Wagner's music.
But an antidote is not in itself a form of nourishment, and in
spite of his "middle period" of aphoristic books like Human,
All Too Human, and The Dawn of Day, he never attained the
sure good judgment of the more serene of his models, like
Montaigne, nor the delicate sensitivity of the more troubled,
like Pascal. Proof of what he failed to get from the French is
II
From all this miscellaneous, but on the whole overwhelm-
ingly literary, abstract, and second-hand experience, Nietzsche
produced what is in many ways a unique and original inter-
pretation of what must be grandly called the meaning of life.
It was not, as we shall see, by any means an interpretation as
unzeitgemäss, as contrary to the spirit of the age, as he believed
it to be. Indeed, Nietzsche's importance for us is that he is a
part of a movement among his contemporaries and near-con-
temporaries which is rather unfortunately called anti-intellectu-
alism, a movement which is in some sense at least as old as
Greek thought, but which in our time has taken on a com-
plexity and a thoroughness perhaps new. Nietzsche belongs in
WHAT NIETZSCHE HATED 83
the history of thought with Marx, Georges Sorel, Freud, Pareto,
and hundreds of lesser men, down to the latest popularizers of
semantics. His work in part differs greatly from theirs. He is
either the enfant terrible or the mad prophet of the movement
— or both. But he is part of a movement, and no solitary. This
scorner of history is a product of history.
Nietzsche himself, at least, could hardly complain too bit-
terly if we accept him on his own grounds, and attempt to
arrange his ideas according to a thoroughly anti-intellectualist
scheme. We shall attempt to see what he hated and what he
wanted; or to use more abstract terms, and perhaps misleading
ones, to distinguish between the negative and the positive
aspects of his work, between Nietzsche the destroyer and
Nietzsche the builder. Again, he has made himself so great a
reputation as the "philosopher with a hammer" that he could
hardly object if we concentrate at first upon what he proudly
regarded as his destructive labors. We shall begin appropriately
with what Nietzsche hated.
He hated extensively and energetically, so that it is hard to
distinguish among his hatreds. One of the most constant of
them, however, one which appears clearly in his very first
book, is a hatred for the tradition of European rationalism.
Socrates, one of the great heroes of that tradition, is for
Nietzsche a villain. Before Socrates, the Greeks had been,
according to Nietzsche, happy creatures of instinct and habit,
fighters, revelers, builders, singers, "the men who fought at
Marathon." With Socrates they began to think — not to think
as healthy animals probably think, and as the old Greeks
thought, simply to find ways of getting what they wanted,
getting what their wills and instincts made them strive for.
84 NIETZSCHE
III
Nietzsche, then, rejected with contempt that current of Euro-
pean rationalism represented in his time by natural science and,
in ethics, political theory, philosophy in general, by positivism,
materialism, empiricism, by the French philosophes and the
English utilitarians. But he disliked quite as vigorously that
strain in European rationalism which is usually labeled "ideal-
ism," a strain clear in the formal philosophy of Plato, the pupil
of the original rationalist, Socrates, and fixed by Leibnitz and
Kant as the dominant form of German philosophy. In his
attacks on philosophic idealism, Nietzsche's hatred ripens into
some of his most remarkable pages of criticism, pages which
ironically foreshadow the attacks on philosophic idealism made
by such modern scientists as Pareto. We can study best this
phase of Nietzsche's work in his famous comments on Kant in
Beyond Good and Evil.
Kant, says Nietzsche, was proud of having made what he
thought was a discovery, the existence in men of the faculty
of synthetic judgment a priori. In other words, Kant, like
Plato, was hunting for an absolute, a formula in words to which
all men would subscribe as the Truth. He had no trouble in
showing that sense-experience could not provide any such
eternal, changeless, absolute Truth, and that scientific laws
were not truths in this sense. But he dug up an absolute — in
words, where it can always be found.
"How arc synthetic judgments a priori possible?" Kant asks himself
— and what is really his answer? "By means of a means (faculty)" —
but unfortunately not in five words, but so circumstantially, imposingly,
and with such display of German profundity and verbal flourishes, that
one altogether loses sight of the comical niaiserie allemande involved in
88 NIETZSCHE
such an answer. . . . But — is that an answer? An explanation? Or is
it not rather merely a repetition of the question? How does opium in-
duce sleep? "By means of a means (faculty)" namely, the virtus dor-
mativa, replies the doctor in Molière,
Quia est in eo virtus dormativa
Cujus est natura sensus assoupire
IV
Nietzsche, then, condemned both the materialistic and the
idealistic philosophical solutions: both were to him essentially
intellectualist at bottom, both were merely more or less in-
genious metaphysical dodging of a problem essentially moral:
right conduct here and now. But he was at least as violent in
condemnation of a solution he, like the late Irving Babbitt and
many other modern thinkers, always associated chiefly with
Rousseau. In spite of his frequent damniñg of "intellect," his
frequent praise of "instinct," "impulse," "nature," he insisted
over and over again that he did not mean by any of these nice
words what Rousseau and his followers seemed to mean by
them. "Rousseau, or the return to nature, in impuris naturali-
busSignificantly, the list of Nietzsche's "impossible people"
from which this malicious characterization is drawn, ends with
a very earnest and unsubtle condemnation: "Zola, or the love
of stinking." 23
The Rousseauists, Nietzsche felt, preached that the lowest
and cheapest human feelings were the best guide to conduct.
They appealed from reason to sentiment, and beyond sentiment
to the deepest well-springs of desire in the animal man, the
plebs, the herd-man. They were justified in attacking the silly
"right reason" of the philosophes and the commonsense school;
but they themselves fell into even sorrier depths when they
appealed from reason and commonsense to common feeling.
Rousseau was really the father of all the worst modern heresies,
democracy, socialism, humanitarianism, pacifism (they had, of
course, many mothers!). He and his followers gave Christian-
" The Twilight of the Idols, "Skirmishes in a War with the Age," § i.
92 NIETZSCHE
ity, which had become a mere tradition, and hence an almost
harmless, if not actually beneficial, opiate for the people, a new
and baleful energy. This new political Christianity, this appeal
to "natural m a n " and his General Will, aspired to a world at
best mere organized mediocrity, at worst a chaos of stupid
conflicts among dog-men.
T o Nietzsche, Rousseau's influence was not at all limited to
the "romanticists" so labeled in our manuals of literary history,
but extended to "realists" as well. Zola was, in fact, the foster-
son of Rousseau. Take away, as Rousseau preached and as our
modern democracies have done, the restraints of convention
and tradition, of a society organized hierarchically, feudally,
and at least as much according to high aristocratic unreason as
according to priestly reason, and you unchain, not the bright
violence of the saving few, but the meagre ambitions or the
dirty lusts of the many. T h e old feudal society and its Renais-
sance successor did protect a few great souls and bodies, did
allow scope for a Frederick of Hohenstaufen, a Michelangelo,
a Cesare Borgia. T h e new democratic society swamps all such
great spirits. Nietzsche, like many another moralist, was not
sure whether democracy tended to produce a society flatly con-
forming to the dull mediocrity of the greengrocer's actual
habits, or a society madly pursuing the unpleasant extremes of
sensual indulgence which he was sure were the greengrocer's
not very secret desires. H e seems to have felt that democracy
could quite inconsistently be both things at once — both an
organized mediocrity and a disorganized and very vulgar rout.
W e are in Nietzsche's mind on the brink of a volcano, and
ready for several other cliches. Perhaps his general formula pro-
vided for a period of conformity and mediocrity, to be ended by
the catastrophic disintegration of a society in which moral disci-
WHAT NIETZSCHE HATED 93
V
Before Nietzsche, then, — to simplify, but not to falsify the
Master's own analysis of his predecessors — Western thinkers
immersed in the high problems of philosophy had gone astray
in three ways. Materialistic or empirical rationalists, taking
their cue from Socrates, had falsified and suppressed full
human experience by erecting the dream-world we now call
science. Idealistic rationalists, taking their cue also from
Socrates, had achieved a similar falsification and suppression by
erecting the even more fantastic dream-world of idealism, a
WHAT NIETZSCHE HATED 97
" I know that there is much in Nietzsche that can be quoted against such
a view. He attacked theories of "race" as products of nineteenth-century herd
morality, of unaristocratic looseness of thought and feeling. He wrote bitter
things against the Germans, w h o had so stupidly neglected him. But in one
of his bitterest attacks on the Germans, he wrote that they display "a number
of virtues more manly than any that other European countries can show."
The Twilight of the Idols, "Things the Germans lack," § 1. T o anyone Who
knows the supreme value Nietzsche set on what he called "manly," the above
passage is final. T h e Nazis have had no trouble in adopting him as their
prophet See also Chapter VIII below.
The Genealogy of Morals, First Essay, § 2.
100 NIETZSCHE
Will to Power, which in our decadent times we cannot even
name without using words of ill-repute, like fighting, cruelty,
greed, lying, voluptuousness. " G o o d " for the herd we herd-
men and Christians can describe in nice words, like peace,
compassion, obedience, self-restraint. And similarly, of course,
with "bad."
Already it should be clear, from the terms used above, that
Nietzsche is facing the ineluctable and insoluble problem of
the origin of evil. H e has decided that somehow, sometime,
somewhere — perhaps in Greece before Socrates — men behaved
as he liked to think of them as behaving. This is his Garden of
Eden, a place extraordinarily like Valhalla, where heroes fought
and cheated all day, and, their wounds miraculously no wounds,
feasted all night. Once the distinction between master-morality
and slave-morality had been as clear on earth and in reality as
it was in Nietzsche's mind. But no longer. There had been a
Fall of Man, and the slaves had come to rule the masters. Good
had somehow become evil, evil good. Inexplicably ? Not quite,
unfortunately. History, aided by Nietzsche, was equal to the
explanation.
Christianity is for him the key. Christ, and even more the
apostle Paul, inspired by Jewish malevolence and Greek phi-
losophy, undid the work of Nature, and set slaves over masters.
What they did was indeed no more than priests everywhere
have tried with varying success to do. But they did it more
completely and more disastrously than it has ever been done —
more so even than in India. There Buddha, a natural if some-
what gentle aristocrat, came to the rescue of the victims of
"super-spiritualization." Buddha was primarily a "hygienist,"
" H e understands goodness as being good — as promoting
WHAT NIETZSCHE HATED ιοί
T h i s was the most fatal kind of megalomania that had ever yet existed
on earth: insignificant little abortions of bigots and liars began to lay
sole claim to the concepts " G o d , " " T r u t h , " " L i g h t , " "Spirit," "Love,"
" W i s d o m , " " L i f e , " as if these things were, so to speak, synonyms of
themselves, in order to fence themselves off from "the w o r l d " ; little
ultra-Jews, ripe for every kind of madhouse, twisted values round in
order to suit themselves just as if the Christian, alone, were the meaning,
the salt, the standard and even the "ultimate tribunal" of all the rest
of mankind. 4 1
VI
On such blanket-terms as rationalism, Christianity, and
democracy Nietzsche centered hatreds which, to take him in
his own terms, are rather more than philosophical. There is a
certain consistency in their variety. Nietzsche hates all that
seems to him hostile to Life, to struggling, to the free expres-
sion of a restless energy in men he called the Will to Power.
He hates anything finished, complete, contented, "dead." Per-
haps this worshipper of succeeding hates anything successful ?
At any rate, we shall not stop now to pursue Nietzsche's per-
sonality into its final — and not very well concealed — hiding-
places. Our list of his hatreds has perhaps been a bit too
abstract, has concentrated on their broadest and most general-
ized expression. We shall do well to consider some of his more
specialized hatreds. They are many, and we can but choose a
few among them. They are also, and not unnaturally, greatly
mixed with love. Nietzsche might have written, odi, ergo amo.
He wrote some bitter things, which, values having been
properly transvalued, he regarded as just and kindly things,
about women. Nietzsche's opinions on women are at least as
well-known as the very similar ones expressed by his master
tt
The Will to Power, § 94.
WHAT NIETZSCHE HATED 109
Schopenhauer. Historically, both represent a reaction against
some of the views about women held in the nineteenth century,
especially in England, America, and Germany, and commonly
known as "Victorian." Such views really were held: read John
Stuart Mill's Autobiography if you doubt it. Women, ran the
common version, are really morally superior to men. They are
gentle, kindly, idealistic, yet sensible. Their minds and desires
are on higher things. They put up, because they have to, with
the wicked lusts of men. They are ignorant now of many im-
portant worldly matters because men conspire to keep them
uneducated, and this ignorance gives them a certain charm.
But since they are really so much better than men, they should
be given at least an equal chance with men, for our common
good. They should be given equal educational opportunities,
should be welcomed into the world of business and politics.
This, indeed, is the more radical version dear to men like Mill.
The ordinary Victorian accepted the premises of Mill's version,
the view of women as ministering angels; but he preferred to
keep them in their present satisfactory place, and to continue
to receive their ministrations.
Against such notions Nietzsche wrote aphorisms scattered
through all his works, and the famous eighteenth chapter of
the first part of Thus Spa\e Zarathustra, "Old and Young
Women." It is roughly possible to distinguish two veins in his
writing about women. In the first vein, he attacks Victorian
notions in his usual manner — by affirming loudly their op-
posâtes. Women are unscrupulous, self-centered, sensual; they
make good schemers, liars, and haters. They are admirable
practitioners of the art of slave-morality, using with intelligent
hypocrisy the "Christian" virtues to establish .their regrettable
no NIETZSCHE
domination over men. And they are intelligent, in a low
way. Established European ideas in the nineteenth century
have got the truth just reversed. Men have "character," women
"intelligence."
T h e intellect of women manifests itself as perfect mastery, presence of
mind, and utilization of all advantages. T h e y transmit it as a funda-
mental quality to their children, and the father adds thereto the darker
background of the will. . . . F o r those w h o know h o w to put a thing
properly: women have intelligence, men have character and passion. 44
Wagner's heroines one and all, once they have been divested of their
heroic husks, are almost all indistinguishable from Madame Bovary. . . .
If it were not for Wagner, who would teach us that innocence has a
preference for saving interesting sinners? (the case in "Tannhäuser").
Or that corrupted old females prefer to be saved by chaste young men?
(the case of Kundry). Or that young hysterics like to be saved by their
doctor? (the case in "Lohengrin"). Or that beautiful girls must love
to be saved by a knight who also happens to be a Wagnerite? (the case
in the "Mastersingers"). Or that even married women also like to be
saved by a knight? (the case of Isolde). . . . Let us wander in the
clouds, let us harangue eternity, let us be careful to group great symbols
all around us. Sarsum! Bumbum! — there is no better advice. The
"heaving breast" shall be our argument, "beautiful feelings" our advo-
cates. Virtue still carries its point against counterpoint. 49
" A remark of Hans von Biilow makes very clear Nietzsche's native taste
in music. Of a "Bacchanal" of Nietzsche's own composing submitted to him
he wrote, "habe ich mehr an den lendemain eines Bacchanals als an dieses
selbst denken müssen" — "it makes me think rather of the day after a Bacchanal
than of a Bacchanal itself." Nietzsche, Gesammelte Briefe, III, 350.
" The Case of Wagner, § 9; 3; 6.
114 NIETZSCHE
assemble at that "Hydro," Bayreuth — "the cultured crétins, the
blasé pigmies, the eternally feminine, the gastrically happy, in
short, the people."50 Wagner's works are an encyclopaedia of
decadence. They end, appropriately, with the worst kind of
decadence — the Christian religiosity of "Parsifal."
Finally, there are the Germans. Nietzsche was fond of call-
ing himself a "good European," but he never forgot that he
was a German. He thought the racial movement a swindle,
but he contributed much to its spread. He was certainly in
the ordinary sense not a good German, and, especially in
his later years, wrote very violently against the Germans —
which is why we have considered this subject among his
hatreds.
It is part of my ambition to be considered as a despiser of Germans
par excellence. . . . The Germans are impossible for me. When I try
to think of a man who runs counter to all my instincts, the result is
always a German. . . . The Germans are canaille. . . . A man debases
himself by consorting with Germans. . . . I cannot endure this race
with which a man is always in bad company, which has no feeling for
nuances (and alas! I am a nuance). . . . The Germans have no idea of
how vulgar they are — which is itself the very acme of vulgarity — they
arc not ashamed of being merely Germans.81
And it is the great noontide, when man is in the middle of his course
between animal and Superman, and celebrating his advance to the
evening as his highest hope: for it is the advance to a new morning.
A t such time will the down-goer bless himself, that he should be an
over-goer; and the sun of his knowledge will be at noontide.
"Dead are all the Gods: now do we desire the Superman to live." —
Let this be our final will àt the great noontide! —
Thus spake Zarathustra. 1
ausgabe), IX, 357. The whole long passage is a most interesting anticipation
of what the Nazis call their völkische Weltanschauung.
* The Dawn of Day, § 308.
ω
Human, All Too Human, "The Wanderer and his Shadow," § 285.
124 NIETZSCHE
II
" Human, All Too Human, "Miscellaneous Maxims and Opinions," § 304.
I2Ó NIETZSCHE
time, no matter what they are called, he is disgusted. France
and England have frankly committed themselves to democracy
and therefore to decadence. Germany, in which the strong old
instincts for a society founded on the Order of Rank were still
alive under Frederick the Great, has since 1813 given way
increasingly to her almost equally old weakness, the desire to
imitate, and excel at their own game, the Western powers.
Even so intelligent and realistic an "old" German as Bismarck
has felt himself obliged to introduce parliamentary government
and in many other ways to compromise with the West. The
result is an unstable mixture of elements natural and unnatural
in Germans, a society enjoying its own peculiar decadence;
"the era of Bismarck — the era of a stupefied Germany" (Aera
der deutschen Verdummung).1B In this sad situation, only
Russia seems to hold a promise, "Russia, the only great nation
today that has some lasting power and grit in her, that can bide
her time, that can still promise something — Russia, the op-
posite of all wretched European petty-statism and neurasthenia,
which the foundation of the German Empire has brought to a
crisis." 16 As for America, all Nietzsche thought we deserved
was an aside, "no American future." It is true he put a ques-
tion-mark after the phrase.17
The politics of all European and American states in the nine-
teenth century, then, — with the possible exception of Russia —
were to Nietzsche impossibly corrupt. And they were deeply
corrupt, not with the petty graft old-maidish reformers worry
about — that was at most a symptom — but with the funda-
15
Werke (Grossoctavausgabe), XIII, 350.
™ The Twilight of the Idols, "Skirmishes in a War with the Age," § 39.
17
The Genealogy of Morals, "Peoples and Countries," § 17.
W H A T NIETZSCHE W A N T E D 127
and builders, but all that a philosopher and a prophet ever need.
Nietzsche foresaw a future which without him might not really
turn out to be a future. The heart of his work is what he sets
forth as a new eschatology, a new morality. Our study of what
Nietzsche wanted in family life, education, economic life, and
politics has led us naturally and inevitably to the traditionally
abstract and generalized form of what this anti-philosopher
wanted — to his philosophy. W e must try now to come to grips
with those famous phrases of Nietzsche's which his followers
have turned into slogans — "the Will to Power,", "immoral-
ism," "the transvaluation of all values," "the Superman"
(Ueber mensch), "the Eternal Recurrence" (ewige Wieder-
kunft).
III
Nietzsche learned from Schopenhauer that Will is the first
principle of the Universe, or at least of human life in the Uni-
verse— and that the intellect is the servant of the Will. But
Schopenhauer's pessimism held human life, and hence Will,
as an evil, to be palliated if not transcended by "living" as little
as possible. This near-death in life he would attain by a kind
of pseudo-oriental quietism, a Nirvana-like state of philosophic
calm and contempt. Nietzsche early decided he would say
"Yea" where his Master had said "Nay," that he would accept
with delight the endless struggles to which his Will invited
him. What Schopenhauer had called the Will to Life, and
A Bad Thing, he would call the Will to Power, and A Good
Thing.
What is good? All that enhances the feeling of power, the Will to
Power, and power itself in man. What is bad? — a l l that proceeds from
weakness. What is happiness? — the feeling that power is increasing —
that resistance has been overcome.
132 NIETZSCHE
N o t contentment, but more power; not peace at any price, but war;
not virtue, but efficiency (virtue in the Renaissance sense, virtù, free from
all moralic acid). T h e weak and the botched shall perish: first principle
of our humanity. A n d they ought even to be helped to perish. 23
The clever and degenerate Priests, realizing that they could not
compete with the Warriors at the Warriors' own level, have
enlisted the aid of the masses against their "natural" masters,
and have established themselves as their "unnatural" masters.
This the priests have achieved by inventing morality and re-
ligion, and especially their masterpiece, Christian morality and
religion. The weak are, in the most literal sense, weak and as
individuals would always go down before the strong — the
good, bodily strong, the nobles, the Warriors. But the weak
are very numerous, and organized into a collectivity, they can
overcome the strong. This organization has been achieved in
the Christian Church and in its contemporary adaptation, the
religion of democracy and progress.
We have already seen how Nietzsche works out his explana-
tion of the nature and triumph of Christianity.27 The upshot
" The Antichrist, § 3. " See above, pp. 97-108.
136 NIETZSCHE
viction, that although a handicraft docs not shame one in any sense, it
certainly reduces one's rank. . . . W e collect precious things, the needs
of higher and fastidious souls; we wish to possess nothing in common.
W e want to have our own books, our own landscapes.29
10 the volume containing The Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist.
These may be found in German in A . Baeumler's edition of Nietzsche's re-
mains, Die Unschuld des Werdens, II, § 1296-1351. T h e quotation above is
from § 1351.
** "Notes on the Eternal Recurrence," § 22. In Die Unschuld des Werdens,
II, § 1330.
WHAT NIETZSCHE WANTED 141
will write again the same appeal, world without end and words
without end. But no Nietzsche will ever have the slightest
memory of another Nietzsche.
It would seem that belief in the Eternal Recurrence might
tempt its adept to cease trying to change the universe. But this
grand and complete determinism no more makes Nietzsche
a determinist in the fleeting life of his consciousness than an
almost equally grand determinism made Marx a practising
determinist. On the contrary it spurs him to intense moral
effort. We must live so that we may be worthy of living again.
We must fight theism, fight beliefs that deny this life and this
world. We must struggle to attain the pure heights on which
alone so stark a doctrine as that of the Eternal Recurrence can
be endured. We must put off softness and take on hardness.
We must give up the little hopes, and cherish the great hope of
hopelessness. We must be what has never been before — never,
at least, during our little rondo in the Eternal Recurrence. We
must become Supermen — once more.
CHAPTER VI
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF
T H E H I S T O R Y OF AN ERROR
1. The true world, attainable to the sage, the pious man and the man
of virtue, — he lives in it, he is it.
(The most ancient form of the idea was relatively clever, simple,
convincing. It was a paraphrase of the proposition "I, Plato, am the
truth.")
2. The true world which is unattainable for the moment, is promised
to the sage, to the pious man and to the man of virtue ("to the sinner
who repents").
(Progress of the idea: it becomes more subtle, more insidious, more
evasive, — it becomes a woman, it becomes Christian.)
3. The true world is unattainable, it cannot be proved, it cannot
promise anything; but even as a thought, alone, it is a comfort, an obliga-
tion, a command.
( A t bottom this is still the old sun; but seen through mist and
skepticism: the idea has become sublime, pale, northern, Königsber-
gian.)
4. The true world — is it unattainable? A t all events it is unattained.
And as unattained it is also unknown. Consequently it no longer com-
forts, nor saves, nor constrains: what could something unknown con-
strain us to?
(The grey of dawn. Reason stretches itself and yawns for the first
time. The cock-crow of positivism.)
5. The "true world" — an idea that no longer serves any purpose,
that no longer constrains one to anything, — a useless idea that has
become quite superfluous, consequently an exploded idea: let us abolish it!
(Bright daylight; breakfast; the return of common sense and of
II
Nietzsche's anti-intellectualism makes him as much a child
of his age as does his evolutionism, an eccentric and spoiled
child, perhaps, but certainly no changeling of Time. Indeed,
in Nietzsche as in his tamer contemporaries, both anti-intellec-
tualism and evolutionism are manifestations of a "climate of
opinion" hard to pin down with a single descriptive label. To
use very old philosophical terms, we may say that the nine-
teenth century was very strongly inspired with a Heraclitan
feeling that all things flow. At all times, no doubt, men are
aware of experiencing sameness (or repetition or permanence)
and also of experiencing difference (or change). Ordinary,
unreflecting men are aware of both, and do not much bother
themselves with the question as to which is real, or more real.
Philosophers, of course, have readily discerned that one sort of
experience is real, or more real, and the other unreal, or less
real; but they have not agreed as to which is which. A historian
may content himself with the statement that the manifesta-
tions of human feelings about permanence and change in
observed phenomena vary in different times and places. Note
150 NIETZSCHE
well that the manifestations of men's sentiments and opinions
about change may also be observed phenomena. Plato's opinion
on the matter, as recorded in the famous metaphor of the
prisoners in the cave, for instance, is a phenomenon that can
be observed. Plato, it need hardly be remarked, was all for the
reality of permanence.
Now, although no mathematical formulation is possible, the
historian can be pretty sure of a number of generalizations
about this matter of permanence and change. The physical
aspects of Paris, for instance, changed less rapidly in the thir-
teenth than in the nineteenth century. That is simple and
certain. Parisians in the thirteenth century felt, or were of the
opinion, that changes of this sort, and changes in laws, clothes,
habits, were not very rapid; Parisians in the nineteenth century
felt, or were of the opinion, that such changes were very rapid.
This is almost as simple and certain as the fact of changes in
buildings and streets, and you can verify it from the materials
of recorded intellectual history. We need not bother ourselves
about the question (which is insoluble) as to whether "physi-
cal" change caused "mental" change, or vice versa. We can,
however, safely take another step, and state that in general
thirteenth-century Parisians were less favorable towards, less
desirous of, changes of a great many sorts than were Parisians
of the nineteenth century. We may extend the scope of the
generalization, and state that the climate of opinion in all
Western Europe was less favorable to change in the thirteenth
than in the nineteenth century. This is not of course to deal
with absolutes and to say that nothing changed in the thirteenth
century and that everything changed in the nineteenth century.
It is a cautious and rather platitudinous generalization about a
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF 151
series of relations among observed phenomena, which would
need at least a volume to be given a semblance of what we may
unphilosophically call reality.
The anti-intellectualism of the later nineteenth century is a
part of its attitude towards change, an attitude extraordinarily
receptive and eager towards all sorts of change. Perhaps in the
sum total life for Western men changed more rapidly in the
nineteenth century than it has ever before changed for men on
this earth. Certainly in the series of phenomena we group
together as the Industrial Revolution, change was more con-
tinuously obvious than it has ever been before, so obvious that
the intellectuals took over from Renaissance Latin the neutral
term "progress," and made it into an almost-popular religious
belief in the desirability of change. But traditionally the Euro-
pean mind, working at the level of theological, philosophical,
and even, in a sense, "scientific," thought, had tended to reach
conclusions that seemed inconsistent with the facts of change,
that seemed to make change undesirable, impossible, unreal. It
is not by any means clear how far such thought, such "intel-
lectualisai," influenced the course of events. But as a process in
the minds of certain men — and that is after all what Nietzsche
all his life was analyzing — its implications are clear.
They are perhaps clearest of all in that manifestation of
intellectualism Nietzsche attacked as "idealism." 7 The ideal-
ist, in the opinion of such critics as Nietzsche, cannot accept
the evidence of his senses as to the reality of change. He does
not want change. He wants to escape the flow of all things,
and take refuge in the absolute, the eternal, the unchanging.
He can do this by a trick of his mind, by using what we call
' See above, pp. 87-90.
152 NIETZSCHE
the intellect to construct — after all, out of his experience, which
must be an experience of change — a system of absolutes which
he calls the "true world." This "true world" is of course a
false one; but since we critics are good relativists, we must
recognize that it is only relatively false. That is, as a mental
construct it afiects the lives of those who made it and of those
who live in it; it is a part of reality. Its "falseness," its "bad-
ness," means in simplest terms that we don't like the way
people who hold it, who live in it, behave. We don't, for
instance, like the way people behave under the influence of
too much alcohol; we don't like drunks. Similarly, we don't
like the way people behave under the influence of too much
philosophical idealism; we don't like Kantians.
We don't like them because, having persuaded themselves
that change is unreal, they try to prevent the kind of changes
we want to bring about. They do not, of course, Succeed in
preventing change; indeed they commonly let themselves and
us in for the most unforeseen and catastrophic changes. For
the intellect, as these searchers after the absolute use it, is readily
satisfied with over-simple formulae, which it erects into "laws"
of all sorts, moral, political, scientific; it then seeks to make all
human experience conform to these laws. But human experi-
ence cannot be so confined — this is a fact of experience —
and when a prolonged and serious attempt is made to so con-
fine it, it accumulates under pressure and finally blows ofï —
a kind of experience we do not like.
When we relativists feel like exercising our noblest vocabu-
lary— we have one — we accuse the absolutists of trying to
dry up the well-springs of human life, of intolerance towards
all who refuse to repeat their meaningless litanies, of a haughty
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF 153
disregard for the fruitful difficulties in attempting the conquest
of which the true scientist and the true artist are one ; we accuse
them of sterility, of verbalism, of seeking death-in-life, of
hating adventurousness, novelty, growth; we accuse them of
being intellectuals, even though we ourselves are by no means
blacksmiths.
Nietzsche in his middle period was fond of this "we" —
"we fearless ones," "we free spirits," "we good Europeans,"
though in his later years the " I " sounds out louder and louder,
until the final crescendo of "Why I am a fatality." But through-
out his career he is crying out against intellectual absolutism,
wherever he finds it — and he finds it not only in the philo-
sophical idealists, but in the historians and in the positivists.
The nineteenth century had, he grants, recognized, though
often reluctantly, the fact of growth. Even Hegel's was a phi-
losophy which aspired to explain growth. That, in fact, was
just the trouble. In his wilder moments, Nietzsche comes close
to saying what some of his Nazi followers put in his mouth,
that one must not try to explain anything, at least not with
words — exclamation-marks are enough. But Nietzsche was
often fairly sober, and as critic rather than as prophet, he
tried to put into words feelings about the inadequacy of
much of the thought of the eighteenth and earlier nineteenth
centuries, feelings which were shared by many of his con-
temporaries.
Nietzsche's major point is that all thinking is an arrange-
ment, an interpretation, of facts (receptor-experiences) which
must be tentative, changing, relative. Thinking is not a form
of magic by which the thinker somehow gets out of himself
and thereby "discovers" static, objective truth. The thing-in-
154 NIETZSCHE
Ill
Nietzsche, then, is not only true to his age in his preoccupa-
tion with questions of growth, development, flow; he is true to
his profession of philosopher in his attempt to find for them a
final answer, to sum up in words experiences that are much
more than words. The historian and skeptic — the two can
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF 157
perhaps be combined in one person — may, however, refuse to
follow Nietzsche in his final flight to the Will to Power and the
Eternal Recurrence, and content himself with noting and com-
menting upon what Nietzsche fished up out of the flow of all
things.
For Nietzsche's conviction that all things can be reduced to
manifestations of the Will to Power by no means prevented his
recognizing the variety and changefulness of human experi-
ence. In fact, the doctrines of the Will to Power and its curious
companion and derivative, the Eternal Recurrence, merely
served him as buttresses for his private hates and loves, as
colossal extensions of his personality. In his more rapt moods,
they helped him to live in a prophetic and — to his followers
as well as himself — consoling world; in his more polemic
moods, they helped him feel sure of the pettiness and undesir-
ability of what he could make out of other people's worlds; and
at all times they acted as a limitation on his ability to widen and
deepen his experience — that is, they made him intolerant —
but perhaps no more than is essential to make sense out of
experience. At least a small amount of metaphysics is, like the
presence of certain minerals in the human diet, perhaps neces-
sary to human life. And Nietzsche's dose of metaphysics was
not a very big one. The common opinion, which refuses to rank
him with men like Kant and Hegel as all philosopher, but puts
him partly in the field of literature, is well justified.
He belongs in the field of literature because, for one thing,
he could write. This is a gift not always lacking in philosophers.
Plato, James, Santayana, to take a few at random, possess it;
Aristotle — to judge from what we have of him — Bentham,
and Hegel do not. There are great obstacles in the way of a
158 NIETZSCHE
IV
Nietzsche's work is a great armory, by no means filled en-
tirely with weapons of precision; there are some fowling-pieces
of great age, and even a few sling-shots, as well as some very
accurate modern pieces. On the whole, his light guns are more
effective than his heavy artillery, though the latter makes a very
loud noise. To drop the metaphor: Nietzsche's work contains
a great variety of ideas, sometimes mutually contradictory,
difficult if not impossible to reduce to a "system," made still
more bewilderingly varied by the aphoristic form in which
they are cast. This variety is the reflection of a many-sided
temperament. Nietzsche had an excellent mind, well if rather
bookishly trained, great aesthetic sensibility, a natural gift for
writing, strong emotions which he could focus in the saeva
indignatio we often call moral purpose, an untrained body, an
unstable nervous system, a total personality never successfully
conditioned to living together with anyone — not in the fam-
ι68 NIETZSCHE
ily, not in the occupational or social group, not in church or
state. He had, finally, a devouring ambition to be admired, a
thirst for disciples, a will to shine which, as the Will to Power,
he built up into a characteristic philosophical ultimate, and
which, syphilis aiding, ended in paranoia.
Among the stresses and strains which compose the unending
conflicts that made Nietzsche, and perhaps made him great,
there is one which will serve well to sum up the man and his
work. This is the conflict between the observer and the re-
former, between the artist and the prophet, between Nietzsche
and Zarathustra. It is a conflict discernible, no doubt, in less
heroic proportions, in the lives of all men. It is a conflict most
of us hardly feel, and which we resolve comfortably in the
routine of living. It is not, by the way, an ultimate. We are
using the dualistic terms in which we describe the conflict as
mere conveniences in putting Nietzsche and his work within
common experience.
The observer has his eye — and all his other organs of sense
— first of all on the immense body of receptor-experiences we
call facts. He does not merely passively record or report these
facts, but tries to arrange them as uniformities put in relation
to a conceptual scheme in such a way that they can be "verified"
— that is, experienced again as receptor-experiences by himself
and others, but this time in an order. The observer's test for
whether his order is "true" is a relational and instrumental one.
Its relation with facts must be continuous; if it ties a falling
barometer and rain together in the formula, a falling barometer
is followed by rain, rain must always follow a falling barometer
or the order ("theory") is not altogether true, and must be
modified, at least to some extent. Its instrumental character is
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF 169
a more complicated matter, but is always, for the type of person
we call the observer, subordinated to its relation with facts.
The reformer, on the other hand, subordinates the relational
character of the order he constructs out of experience to its
instrumental character. The extreme type of reformer may
even refuse to bother himself about the relational character of
his "order," his "theories." If he has decided that a falling
barometer ought to be followed by rain, he will do something
about it — almost anything, in fact, but observe the conditions
under which rain actually falls. He will construct complicated
and lovely barometers, and try to make everybody use them;
he will pass a law requiring falling barometers to be followed
by rain; he will define rain to include fair weather; he will
refuse to admit that it is raining, unless the barometer has
fallen, or that the barometer has fallen, unless it is raining.
We have, of course, caricatured the reformer. But any full
treatment of the distinction we have attempted to make be-
tween the observer and the reformer would run into a volume.
The important thing here is to note that though all conscious
thinking is an ordering of experience, some kinds of thinking
are directed by the thinker rather towards sorting experience
into recognizable uniformities which are repetitive, verifiable,
predictable, and which seem to the thinker to possess these
qualities whether he wants them to or not; and that some
kinds of thinking are directed by the thinker towards sorting
experience into an order which is a modification of experience
into something "better," something which he feels can be made
true for himself and others, something which he rather proudly
holds comes from himself (through God, perhaps) or from
"things" independent of himself. We have, perhaps, done no
170 NIETZSCHE
more than put rather confusingly the well-worn distinction
between "objective" and "subjective" which has exhausted
generations of philosophers, but seems itself inexhaustible.
It is a useful distinction, even though no one ever put his
finger — or his mind — on either a subject or an object. Con-
cretely, we can recognize that a biologist attempting to find
order in human heredity is likely to think "objectively" and
that a preacher of eugenics attempting to get human beings to
breed as he wants them to breed is likely to think "subjectively."
The two kinds of thinkers are constantly borrowing one from
the other, are indeed frequently the same person. But as types
they certainly exist, and not only in the stark contrast between
the scientist and the preacher. Literature is as much a matter of
good observing as is science, and some very great writers, like
Shakespeare, have been much more interested in what is than
in what it ought to be. Even philosophers have their grada-
tions; Aristotle was a better observer than was Plato. Nietzsche
was a better observer than Zarathustra.
The contrast we have set up between Nietzsche the observer
and Nietzsche the reformer is by no means an imaginary one.
It was real enough so that it must have contributed to his
mental suffering, to have given him a kind of split personality.
There are people so immersed in understanding and coping
with their experience of what is, that they do not bother them-
selves much with what ought to be; and there are people so
immersed in satisfying themselves about what ought to be that
they are not much disturbed by what is. There are people who
can live happily in this world, and others who can live happily
in any number of other worlds. Nietzsche could do neither.
He was too acute an observer, too sensitive an artist, to spin
NIETZSCHE IN UNIFORM
From a photograph, 1868
NIETZSCHE-IN-HIMSELF 171
out theories without regard for facts; and he was too bitten
with reforming zeal, too impatient, too exalted, perhaps at
bottom too insanely or divinely convinced that he alone was the
measure of all things, to accept the humbling limitations im-
posed by regard for facts. And so he made his unhappy down-
going and over-going to that strangest of "true worlds," the
world of the Supermen, beyond good and evil, beyond you
and me, beyond himself.
But not beyond an Italian socialist hack, not beyond an
Austrian corporal. One of the strange, and to some of us, dis-
couraging things about the activities of reformers is the unpre-
dictable effects their labors so often have in practice. The
noblest dreams of the prophet turn into nightmares when they
come true. Nietzsche called for the Supermen. Mussolini and
Hitler answered the call. It does not much matter that in all
probability Nietzsche would have scorned them as perverters
of his doctrine, would have opposed them bitterly. It does, not
even matter that had Nietzsche never written these men would
in all probability have come to power much as they did. They
have found a use for Nietzsche, a use he probably never intended
his words to provide. That is a risk all men run who build with
words, but it is a risk peculiarly great for those who out of
their discontents build with grand words a refuge from this
poor world, a noble castle in the philosophic air. Such castles
are often roomy and comfortable, but very hard to keep clean.
CHAPTER VII
T H E G R O W T H OF A R E P U T A T I O N
is the test? The work of a man who has passed on grows and changes;
he is still finishing it from beyond. It has long since moved from the
point where we once found it, when we were young and Nietzsche was
alive. 1
1
H . Mann, "Presenting Nietzsche," The Living Thoughts of Nietzsche
(rçpg), ι.
2
Daniel Halévy, The Lije of Friedrich Nietzsche, 209.
174 NIETZSCHE
brought out at the expense of the author. Publication at the
author's own expense usually marks the author as a dilettante
or an unread scholar, as an unimportant man, perhaps even
as a crank, a crackpot, a failure; and Nietzsche knew, with in-
sane certainty, that he was not an unimportant man, not a
crank, not a failure.
There were, in the last few years of Nietzsche's active life,
some signs of coming fame, Georg Brandes, the Danish critic
whose European reputation was already established, probably
deserves the distinction of having discovered Nietzsche. 3 It is
true that Nietzsche himself helped the discovery by having his
publisher send copies of Beyond Good and Evil to various dis-
tinguished literary persons. This by no means uncommon
practice is rarely, one suspects, very fruitful. But Nietzsche
had the satisfaction of receiving intelligent letters of apprecia-
tion from Taine and Brandes, and through Brandes, from
Strindberg. Brandes actually lectured on Nietzsche's ideas at
Copenhagen, and the two kept up a lively correspondence until
Nietzsche went mad. Nietzsche had, then, the pleasure of hear-
ing the first faint rumblings of the great noise his name was to
make in the world. But by the time Brandes got around to
printing, in 1889, a long article on "Nietzsche: A n Essay on
Aristocratic Radicalism," his subject was no longer able to
understand what fame meant.
There is indeed no danger that the Nietzscheans will let us
forget the way the world neglected the Master. W e must not
exaggerate. Even during his lifetime Nietzsche was not abso-
lutely unheard. The conspicuous critics left him alone, but
* At any rate, Brandes later claimed the distinction for himself. G. Brandes,
Friedrich Nietzsche. Translated from the Danish by A. C. Chater (n.d.), 59.
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 175
every now and then a magazine brought up his name, and in
1880 a writer in the popular weekly Die Gegenwart gave five
whole columns to this "modern 'free spirit' . . . , whose name
is not unknown to our literature."4 His little circle of friends,
and the larger number he no longer considered his friends,
served to spread his reputation. Brandes's article on Nietzsche
the aristocratic radical was translated into German and pub-
lished in April 1890 in the Deutsche Rundschau, equivalent
in America to the accolade of the Atlantic or Harper's. By the
beginning of the 1890's little trickles from various sources had
begun to unite into a stream. Nietzsche's reputation grew with
amazing speed after 1890, but it by no means sprang up over
night.
The periodicals took him up first, and made his name quite
suddenly the fashion among the kind of people who need to
talk fashionably — so much so that when ten years later the
distinguished philosopher Hans Vaihinger wrote a book about
Nietzsche, he had to defend himself against the charge of
writing about "a merely fashionable writer" (ein blosser Mo-
deschriftsteller).δ Die Gegenwart published articles on Nie-
tzsche in 1889 and in 1891, the second by a well-known writer
of Swedish origin, Ola Hansson. Lou Salomé could scarcely
let a chance like this slip by. It began to look as though
Nietzsche had been a great man after all. She published in
the Sunday Supplement of the Vossische Zeitung during Janu-
ary 1891 some articles on Nietzsche which were shortly after-
* H . Herrig, "Ein moderner Freigeist," Die Gegenwart (August 7, 1880),
XVIII, 85. For other examples see M. Wirth, "Die Zukunft der Reminiscenz:
Variationen über Themen von Friedrich Nietzsche," Die Kunstwart (1888),
II, 52; Das musikalische Wochenblatt (1887), XVIII, 441.
6
H . Vaihinger, Nietzsche als Philosoph (1902), 13.
176 NIETZSCHE
wards expanded into a book. It was by no means a bad book,
rather pretentious philosophically, but sensible about Nietzsche
as a person. Nietzsche's Wagner heresies were attracting more
and more attention in the musical press. They were still
heresies — his remarks about Bizet's superiority over Wagner
were of course beneath disdain — but they made good copy.
The Allgemeine Zeitung des Judentums published in 1892
what is probably the first essay on Nietzsche and the Jewish
question. The quality magazines were now working the new
vein very hard. The Deutsche Rundschau, Nord und Süd, the
Preussische Jahrbücher, Westermanns Monatshefte assigned to
him long articles by well-known writers. One of these was
Eduard von Hartmann, a now almost forgotten professor of
philosophy, who had synthetized one of the most extraordinary
brews ever made, in which Hegel, Schopenhauer, and the in-
ductive method so successful in the natural sciences were mixed
— Hartmann's word was "reconciled." Hartmann was already
going out of fashion, and Nietzsche was coming into fashion,
but as Hartmann was not altogether aware of this, he treats
Nietzsche soberly and without bitterness — Nietzsche's "sys-
tem" he found, of course, inadequate, and not even new. 6
In 1892 and 1893, the original German volumes of Max
8
For instance: T . de Wyzewa, "Friedrich Nietzsche, le dernier métaphysi-
cien," Revue bleue (7 Nov. 1891), X L V I I I , 586; J. de Nethy, "Nietzsche-
Zarathustra," Revue blanche (Apr. 1892), II, 206. G. B. S.[haw], "Nietzsche
in English," Saturday Review ( 1 1 Apr. 1896), L X X X I , 373. The decisive
article in English — it is still worth reading — appeared as "The Ideals of
Anarchy — Friedrich Nietzsche" in the Quarterly Review (Oct 1896),
C L X X X I V , 299.
T H E GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 179
II
We are today hesitant about referring to the "influence" of a
writer, partly no doubt because of the influence of Nietzsche
himself. Ideas are no longer for us the wonder-workers they
were for our grandfathers. We distrust studies in the affiliation
or genealogy of ideas. Some of our more innocent anti-intel-
lectuals apparently hold that all generalizations — except
perhaps those of Marx when properly interpreted — are increas-
ingly useless disguises for our simpler lusts. Yet in those impor-
" One of the first of these was W. Jesinghaus, Der innere Zusammenhang
der Gedanken vom Uebermensch bei Nietzsche. Inaugural Dissertation at
the University of Bonn (1901). There have been dozens and dozens of them
since and on some very remarkable phases of Nietzsche's life and influence.
My own favorite is F. Sprengel, Nietzsche und das Ding-an-sich (1933).
10
H. Albert, "Friedrich Nietzsche," Mercure de France (Jan. 1893), VII,
47-48.
l8o NIETZSCHE
tant moments of carelessness which reveal the habits of routine,
uninspired, and useful thinking, the most conscientious anti-
intellectual is likely to let drop the phrase "influence of the
ideas of" so-and-so. Nietzsche's influence on the world, in the
sense of mere stir in the world, has been considerable, and very
varied. Without attempting yet to come to grips with the
problem of what relation — if any — that stir has had on events,
on the actions of men, we may try to see first what kind of men
the discoverers of Nietzsche were, what they found in him in
this first decade of his fame.
The intellectuals of the 1890's were not as wicked as they
aspired to be. What strikes one looking back on them from the
i94o's is the energy, liveliness, indeed the optimism, with which
they sought disillusion. They could defy most enjoyably the
philistine conventions of middle-class society. The middle
class was still there, apparently solidly established and well
worth defying. Anarchism was one of the very best of attitudes
for defying the middle class. On the whole, it seemed to give
more substantial nourishment to the pride of the defiant artist,
writer, and thinker than socialism — though of course, the two
together made a nice combination. Nietzsche's ideas seemed to
most of those who read him in the 1890's a new and attractive
variant of anarchism, an aristocratic, radical, aesthetic anar-
chism, unsullied by the vulgar conspiratorial atmosphere and
silly humanitarian aims of traditional anarchism. Nietzsche
appears first, therefore, in the history of opinion as the complete
anti-philistine, the emancipated poet of dionysian joy, the mas-
ter of those who live.
He appears, of course, in no such simple terms. Brandes
called him the "aristocratic radical," a phrase which gave
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 181
Ill
To some of the reasons for Nietzsche's charm over his readers
we shall return. The amazing variety of things his readers and
disciples have said they have found in him is explicable partly
by the variety of people his charm has attracted. It is also
explicable partly by the fact that his published writings actually
do contain varied and in some senses contradictory materials.
In the first place, Nietzsche seems to have changed direction
after he left Wagner. Some of his more unyielding worshippers
insist that, though he may have developed, he never changed,
that all his writings, of youth as well as of maturity, form one
splendid unity.13 Some such remark has certainly been made of
all thinkers, and about all of them it may have a degree of
truth. But to many an observer, the Nietzsche of The Birth of
Tragedy seemed a different man from the aphorisitc Nietzsche
of The Dawn of Day, and the "philosopher with a hammer" of
the Twilight of the Idols seemed still another man — if, indeed,
" T h i s is now the fashionable view among the Nazis. See R. Oehler,
Nietzsche und die deutsche Zukunft (1935).
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 183
he were a man at all. In other words, Nietzsche's works can
be divided into "periods" perhaps a bit more easily than most
men's. It is then possible to say that the "real" Nietzsche was
the Nietzsche of a certain period, and that the rest of his work
is not truly Nietzschean.
Moreover, Nietzsche wrote almost entirely in brief aphoristic
passages, composed in moments of high excitement, noted down
and strung together into a book. Here, too, critics have had no
trouble finding all sorts of underlying unity. But it is a fact
that Nietzsche was not tied down by any formal structure in
his books, that he had no brief to follow, no special audience
to adapt himself to. He had, it must be admitted, a love for
neatness and bite in phrasing, a love which he sometimes in-
dulged at the expense of accuracy in reflecting his actual judg-
ments. The works are a mass of reflections, a kind of running
note-book, a written Table-Talk, in which anyone can find
contradictions.
Finally, any body of written work, at least outside the natural
sciences and exact scholarship, lives on at the mercy of fashion.
What Nietzsche had to say was necessarily inexact, for he dealt
with matters about which men's feelings and habits have always
been more trustworthy expressions than their words — though
they cannot, if they are men like Nietzsche, give up the des-
perate task of fitting them to words. Nietzsche's work survives
as the subject of great disputes, partly because he failed to say
exactly what he meant; and no one who has tried to say the
kind of thing Nietzsche tried to say has succeeded much
better. We are still disputing about some of the things said by
Jesus of Nazareth. And so we ought not to be surprised that
men differ on what Nietzsche wrote, differ in some senses al-
184 NIETZSCHE
All sorts of men have looked into Nietzsche's works, and seen
themselves. Any attempt to classify them will be unworthy of
their variety. It may be well, therefore, to adopt a frankly
dualistic device, a neat conceptual polarity. There are two sorts
of Nietzscheans, the gentle and the tough. There are no doubt
many in between the extremes, who might almost be called
medium Nietzscheans. Though the Master himself was most
immoderate, one might without too much violence to good
sense find some followers who could be called "moderate"
Nietzscheans. But the simple polar distinction between gentle
Nietzscheans and tough ones is a useful one, which is about all
one may expect of a distinction.
The gentle Nietzscheans regard the Master, in a nowadays
cant phrase, as a man of good will. For them, Nietzsche's work
is in a central great tradition of ethics marked by Socrates,
Jesus, Buddha, Luther, and other children of God. Nietzsche,
they hold, wanted men to be good; and by good he meant what
the great heroes of religion and morals have always meant by
good, good in a somewhat stoic sense. Because men were not
" A . Kesser, "Elemente zur Beurteilung Nietzsches," Neue Schweizer
Rundschau (1937), IV, 535.
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 185
good in the nineteenth-century Western world, he lost his tem-
per with them, and broke into prophetic violence. But at heart
he wanted them to be peaceful, happy, just, pure, honest, kindly,
humane. The gentle Nietzscheans have had to do a lot of ex-
plaining. They have taken in stride paradoxes that would have
given their Master pause. One of their favorites, phrased in a
dozen ways, runs something like this: Nietzsche was a most
Christian anti-Christian; he hated the sham Christianity of his
age as only a true follower of Jesus could hate it.
The tough Nietzscheans have had rather easier going, at least
with their logic. For themf the Master was an aristocrat of the
heart and the head, a man filled with a great contempt for the
pig-men about him, a tortured, sensitive, subtle soul in rebellion
against the middle-class stupidities of the nineteenth century.
When, according to them, he damned Christianity for its slave-
morality, its compassion for the weak, its distrust of the flesh,
he meant that he regarded Christianity as a bad thing. They
add the gloss that Nietzsche did not object to Christianity as a
solace for the masses, who could never be more than masses,
but that he hated it for corrupting the minority capable of
bright strength and cruelty, for preventing aristocrats from
behaving like aristocrats. Their Nietzsche was the dionysian
rebel, the unashamed pagan, the joyous fighter, the flashing
thinker, the superb ironist, whose wit danced merrily through
the bewildered herd, and now and then knocked down some
loud bawling beast.
IV
Elizabeth's biography of her brother, together with many
magazine articles pointing out Nietzsche's great literary virtues,
i86 NIETZSCHE
no doubt helped to lay the foundations on which the gentle
Nietzscheans have built. Yet it was his adoption as a philoso-
pher by German academic philosophers that first gave him the
respectability without which the gentle Nietzscheans might
have labored in vain. Why these academic philosophers should
have accepted him as a philosopher is hard to make out. He
did, it is true, frequently refer to himself as a philosopher; but
German writers all call themselves philosophers, somewhere,
before they get through. He left an unpublished set of apho-
risms labelled The Will to Power, which he often referred to
as his systematic opus mains, but which looks and sounds ex-
actly like the rest of his unsystematic works, save that it is
much duller. The best of Nietzsche's work is in fact more like
that of Montaigne, Pascal, La Rochefoucauld than like that of
Kant or Hegel. But the Frenchmen were also philosophers?
Perhaps, but you will not find much attention paid them in
formal manuals of philosophy.15
The best of German philosophical writing on Nietzsche has
been of a high order. Books like those of Alois Riehl, Hans
Vaihinger, Raoul Richter, Richard Meyer have, in a good sense,
brought him down to earth, have made him an understand-
able figure.18 These writers must, on the whole, be classed as
gentle Nietzscheans. Even when, as with Vaihinger, they limit
themselves to expounding systematically what Nietzsche wrote
in a rush of words, they tend to tame him a bit, to subdue him to
u
In one of the best — and briefest — critical studies of Nietzsche, Vaihinger
insists that Nietzsche is properly designated a philosopher. But he also makes
the point I have made above, that Montaigne and his company are properly
philosophers. H. Vaihinger, Nietzsche als Philosoph, 15. Here there is no use
disputing about words.
M
A. Riehl, Friedrich Nietzsche, der Künstler und der Denker (1897);
H. Vaihinger, Nietzsche als Philosoph (1902); R. Richter, Friedrich Nietzsche
sein Leben und sein Wer\ (1903); R. W. Meyer, Nietzsche (1913).
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 187
18
C. Andler, Nietzsche, sa vie et sa pensée, V, 321. Andler was not the
first to call Nietzsche a Socialist. E. Gystrow, in the Sozialistische Monatsheft
for October 1900 wrote ecstatically, "He was one of us!" See F. Mess, Nietzsche
der Gesetzgeber (1930), 183-184.
190 NIETZSCHE
'Jansenism,' or 'Protestantism,' arid which will now be called
Nietzscheanism, because Nietzsche dared formulate to the very
extreme that which was still latently murmuring in it." 19
One of the most thorough jobs of softening Nietzsche's doc-
trines was done by an American, the late W. M. Salter, whose
Nietzsche the Thinner appeared in 1917. Salter is no Andler;
he does not try to make Nietzsche out a lover of his fellow-men,
nor even a primitive Christian. At no one point does he seem
to do much more than quote or paraphrase Nietzsche. Yet the
net impression one gets from Salter's book is of a Nietzsche no
longer very excited or exciting. All the impatience, all the
drum-beating, all the mystic exaltation have disappeared, and
we are left with a wise old gentleman thoughtfully pursuing
àperq and virtù for the good of generations to come.20 Salter
feels constantly obliged to defend the personal qualities of his
hero — his sanity, modesty, honesty, attractiveness, general all-
around balance of character. Nietzsche has to be a sage, and
sages have to be mellow, like Goethe or Emerson. But nothing
can be more certain than that Nietzsche's personal qualities
were most unendearing, that during the decade in which he
wrote his great books he was as unpleasant a person as any
clinical record of literature can show. Nietzsche's greatness
may have come from his more than Promethean suffering; but
it is a tortured, frenetic, shrilly intellectual cry that comes from
his suffering, a cry one does not hear in Salter's conscientious
book.
The English Nietzscheane formed in the earlier years of the
century a devoted band, now rather broken up by time and two
" Gide, Oeuvres complètes, III, 237, "Lettres à Angèle."
™ W . M. Salter, Nietzsche the Thinner, especially p. 375.
THE GROWTH OF A REPUTATION 191
wars against Nietzsche's fatherland. Some of them were, at
least in appearance, tough Nietzscheans. As a band, however,
they tended to support, and spread abroad among literate Eng-
lishmen, the conception of Nietzsche as at bottom a profound
evolutionist, a moralist who really wanted what Herbert
Spencer wanted, peace and plenty, but saw that nineteenth-
century Englishmen weren't getting it very fast. They were a
somewhat disparate and not very popular group, who centered
their work around the eighteen-volume translation of the
Master into English, edited by Oscar Levy. J. M. Kennedy, who
translated some of the volumes, was perhaps their leading
pundit. He published during the War of 1914-1918 a short
volume on Nietzsche, ironically sub-titled "The Mind that
caused the Great War," and aiming to prove that Nietzsche
had in no sense influenced the Germans to make war. That
evil thing Treitschke had done, not Nietzsche. The good
Master, urging force, wrote "with an ideal Europe in mind." 2 1
Kennedy indeed, as did most of the English Nietzscheans, took
the Master's anti-democratic ideas very seriously. Some of
Kennedy's schemes for keeping the lower classes lower sound
almost tough. But so do some of Plato's schemes for achieving
the same end, and no one ever called Plato tough.
The philosophical and the aesthetic strains are the ones most
heard among the gentle Nietzscheans of any country. Brandes,
d'Annunzio, André Gide, Havelock Ellis, otherwise a strange
gathering, are all gentle Nietzscheans who found the Master
first of all a Poet.22 Poets, in spite of the authority of Shelley,
a
J . M. Kennedy, Nietzsche ( 1 9 1 4 ) , 9.
"Ellis's essay on Nietzsche was published in Affirmations (1898) and re-
mains an admirable specimen of the aesthetic touch applied to the Master.
192 NIETZSCHE
that the gentle Nietzscheans as a sect are dying out. But they
are far from extinct. The increasing use of Nietzsche's name
by the German National Socialists in defense of the way of life
of the Third Reich, the attempt to make of him a kind of John
the Baptist for the Savior Hitler, has infuriated the gentle
Nietzscheans, and made them vocal again. One of them writes:
T h e herald of " T h e Higher M a n , " of the "roaming blond beast," this
aberration from the main line of his productivity, is played up [by the
Nazis] against the "good European," which he remained his whole
life long. . . . He, who appreciated the chivalrous greatness of the
English spirit just as he did the deep leaning to psychology of the Rus-
sians, he the enthusiastic worshipper of Stendhal, the admirer of Sterne,
Heine, Voltaire, is above every suspicion of having glorified Power in the
sense of nationalistic racial arrogance. W h a t final tragic fate it is, that
this martyr of thought, whose life has been an eternal battle against the
traditional and the outworn in his own heart, this actual martyr to
truthfulness, should be held aloft as their approving prophet by the
untruthful of today. 2 5
NIETZSCHE A N D T H E NAZIS
1
0 . Henne am Rhyn, Anti-Zarathustra (1899), IX. Henne am Rhyn
was especially grieved by a gentle Nietzschean who had asserted that Nietzsche
preached "Freedom and the Dignity of Woman."
202 NIETZSCHE
"O. Levy, "Nietzsche im Krieg," Die weissen Blätter (1919), VI, 277-278.
This article contains a good list of those who attacked and those who de-
fended Nietzsche in relation to "war-guilt."
NIETZSCHE A N D THE NAZIS 203
The idea of Power and the idea of War both entered into the work —
the later work, it is important to remember — of Nietzsche. But in his
hands they became spiritualized and transformed. Power was no longer
the force of success in this world, and War was no longer a method of
overcoming mere human enemies, but both alike belonged to the sphere
of the evolving soul. . . . My study of Nietzsche is not a study of the
Nietzsche of the moment but of the essential and significant Nietzsche.3
II
National Socialism, like almost all successful revolutionary
movements, has in it elements which are also found in religious
bodies. One of these is the possession of holy writings. The
National Socialist canon is not yet completed, has not yet indeed
reached even the rough state of fixity attained by wholly estab-
lished religions. This is perhaps no more than to say that Na-
tional Socialism is still a growing and active faith. Mein Kampf
is already the central piece of the Nazi canon; but Hitler's
gospel needs some reinforcing. It needs antecedents, and if pos-
sible antecedents that will give it a philosophical respectability
it does not in itself seem — especially to the unconverted — to
have. Gobineau, H. S. Chamberlain, Treitschke, Spengler,
Alfred Rosenberg have all made their contributions to the
articles of faith. Nietzsche, too, has been drafted into service.
There can be no doubt that there is being made by important
people in contemporary Germany a conscious effort to enlist
Nietzsche as one of the pillars of the Nazi society.
The books and articles published on Nietzsche in Nazi Ger-
many are in themselves quite adequate evidence that such an
effort is being made. It should be clear from what has already
been said in this study about the vogue of Nietzsche since the
mid-nineties that there is nothing new in the mere fact that
articles and books on the Master keep appearing. But hitherto,
especially in Germany, such writing has been mainly addressed
to scholars, philosophers, lovers of the beautiful; and even when
it has been directed at popularizing the Master, it has been the
work of gentle Nietzscheans. What is striking in the Nietzsche
literature of the last dozen years in Germany is the emergence
NIETZSCHE AND THE NAZIS 207
of short popular books expressly intended to make Nietzsche
clear to ordinary literate Germans, and to show just how his
ideas fit into the Nazi völkische Weltanschauung?
Fair samples of such books are Alfred Baeumler's Nietzsche
der Philosoph und Politiker (Nietzsche the Philosopher and
Political Thinker), published in 1931 in Reclams Universal-
Bibliothe\, which is a sort of German equivalent of our Home
University Library; Hans Prinzhorn's Nietzsche und das XX
Jahrhundert (Nietzsche and the Twentieth Century), which in
1928 already anticipates official Nazi interpretations of Nie-
tzsche's work; Dr. Gottlieb Scheuffler's Friedrich Nietzsche im
Dritten Reich (Friedrich Nietzsche in the Third Reich), pub-
lished late in 1933, in celebration of the linking of the spiritual
children of Nietzsche, the two great natural aristocrats, Hitler
and Mussolini; Richard Oehler's Friedrich Nietzsche und die
deutsche Zukunft (Friedrich Nietzsche and the German Fu-
ture), published in 1935; and the handbook which Heinrich
Haertle brought out in 1937 under the title of Nietzsche und
der Nationalsozialismus (Nietzsche and National Socialism).
This last went into a second edition in 1939. Nietzsche's name
appears frequently in current German periodicals, and by no
means solely in philosophical and other learned journals. Here
again it is clear that the writers are working to impress Nie-
tzsche into the service of the new Nazi society.8
7
A good Nazi writer says this specifically: "And now it has come about
that the hitherto purely learned interest in the philosopher Nietzsche has
been broadened into love and reverence towards the man." F. Erdmann, in
the Ostdeutsche Monatshefte (1936), XVIII, 515. Erdmann is reviewing the
first volumes of the historisch-britische Ausgabe of Nietzsche. He adds that
now everything of Nietzsche must be printed. His work has become too
sacred for mere editors to pick and choose from it.
"For instance, "Nietzsche und wir" (Nietzsche and Ourselves), by M. O.
2o8 NIETZSCHE
The Historisch-\ritische Gesamtausgabe of the works and the
letters of Nietzsche is coming along slowly with the aid of
the Nietzsche-Archiv in Weimar. It is being undertaken with
the care, reverence, and detail given usually only to great men
of letters or great prophets. The four volumes of the works so
far issued reach only to Nietzsche's days as a student at Leipzig
— they are all, in fact, mere juvenilia or philological apprentice-
work and notes. Apparently any scrap of paper on which he
traced his childish fancies or student needs seems to the editors
worth reprinting. The war has undoubtedly slowed up this
edition, but only a catastrophe will stop it. As a thorough edi-
torial job — and also, though this must be an accident, some-
what in format and general appearance — this Gesamtausgabe
resembles another famous Gesamtausgabe that used to come out
of Germany before 1933, that of Marx and Engels. There may
be something symbolic here.
Finally, the Fuehrer himself has publicly gone on record as
having learned from Nietzsche. Hitler does not specifically
mention Nietzsche among the authors he read in his Vienna
days of unemployment, but it seems quite likely that many of
Nietzsche's notions filtered down to him second-hand even
before he went actively into politics. Since the revolution of
1933, Hitler has made several public visits to the Nietzsche-
w
£
IN
Os
υ S
Ρύ O
«
ω -«Γ
Χ 'S-
ο <s
UÏ g?
Ν
Η ο
Μ
o.
W
Χ
Η
Η
<
ai
ω
J
Η
NIETZSCHE A N D T H E NAZIS 209
Ill
Nazi exegetes have been obliged to quote Nietzsche directly
and exactly — in these days of cheap printing, simple falsifying
of such texts is difficult. It should be plain, even from the
necessarily brief and schematic outline of Nietzsche's ideas
given in previous chapters of this study, that they can find
much in the Master which they can appropriate directly for
their own uses. Whatever their ultimate destiny, the Nazis are
revolutionists, and they are revolting against a society Nietzsche
had earlier revolted against. A good Nazi curls his lips as
212 NIETZSCHE
Twilight of the Idols, "Skirmishes in a War with the Age," §39, 38;
u
" Genealogy of Morals, "Peoples and Countries," § 14, 17; Will to Power,
§ 912; Zarathustra, Part I, chap. 10.
"The'Will to Power, §954.
214 NIETZSCHE
" Genealogy of Morals, Part I, § n . Note that already in 1883, the Japanese
are apparently "honorary Aryans."
17 Haertle, Nietzsche und der Nationalsozialismus, 6ι.
NIETZSCHE A N D T H E NAZIS 215
views, especially in so far as they depend on a knowledge of
genetics, are not as unzeitgemässe as he liked to think. Nie-
tzsche accepts the notion of blended inheritance in its simpler
forms. Occasionally he comes very close indeed to the Nazi
program, as in the following recommendations in a matter of
which he probably had less actual experience than is usual,
even among German philosophers:
Concerning the future of marriage — A super-tax on inherited property,
a long term of military service for bachelors. . . . Privileges of all sorts
for fathers who lavish boys upon the world, and perhaps plural votes
as well. A medical certificate as a condition of marriage, endorsed by
the parochial authorities, on which a series of questions addressed to the
parties and the medical officers must be answered ("family histories").
A s a counter-agent to prostitution, or as its ennoblement, I would recom-
mend leasehold marriages, to last for a term of years or months, with
adequate provision for the children. 18
Part IV, §26; Will to Power, § 184, 864; Beyond Good and Evil, §251; and
especially Antichrist, 24-27.
Beyond Good and Evil, § 251. Clearly a discerning Nazi would need
to make suppressions here, but the substance is good Nazi doctrine.
NIETZSCHE A N D T H E NAZIS 217
urged this break, and the book which he hoped would be the
bible of the new dispensation, are both worth our attention
here. It may well be that the relatively concrete hatreds and
hopes we have just been outlining are more fundamental in
current Nazi education than such Nietzschean abstractions as
the "transvaluation of all values," the "Superman" and the
"Will to Power," or such Nietzschean poetic and prophetic
strains as resound in Also sprach Zarathustra; none the less,
both Nietzsche's metaphysics and his prophetic writings are
popular in contemporary Germany, and throw additional light
on the nature of National Socialist plans for the Good Society.
In fact, most of Nietzsche's grand abstract terms, though
they can be given a variety of interpretations, contain overtones,
implications, admirably suited to Nazi uses. The famous phrase
"Will to Power" suggests ruthlessness, aggression, a policy of
expansion perfectly illustrated since Hitler's accession to power.
The concept of a new race of Supermen, though Nietzsche
himself left it as obscure in form and in detail as are most such
eschatological concepts of recent invention, has proved very
flattering to an aspiring Nazi elite, who have considered that
they were at least making possible the development of a new
race of men. 21
This most famous Nietzschean doctrine is, however, danger-
ous as well as useful for the purposes of Nazi leaders. It does,
as we have seen, sketch out a Fuehrerprinzip·, but it also sug-
gests an inner conflict which may give them real trouble.
Hitler himself does not conceal that he shares the contempt for
IV
So much for what the Nazis find good and immediately
quotable in the work of Nietzsche. There is all told a very
great deal of it, especially in The Will to Power and in some
of the unpublished fragments which Baeumler has published
under the title The Innocence of Becoming?* Yet there is a lot
more that it would be indiscreet, and indeed dangerous, to
announce publicly in Germany today without very careful
attribution to Nietzsche, and some very ingenious explanation
to boot. Here are a few passages of the sort that the gentle
Nietzscheans have been flinging back at the tough ones for
forty years:
The Germans may well be the most mixed of all peoples. . . . Bismarck
a Slav. Let anyone look upon the face of the Germans. Everything that
had manly, exuberant blood in it went abroad. Over the smug populace
remaining, the slave-souled people, there came an improvement from
abroad, especially by a mixture of Slavic blood. . . . What a blessing a
Jew is among Germans I See the obtuseness, the flaxen hair, the blue eye,
and the lack of intellect in the face, the language, and the bearing . . .
among Germans. . . . The Jews are beyond all doubt the strongest,
toughest, and purest race now living in Europe. 27
" A. Baeumler, ed., Die Unschuld des Werdens: Der Nachlass (1931).
" Genealogy of Morals, "Peoples and Countries," § 1 3 ; Beyond Good and
Evil, §251.
222 NIETZSCHE
and evil, and certainly not prepared to go beyond good and evil.
There are still serious problems before Nazi educators who
wish to use Nietzsche properly. Probably the commonest solu-
tion is to blame Nietzsche's errors on his environment. Haertle,
for instance, admits that Nietzsche did make mistakes. He is
quite frank about the matter. Some parts of Nietzsche's writ-
ings, he admits, are really the opposite of Nazi truth. "In the
measure that the interest in Nietzsche grows, the danger of
misunderstanding grows" — that is, the danger that young
Germans may actually accept what is anti-Nazi in him as just
as valid as what is pro-Nazi. Haertle therefore lists "errors"
very carefully, under headings such as "race," "the Jewish
question," "state" and so on. But he minimizes their place in
Nietzsche's work, and always he is able to explain them, usually
as an effect of the nineteenth-century environment. Nietzsche
saw many and great truths; but he saw them as from the midst
of a swamp, the swamp of nineteenth-century liberalism and
democracy, and inevitably the rising mists obscured his vision.
When he agrees with the Nazis, he is the prophet to whom is
granted the true vision of things to come; when he disagrees
with them, he is the mortal who cannot be expected to rise
entirely above his environment.31
There are variations on this explanation. Such, for instance,
is the assertion, dear to Baeumler, that Nietzsche had to push
his thoughts to paradoxical and violent extremes in order to
make any impression on so stupid an age; that, for instance, he
had to pretend to see some good things in the Jews and many
bad things in organized anti-semitism, in order to get any
81
Haertle, Nietzsche und der Nationalsozialismus, especially Part I, "Ein-
leitung."
226 NIETZSCHE
" " W e are feeling the consequences of the doctrine, preached lately from
all the housetops, that the state is the highest end of man and that there is
no higher duty than to serve it: I regard this not as a relapse into paganism,
but into stupidity." Thoughts out of Season, "Schopenhauer as Educator,"
chap. iv. Needless to say this passage, which could be duplicated in essentials
from any of Nietzsche's works, save perhaps The Will to Power and others
of his very latest period, is not used as a text by the N a z i preachers.
228 NIETZSCHE
(germanisch) qualities of virility, joy, simplicity, strength, and
so on. Were there on earth a state germanisch instead of
deutsch, Nietzsche would at once submit himself gratefully to
such a state. There is now such a state, the Third Reich, and
Nietzsche is undoubtedly smiling down upon it from Valhalla.
Baeumler then clinches his argument: Nietzsche hated a Reich
governed by a Kaiser, a bad Teutonic copy of the Roman
Caesar; he would have loved a Reich governed by a head
ineffably German, a Fuehrer.34
It is hardly necessary to pursue Baeumler much further. The
dialectical skill reported above is characteristic enough. Noth-
ing, in fact, stumps him. Did Nietzsche call himself something
that sounds like "freethinker," and does freethinker suggest to
the uninitiated Voltaire, Tom Paine, and other clearly non-
German writers? Mistake. "Not Latin freethinking {latein-
ische Freigeisterei) but Siegfried stands back of Nietzsche's
attack on Christianity." Even when Nietzsche praises the
Renaissance, he is praising nothing Latin. He is praising the
fighting spirit of the period; moreover, the north and central
Italians Nietzsche admired came of the nobility, and were
"extremely probably" of German blood. Baeumler ends with
a little prophetic flight of his own: "The German state of the
future will not be a continuation of the work of Bismarck; it
will rather be built out of the spirit of Nietzsche and the spirit
of the Great War." 3 5
The Italians themselves have made Nietzsche a good fascist.
The Nazis then, and their fascist followers are tough Nie-
tzscheane in a more than literary and aesthetic sense. Nietzsche
is held in high honor today in his native land. He has become
one of the Early Fathers of the revolutionary Nazi faith. Point
for point he preached, along with a good deal else which the
Nazis choose to disremember, most of the cardinal articles of
the professed Nazi creed — a transvaluation of all values, the
sanctity of the* will to power, the right and duty of the strong
to dominate, the sole right of great states to exist, a renewing,
a rebirth, of German and hence European society. More
vaguely, Nietzsche preached the coming of the Superman; and
though many different ethical values can be, and have been,
attached to this concept of the Superman, both the Nazi idea
of the Master-race and the Nazi appeal to the, principle of
leadership (Fuehrerprinzip) are among the most obvious arid
congruous derivatives of that concept. Finally, the emotional
tone of Nietzsche's life and writings, as distinguished from his
ideas, is much like what we hear of the emotional tone of inner
Nazi circles. The unrelieved tension, the feverish aspiration,
the driving madness, the great noise Nietzsche made for him-
self, the Nazi elite is making for an uncomfortably large part
of the world. But these are vague, grand terms. The situation
can be described much more simply. Nietzsche, like the Nazi
leaders, was never really house-broken.
CHAPTER IX
N I E T Z S C H E IN W E S T E R N T H O U G H T :
PROPHECY ON A PROPHET
I
NIETZSCHE'S WORKS
A . T H E WRITINGS
Π
MAINLY BIOGRAPHICAL
•Andler, Charles, Nietzsche, sa vie et sa pensée, 6 vols. (Paris: Bossard,
1920-1931).
Vol. II, La jeunesse de Nietzsche and Vol. IV, La maturité de Nietzsche
jusqu'à sa mort are mainly biographical. This is the most scholarly
study of Nietzsche's life. It neglects no important evidence, and tries
to hold the balance between the Nietzsche-Archiv and Bernoulli-
Overbeck. But it is frankly adulatory, the work of a very gentle
Nietzschean. Andler actually thinks Nietzsche was at heart a socialisti
Andréas-Salomé, Lou, Friedrich Nietzsche in seinen Werfen, new
edition (Dresden: C. Reissner, 1927).
Unaltered reprint of the original edition of 1894. Lou "reveals" less
personally than might be expected. Remains an interesting source for
Nietzsche's biography.
•Bernoulli, C. Α., Franz Overbeck und Friedrich Nietzsche: Eine
Freundschaft, 2 vols. (Jena: 1908).
This, with its opposite, the work of Elizabeth Förster-Nietzsche, is
the basis of any study of Nietzsche biography. Bernoulli has on the
whole kept himself out of his book, content to put together material
Overbeck had accumulated. Overbeck was a sensible man, who liked
and admired Nietzsche, but who was aware of, and reported, traits
not brought out by Elizabeth. The publication of this book began
a most undignified feud, carried on in the best traditions of the
German learned world, between Elizabeth and Bernoulli. Elizabeth
got a court judgment suppressing from Vol. II of Overbeck und
Nietzsche certain letters of Peter Gast's which the court decided
were her property, as Nietzsche's heir. These passages are inked
over in most copies of this volume, but with patience the words can
be made out beneath the inking. They are not important.
Brann, H . W . , Nietzsche und die Frauen (Leipzig: Meiner, 1 9 3 1 ) .
A very fair treatment of a difficult subject. Inevitably a certain amount
of psychiatric and psychological jargon. Brann's general view is that
Nietzsche wanted very much to have a normal sexual life, and that
his failure to attain that purpose further disturbed his mental and
physical balance.
Cohn, P., Um Nietzsches Untergang (Hannover: Morris-Verlag, 1 9 3 1 ) .
A modernized version of the pietistic Nietzsche-Archiv attitude to-
wards Nietzsche's health.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 251
•Forster-Nietzsche, E., The Life of Nietzsche, translated by A. M. Ludo-
vici, 2 vols. (London and New York: 1912-1915). Vol. I, The
Young Nietzsche; Vol. II, The Lonely Nietzsche.
This is for most purposes the most useful of the various biographical
writings his sister Elizabeth devoted to Nietzsche. It is pure worship,
straight hagiographical writing. Elizabeth had all of her brother's
determination, energy, and sense of being right. Otherwise, she was
very stupid. She has no capacity at all for handling ideas. The book
does, however, give biographical details nowhere else available.
Halévy, D., The Life of Friedrich Nietzsche, translated from the French
by J. M. Hone (London: 1 9 1 1 ) .
This is a good translation of a well-known French short life of
Nietzsche, published in France in 1909. It is based largely on Eliza-
beth Förster-Nietzsche's work, but put together with infinitely more
literary skill and tact. It is most sympathetic towards Nietzsche, who
is pictured as a heroic martyr to Truth and Beauty in a vulgar,
anarchic society. Halévy writes with full French sentimentality.
Meyer, R. M., Nietzsche, sein Leben und seine Wer\e (Munich: 1913).
One of the pleasantest and soberest of German lives.
Miigge, Μ. Α., Friedrich Nietzsche. His Life and Wor\, third edi-
tion (London: 1 9 1 1 ) . '
Part IV, pages 385-442, is headed "Bibliography and Iconography."
It is very thorough, covering magazine articles in the major European
languages. That a bibliography in 1911 could be so huge is sympto-
matic. It could no doubt be tripled in length today. Mügge's Life
is not a distinguished one.
Podach, E. F., Nietzsches Zusammenbruch (Heidelberg: Ν . Kamp-
mann, 1930). French translation, L'Effondrement de Nietzsche
(Paris: Librairie Gallimard, 1931). English translation, The Mad-
ness of Nietzsche (London and New York: Putnam, 1931).
The soundest general treatment of Nietzsche's physical and mental
ills. Podach's notes incorporate a very full bibliography of the sub-
ject up to 1930.
Der Kran\e Nietzsche: Briefe seiner Mutter am Franz Overbec\,
edited by E. F. Podach (Vienna: Bermann-Fischer Verlag, 1937).
These letters from his mother to Overbeck cover the years 1889 to
1897, and give all sorts of details of Nietzsche's last illness.
252 NIETZSCHE
III
MAINLY CRITICAL
A. NIETZSCHE'S IDEAS
IV
NIETZSCHE'S REPUTATION AND INFLUENCE
A. GENERAL
It is too bad that the late Charles Andler, who knew more about
Nietzsche than any scholar ever has known, did not add a volume
on Le rayonnement des idées de Nietzsche. This most important
study of what men have made of Nietzsche's ideas is the most neg-
lected phase of Nietzschean scholarship. I have had to piece together
my chapters on Nietzsche's reputation and influence from very diverse
materials. Here I list only those books that deal with fairly large
aspects of Nietzsche's influence.
Benda, J., La trahison des clercs (Paris: Β. Grasset, 1927). Translated
into English by R. Aldington as The Treason of the Intellectuals
(New York: W. Morrow, 1928).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 257
Nietzsche is for Benda one of the most important of the literary men
of our time who have "betrayed" us.
Bianquis, Geneviève, Nietzsche en France (Paris: F. Alean, 1929).
By a disciple of Andler. Thorough and very useful. Good bibliography.
Deesz, Gisela, Die Entwicklung des Nietzsche-Bildes in Deutschland
(Würzburg: Κ. Triltsch, 1933).
A doctoral dissertation, and rather slender. Deals chiefly with the
interpretation of Nietzsche by German academic philosophers from
Vaihinger to Baeumler. A useful, if limited, summary.
Gundolf, E. and Hildebrandt, Κ., Nietzsche als Richter unser Zeit
(Breslau: F. Hirt, 1923).
Horneffer, E., Nietzsche als Vorbote der Gegenwart (Düsseldorf:
A. Bagel, 1935).
Nicolas, M. P., De Nietzsche à Hitler (Paris: Fasquelle, 1936). English
translation, From Nietzsche down to Hitler (London: W. Hodge
and Company, 1938).
A warm defense of Nietzsche from "abuse" by the Nazis. Nicolas
insists that nothing in Nietzsche's writings can be legitimately and
logically given a sense favorable to the Nazis. The notes cover a good
range of the literature on Nietzsche.
Spengler, O., "Nietzsche und sein Jahrhundert," in his Reden und
Aufsätze (Munich: C. H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1937).
More of Spengler.
Spenlé, J. E., "Nietzsche médiateur spirituel entre la France et l'Alle-
magne," Mercure de France (Paris), CCLXXVI (1937), 275.
Alas!
Stewart, H. L., Nietzsche and the Ideals of Modem Germany (Lon-
don: 1915).
A good example of a book produced by the Four Years' War. Stewart
thinks Nietzsche had a large part in preparing Germany to make
the aggression of 1914.
B. N I E T Z S C H E AND T H E N A Z I S