The Reconstruction
The Reconstruction
The Reconstruction
OF RELIGIOUS
THOUGHT IN ISLAM
encountering traditions
M U H A M M A D I Q BA L
LECTURE I
Knowledge and Religious Experience 1
LECTURE II
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations
of Religious Experience 23
LECTURE III
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer 50
LECTURE IV
The Human Ego—His Freedom and Immortality 76
LECTURE V
The Spirit of Muslim Culture 99
LECTURE VI
The Principle of Movement in the Structure of Islam 116
LECTURE VII
Is Religion Possible? 143
vi Contents
Notes and References 158
Bibliography 215
- Index
Qur’anic 236
Index 242
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
,WLVGLIÀFXOWWRLGHQWLI\DWKLQNHUZKRLQWHJUDWHVDVPDQ\RSSRVLWHVLQ
his person and in his ideas as Muhammad Iqbal (1877–1938). A juxta-
position of some of the opposites that he integrates would look like this:
He is among the last classical Persian and Urdu poets.
+HLVDPRQJWKHÀUVWPRGHUQ0XVOLPSKLORVRSKHUV
He is considered the intellectual father of Pakistan.
One of his poems is among the national songs of India.
His Javed Namah is an expression of his love for Rumi.
His Payam-e-Mashriq is an expression of his love for Goethe.
The Turks honored him, giving him an honorary resting place
alongside Rumi in Konya.
The Germans honored him by naming a park after him in
Heidelberg.
He counted Rumi, Ibn Khaldun, Ghazali, Akbar Allahabadi
among his teachers.
He openly acknowledged his debt to Emerson, Whitehead,
Bergson, James, Royce.
The leading philosophers of his day counted him as one of their
own.
The leading mystics of his day counted him as one of their own.
His work demonstrates intimate knowledge of modern science
and Western philosophy.
He considered all his poetry and philosophy to be an exegesis of
the Qur’an.
Iqbal’s quest to build bridges and establish relationship between
opposites embodies the spirit of Tawheed and is a major reason for
his widespread popularity in the Muslim world. His Urdu poetry
is known throughout the Indo-Pak subcontinent and his Persian
viii The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
poetry—in Iran and the Persian-speaking Central Asian republics.
Arabic translations of his poetry have been put to song by the Arab
icon Umm Kulthum. His works in translation are avidly read in
Turkey, Malaysia, and Indonesia. With the spread of the Muslim
diaspora in the West, academies have been established in England,
Norway, the United States, and elsewhere to disseminate his work.
As Iqbal points out repeatedly in his poetry and prose, his quest
to build bridges and establish relations is the result of a Qur’anically
inspired vision. This tawheedic vision aspires to transform life-
denying divisions into life-giving relationships. A partial list of the
divisions that are transformed into relationships in Iqbal’s thought
would include: modernity/tradition, East/West, religion/science,
philosophy/mysticism, and the human self/Divine Other. His best-
known work in prose, The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in
Islam, is the one place where Iqbal’s philosophy is outlined most
clearly and systematically. This is a seminal text for both Islamic
and modern Western philosophy. For a variety of reasons, it has
been published only once by a Western press, Oxford University
Press in 1934, in an unedited, unfootnoted form. After a lapse of
almost eighty years, a collaboration between the Iqbal Academy
Pakistan and Stanford University Press addressed this lacuna. Given
the centrality of the Qur’an in Iqbal’s thought (the Qur’an is the
most often cited source in The Reconstruction of Religious Thought
in IslamLWLVYHU\ÀWWLQJWKDWWKLVWH[WLVEHLQJUHLQWURGXFHGWR
a Western audience as part of the Encountering Traditions series.
The publication of this classic by Stanford University Press in-
troduces the thought of one of the most important Muslim thinkers
of the twentieth century to a new generation of Western scholars.
Iqbal’s thought played a decisive role in the establishment of one
Muslim nation-state (Pakistan), it played a critical role in one of
the major political revolutions in the twentieth century (the Iranian
5HYROXWLRQDQGLWPDGHDVLJQLÀFDQWFRQWULEXWLRQWRWKHVXUYLYDO
RI0XVOLPLGHQWLW\LQSDUWVRIWKHIRUPHU8665*LYHQWKHVLJQLÀ-
cant impact of Iqbal’s ideas in different parts of the Muslim world,
direct access to this text opens up the possibility of a better under-
standing of the Muslim world.
6WLOOLWZRXOGEHDJURVVXQGHUHVWLPDWLRQRIWKHVLJQLÀFDQFHRI
Iqbal’s thought if one were to assume that its relevance is limited
to the Muslim world. Robert Whittemore argues that while Iqbal’s
Preface to the American Edition ix
philosophy is faithful to the teachings of the Qur’an, it is “an achieve-
ment possessing a philosophical importance far transcending the
world of Islam.”1 Iqbal’s falsafa-e-khudi offers a possible resolu-
WLRQWRRQHRIWKHPRVWLQWUDFWDEOHFRQÁLFWVLQJOREDOL]HG:HVWHUQ
PRGHUQLW\´WKHSHUHQQLDOFRQÁLFWEHWZHHQVFLHQFHSKLORVRSK\
and religion.”2 Commenting on the place of The Reconstruction
of Religious Thought in Islam in modern philosophy, Whittemore
notes, “Iqbal, in fact, has added yet another dimension to that cosmo-
theological point of view associated in the west with such names as
Whitehead, Berdyaev, Montague, Hartshorne, and William James.”3
Iqbal’s work does not add to modern philosophy in merely quanti-
tative terms. Whittemore concludes his analysis by suggesting that
the breadth and success of Iqbal’s reconstruction project make it a
unique achievement in the annals of modern Western philosophy.
&KDUOHV7D\ORUDUJXHVWKDW,TEDO·VWKRXJKWLVVLJQLÀFDQWQRWRQO\
from the perspective of intellectual history but also because it speaks
directly to our present cultural condition. After noting (in 2010) that
“we must reread Iqbal,” Taylor goes on to explain:
We . . . have shared reasons, Western, Muslim and Eastern merged together,
in reading this remarkable man. Because our dialogues are troubled by a
deep and mutual distrust. This distrust is partly derived from our own un-
certainty regarding our identity, which sometimes gives us a feeling of in-
security under the gaze of others. It’s this feeling that can lead to a sort
RIK\SHUFRQÀGHQFHWLJKWHQLQJDURXQGDULJLGLGHQWLW\DQGWKHEHOOLJHUHQW
UHMHFWLRQRIWKHRWKHUDVWKHEHDUHURIHYLO7RVHHNRXWDQGGHÀQHRQHVHOI
using references found in the other’s tradition becomes impossible, becomes
treasonous.4
Notes
1. R. Whittemore, “Iqbal’s Panentheism,” The Review of Metaphysics 9, no. 4
(June 1956): 681–99, 682.
2. Ibid., 698.
3. Ibid., 682.
4. C. Taylor, “Preface” in S. B. Diagne, Islam and Open Society: Fidelity and
Movement in the Philosophy of Muhammad Iqbal, xi–xii; translated from the French
by Melissa McMahon (Dakar, Senegal: Council for the Development of Social Science
Research in Africa, 2010), xi.
5. Ibid., xii.
6. Ibid.
INTRODUCTION TO MUHAMMAD IQBAL’S
THE RECONSTRUCTION OF RELIGIOUS THOUGHT
IN ISLAM
Javed Majeed
Cosmopolitanism
A striking feature of The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in
Islam is the depth of its cosmopolitanism, as expressed, for exam-
ple, in the wide range of its references to texts and thinkers from
across different traditions and epochs. In part, this intellectual cos-
Introduction xiii
mopolitanism is a consequence of British colonialism itself, which
brought together diverse areas and regions in ways that enabled
not just the circulation of goods and commodities but also texts
and ideas in multiple languages and translations. This circulation
of ideas and texts created what Kris Manjapra and Sugata Bose
have called “cosmopolitan thought zones” for Indian thinkers who
engaged with the works of writers and thinkers from all over the
world.11 Iqbal’s work bears the imprint of this cosmopolitanism. It
ZHDYHVWRJHWKHUUHIHUHQFHVWRWKH4XU·ăQDQGDSSUR[LPDWHO\IRUW\
nine writers (both Muslims and European), blending them together
in relation to key philosophical problems and themes.12 He also
draws parallels between the intellectual situations of Muslim and
Western thinkers, for example, by suggesting similarities between
al-Ghazali and Kant in terms of their “apostolic” missions.13
Thus, Iqbal’s Reconstruction emerges from the cosmopolitan
thought zones and global conversations that underpinned Indian
intellectual life as a style and way of thinking in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries. In order to put thinkers in different traditions
in dialogue with each other, Iqbal de-temporalizes the history of
thought, presenting these thinkers as if they were contemporaries
who discuss the same philosophical and metaphysical questions.
In this way, the “pursuit of conversations across lines of differ-
ence” (as Manjapra puts it) becomes central to the way the book
positions Muslim religious thought in its encounters with Europe.14
By de-temporalizing the history of the engagement between Islam
and European thought, Iqbal presents the encounter as a conversa-
tion among intellectual equals, lifting it above the hierarchies of
power created by European colonialism. In this way, the style and
methodology of the book creates a kind of anti-colonial cosmo-
politanism in which intellectual self-assertion, grounded in learned
reading, is key.15 However, this sometimes means that the text reads
as if cosmopolitan eclecticism were an end in its own right. The
display of wide reading, the suggestion of linkages, or what Iqbal
calls “unsuspected mutual harmonies,”16 and the dense, convoluted
texture of the book exceeds the imperatives of argumentation. At
times the Reconstruction is in danger of being overwhelmed by ir-
resolution, as it weaves together fragments of texts in relation to a
wider set of concerns that are sometimes obscured by the richness
of its own cosmopolitanism.17
xiv The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
The cosmopolitan thought zones of Indian intellectuals extended
beyond the Britain-India axis created by empire. A number of in-
ÁXHQWLDO,QGLDQVWUDYHOOHGZRUNHGDQGVWXGLHGLQWKHFRQWLQHQWRI
Europe, especially in Germany, and Iqbal was one of them.18 The
Reconstruction makes substantial reference to German thinkers, in-
cluding Kant, Hegel, Goethe, and Schopenhauer, as well as French
thinkers like Bergson and Descartes. The experience and motifs of
travel are central to Iqbal’s work, as well as to the texts of a number
of major nationalist thinkers in India. The ReconstructionUHÁHFWV
something of the qualities of a travelling identity and the restless
but creative mobility that characterized the outlook of many Indian
writers and thinkers during the colonial period.19
Indian intellectual life in the colonial period was generated out
of a set of institutions revolving around newspapers, law courts,
public meetings, and learned societies. This gave rise to a range
of speaking styles, debating techniques, and models of rhetorical
persuasion, ranging from legal and theological disputation to po-
litical polemic.20 Iqbal was a major poet in both Urdu and Persian
DQGDOVRDWUDLQHGODZ\HU7KHÀUVWHGLWLRQRIWKHReconstruction,
entitled Six Lectures on the Reconstruction of Religious Thought
in Islam (1930), was based on a series of lectures he gave in India
at Madras, Hyderabad, and Aligarh at the invitation of the Madras
Muslim Association. The second edition (1934), which is the text
used here, added a seventh lecture called “Is Religion Possible?”
This additional lecture was delivered by Iqbal to the Aristotelian
Society in London in December 1932. The book retains the style
of exposition appropriate to a lecture. It reads like notes designed
IRURUDOGHOLYHU\UDWKHUWKDQDÀQLVKHGWH[W,TEDO·VSRHWU\VKRZVD
strong command of the form of the rhyming couplet, and his dis-
tinctive voice emerges from the interplay between the tightness of
that form and the innovative nature of his subject matter.21 In the
Reconstruction the absence of this discipline of writing in couplets
ZLWKFDUHIXOO\PHDVXUHGPHWHUVSURGXFHVDPRUHÁXLGRSHQHQGHG
ZRUNLQ(QJOLVK,QVWHDGRIDSROLVKHGDHVWKHWLFDUWLÀFHZHKDYHD
text in progress.227KHRSHQTXHVWLRQLQWKHKHDGLQJRIWKHÀQDOOHF-
ture, “Is Religion Possible?,” is therefore appropriate for a project
that by its very nature cannot be concluded. This is also in keeping
ZLWK,TEDO·VFRQWHQWLRQWKDWWKHUHLVQRÀQDOLW\LQ0XVOLPODZDQG
WKDWWKHIRXQGHUVRI,VODPLFODZQHYHUFODLPHG´ÀQDOLW\IRUWKHLU
Introduction xv
reasonings and interpretations.”23 In its form and style the Recon-
struction dramatizes what Iqbal calls the “principle of movement
in the structure of Islam,” a principle that he attempts to recover as
the basis of his reconstruction of Islamic thought, not least in his
VWUHVVRQWKH´G\QDPLFRXWORRNµRIWKH4XU·ăQ24
Iqbal’s Reconstruction also draws on and continues earlier tradi-
tions of cosmopolitanism that pre-dated British colonialism. This
parallels re-enactments of other forms of vernacular cosmopolitanism
by thinkers and writers in the Indian subcontinent, such as Nehru.25
In Iqbal’s case, this earlier cosmopolitanism consisted of the long
history of interaction between Islamic philosophy and science and
*UHHNWKRXJKWZKLFKEHJDQLQHDUQHVWZLWKWKH¶$EEăVLG&DOLSKDWH
in the early ninth century.26$VZHKDYHVHHQWKHÀQDOOHFWXUHLQWKH
Reconstruction was based on a talk he gave to the Aristotelian Soci-
HW\LQ/RQGRQ,QKLVZRUNDVDZKROH,TEDOUHÁHFWVRQWKLVKLVWRU\
as he explores and reconstructs relationships between Islam and the
West. In particular, he focuses on the impact that Neoplatonism had
on the development of Islamic mysticism, which he argued played
a role in the decline of Islamic civilization.27 In the Reconstruc-
tion, Iqbal is keen to draw attention to Islamic Hellenism in order
to rebut Eurocentric notions of history. He stresses the creativity
of Islam’s engagement with Greek thought, showing how Muslims
added to and transformed Hellenistic learning. In his earlier English
work, The Development of Metaphysics in Persia (1907), he argued
that this partly stemmed from the very nature of that engagement,
which took place through processes of translation. Because “care-
less translators” of Greek philosophy introduced “a hopeless mass
of absurdities” in the texts, the commentaries on Greek philosophy
by thinkers such as Ibn Sina, Ibn Rushd, and others became “an
effort at discovery, not exposition. . . . They had largely to rethink
the Philosophies of Aristotle and Plato.”28 A similar point has been
made by contemporary scholars, who characterize the translation
activity that brought together Islam and Greece as a consciously
creative act,29 rather than (to use Iqbal’s words) an act of “servile
imitation.”30 Translation both in the sense of re-creating texts by
converting them from one language to another, and of merging dif-
ferent conceptual languages and cultures into each other, was a key
intellectual strategy of Indian thinkers and writers in the colonial
period, as well as of Muslim thinkers in the wider Islamic world.31
xvi The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
Reconstruction relies on works in translation and translates pas-
sages from other texts as well.32 More broadly, the Reconstruction
is an act of translation as the discovery and creative rethinking of
PRGHUQ(XURSHDQWKRXJKWZLWKLQDUHGHÀQHG,VODPLFIUDPHZRUN
Its approach dramatizes and continues the earlier cosmopolitanism
of Islamic Hellenism as an earlier episode in the interaction between
the evolving categories of Islam and Europe.
Conclusion
Iqbal’s Reconstruction remains a key reference point and resource
IRUWKRVHZKRUHÁHFWRQWKHSODFHRI,VODPLQWKHPRGHUQZRUOG
$OL$OODZLIRUH[DPSOHGHVFULEHVLWDV´WKHÀUVWPRGHUQDWWHPSW
by a committed Muslim to rediscover the vitality of Islam in the
light of the evolution of Western philosophical thought and of the
realities of the new, West-dominated world.”84 I have suggested
elsewhere that there are multiple Wests in Iqbal’s work, ranging
from pre-modern Christendom to the site of secular modernity,
the seat of imperial powers and the place of modern science, as
well as the heir of a Hellenistic heritage shared with Islam. The
category of Islam in the Reconstruction is also multifaceted. In its
UHFRQVWUXFWHGIRUPLWVLJQLÀHVDPRQJVWRWKHUWKLQJVDVRFLDOH[-
periment in deracialisation and transnationalism with a concomi-
xxvi The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
tant legal project in political spirituality; a formative contribution
to the inception of modern science; a key narrative (repressed by
others) in the development of modernity; a site for the reconstruc-
tion of individuated selfhood using religious and mystical experi-
ences of the past; a testing ground for the future of religion in the
modern world especially in relation to the truth claims of science;
a response to the opposition between subject and object; and a re-
OLJLRXVO\LQÁHFWHGSRVWFRORQLDOLVP
This list is by no means exhaustive and the fact that the reader
might supplement it is testimony to the open-ended nature of the
FDWHJRU\RI,VODPLQWKHERRN7KHÁXLGLW\DQGFDSDFLRXVQHVVRI
that category, while dramatizing what Iqbal calls the “elasticity
of Islamic thought,” the “ceaseless activity of our early thinkers,”
and its “assimilative spirit,” which he re-enacts in the present,85
also creates its own problems, insofar as ‘Islam’ can lose its speci-
ÀFLW\DQGHIÀFDF\E\EHLQJFRH[WHQVLYHZLWKDUDQJHRIPHDQ-
ings (although if Iqbal were to present a picture of Islam as a core
RIFOHDUO\GHÀQHGEHOLHIVKHZRXOGEHGLVPLVVHGRXWRIKDQGDV
‘fundamentalist’). However, while in Iqbal’s work the boundaries
between the West and Islam can sometimes be porous, it is not the
case, as in the work of some thinkers such as Muhammad ‘Abduh,
that Islam becomes identical with the dominant ideas of modern
Europe.86 Instead, the style and texture of the text, with its inter-
WZLQHGQDUUDWLYHVLWVFRQÁXHQFHRIWH[WXDOIUDJPHQWVIURPDYDUL-
ety of currents of thought, and its avoidance (and even celebration
of) a lack of textual ‘wholeness’, calls attention to the problems of
relating Islam to the West. This stylistic distinctiveness also fore-
JURXQGVWKHGLIÀFXOWLHVRIZKDW,TEDOFDOOVWKH´LPPHQVHµWDVNWR
“rethink the whole system of Islam without completely breaking
with the past.”87 Moreover, the weaving together of fragments and
the text’s creative irresolution articulates the complex relationship
between reconstruction and disintegration. Iqbal opens up spaces
for rethinking by dismantling and reconstituting Islam in a non-
systemic way. The rubble of past tradition (in part created by Iqbal
himself) is selectively appropriated to refashion Islam in the age
of modernity. The text’s distinctive style and aesthetic prompt a
particular kind of reading experience; piecing the text together out
of its fragments, while identifying, teasing out, and disentangling
LWVQDUUDWLYHVWKHUHDGHUVLPXOWDQHRXVO\XQLÀHVDQGGLYLGHVWKH
Introduction xxvii
text. In doing so, s/he participates in the interplay between recon-
struction and disintegration that Iqbal dramatizes and becomes a
co-worker in his project.
Notes
1. Francis Robinson, “The British Empire and the Muslim World,” in The Twentieth
Century, ed. Judith Brown and Wm. Roger Louis, vol. 4 of The Oxford History of
the British Empire, ed. Wm. Roger Louis (Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press, 2001), 398.
2. Albert Hourani, Arabic Thought in the Liberal Age (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press,1983), 103–4, 112–13.
3. Aziz Ahmad, Islamic Modernism in India and Pakistan, 1857–1964 (London:
Oxford University Press, 1967).
4. Kenneth Jones, Socio-Religious Reform Movements in British India (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989).
5. C. A. Bayly, Recovering Liberties: Indian Thought in the Age of Liberalism and
Empire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
6. Muhammad Iqbal, The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam, ed. M.
Saeed Sheikh (1934; repr., Lahore, India: Institute of Islamic Culture, 1999), 132.
7. Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests, trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro
(London: Heinemann, 1972), 4.
8. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 129.
9. Javed Majeed, Muhammad Iqbal: Islam, Aesthetics and Postcolonialism (London,
New York, and New Delhi: Routledge, 2009), 66, 77, 96–97, 146–47.
10. For which, see Bayly, Recovering Liberties, 5; Ranabir Samaddar, Emergence
of the Political Subject (Los Angeles: Sage Publications, 2010), 12.
11. Kris Manjapra and Sugata Bose, eds., Cosmopolitan Thought Zones: South
Asia and the Global Circulation of Ideas (New York: Macmillan, 2010).
12. For telling examples, see Iqbal, Reconstruction, 78–80.
13. Ibid., 4.
14. Kris Manjapra, “Introduction” to Manjapra and Bose, Cosmopolitan Thought
Zones, 1.
15. This strategy of displaying one’s reading for the purposes of creating an
authoritative persona in the public sphere is also evident in the texts of such major
ÀJXUHVDV*DQGKLDQG1HKUX
16. Iqbal, Reconstruction, xxii.
17. Majeed, Iqbal, 56–57.
18. Annemarie Schimmel, Gabriel’s Wing: A Study into the Religious Ideas of Sir
Muhammad Iqbal (Lahore, India: Iqbal Academy, 1989), 37–39.
19. Majeed, Iqbal, chap. 5; Javed Majeed, Autobiography, Travel and Postnational
Identity: Nehru, Gandhi and Iqbal (Basingstoke, UK, and New York: Palgrave Macmillan,
2007); Bayly, Recovering Liberties, 150–60.
20. Bayly, Recovering Liberties, 32, 134–36; Samaddar, Emergence of the Political
Subject, 14–16.
21. Majeed, Iqbal, 1–39.
xxviii The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
22. Although Iqbal’s poetry is also process driven; see ibid.
23. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 134.
24. Ibid., xxi, 132, chap. 6.
25. Majeed, Autobiography, Travel and Postnational Identity, chap. 4.
26. For useful accounts, see Franz Rosenthal, The Classical Heritage in Islam, trans.
Emile and Jenny Marmorstein (London: R. K. Paul, 1975); Majid Fakhry, Philosophy,
Dogma and the Impact of Greek Thought in Islam (Aldershot, UK, and Burlington,
Vermont: Ashgate, 1994); Montgomery Watt, Islamic Philosophy and Theology: An
Extended Survey (Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press, 1985).
27. For a detailed exposition of Iqbal’s Islamic Hellenism, see Majeed, Iqbal, chap. 7.
28. Muhammad Iqbal, The Development of Metaphysics in Persia (1907; repr.,
Lahore, India: Bazm-e Iqbal, n.d.), 22–23.
29. Rosenthal, Classical Heritage in Islam, 1–23.
30. Iqbal, Metaphysics in Persia, 23.
31. Bayly, Recovering Liberties, and Hourani, Arabic Thought in the Liberal
Age, both discuss this in some detail. See also Javed Majeed, “Nature, Hyperbole,
and the Colonial State: Some Muslim Appropriations of European Modernity in Late
Nineteenth Century Urdu Literature,” in Islam and Modernity, ed. John Cooper et al.
(London: I. B. Tauris, 1998).
32. For details, see M. Saeed Sheikh, “Introduction” to Muhammad Iqbal, The
Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam (Lahore, India: Institute of Islamic
Culture, 1999), vi–vii, xv–xvi.
33. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 64, 102–3, 106, 113. As examples, Iqbal refers to works
on optics, psychology, logic, and mathematics. For the analogy between Plato and the
4XU·ăQVHHSDJHZKHUHKHUHIHUVWRKRZWKHODWWHU´FRQVLGHUVLWQHFHVVDU\WRXQLWH
religion and state, ethics and politics in a single revelation much in the same way as
Plato does in the Republic.”
34. Ibid., 3.
35. Ibid., 3, 8, 11, 100–101, 103–4, 106–7.
36. Ibid., xxi.
37. Ibid. This narrative is pursued on xxi, 1, 21, 14–18, 149–50. See also 143–44,
on “higher religion” as based on experience and as a “genuine effort to clarify human
consciousness.”
38. Ibid., xxii, 26–28, 33–34.
39. Ibid., 142.
40. Ibid., 72–73.
41. Ibid., 91, 100.
42. Majeed, Iqbal, chap. 6.
43. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 6.
44. Ibid., 63.
45. Ibid., 57.
46. Ibid., 112–13, 14.
47. Ibid., 154–55.
48. Bayly, Recovering Liberties, 141.
49. David Arnold, Science, Technology and Medicine in Colonial India (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2000), 4.
Introduction xxix
50. For these developments, see ibid., 153–62.
51. B. Prashad, “Introduction” to B. Prashad, ed., The Progress of Science in India
'XULQJWKH3DVW7ZHQW\ÀYH<HDUV (Calcutta: Indian Science Congress Association, 1938).
52. Bayly, Recovering Liberties, 255–57, 278; Arnold, Science, Technology and
Medicine, 169–76.
53. Arnold, Science, Technology and Medicine, 189–90. For an early statement of
Gandhi’s critique, see M. K. Gandhi, Hind Swaraj and Other Writings, ed. Anthony
Parel (1909; repr., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009). Gandhi developed
the themes in Hind Swaraj in his later work, as well as in his An Autobiography or the
Story of My Experiments with Truth (1927–29).
54. Arnold, Science, Technology and Medicine, chap. 4.
55. Ibid., chap. 3.
56. For the popularity of these systems in colonial India, see ibid., 176–85.
57. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 54–57.
58. Schimmel, Gabriel’s Wing, 42–44; Majeed, Iqbal, 24–29.
59. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 156–57.
60. Ibid., 92–94.
61. Ibid., 45, 47–9, 50–51, 57–58, 61–62, 75, 85, 86–87.
62. Ibid., 82.
63. Ibid., 70.
64. Ibid.
65. Ibid., 10, 86–87, 58.
66. M. S. Raschid, Iqbal’s Concept of God (London: R. K. Paul, 1981), 59–60, 62.
67. Majeed, Iqbal, 31–32.
68. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 99.
69. Ibid., 72, 77, 152.
70. Ibid., 145.
71. For a detailed exposition, see Majeed, Iqbal, passim.
72. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 87, 114.
73. Ibid., 114–15.
74. Majeed, Iqbal, chap. 3.
75. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 7–8, 12–13.
76. Ibid., 132–33.
77. Ibid., 126. For Iqbal’s transnational Islam as a process of “deracialisation,”
see Majeed, Iqbal, chap. 4.
78. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 120.
79. Ibid., 120. ,MWLKăG literally means effort, physical or mental, expended in a
particular activity. In legal terms it denotes the exertion of a jurist’s mental faculties
LQÀQGLQJDVROXWLRQWRDOHJDOTXHVWLRQDQGPRUHEURDGO\WKHXVHRILQGHSHQGHQW
reason in interpreting law.
80. Ibid., 134, 121; my emphasis.
81. Ibid., 138–40.
82. Ibid., 121.
83. Ibid., 132.
84. Ali A. Allawi, The Crisis of Islamic Civilisation (New Haven, CT, and London:
Yale University Press, 2009), 52. Allawi’s book interacts with Iqbal in other ways;
xxx The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
the prologue begins with an epigraph from one of Iqbal’s major poems, ‘Shikvâ’
(‘Complaint’), and ends with a citation from it, while chapter 2 begins with an epigraph
from the same poem.
85. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 130.
86. Hourani, Arabic Thought in the Liberal Age, 144.
87. Iqbal, Reconstruction, 78.
EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION
God causeth the day and the night to take their turn. Verily in this
is teaching for men of insight (24: 44).
This is why the Prophet said: "Do not vilify time, for time is
God."24 And this immensity of time and space carries in it the
promise of a complete subjugation by man whose duty is to
Knowledge and Religious Experience 9
reflect on the signs of God, and thus discover the means of
realizing his conquest of Nature as an actual fact:
See ye not how God hath put under you all that is in the Heavens,
and all that is on the earth, and hath been bounteous to you of His
favours both in relation to the seen and the unseen? (31: 20).
And He hath subjected to you the night and the day, the sun and
the moon, and the stars too are subject to you by His behest; verily
in this are signs for those who understand. (16: 12).
Such being the nature and promise of the universe, what is
the nature of man whom it confronts on all sides? Endowed with
a most suitable mutual adjustment of faculties he discovers
himself down below in the scale of life, surrounded on all sides
by the forces of obstruction:
William James, 42
some have always been too patently silly, among the trances and
convulsive seizures some have been too fruitless for conduct and
character, to pass themselves off as significant, still less as divine. In
the history of Christian mysticism the problem how to discriminate
between such messages and experiences as were really divine
miracles, and such others as the demon in his malice was able to
counterfeit, thus making the religious person twofold more the child
of hell he was before, has always been a difficult one to solve,
needing all the sagacity and experience of the best directors of
conscience. In the end it had come to our empiricist criterion: By
their fruits ye shall know them, not by their roots.
The problem of Christian mysticism alluded to by Professor
James has been in fact the problem of all mysticism. The demon
in his malice does counterfeit experiences which creep into the
circuit of the mystic state. As we read in the Qur' an:
We have not sent any Apostle or Prophet 43 before thee among whose
desires Satan injected not some wrong desire, but God shall bring to
naught that which Satan had suggested. Thus shall God affirm His
revelations, for God is Knowing and Wise (22: 52).
And it is in the elimination of the satanic from the Divine that
the followers of Freud have done inestimable service to religion;
though I cannot help saying that the main theory of this newer
psychology does not appear to me to be supported by any
adequate evidence. If our vagrant impulses assert themselves in
our dreams, or at other times we are not strictly ourselves, it
does not follow that they remain imprisoned in a kind of lumber
room behind the normal self. The occasional invasion of these
suppressed impulses on the region of our normal self tends more
to show the temporary disruption of our habitual system of
responses rather than their perpetual presence in some dark
corner of the mind. However, the theory is briefly this. During
the process of our adjustment to our environment we are
exposed to all sorts of stimuli. Our habitual responses to these
stimuli gradually fall into a relatively fixed system, constantly
20 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
growing in complexity by absorbing some and rejecting other
impulses which do not fit in with our permanent system of
responses. The rejected impulses recede into what is called the
unconscious region" of the mind, and there wait for a suitable
1/
II
connexion has misled Wildon Carr into the view that the Theory
of Relativity inevitably leads to Monadistic Idealism. It is true
that according to the theory the shapes, sizes, and durations of
phenomena are not absolute. But as Professor Nunn points out,
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 31
the space-time frame does not depend on the observer's mind; it
depends on the point of the material universe to which his body is
attached. In fact, the "observer" can be easily replaced by a recording
apparatus,17 Personally, I believe that the ultimate character of
Reality is spiritual: but in order to avoid a widespread misunder-
standing it is necessary to point out that Einstein's theory, which, as
a scientific theory, deals only with the structure of things, throws
no light on the ultimate nature of things which possess that
structure. The philosophical value of the theory is twofold. First, it
destroys, not the objectivity of Nature, but the view of substance as
simple location in space- a view which led to materialism in
Classical Physics. "Substance" for modern Relativity-Physics is
not a persistent thing with variable states, but a system of
interrelated events. In Whitehead's presentation of the theory the
notion of "matter" is entirely replaced by the notion of "organism".
Secondly, the theory makes space dependent on matter. The
universe, according to Einstein, is not a kind of island in an
infinite space; it is finite but boundless; beyond it there is no
empty space. In the absence of matter the universe would shrink
to a point. Looking, however, at the theory from the standpoint
that I have taken in these lectures, Einstein's Relativity presents
one great difficulty, i.e. the unreality of time. A theory which
takes time to be a kind of fourth dimension of space must, it
seems, regard the future as something already given, as
indubitably fixed as the past. 18 Time as a free creative movement
has no meaning for the theory. It does not pass. Events do not
happen; we simply meet them. It must not, however, be
forgotten that the theory neglects certain characteristics of time
as experienced by us; and it is not possible to say that the nature
of time is exhausted by the characteristics which the theory does
note in the interests of a systematic account of those aspects of
Nature which can be mathematically treated. Nor is it possible
for us laymen to understand what the real nature of Einstein's
time is. It is obvious that Einstein's time is not Bergson's pure
duration. Nor can we regard it as serial time. Serial time is the
essence of causality as defined by Kant. The cause and its effect
are mutually so related that the former is chronologically prior
to the latter, so that if the former is not, the latter cannot be. If
mathematical time is serial time, then on the basis of the theory it
is possible, by a careful choice of the velocities of the observer
32 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
and the system in which a given set of events is happening, to
make the effect precede its cause. 19 It appears to me that time
regarded as a fourth dimension of space really ceases to be time.
A modem Russian writer, Ouspensky, in his book called Tertium
Organum, conceives the fourth dimension to be the movement of
a three-dimensional figure in a direction not contained in itself. 20
Just as the movement of the point, the line and the surface in a direction
not contained in them gives us the ordinary three dimensions of
space, in the same way the movement of the three-dimensional figure
in a direction not contained in itself must give us the fourth
dimension of space. And since time is the distance separating events
in order of succession and binding them in different wholes, it is
obviously a distance lying in a direction not contained in the
three-dimensional space. As a new dimension this distance,
separating events in the order of succession, is incommensurable
with the dimensions of three-dimensional space, as a year is
incommensurable with st. Petersburg. It is perpendicular to all
directions of three-dimensional space, and is not parallel to any
of them. Elsewhere in the same book Ouspensky describes our
time-sense as a misty space-sense and argues, on the basis of our
psychic constitution, that to one-, two-, or three-dimensional
beings the higher dimension must always appear as succession
in time. This obviously means that what appears to us three-
dimensional beings as time is in reality an imperfectly sensed
space-dimension which in its own nature does not differ from
the perfectly sensed dimensions of Euclidean space. In other
words, time is not a genuine creative movement; and that what
we call future events are not fresh happenings, but things
already given and located in an unknown space. Yet in his
search for a fresh direction, other than the three Euclidean
dimensions, Ouspensky needs a real serial time, i.e. a distance
separating events in the order of succession. Thus time which
was needed and consequently viewed as succession for the
purposes of one stage of the argument is quietly divested, at a
later stage, of its serial character and reduced to what does not
differ in anything from the other lines and dimensions of space.
It is because of the serial character of time that Ouspensky was
able to regard it as a genuinely new direction in space. If this
characteristic is in reality an illusion, how can it fulfil
Ouspensky's requirements of an original dimension?
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 33
Passing now to other levels of experience- life and consciousness.
Consciousness may be imagined as a deflection from life. Its
function is to provide a luminous point in order to enlighten the
forward rush of life. 21 It is a case of tension, a state of self
concentration, by means of which life manages to shut out all
memories and associations which have no bearing on a present
action. It has no well-defined fringes; it shrinks and expands as
the occasion demands. To describe it as an epiphenomenon of
the processes of matter is to deny it as an independent activity,
and to deny it as an independent activity is to deny the validity
of all knowledge which is only a systematized expression of
consciousness. Thus consciousness is a variety of the purely
spiritual principle of life which is not a substance, but an
organizing principle, a specific mode of behaviour essentially
different to the behaviour of an externally worked machine.
Since, however, we cannot conceive of a purely spiritual energy,
except in association with a definite combination of sensible
elements through which it reveals itself, we are apt to take this
combination as the ultimate ground of spiritual energy. The
discoveries of Newton in the sphere of matter and those of Darwin
in the sphere of Natural History reveal a mechanism. All problems,
it was believed, were really the problems of physics. Energy and
atoms, with the properties self-existing in them, could explain
everything including life, thought, will, and feeling. The concept
of mechanism- a purely physical concept- claimed to be the all-
embracing explanation of Nature. And the battle for and against
mechanism is still being fiercely fought in the domain of Biology.
The question, then, is whether the passage to Reality through the
revelations of sense-perception necessarily leads to a view of Reality
essentially opposed to the view that religion takes of its ultimate
character. Is Natural Science finally committed to materialism?
There is no doubt that the theories of science constitute
trustworthy knowledge, because they are verifiable and enable us
to predict and control the events of Nature. But we must not forget
that what is called science is not a single systematic view of
Reality. It is a mass of sectional views of Reality- fragments of a
total experience which do not seem to fit together. Natural
Science deals with matter, with life, and with mind; but the moment
you ask the question how matter, life, and mind are mutually
related, you begin to see the sectional character of the various
34 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
sciences that deal with them and the inability of these sciences,
taken singly, to furnish a complete answer to your question. In
fact, the various natural sciences are like so many vultures
falling on the dead body of Nature, and each running away with
a piece of its flesh. Nature as the subject of science is a highly
artificial affair, and this artificiality is the result of that selective
process to which science must subject her in the interests of
precision. The moment you put the subject of science in the total
of human experience it begins to disclose a different character.
Thus religion, which demands the whole of Reality and for this
reason must occupy a central place in any synthesis of all the
data of human experience, has no reason to be afraid of any
sectional views of Reality. Natural Science is by nature sectional;
it cannot, if it is true to its own nature and function, set up its
theory as a complete view of Reality. The concepts we use in the
organization of knowledge are, therefore, sectional in character,
and their application is relative to the level of experience to
which they are applied. The concept of "cause", for instance, the
essential feature of which is priority to the effect, is relative to
the subject-matter of physical science which studies one special
kind of activity to the exclusion of other forms of activity
observed by others. When we rise to the level of life and mind
the concept of cause fails us, and we stand in need of concepts of
a different order of thought. The action of living organisms,
initiated and planned in view of an end, is totally different to
causal action. The subject-matter of our inquiry, therefore,
demands the concepts of "end" and "purpose", which act from
within unlike the concept of cause which is external to the effect
and acts from without. No doubt, there are aspects of the activity
of a living organism which it shares with other objects of Nature.
In the observation of these aspects the concepts of physics and
chemistry would be needed; but the behaviour of the organism
is essentially a matter of inheritance and incapable of sufficient
explanation in terms of molecular physics. However, the concept
of mechanism has been applied to life and we have to see how
far the attempt has succeeded. Unfortunately, I am not a
biologist and must turn to biologists themselves for support.
After telling us that the main difference between a living
organism and a machine is that the former is self-maintaining
and self-reproducing, J. S. Haldane says:22
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 35
It is thus evident that although we find within the living body many
phenomena which, so long as we do not look closely, can be
interpreted satisfactorily as physical and chemical mechanism, there
are side by side other phenomena [i.e. self-maintenance and
reproduction] for which the possibility of such interpretation seems
to be absent. The mechanists assume that the bodily mechanisms are
so constructed as to maintain, repair, and reproduce themselves. In
the long process of natural selection, mechanisms of this sort have,
they suggest, been evolved gradually.
Let us examine this hypothesis. When we state an event in
mechanical terms we state it as a necessary result of certain simple
properties of separate parts which interact in the event.... The
essence of the explanation or re-statement of the event is that after
due investigation we have assumed that the parts interacting in the
event have certain simple and definite properties, so that they
always react in the same way under the same conditions. For a
mechanical explanation the reacting parts must first be given.
Unless an arrangement of parts with definite properties is given, it is
meaningless to speak of mechanical explanation.
To postulate the existence of a self-producing or self-maintaining
mechanism is, thus, to postulate something to which no meaning
can be attached. Meaningless terms are sometimes used by
physiologists; but there is none so absolutely meaningless as the
expression "mechanism of reproduction". Any mechanism there
may be in the parent organism is absent in the process of
reproduction, and must re-constitute itself at each generation, since
the parent organism is reproduced from a mere tiny speck of its own
body. There can be no mechanism of reproduction. The idea of a
mechanism which is constantly maintaining or reproducing its own
structure is self-contradictory. A mechanism which reproduced
itself would be a mechanism without parts, and, therefore, not a
mechanism.
Life is, then, a unique phenomenon and the concept of
mechanism is inadequate for its analysis. Its "factual wholeness", to
use an expression of Driesch- another notable biologist- is a
kind of unity which, looked at from another point of view, is
also a plurality. In all the purposive processes of growth and
adaptation to its environment, whether this adaptation is
secured by the formation of fresh or the modification of old
habits, it possesses a career which is unthinkable in the case of a
machine. And the possession of a career means that the sources
of its activity cannot be explained except in reference to a remote
past, the origin of which, therefore, must be sought in a spiritual
36 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
reality revealable in, but non-discoverable by, any analysis of
spatial experience. It would, therefore, seem that life is
foundational and anterior to the routine of physical and
chemical processes which must be regarded as a kind of fixed
behaviour formed during a long course of evolution. Further, the
application of the mechanistic concepts to life, necessitating the
view that the intellect itself is a product of evolution, brings
science into conflict with its own objective principle of
investigation. On this point I will quote a passage from Wildon
Carr, who has given a very pointed expression to this conflict: 23
If intellect is a product of evolution the whole mechanistic concept
of the nature and origin of life is absurd, and the principle which
science has adopted must clearly be revised. We have only to state it
to see the self-contradiction. How can the intellect, a mode of
apprehending reality, be itself an evolution of something which only
exists as an abstraction of that mode of apprehending, which is the
intellect? If intellect is an evolution of life, then the concept of the life
which can evolve intellect as a particular mode of apprehending
reality must be the concept of a more concrete activity than that of
any abstract mechanical movement which the intellect can present
to itself by analyzing its apprehended content. And yet further, if
the intellect be a product of the evolution of life, it is not absolute
but relative to the activity of the life which has evolved it; how then,
in such case, can science exclude the subjective aspect of the
knowing and build on the objective presentation as an absolute?
Clearly the biological sciences necessitate a reconsideration of the
scientific principle.
I will now try to reach the primacy of life and thought by
another route, and carry you a step farther in our examination of
experience. This will throw some further light on the primacy of
life and will also give us an insight into the nature of life as a
psychic activity. We have seen, that Professor Whitehead
describes the universe, not as something static, but as a structure
of events possessing the character of a continuous creative flow.
This quality of Nature's passage in time is perhaps the most
significant aspect of experience which the Qur' an especially
emphasizes and which, as I hope to be able to show in the
sequel, offers the best clue to the ultimate nature of Reality. To
some of the verses (3: 190-91; 2: 164; 24: 44)24 bearing on the point
I have already drawn your attention. In view of the great
importance of the subject I will add here a few more:
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 37
Verily, in the alternations of night and of day and in all that God
hath created in the Heavens and in the earth are signs to those who
fear him (10: 6).
And it is He Who hath ordained the night and the day to succeed
one another for those who desire to think on God or desire to be
thankful (25:62).
Seest thou not that God causeth the night to come in upon the day,
and the day to come in upon the night; and that He hath subjected
the sun and the moon to laws by which each speedeth along to an
appointed goal (31: 29).
It is of Him that the night returneth on the day, and that the day
returneth on the night (39: 5).
And of Him is the change of the night and of the day (23: 80).
There is another set of verses which, indicating the relativity
of our reckoning of time, suggests the possibility of unknown
levels of consciousness;25 but I will content myself with a
discussion of the familiar, yet deeply significant, aspect of
experience alluded to in the verses quoted above. Among the
representatives of contemporary thought, Bergson is the only
thinker who has made a keen study of the phenomenon of
duration in time. I will first briefly explain to you his view of
duration and then point out the inadequacy of his analysis in
order fully to bring out the implications of a completer view of
the temporal aspect of existence. The ontological problem before
us is how to define the ultimate nature of existence. That the
universe persists in time is not open to doubt. Yet, since it is
external to us, it is possible to be sceptical about its existence. In
order completely to grasp the meaning of this persistence in time
we must be in a position to study some privileged case of
existence which is absolutely unquestionable and gives us the
further assurance of a direct vision of duration. Now my
perception of things that confront me is superficial and external;
but my perception of my own self is internal, intimate, and
profound. It follows, therefore, that conscious experience is that
privileged case of existence in which we are in absolute contact
with Reality, and an analysis of this privileged case is likely to
throw a flood of light on the ultimate meaning of existence.
What do I find when I fix my gaze on my own conscious
experience? In the words of Bergson: 26
I pass from state to state. I am warm or cold. I am merry or sad, I
work or I do nothing, I look at what is around me or I think of
something else. Sensations, feelings, volitions, ideas- such are the
38 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
changes into which my existence is divided and which colour it in
turns. I change then, without ceasing.
Thus, there is nothing static in my inner life; all is a constant
mobility, an unceasing flux of states, a perpetual flow in which
there is no halt or resting place. Constant change, however, is
unthinkable without time. On the analogy of our inner
experience, then, conscious existence means life in time. A
keener insight into the nature of conscious experience, however,
reveals that the self in its inner life moves from the centre
outwards. It has, so to speak, two sides which may be described
as appreciative and efficient. On its efficient side it enters into
relation with what we call the world of space. The efficient self is
the subject of associationist psychology- the practical self of
daily life in its dealing with the external order of things which
determine our passing states of consciousness and stamp on
these states their own spatial feature of mutual isolation. The self
here lives outside itself as it were, and, while retaining its unity
as a totality, discloses itself as nothing more than a series of
specific and consequently numberable states. The time in which
the efficient self lives is, therefore, the time of which we
predicate long and short. It is hardly distinguishable from space.
We can conceive it only as a straight line composed of spatial
points which are external to one another like so many stages in a
journey. But time thus regarded is not true time, according to
Bergson. Existence in spacialized time is spurious existence. A
deeper analysis of conscious experience reveals to us what I have
called the appreciative side of the self. With our absorption in
the external order of things, necessitated by our present
situation, it is extremely difficult to catch a glimpse of the
appreciative self. In our constant pursuit after external things we
weave a kind of veil round the appreciative self which thus
becomes completely alien to us. It is only in the moments of
profound meditation, when the efficient self is in abeyance, that
we sink into our deeper self and reach the inner centre of
experience. In the life-process of this deeper ego the states of
consciousness melt into each other. The unity of the appreciative
ego is like the unity of the germ in which the experiences of its
individual ancestors exist, not as a plurality, but as a unity in
which every experience permeates the whole. There is no
numerical distinctness of states in the totality of the ego, the
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 39
multiplicity of whose elements is, unlike that of the efficient self,
wholly qualitative. There is change and movement, but change
and movement are indivisible; their elements interpenetrate and
are wholly non-serial in character. It appears that the time of the
appreciative-self is a single "now" which the efficient self, in its
traffic with the world of space, pulverizes into a series of "nows"
like pearl beads in a thread. Here is, then, pure duration
unadulterated by space. The Qur'an with its characteristic
simplicity alludes to the serial and non-serial aspects of duration
in the following verses:
And put thou thy trust in Him that liveth and dieth not, and
celebrate His praise Who in six days created the Heavens and the
earth, and what is between them, then mounted His Throne; the
God of mercy (25: 58-59).
All things We have created with a fixed destiny: Our command was
but one, swift as the twinkling of an eye (54: 49-50).
If we look at the movement embodied in creation from the
outside, that is to say, if we apprehend it intellectually, it is a
process lasting through thousands of years; for one Divine day,
in the terminology of the Qur' an, as of the Old Testament, is
equal to one thousand years. 27 From another point of view, the
process of creation, lasting through thousands of years, is a
single indivisible act, "swift as the twinkling of an eye". It is,
however, impossible to express this inner experience of pure
duration in words, for language is shaped on the serial time of
our daily efficient self. Perhaps an illustration will further
elucidate the point. According to physical science, the cause of
your sensation of red is the rapidity of wave motion the
frequency of which is 400 billions per second. If you could
observe this tremendous frequency from the outside, and count
it at the rate of 2,000 per second, which is supposed to be the
limit of the perceptibility of light, it will take you more than six
thousand years to finish the enumeration. 28 Yet in the single
momentary mental act of perception you hold together a
frequency of wave motion which is practically incalculable. That
is how the mental act transforms succession into duration. The
appreciative self, then, is more or less corrective of the efficient
self, inasmuch as it synthesizes all the "heres" and" nows" - the small
changes of space and time, indispensable to the efficient self- into the
coherent wholeness of personality. Pure time, then, as revealed
40 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
by a deeper analysis of our conscious experience, is not a string
of separate, reversible instants; it is an organic whole in which
the past is not left behind, but is moving along with, and
operating in, the present. And the future is given to it not as
lying before, yet to be traversed; it is given only in the sense that
it is present in its nature as an open possibility.29 It is time regarded
as an organic whole that the Qur'an describes as Taqdir or the
destiny- a word which has been so much misunderstood both in and
outside the world of Islam. Destiny is time regarded as prior to the
disclosure of its possibilities. It is time freed from the net of causal
sequence- the diagrammatic character which the logical
understanding imposes on it. In one word, it is time as felt and
not as thought and calculated. If you ask me why the Emperor
Humayfm and Shah Tahmasp of Persia were contemporaries, I
can give you no causal explanation. The only answer that can
possibly be given is that the nature of Reality is such that among
its infinite possibilities of becoming, the two possibilities known as
the lives of Hurnayiin and Shah Tahrnasp should realize themselves
together. Time regarded as destiny forms the very essence of things.
As the Qur' an says: God created all things and assigned to each its
11
succeed one another for those who desire to think on God or desire to be
thankful." 36 A critical interpretation of the sequence of time as
revealed in our selves has led us to a notion of the Ultimate Reality as
pure duration in which thought, life, and purpose interpenetrate
to form an organic unity. We cannot conceive this unity except as
the unity of a self- an all-embracing concrete self- the ultimate source
of all individual life and thought. I venture to think that the error
of Bergson consists in regarding pure time as prior to self, to
which alone pure duration is predicable. Neither pure space nor
pure time can hold together the multiplicity of objects and
events. It is the appreciative act of an enduring self only which
can seize the multiplicity of duration- broken up into an infinity
of instants- and transform it to the organic wholeness of a
The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience 45
synthesis. To exist in pure duration is to be a self, and to be a self
is to be able to say "I am". Only that truly exists which can say "I
am". It is the degree of the intuition of "l-amness" that
determines the place of a thing in the scale of being. We too say
"I am". But our "l-amness" is dependent and arises out of the
distinction between the self and the not-self. The Ultimate Self,
in the words of the Qur' an, "can afford to dispense with all the
worlds."37 To Him the not-self does not present itself as a
confronting other", or else it would have to be, like our finite
II
III
And no one thing is here, but with Us are its store-houses; and We
send it not down but in fixed quantities. (15: 21).
,;1 L j;
Reality is, therefore, essentially spirit. But, of course, there are
degrees of spirit. In the history of Muslim thought the idea of degrees
of Reality appears in the writings of Shihabuddln Suhrawardl
Maqtul. In modem times we find it worked out on a much larger
scale in Hegel and, more recently, in the late Lord Haldane's Reign
of Relativity, which he published shortly before his death.25 I
have conceived the Ultimate Reality as an Ego; and I must add
now that from the Ultimate Ego only egos proceed. The creative
energy of the Ultimate Ego, in whom deed and thought are
identical, functions as ego-unities. The world, in all its details,
from the mechanical movement of what we call the atom of matter
to the free movement of thought in the human ego, is the self-
revelation of the "Great I am".26 Every atom of Divine energy,
however low in the scale of existence, is an ego. But there are degrees
in the expression of egohood. Throughout the entire gamut of being
runs the gradually rising note of egohood until it reaches its perfection
in man. That is why the Qur' an declares the Ultimate Ego to be
"nearer to man than his own neck-vein."27 Like pearls do we live
58 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
and move and have our being in the perpetual flow of Divine
life.
Thus a criticism, inspired by the best traditions of Muslim
thought, tends to turn the Ash' arite scheme of atomism into a
spiritual pluralism, the details of which will have to be worked
out by the future theologians of Islam. It may, however, be asked
whether atomicity has a real seat in the creative energy of God,
or presents itself to us as such only because of our finite mode of
apprehension. From a purely scientific point of view I cannot say
what the final answer to this question will be. From the
psychological point of view one thing appears to me to be
certain. Only that is, strictly speaking, real which is directly
conscious of its own reality. The degree of reality varies with the
degree of the feeling of egohood. The nature of the ego is such
that, in spite of its capacity to respond to other egos, it is self-
centred and possesses a private circuit of individuality excluding
all egos other than itself.28 In this alone consists its reality as an
ego. Man, therefore, in whom egohood has reached its relative
perfection, occupies a genuine place in the heart of Divine
creative energy, and thus possesses a much higher degree of
reality than things around him. Of all the creations of God he
alone is capable of consciously participating in the creative life of
his Maker. 29 Endowed with the power to imagine a better world,
and to mould what is into what ought to be, the ego in him
aspires, in the interests of an increasingly unique and
comprehensive individuality, to exploit all the various
environments on which he may be called upon to operate during
the course of an endless career. But I would ask you to wait for a
fuller treatment of this point till my lecture on the Immortality
and Freedom of the Ego. In the meantime, I want to say a few
words about the doctrine of atomic time which I think is the
weakest part of the Ash' arite theory of creation. It is necessary to
do so for a reasonable view of the Divine attribute of Eternity.
The problem of time has always drawn the attention of Muslim
thinkers and mystics. This seems to be due partly to the fact that,
according to the Qur' an, the alternation of day and night is one of the
greatest signs of God, and partly to the Prophet's identification of
God with Dahr (time) in a well-known tradition referred to before. 30
Indeed, some of the greatest Muslim Sufis believed in the mystic properties
of the word Dahr. According to Muhyiddin Ibn al-' Arabi, Dahr is
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer 59
one of the beautiful names of God, and Razi tells us in his
commentary on the Qur' an that some of the Muslim saints had
taught him to repeat the word Dahr, Daihitr, or Daihar. The
Ash' arite theory of time is perhaps the first attempt in the
history of Muslim thought to understand it philosophically.
Time, according to the Ash' arite, is a succession of individual
"nows". From this view it obviously follows that between every
two individual "nows" or moments of time, there is an
unoccupied moment of time, that is to say, a void of time. The
absurdity of this conclusion is due to the fact that they looked at
the subject of their inquiry from a wholly objective point of view.
They took no lesson from the history of Greek thought, which
had adopted the same point of view and had reached no results.
In our own time Newton described time as "something which in
itself and from its own nature flows equally."31 The metaphor of
stream implied in this description suggests serious objections to
Newton's equally objective view of time. We cannot understand
how a thing is affected on its immersion in this stream, and how
it differs from things that do not participate in its flow. Nor can
we form any idea of the beginning, the end, and the boundaries
of time if we try to understand it on the analogy of a stream.
Moreover, if flow, movement, or "passage" is the last word as to
the nature of time, there must be another time to time the
movement of the first time, and another which times the second
time, and so on to infinity. Thus the notion of time as something
wholly objective is beset with difficulties. It must, however, be
admitted that the practical Arab mind could not regard time as
something unreal like the Greeks. Nor can it be denied that, even
though we possess no sense-organ to perceive time, it is a kind
of flow and has, as such, a genuine objective, that is to say,
atomic aspect. In fact, the verdict of modern science is exactly the
same as that of the Ash' aritei for recent discoveries in physics
regarding the nature of time assume the discontinuity of matter.
The following passage from Professor Rougier's Philosophy and
New Physics is noteworthy in this connexion: 32
Contrary to the ancient adage, natura nihil tacit per saltum (nature
hates all sudden changes. Ed.) it becomes apparent that the universe
varies by sudden jumps and not by imperceptible degrees. A
physical system is capable of only a finite number of distinct states ..
. . Since between two different and immediately consecutive states
60 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
the world remains motionless, time is suspended, so that time itself
is discontinuous: there is an atom of time.
The point, however, is that the constructive endeavour of the
Ash' arite, as of the moderns, was wholly lacking in
psychological analysis, and the result of this shortcoming was
that they altogether failed to perceive the subjective aspect of
time. It is due to this failure that in their theory the systems of
material atoms and time-atoms lie apart, with no organic relation
between them. It is clear that if we look at time from a purely
objective point of view serious difficulties arise; for we cannot
apply atomic time to God and conceive Him as a life in the
making, as Professor Alexander appears to have done in his
Lectures on Space, Time, and Deity.33 Later Muslim theologians
fully realized these difficulties. Mulla Jalaluddln Dawwani in a
passage of his Zaura, which reminds the modern student of
Professor Royce's view of time, tells us that if we take time to be
a kind of span which makes possible the appearance of events as
a moving procession and conceive this span to be a unity, then
we cannot but describe it as an original state of Divine activity,
encompassing all the succeeding states of that activity. But the
Mulla takes good care to add that a deeper insight into the
nature of succession reveals its relativity, so that it disappears in
the case of God to Whom all events are present in a single act of
perception. The Sufi poet 'IraqI34 has a similar way of looking at
the matter. He conceives infinite varieties of time, relative to the
varying grades of being, intervening between materiality and
pure spirituality. The time of gross bodies which arises from the
revolution of the heavens is divisible into past, present, and future;
and its nature is such that as long as one day does not pass away
the succeeding day does not come. The time of immaterial beings is
also serial in character, but its passage is such that a whole year in
the time of gross bodies is not more than a day in the time of an
immaterial being. Rising higher and higher in the scale of
immaterial beings we reach Divine time- time which is absolutely
free from the quality of passage, and consequently does not admit
of divisibility, sequence, and change. It is above eternity; it has
neither beginning nor end. The eye of God sees all the visibles,
and His ear hears all the audibles in one indivisible act of
perception. The priority of God is not due to the priority of time;
on the other hand, the priority of time is due to God's priority.35
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer 61
Thus Divine time is what the Qur' an describes as the "Mother of
Books"36 in which the whole of history, freed from the net of
causal sequence, is gathered up in a single super-eternal "now".
Of all the Muslim theologians, however, it is Fakhruddin Razi
who appears to have given his most serious attention to the
problem of time. In his Eastern Discussions, Razi subjects to a
searching examination all the contemporary theories of time. He
too is, in the main, objective in his method and finds himself
unable to reach any definite conclusions. "Until now," he says,
I have not been able to discover anything really true with regard to
the nature of time; and the main purpose of my book is to explain
what can possibly be said for or against each theory without any
spirit of partisanship, which I generally avoid, especially in
connexion with the problem of time. 37
The above discussion makes it perfectly clear that a purely
objective point of view is only partially helpful in our under-
standing of the nature of time. The right course is a careful
psychological analysis of our conscious experience which alone
reveals the true nature of time. I suppose you remember the
distinction that I drew in the two aspects of the self, appreciative
and efficient. The appreciative self lives in pure duration, i.e.
change without succession. The life of the self consists in its
movement from appreciation to efficiency, from intuition to
intellect, and atomic time is born out of this movement. Thus the
character of our conscious experience our point of departure in
all knowledge- gives us a clue to the concept which reconciles
the opposition of permanence and change, of time regarded as
an organic whole or eternity, and time regarded as atomic. If
then we accept the guidance of our conscious experience, and
conceive the life of the all-inclusive Ego on the analogy of the
finite ego, the time of the Ultimate Ego is revealed as change
without succession, i.e. an organic whole which appears atomic
because of the creative movement of the ego. This is what Mir
Muhammad Baqir Damad 38 means when they say that time is
born with the act of creation by which the Ultimate Ego realizes
and measures, so to speak, the infinite wealth of His own
undetermined creative possibilities. On the one hand, therefore,
the ego lives in eternity, by which term I mean non-successional
change; on the other, it lives in serial time, which I conceive as
62 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
organically related to eternity in the sense that it is a measure of
non-successional change. In this sense alone it is possible to
understand the Qur'anic verse: "To God belongs the alternation of
day and night."39 But on this difficult side of the problem I have
said enough in my preceding lecture. It is now time to pass on to
the Divine attributes of Knowledge and Omnipotence.
The word "knowledge", as applied to the finite ego, always
means discursive knowledge- a temporal process which moves round
a veritable "other", supposed to exist per se and confronting the
knowing ego. In this sense knowledge, even if we extend it to the
point of omniscience, must always remain relative to its confronting
"other", and cannot, therefore, be predicated of the Ultimate Ego
who, being all-inclusive, cannot be conceived as having a perspective
like the finite ego. The universe, as we have seen before, is not an
"other" existing per se in opposition to God. It is only when we
look at the act of creation as a specific event in the life-history of
God that the universe appears as an independent" other". From
the standpoint of the all-inclusive Ego there is no "other". In Him
thought and deed, the act of knowing and the act of creating, are
identical. It may be argued that the ego, whether finite or infinite,
is inconceivable without a confronting non-ego, and if there is
nothing outside the Ultimate Ego, the Ultimate Ego cannot be
conceived as an ego. The answer to this argument is that logical
negations are of no use in forming a positive concept which must be
based on the character of Reality as revealed in experience. Our
criticism of experience reveals the Ultimate Reality to be a
rationally directed life which, in view of our experience of life,
cannot be conceived except as an organic whole, a something closely
knit together and possessing a central point of reference. 4o This
being the character of life, the ultimate life can be conceived only as
an ego. Knowledge, in the sense of discursive knowledge, however
infinite, cannot, therefore, be predicated of an ego who knows, and,
at the same time, forms the ground of the object known.
Unfortunately, language does not help us here. We possess no word
to express the kind of knowledge which is also creative of its object.
The alternative concept of Divine knowledge is omniscience in the
sense of a single indivisible act of perception which makes God
immediately aware of the entire sweep of history, regarded as an
order of specific events, in an eternal "now". This is how
Jalaluddin Dawwani, 'Iraqi, and Professor Royce in our own
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer 63
times conceived God's knowledge. 41 There is an element of truth
in this conception. But it suggests a closed universe, a fixed
futurity, a predetermined, unalterable order of specific events
which, like a superior fate, has once for all determined the
directions of God's creative activity. In fact, Divine knowledge
regarded as a kind of passive omniscience is nothing more than
the inert void of pre-Einsteinian physics, which confers a
semblance of unity on things by holding them together, a sort of
mirror passively reflecting the details of an already finished
structure of things which the finite consciousness reflects in
fragments only. Divine knowledge must be conceived as a living
creative activity to which the objects that appear to exist in their
own right are organically related. By conceiving God's knowledge
as a kind of reflecting mirror, we no doubt save His fore-
knowledge of future events; but it is obvious that we do so at the
expense of His freedom. The future certainly pre-exists in the organic
whole of God's creative life, but it pre-exists as an open possibility,
not as a fixed order of events with definite outlines. An
illustration will perhaps help us in understanding what I mean.
Suppose, as sometimes happens in the history of human thought, a
fruitful idea with a great inner wealth of applications emerges into
the light of your consciousness. You are immediately aware of the
idea as a complex whole; but the intellectual working out of its
numerous bearings is a matter of time. Intuitively all the possibilities
of the idea are present in your mind. If a specific possibility, as
such, is not intellectually known to you at a certain moment of time, it
is not because your knowledge is defective, but because there is yet
no possibility to become known. The idea reveals the possibilities of
its application with advancing experience, and sometimes it takes
more than one generation of thinkers before these possibilities
are exhausted. Nor is it possible, on the view of Divine knowledge
as a kind of passive omniscience, to reach the idea of a creator. If
history is regarded merely as a gradually revealed photo of a
predetermined order of events, then there is no room in it for
novelty and initiation. Consequently, we can attach no meaning to
the word "creation", which has a meaning for us only in view of
our own capacity for original action. The truth is that the whole
theological controversy relating to predestination is due to pure
speculation with no eye on the spontaneity of life, which is a fact
of actual experience. No doubt, the emergence of egos endowed
64 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
with the power of spontaneous and hence unforeseeable action
is, in a sense, a limitation on the freedom of the all-inclusive Ego.
But this limitation is not externally imposed. It is born out of His
own creative freedom whereby He has chosen finite egos to be
participators of His life, power, and freedom.
But how, it may be asked, is it possible to reconcile limitation
with Omnipotence? The word "limitation" needs not frighten us.
The Qur' an has no liking for abstract universals. It always fixes
its gaze on the concrete which the theory of Relativity has only
recently taught modem philosophy to see. All activity, creational
or otherwise, is a kind of limitation without which it is
impossible to conceive God as a concrete operative Ego.
Omnipotence, abstractly conceived, is merely a blind,
capricious power without limits. The Qur' an has a clear and
definite conception of Nature as a cosmos of mutually related
forces. 42 It, therefore, views Divine omnipotence as intimately
related to Divine wisdom, and finds the infinite power of God
revealed, not in the arbitrary and the capricious, but in the
recurrent, the regular, and the orderly. At the same time, the
Qur'an conceives God as "holding all goodness in His hands."43 If,
then, the rationally directed Divine will is good, a very serious
problem arises. The course of evolution, as revealed by modem
science, involves almost universal suffering and wrongdoing. No
doubt, wrongdoing is confined to man only. But the fact of pain
is almost universal, though it is equally true that men can suffer
and have suffered the most excruciating pain for the sake of
what they have believed to be good. Thus the two facts of moral
and physical evil stand out prominent in the life of Nature. Nor
can the relativity of evil and the presence of forces that tend to
transmute it be a source of consolation to us; for, in spite of all
this relativity and transmutation, there is something terribly
positive about it. How is it, then, possible to reconcile the
goodness and omnipotence of God with the immense volume of
evil in His creation? This painful problem is really the crux of
Theism. No modem writer has put it more accurately than
Naumann in his Briefe iiberg Religion. "We possess", he says: 44
a knowledge of the world which teaches us a God of power and
strength, who sends out life and death as simultaneously as shadow
and light, and a revelation, a faith as to salvation which declares the
same God to be father. The following of the world-God produces the
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer 65
morality of the struggle for existence, and the service of the Father of
Jesus Christ produces the morality of compassion. And yet they are not
two gods, but one God. Somehow or other, their arms intertwine.
Only no mortal can say where and how this occurs.
To the optimist Browning all is well with the world;45 to the
pessimist Schopenhauer the world is one perpetual winter
wherein a blind will expresses itself in an infinite variety of
living things which bemoan their emergence for a moment and
then disappear forever. 46 The issue thus raised between
optimism and pessimism cannot be finally decided at the present
stage of our knowledge of the universe. Our intellectual
constitution is such that we can take only a piecemeal view of
things. We cannot understand the full import of the great cosmic
forces which work havoc, and at the same time sustain and
amplify life. The teaching of the Qur'an, which believes in the
possibility of improvement in the behaviour of man and his
control over natural forces, is neither optimism nor pessimism. It
is meliorism, which recognizes a growing universe and is
animated by the hope of man's eventual victory over evil.
But the clue to a better understanding of our difficulty is
given in the legend relating to what is called the Fall of Man. In
this legend the Qur' an partly retains the ancient symbols, but the
legend is materially transformed with a view to put an entirely
fresh meaning into it. The Qur' anic method of complete or
partial transformation of legends in order to besoul them with
new ideas, and thus to adapt them to the advancing spirit of
time, is an important point which has nearly always been
overlooked both by Muslim and non-Muslim students of Islam.
The object of the Qur' an in dealing with these legends is seldom
historical; it nearly always aims at giving them a universal moral
or philosophical import. And it achieves this object by omitting
the names of persons and localities which tend to limit the
meaning of a legend by giving it the colour of a specific
historical event, and also by deleting details which appear to
belong to a different order of feeling. This is not an uncommon
method of dealing with legends. It is common in non-religious
literature. An instance in point is the legend of Faust,47 to which
the touch of Goethe's genius has given a wholly new meaning.
Turning to the legend of the Fall we find it in a variety of
forms in the literatures of the ancient world. It is, indeed,
66 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
impossible to demarcate the stages of its growth, and to set out
clearly the various human motives which must have worked in
its slow transformation. But confining ourselves to the Semitic
form of the myth, it is highly probable that it arose out of the
primitive man's desire to explain to himself the infinite misery of
his plight in an uncongenial environment, which abounded in
disease and death and obstructed him on all sides in his
endeavour to maintain himself. Having no control over the
forces of Nature, a pessimistic view of life was perfectly natural
to him. Thus, in an old Babylonian inscription, we find the
serpent (phallic symbol), the tree, and the woman offering an
apple (symbol of virginity) to the man. The meaning of the myth
is clear- the fall of man from a supposed state of bliss was due to
the original sexual act of the human pair. The way in which the
Qur' an handles this legend becomes clear when we compare it
with the narration of the Book of Genesis. 48 The remarkable
points of difference between the Qur' anic and the Biblical
narrations suggest unmistakably the purpose of the Qur'anic
narration.
1. The Qur'an omits the serpent and the rib-story altogether.
The former omission is obviously meant to free the story from its
phallic setting and its original suggestion of a pessimistic view of
life. The latter omission is meant to suggest that the purpose of
the Qur' anic narration is not historical, as in the case of the Old
Testament, which gives us an account of the origin of the first
human pair by way of a prelude to the history of Israel. Indeed,
in the verses which deal with the origin of man as a living being,
the Qur' an uses the words Bashar or Insan, not Adam, which it
reserves for man in his capacity of God's vicegerent on earth. 49
The purpose of the Qur' an is further secured by the omission of
proper names mentioned in the Biblical narration- Adam and
Eve. 5o The word Adam is retained and used more as a concept
than as the name of a concrete human individual. This use of the
word is not without authority in the Qur' an itself. The following
verse is clear on the point:
We created you; then fashioned you; then said We to the angels, 'prostrate
yourself unto Adam' (7: 11).
But Satan whispered him (Adam); said he, 0 Adam! shall I show thee the
tree of Eternity and the Kingdom that faileth not? And they both ate
thereof, and their nakedness appeared to them, and they began to sew of the
leaves of the garden to cover them, and Adam disobeyed his Lord, and went
astray. Afterwards his Lord chose him for Himself, and was turned towards
him, and guided him. (20: 120-22).
Verily We proposed to the heavens and to the earth and to the mountains to
receive the "trust" but they refused the burden and they feared to receive it.
Man undertook to bear it, but hath proved unjust, senseless! (33: 72).
J" JJ 7-
The East and West is God's: therefore whichever way ye tum, there is the
face of God. (2: 115).
There is no piety in turning your faces towards the East or the West, but he
is pious who believeth in God, and the Last Day, and the angels, and the
scriptures, and the prophets; who for the love of God disburseth his wealth
to his kindred, and to the orphans, and the needy, and the wayfarer, and
those who ask, and for ransoming; who observeth prayer, and payeth the
legal alms, and who is of those who are faithful to their engagements when
they have engaged in them; and patient under ills and hardships, in time of
trouble: those are they who are just, and those are they who fear the Lord
(2: 177).
IV
And they ask thee of the soul. Say: the soul proceeded from my Lord's Arm
[Command}: but of knowledge, only a little to you is given' (17: 85).
Now offine clay have We created man: Then We placed him, a moist germ,
in a safe abode; then made We the moist germ a clot of blood: Then made the
clotted blood into a piece of flesh; then made the piece of flesh into bones:
and We clothed the bones with flesh: Then brought forth man of yet
another make. Blessed, therefore, be God- the most excellent of makers.
(23: 12-14).
And say: The truth is from your Lord: Let him, then, who will,
believe; and let him who will, be an unbeliever. (18: 29).
If ye do well to your own behoof will ye do well; and if ye do evil
against yourselves will ye do it. (17: 7).
Indeed Islam recognizes a very important fact of human
psychology, i.e. the rise and fall of the power to act freely, and is
anxious to retain the power to act freely as a constant and
undiminished factor in the life of the ego. The timing of the daily
prayer which, according to the Qur' an, restores" self-possession"
to the ego by bringing it into closer touch with the ultimate
source of life and freedom, is intended to save the ego from the
mechanizing effects of sleep and business. Prayer in Islam is the
ego's escape from mechanism to freedom.
It cannot, however, be denied that the idea of destiny runs
throughout the Qur' an. This point is worth considering, more
especially because Spengler in his Decline of the West seems to
think that Islam amounts to a complete negation of the ego. 33 I
have already explained to you my view of Taqdlr (destiny) as we
find it in the Qur' an. 34 As Spengler himself points out, there are
two ways of making the world our own. The one is intellectual;
the other, for want of a better expression, we may call vital. The
intellectual way consists in understanding the world as a rigid
system of cause and effect. The vital is the absolute acceptance of
the inevitable necessity of life, regarded as a whole which in
evolving its inner richness creates serial time. This vital way of
appropriating the universe is what the Qur' an describes as Iman.
Iman is not merely a passive belief in one or more propositions of
a certain kind; it is living assurance begotten of a rare
experience. Strong personalities alone are capable of rising to
this experience and the higher "Fatalism" implied in it.
Napoleon is reported to have said: "I am a thing, not a person."
This is one way in which unitive experience expresses itself. In
the history of religious experience in Islam which, according to
the Prophet, consists in the "creation of Divine attributes in
man," this experience has found expression in such phrases as "I
88 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
am the creative truth" (Hallaj), "I am Time" (Muhammad), "I am
the speaking Qur' an" (,All), "Glory to me" (Ba Yazid). In the
higher Sufism of Islam unitive experience is not the finite ego
effacing its own identity by some sort of absorption into the
Infinite Ego; it is rather the Infinite passing into the loving
embrace of the finite. 35 As Rumi says:
Passing now to the teachings of the Qur' an. The Qur' anic
view of the destiny of man is partly ethical, partly biological. I
say partly biological because the Qur' an makes in this connexion
certain statements of a biological nature which we cannot
understand without a deeper insight into the nature of life. It
mentions, for instance, the fact of Barzakh 50 - a state, perhaps of
some kind of suspense between Death and Resurrection.
Resurrection, too, appears to have been differently conceived.
The Qur'an does not base its possibility, like Christianity, on the
evidence of the actual resurrection of an historic person. It seems
to take and argue resurrection as a universal phenomenon of life,
in some sense, true even of birds and animals (6: 38).
Before, however, we take the details of the Qur' anic doctrine of
The Human Ego- His Freedom and Immortality 93
personal immortality we must note three things which are
perfectly clear from the Qur' an and regarding which there is, or
ought to be, no difference of opinion:
(i) That the ego has a beginning in time, and did not pre-exist
its emergence in the spatia-temporal order. This is clear from the
verse which I cited a few minutes ago. 51
(ii) That according to the Qur'anic view, there is no possibility
of return to this earth. This is clear from the following verses:
When death overtaketh one of them, he saith, "Lord! send me back again,
that I may do the good that I have left undone!" By no means, these are the
very words which he shall speak. But behind them is a barrier (Barzakh),
until the day when they shall be raised again. (23: 99-100).
And by the moon when at her full, that from state to state shall ye be surely
carried onward. (84: 18-19).
The germs of life- Is it ye who create them? Or are we their Creator? It is
We Who have decreed that death should be among you; yet We are not
thereby hindered from replacing you with others, your likes, or from
creating you again in forms which ye know not! (56: 58-61).
(iii) That finitude is not a misfortune:
Verily there is none in the heavens and in the earth but shall approach the
God of Mercy as a servant. He hath taken note of them and numbered them
with exact numbering: and each of them shall come to Him on the Day
of Resurrection as a single individual. (19: 93-95).52
And every man's fate have we fastened about his neck: and on the Day of
Resurrection will We bring forthwith to him a book which shall be proffered
to him wide open: "Read thy book: there needeth none but thyself to make
out an account against thee this day. (17: 13-14).
Whatever may be the final fate of man it does not mean the
loss of individuality. The Qur'an does not contemplate complete
liberation from as the highest state of human bliss. The
"unceasing reward" 53 of man consists in his gradual growth in
self-possession, in uniqueness, and intensity of his activity as an
94 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
ego. Even the scene of "Universal Destruction" immediately
preceding the Day of Judgement 54 cannot affect the perfect calm
of a full-grown ego:
And there shall be a blast on the trumpet, and all who are in the heavens
and all who are in the earth shall faint away, save those in whose case God
wills otherwise. (39: 68).55
Who can be the subject of this exception but those in whom
the ego has reached the very highest point of intensity? And the
climax of this development is reached when the ego is able to
retain full self-possession, even in the case of a direct contact
with the all-embracing Ego. As the Qur' an says of the Prophet's
vision of the Ultimate Ego: "His eye turned not aside, nor did it
wander." (53: 17).
This is the ideal of perfect manhood in Islam. Nowhere has it
found a better literary expression than in a Persian verse which
speaks of the Holy Prophet's experience of Divine illumination:
.,;.,\P..P ":;).J J J1 ; ifyo
t.5-" .JJ uf d .,;.,fj ;
And how to make the soul grow and save it from corruption?
By action:
Life offers a scope for ego-activity, and death is the first test
of the synthetic activity of the ego. There are no pleasure-giving
and pain-giving acts; there are only ego-sustaining and ego-
dissolving acts. It is the deed that prepares the ego for
dissolution, or disciplines him for a future career. The principle
of the ego-sustaining deed is respect for the ego in myself as well
as in others. Personal immortality, then, is not ours as of right; it
is to be achieved by personal effort. Man is only a candidate for
it. The most depressing error of Materialism is the supposition
that finite consciousness exhausts its object. Philosophy and
science are only one way of approaching that object. There are
other ways of approach open to us; and death, if present action
has sufficiently fortified the ego against the shock that physical
dissolution brings, is only a kind of passage to what the Qur' an
describes as Barzakh. The records of Sufistic experience indicate
that Barzakh is a state of consciousness characterized by a change
in the ego's attitude towards time and space. There is nothing
improbable in it. It was Helmholtz who first discovered that
nervous excitation takes time to reach consciousness. 58 If this is
so, our present physiological structure is at the bottom of our
present view of time, and if the ego survives the dissolution of this
96 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
structure, a change in our attitude towards time and space seems
perfectly natural. Nor is such a change wholly unknown to us.
The enormous condensation of impressions which occurs in our
dream-life, and the exaltation of memory, which sometimes
takes place at the moment of death, disclose the ego's capacity
for different standards of time. The state of Barzakh, therefore,
does not seem to be merely a passive state of expectation; it is a
state in which the ego catches a glimpse of fresh aspects of
Reality, and prepares himself for adjustment to these aspects. It
must be a state of great psychic unhingement, especially in the
case of full-grown egos who have naturally developed fixed
modes of operation on a specific spatio-temporal order, and may
mean dissolution to less fortunate ones. However, the ego must
continue to struggle until he is able to gather himself up, and
win his resurrection. The resurrection, therefore, is not an
external event. It is the consummation of a life-process within
the ego. Whether individual or universal it is nothing more than
a kind of stock-taking of the ego's past achievements and his
future possibilities. The Qur'an argues the phenomenon of re-
emergence of the ego on the analogy of his first emergence:
Man saith: "What! After I am dead, shall I in the end be brought forth
alive?" Doth not man bear in mind that We made him at first when he was
naught? (19: 66-67).
It is we who have decreed that death should be among you. Yet We are not
thereby hindered from replacing you with others your likes, or from
producing you in a form which ye know not! Ye have known the first
creation: will you not reflect? (56: 60-62).
v
THE SPIRIT OF MUSLIM CULTURE
o company of Jinn and men, if you can overpass the bounds of the Heaven
and the earth, then overpass them. But by power alone shall ye overpass
them. (55: 33).
Of old did we send Moses with Our signs, and said to him: "Bring forth
thy people from the darkness into the light, and remind them of the days of
God." Verily, in this are signs for every patient, grateful person. (14: 5)
And among those whom we had created are a people who guide others with
truth and in accordance therewith act justly. But as for those who treat
Our signs as lies, We gradually bring them down by means of which
they know not; and though I lengthen their days, verily, My
stratagem is effectual. (7: 181-83)
The Spirit of Muslim Culture III
Already, before your time, have precedents been made. Traverse the
earth then and see what hath been the end of those who falsify the
signs of God. (3: 137)
If a wound hath befallen you, a wound like it hath already befallen others;
We alternate the days of successes and reverses among peoples. (3: 140)
Every nation hath its fixed period. (7: 34)
The Arabs of the desert are most stout in unbelief and dissimulation; and
likelier it is that they should be unaware of the laws which God hath sent
down to His Apostle; and God is Knowing, Wise.
Of the Arabs of the desert there are some who reckon what they expend in
the cause of God as tribute, and wait for some change of fortune to befall
you: a change for evil shall befall them! God is the Hearer, the Knower. (9:
97-98)
VI
These lines clearly indicate the trend of modern Islam. For the
present every Muslim nation must sink into her own deeper self,
temporarily focus her vision on herself alone, until all are strong
and powerful to form a living family of republics. A true and
living unity, according to the nationalist thinkers, is not so easy
as to be achieved by a merely symbolical overlordship. It is truly
manifested in a multiplicity of free independent units whose
racial rivalries are adjusted and harmonized by the unifying
bond of a common spiritual aspiration. It seems to me that God
is slowly bringing home to us the truth that Islam is neither
Nationalism nor Imperialism but a League of Nations which
recognizes artificial boundaries and racial distinctions for facility
of reference only,26 and not for restricting the social horizon of its
members.
From the same poet the following passage from a poem
called "Religion and Science" will throw some further light on
the general religious outlook which is being gradually shaped in
the world of Islam today: 27
The Principle of Movement in the Structure of Islam 127
"Who were the first spiritual leaders of mankind? Without doubt
the prophets and holy men. In every period religion has led
philosophy; from it alone morality and art receive light. But then
religion grows weak, and loses her original ardour! Holy men
disappear, and spiritual leadership becomes, in name, the heritage
of the Doctors of Law! The leading star of the Doctors of Law is
tradition; they drag religion with force on this track; but philosophy
says: "My leading star is reason: you go right, I go left."
"Both religion and philosophy claim the soul of man and draw it on
either side!"
"When this struggle is going on" pregnant experience delivers up
positive science, and this young leader of thought says, "Tradition is
history and Reason is the method of history! Both interpret and
desire to reach the same indefinable something!"
"But what is this something?"
"Is it a spiritualized heart?"
"If so, then take my last word- Religion is positive science, the
purpose of which is to spiritualize the heart of man!"
The land where the call to prayer resounds in Turkish; where those
who pray understand the meaning of their religion; the land where
the Qur' an is learnt in Turkish; where every man, big or small,
knows full well the command of God; O! Son of Turkey! that land is
thy fatherland!
while those of Hijaz laid stress on its temporal aspect. The latter,
The Principle of Movement in the Structure of Islam 141
however, did not see the full significance of their own position,
and their instinctive partiality to the legal tradition of Hijaz
narrowed their vision to the "precedents" that had actually
happened in the days of the Prophet and his companions. No
doubt they recognized the value of the concrete, but at the same
time they eternalized it, rarely resorting to Qiyiis based on the
study of the concrete as such. Their criticism of Abu Hanifah and
his school, however, emancipated the concrete as it were, and
brought out the necessity of observing the actual movement and
variety of life in the interpretation of juristic principles. Thus the
school of Abu Hanlfah which fully assimilated the results of this
controversy is absolutely free in its essential principle and
possesses much greater power of creative adaptation than any
other school of Muhammadan Law. But, contrary to the spirit of
his own school, the modern Hanafl legist has eternalized the
interpretations of the founder or his immediate followers much
in the same way as the early critics of Abu Hamfah eternalized
the decisions given on concrete cases. Properly understood and
applied, the essential principle of this school, i.e. Qiyiis, as Shafi'i
rightly says, is only another name for Ijtihiid 55 which, within the
limits of the revealed texts, is absolutely free; and its importance
as a principle can be seen from the fact that, according to most of
the doctors, as Qadi Shaukani tells us, it was permitted even in
the lifetime of the Holy Prophet. 56 The closing of the door of
Ijtihiid is pure fiction suggested partly by the crystallization of
legal thought in Islam, and partly by that intellectual laziness
which, especially in the period of spiritual decay, turns great
thinkers into idols. If some of the later doctors have upheld this
fiction, modern Islam is not bound by this voluntary surrender
of intellectual independence. Zarkashi writing in the eighth
century of the Hijrah rightly observes: 57
If the upholders of this fiction mean that the previous writers had
more facilities, while the later writers had more difficulties, in their
way, it is, nonsense; for it does not require much understanding to
see that ijtihad for later doctors is easier than for the earlier doctors.
Indeed the commentaries on the Koran and sunnah have been
compiled and multiplied to such an extent that the mujtahid of today
has more material for interpretation than he needs.
VII
Is RELIGION POSSIBLE? 1
BROADLY speaking religious life may be divided into three
periods. These may be described as the periods of "Faith",
"Thought", and "Discovery." In the first period religious life
appears as a form of discipline which the individual or a whole
people must accept as an unconditional command without any
rational understanding of the ultimate meaning and purpose of
that command. This attitude may be of great consequence in the
social and political history of a people, but is not of much
consequence in so far as the individual's inner growth and
expansion are concerned. Perfect submission to discipline is
followed by a rational understanding of the discipline and the
ultimate source of its authority. In this period religious life seeks
its foundation in a kind of metaphysics- a logically consistent
view of the world with God as a part of that view. In the third
period metaphysics is displaced by psychology, and religious
life develops the ambition to come into direct contact with the
Ultimate Reality. It is here that religion becomes a matter of
personal assimilation of life and power; and the individual
achieves a free personality, not by releasing himself from the
fetters of the law, but by discovering the ultimate source of the
law within the depths of his own consciousness. As in the words
of a Muslim Sufi- "no understanding of the Holy Book is
possible until it is actually revealed to the believer just as it was
revealed to the Prophet." 2 It is, then, in the sense of this last
phase in the development of religious life that I use the word
religion in the question that I now propose to raise. Religion in
this sense is known by the unfortunate name of Mysticism,
which is supposed to be a life-denying, fact-avoiding attitude of
mind directly opposed to the radically empirical outlook of our times.
Yet higher religion, which is only a search for a larger life, is
essentially experience and recognized the necessity of experience
144 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
as its foundation long before science learnt to do so. It is a
genuine effort to clarify human consciousness, and is, as such, as
critical of its level of experience as Naturalism is of its own level.
As we all know, it was Kant who first raised the question: "Is
metaphysics possible?" 3 He answered this question in the
negative; and his argument applies with equal force to the
realities in which religion is especially interested. The manifold
of sense, according to him, must fulfil certain formal conditions
in order to constitute knowledge. The thing-in-itself is only a
limiting idea. Its function is merely regulative. If there is some
actuality corresponding to the idea, it falls outside the
boundaries of experience, and consequently its existence cannot
be rationally demonstrated. This verdict of Kant cannot be easily
accepted. It may fairly be argued that in view of the more recent
developments of science, such as the nature of matter as
"bottled-up light waves", the idea of the universe as an act of
thought, finiteness of space and time and Heisenberg's principle
of indeterminacy 4 in Nature, the case for a system of rational
theology is not so bad as Kant was led to think. But for our
present purposes it is unnecessary to consider this point in
detail. As to the thing-in-itself, which is inaccessible to pure
reason because of its falling beyond the boundaries of
experience, Kant's verdict can be accepted only if we start with
the assumption that all experience other than the normal level of
experience is impossible. The only question, therefore, is
whether the normal level is the only level of knowledge-yielding
experience. Kant's view of the thing-in-itself and the thing as it
appears to us very much determined the character of his
question regarding the possibility of metaphysics. But what if
the position, as understood by him, is reversed? The great
Muslim Sufi philosopher, MuhyiddIn Ibn al-' ArabI of Spain, has
made the acute observation that God is a percept, the world is a
concept. s Another Muslim Sufi thinker and poet, 'IraqI,
insists on the plurality of space-orders and time-orders and
speaks of a Divine Time and a Divine Space. 6 It may be that
what we call the external world is only an intellectual
construction, and that there are other levels of human
experience capable of being systematized by other orders of
Is Religion Possible? 145
space and time- levels in which concept and analysis do not play
the same role as they do in the case of our normal experience. It
may, however, be said that the level of experience to which
concepts are inapplicable cannot yield any knowledge of a
universal character, for concepts alone are capable of being
socialized. The standpoint of the man who relies on religious
experience for capturing Reality must always remain individual
and income-municable. This objection has some force if it is meant
to insinuate that the mystic is wholly ruled by his traditional ways,
attitudes, and expectations. Conservatism is as bad in religion as in
any other department of human activity. It destroys the ego's
creative freedom and closes up the paths of fresh spiritual
enterprise. This is the main reason why our medieval mystic
techniques can no longer produce original discoveries of ancient
Truth. The fact, however, that religious experience is
incommunicable does not mean that the religious man's pursuit is
futile. Indeed, the incommunicability of religious experience
gives us a clue to the ultimate nature of the ego. In our daily social
intercourse we live and move in seclusion, as it were. We do not care
to reach the inmost individuality of men. We treat them as mere
functions, and approach them from those aspects of their identity
which are capable of conceptual treatment. The climax of religious
life, however, is the discovery of the ego as an individual deeper
than his conceptually describable habitual self-hood. It is in contact
with the Most Real that the ego discovers its uniqueness, its
metaphysical status, and the possibility of improvement in that
status. Strictly speaking, the experience which leads to this
discovery is not a conceptually manageable intellectual fact; it is
a vital fact, an attitude consequent on an inner biological
transformation which cannot be captured in the net of logical
categories. It can embody itself only in a world-making or world-
shaking act; and in this form alone the content of this timeless
experience can diffuse itself in the time-movement, and make
itself effectively visible to the eye of history. It seems that the
method of dealing with Reality by means of concepts is not at all
a serious way of dealing with it. Science does not care whether
its electron is a real entity or not. It may be a mere symbol, a
mere convention. Religion, which is essentially a mode of actual
living, is the only serious way of handling Reality. As a form of
higher experience it is corrective of our concepts of philosophical
146 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
theology or at least makes us suspicious of the purely rational
process which forms these concepts. Science can afford to ignore
metaphysics altogether, and may even believe it to be "a justified
form of poetry",7 as Lange defined it, or "a legitimate play of
grown-ups", as Nietzsche described it. But the religious expert
who seeks to discover his personal status in the constitution of
things cannot, in view of the final aim of his struggle, be satisfied
with what science may regard as a vital lie, a mere "as-if"s to
regulate thought and conduct. In so far as the ultimate nature of
Reality is concerned, nothing is at stake in the venture of science;
in the religious venture the whole career of the ego as an
assimilative personal centre of life and experience is at stake.
Conduct, which involves a decision of the ultimate fate of the
agent cannot be based on illusions. A wrong concept misleads the
understanding; a wrong deed degrades the whole man, and may
eventually demolish the structure of the human ego. The mere
concept affects life only partially; the deed is dynamically related to
Reality and issues from a generally constant attitude of the whole
man towards reality. No doubt the deed, i.e. the control of
psychological and physiological processes with a view to tune up the
ego for an immediate contact with the Ultimate Reality is, and
cannot but be, individual in form and content; yet the deed, too, is
liable to be socialized when others begin to live through it with a
view to discover for themselves its effectiveness as a method of
approaching the Real. The evidence of religious experts in all ages
and countries is that there are potential types of consciousness lying
close to our normal consciousness. If these types of consciousness
open up possibilities of life-giving and knowledge-yielding
experience, the question of the possibility of religion as a form of
higher experience is a perfectly legitimate one and demands our
serious attention.
But, apart from the legitimacy of the question, there are
important reasons why it should be raised at the present
moment of the history of modern culture. In the first place, the
scientific interest of the question. It seems that every culture has
a form of Naturalism peculiar to its own world-feeling; and it
further appears that every form of Naturalism ends in some sort
of Atomism. We have Indian Atomism, Greek Atomism, Muslim
Atomism, and Modern Atomism. 9 Modern Atomism is,
however, unique. Its amazing mathematics, which sees the
Is Religion Possible? 147
universe as an elaborate differential equation; and its physics
which, following its own methods, has been led to smash some
of the old gods of its own temple, have already brought us to the
point of asking the question whether the causality-bound aspect
of Nature is the whole truth about it? Is not the Ultimate Reality
invading our consciousness from some other direction as well? Is
the purely intellectual method of overcoming Nature the only
method? "We have acknowledged", says Professor Eddington: 10
that the entities of physics can from their very nature form only a
partial aspect of the reality. How are we to deal with the other part?
It cannot be said that other part concerns us less than the physical
entities. Feelings, purpose, values, make up our consciousness as
much as sense-impressions. We follow up the sense-impressions
and find that they lead into an external world discussed by science;
we follow up the other elements of our being and find that they
lead- not into a world of space and time, but surely somewhere.
Yet Jung has violated his own principle more than once in his
writings. The result of this procedure is that, instead of giving us
a real insight into the essential nature of religion and its meaning
for human personality, our modern psychology has given us
quite a plethora of new theories which proceed on a complete
misunderstanding of the nature of religion as revealed in its
higher manifestations, and carry us in an entirely hopeless
direction. The implication of these theories, on the whole, is that
religion does not relate the human ego to any objective reality
beyond himself; it is merely a kind of well-meaning biological
device calculated to build barriers of an ethical nature round
human society in order to protect the social fabric against the
otherwise unrestrainable instincts of the ego. That is why,
according to this newer psychology, Christianity has already
fulfilled its biological mission, and it is impossible for the
modern man to understand its original significance. Jung
concludes: 16
Most certainly we should still understand it, had our customs even a
breath of ancient brutality, for we can hardly realize in this day the
whirlwinds of the unchained libido which roared through the ancient
Rome of the Caesars. The civilized man of the present day seems
very far removed from that. He has become merely neurotic. So for us
the necessities which brought forth Christianity have actually been lost,
152 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
since we no longer understand their meaning. We do not know against
what it had to protect us. For enlightened people, the so-called
religiousness has already approached very close to a neurosis. In the
past two thousand years Christianity has done its work and has
erected barriers of repression, which protect us from the sight of our
own sinfulness.
hardening of the hearts, so that they were like rocks: see 2: 74, 5: 13; 6:
43; 39: 22; and 57: 16.
This shows that Allama Iqbal, through his keenly perceptive study of
the Qur' an, had psychically assimilated both its meanings and its
diction so much so that many of his visions, very largely found in his
poetical works, may be said to be born of this rare assimilation; d. Dr.
Ghul<im Mustafa Khan's voluminous Iqbiil aur Qur'an (Urdu), Iqbal
Academy Pakistan, Lahore, 1994. Also see Hamid Saeed Akhtar,
"Qur'an aur Iqbal", Iqbiiliyiit, Journal of the Iqbal Academy Pakistan,
Lahore, Vol. 43, No.1, 2002, pp. 17-28; T. H. Tanuli, "Fikr i Iqbal aur
Fehm i Qur'an ki Jihat", Iqbiiliyiit, Vol. 48, No.2, 2007, pp. 75-94.
27 Qur'an, 41: 53; also 51: 20-21.
28 Reference here is to the Mathnawi; ii, 52:
)) J J .:;.,1 (jl-\,I ) /
)4 J ;1 ,if
The bodily sense is eating the food of darkness
The spiritual sense is feeding from a sun.
(trans. Nicholson)
29 Qur'an, 53: 11-12.
30 Ibid., 22: 46.
31 Cf. Bukhari, Sahih, 'Jana'iz', 79, 'Shahadah' 3, 'Jihad', 160, 178;
Muslim, Sahih, 'Fitan', 95-96. D. J. Halperin's article: 'The Ibn Sayyad
Traditions and the Legend of al-Dajjal', Journal of the American Oriental
Society, XCII/ii (1976), 213-25, gives an atomistic analytic account of the
Hadith narratives listed by him.
32 In Arabic: law taraktuhu bayyana, an invariable part of the text of a
number of Hadith accounts about Ibn Sayyad; d. D. B. Macdonald, The
Religious Attitude and Life in Islam, pp. 35 ff.; this book, which represents
Macdonald's reputed Haskell Lectures on Comparative Religion at
Chicago University in 1906, seems to have attracted Allama's attention
in the present discussion. Also see Ibn Khaldun, Muqaddimah, trans.
Rosenthall, Vol. III, Section vi, Discourse: 'The Science of Sufism'; D. B.
Macdonald, Religious Attitude and Life in Islam, pp. 165-74, and M. Syrier,
'Ibn Khaldun and Mysticism', Islamic Culture, XXI/ii (1947),264-302.
33 Cf. D. B. Macdonald, The Religious Attitude and Life in Islam, p. 36.
34 Cf. Lecture V, pp. 100 ff.
35 The term 'subliminal self' was coined by F. W. H. Myers in the 1890's
which soon became popular in 'religious psychology' to designate what
was believed to be the larger portion of the self lying beyond the level of
consciousness yet constantly influencing thought and behaviour as in
para-psychic phenomena. With William James the concept of subliminal
self came to stand for the area of human experience in which contact
162 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
with the Divine Life may occur (d. The Varieties of Religious Experience,
pp.511-15).
36 Macdonald, op. cit., p. 42.
37 Cf. Muhyiddin Ibn' Arabi's observation that 'God is a percept, the
world is a concept', referred to in Lecture VII, p. 144.
38 Ibid., p. 145, where it is observed: 'Indeed the incommunicability of
religious experience gives us a clue to the ultimate nature of the human
ego.'
39 W. E. Hocking, The Meaning of Cod in Human Experience, p. 66. It is
important to note here that according to Richard C. Gilman this concept
of the inextricable union of idea and feeling is 'the source of the strong
strain of mysticism in Hocking's philosophy, but it is a mysticism which
does not abandon the role of intellect in clarifying and correcting intuition;
d. article: 'Hocking, William Ernest', Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, IV, 47
(italics mine).
40 Reference here perhaps is to the hot and long-drawn controversy
between the Mu'tazilites (early Muslim rationalists) and the Ash'arties
(the orthodox scholastics) on the issue of Khalq al-Qur'an, i.e. the
createdness or the eternity of the Qur' an; for which see Lecture VI, note
9. The context of the passage, however, strongly suggests that Allama
Iqbal means to refer here to the common orthodox belief that the text of
the Qur'an is verbally revealed, i.e. the 'word' is as much revealed as
the 'meaning'. This has perhaps never been controverted and rarely if
ever discussed in the history of Muslim theology- one notable instance
of its discussion is that by Shah WaH Allah in Sata'at and Fuyud al-
Haramain. Nevertheless, it is significant to note that there is some
analogical empirical evidence in Allama's personal life in support of the
orthodox belief in verbal revelation. Once asked by Professor Lucas,
Principal of a local college, in a private discourse, whether, despite his
vast learning, he too subscribed to belief in verbal revelation, Allama
immediately replied that it was not a matter of belief with him but a
veritable personal experience for it was thus, he added, he composed
his poems under the spells of poetic inspiration- surely, Prophetic
revelations are far more exalted. Cf. 'Abdul Majid Salik, Dhikr-i Iqbal,
pp. 244-45 and Faq!r Sayyid Wahid-ud-Dln, Ruzgar-i Faqir, pp. 38-39.
After Allama's epoch-making Mathnawi: Asrar-i Khudi (Secrets of the
Self) was published in 1915 and it had given rise to some bitter
controversy because of his critique of Persianate Sufism and the great
Hafiz, he in a letter dated 14 April 1916 addressed to Maharaja Kishen
Parshad Shad confided strictly in a personal way: 'I did not compose
the mathnawi myself; I was made to (guided to), to do so'; d. M.
'Abdullah Quraishi, 'Nawadir-i Iqbal' (Chair Matbu'ah Khutut)" Sahifah,
Bazm i Iqbal, Lahore, 'Special Iqbal Issue' (October 1973), Letter No. 41,
Notes and References 163
p.168.
41 Cf. William James, op. cit., p. 15.
42 Ibid., p. 21.
43 The designation 'apostle' (rasul) is applied to bearers of divine
revelations which embody a new doctrinal system or dispensation; a
'prophet' (nabi), on the other hand, is said to be one whom God has
entrusted with enunciation and elucidation of ethical principles on the
basis of an already existing dispensation, or of principles common to all
dispensations. Hence, every apostle is a prophet as well, but every
prophet is not an apostle.
44 Cf. Lecture VII, pp. 143-44, where this point is reiterated.
45 E. W. Hocking, op. cit., pp. 106-07.
15 Cf. Bertrand Russell, Our Knowledge of the External World, pp. 169-88;
also Mysticism and Logic, pp. 84-91.
16 This is not Russell's own statement but that of H. Wildon Carr made
during the course of his exposition of Russell's views on the subject; see
Wildon Carr, The General Principle of Relativity, p. 36.
17 Views of H. Wildon Carr and especially of Sir T. Percy Nunn on
relativity in the present context are to be found in their symposium
papers on 'The Idealistic Interpretation of Einstein's Theory' published
in the Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, N. S. XXII (1921-22),123-27
and 127-30. Wildon Carr's doctrine of Monadistic Idealism, however, is
to be found much more fully expounded in his General Principle of
Relativity (1920) and A Theory of Monads: Outlines of the Philosophy of the
Principle of Relativity (1922); passages from both of these books have
been quoted in the present Lecture (d. notes 16 and 23 below).
T. Percy Nunn, best known as an educationist, wrote little philosophy;
but whatever little he wrote, it made him quite influential with the
leading contemporary British philosophers: Whitehead, Samuel
Alexander, Russell, Broad, and others. He is said to have first
formulated the characteristic doctrines of neo-Realism, an important
philosophical school of the century which had its zealot and able
champions both in England and in the United States. His famous sym-
posium paper: 'Are Secondary Qualities Independent of Perception?'
read in a meeting of the Aristotelian Society in 1909 was widely studied
and discussed and as J. Passmore puts it: 'it struck Bertrand Russell's
roving fancy' (A Hundred Years of Philosophy, p. 258). It is significant to
note that Nunn's correction put on Wildon Carr's idealistic
interpretation of relativity in the present passage is to be found almost
in the same philosophical diction in Russell's valuable article:
'Relativity; Philosophical Consequences', in Encyclopaedia Britannica
(1953), XIX, 99d, Russell says: 'It is a mistake to suppose that relativity
adopts any idealistic picture of the world .... The "observer" who is
often mentioned in expositions of relativity need not be a mind, but
may be a photographic plate or any kind of recording instrument:
18 On this rather debatable interpretation of Einstein's theory of
relativity see Dr. M. Razi-ud-din Siddiqi, 'Iqbal's Conception of Time
and Space' in Iqbal as A Thinker" pp. 29-31, and Philipp Frank,
'Philosophical Interpretations and Misinterpretations of the Theory of
Relativity, in H. Feigel and Mary Brodbeck (eds.), Readings in the
Philosophy of Science, pp. 222-26, reprinted from his valuable work,
Interpretations and Misinterpretations of Modem Physics (1938).
19 Cf. Hans Reichenbach, 'The Philosophical Significance of the Theory
of Relativity', in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert-Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist,
section iv.
166 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
,,)1
-: '/
fl5-!:J i j i )
48 Cf. Kitiib al-Fisal, II, 158; also I. Goldziher, The Ziihiris, pp. 113ff.
49 Qur' an, 50: 38.
50 Ibid., 2: 255.
51 Goethe, Alterswerke (Hamburg edition), I, 367, quoted by Spengler, op.
cit., on fly-leaf with translation on p. 140. For locating this passage in
Goethe's Alterswerke, I am greatly indebted to Professor Dr. Annemarie
Schimmel.
52 Reference here is to the Prophet's last words: al-saliitu, al-saliitu wa mii
malakat aimiinukum (meaning: be mindful of your prayers and be kind to
persons subject to your authority) reported through three different
chains of transmitters in Ahmad b. Hanbal's Musnad: VI, 290, 311 and
321.
Lecture III: The Conception of God
1 Cf. Creative Evolution, p. 13; also pp. 45-46.
2 Ibid., p. 14.
3 See Qur'an, for example, 2: 163,4: 171, 5: 73. 6: 19, 13: 16, 14: 48, 21: 108,
39: 4 and 40: 16, on the Unity of Allah and 4: 171, 6: 101, 10: 68, 17: 111,
19: 88-92 emphatically denying the Christian doctrine of His sonship.
4 Cf. 1. R. Farnell, The Attributes of God, p. 56.
5 The full translation here is 'a glistening star', as required by the nass of
the Qur'an, 'Kaukabun durriyun'.
6 On this fine distinction of God's infinity being intensive and not
extensive, see further Lecture IV, p. 94.
7 For the long-drawn controversy on the issue of the creation of the
universe, see, for instance, Ghazali, Tahiifatu al-Faliisifah, English
translation by S. A. Kamali: Incoherence of the Philosophers, pp. 13-53 and
Ibn Rushd, Tahiifatu al-Tahiifah, English translation by Simon van den
Bergh: The Incoherence of the Incoherence, pp. 1-69. A more accurate and
annotated translation with the critical text of the Tahiifatu al-Faliisifah
wsa made by Michael E. Marmura in his Incoherence of the Philosophers,
Bagham University Press, Rep. Suhail Academy, Lahore, 2007. Cf. also
G. F. Hourani, 'Alghazali and the Philosophers on the Origin of the
World', The Muslim World, XLVII/2(1958), 183-91,308-14 and M. Saeed
Sheikh, 'Al-Ghazali: Metaphysics', A History of Muslim Philosophy, ed.
Notes and References 169
28 For further elucidation of the privacy of the ego, see Lecture IV, pp.
79-80.
29 Cf. p. 64 where Iqbal says that God 'out of His own creative freedom
... has chosen finite egos to be participators of His life, power, and
freedom.'
30 The tradition: 'Do not vilify time, for time is God' referred to in
Lecture I, p. 8.
31 Cf. The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosaphy, Vol. I, Definition
viii, Scholium i.
32 Cf. Louis Rougier, Philosaphy and the New Physics (An Essay on the
Relativity Theory and the Theory of Quanta), p. 143. The work belongs
to the earlier phase of Rougier's philosophical output, a phase in which
he was seized by the new discoveries of physicists and mathematicians
such as Henry Poincare (celestial mechanics and new geometry), Max
Planck (quantum theory) Nicolas L. Carnot (thermodynamics), Madame
Curie (radium and its compounds) and Einstein (principle of relativity).
This was followed by his critical study of theories of knowledge:
Notes and References 171
SJ..l.i ...,......i...o .))• ...,.....u ) ')J. L,.::....i u,..::..J1 "Y'" ':/1 ....AJ,S:.; 1..01 ) "';1.>. JS" ,J' .)1
74 Cf. ibid., Vol. IV, 2 (Books i and ii- translation), p. 230. It is to be noted
that quite a few minor changes made by Allama Iqbal in Nicholson's
English translation of the verses quoted here from the Mathnawl are due
to his dropping Nicholson's parentheses used by him for keeping his
translation literally as close to the text as it was possible. Happily,
Allama's personal copies of Volumes 2-5 and 7 of Nicholson's edition of
the Mathnawi are preserved in Allama Iqbal Museum (Lahore) and it
would be rewarding to study his usual marginal marks and jottings on
these volumes.
75 Cf. the Qur'anic verse 3: 19 where so far as private prayers are
concerned the faithful ones are spoken of remembering God standing
and sitting and lying on their sides.
76 The Qur'an speaks of all mankind as 'one community'; see verses 2:
213,10: 19.
77Ibid., 49: 13.
Lecture IV: The Human Ego-His Freedom and Immortality
1 Cf. Qur'an, 6:94, 19:80 and 19:93-95; see also p. 93 where Allama Iqbal,
referring to these last verses, affirms that in the life hereafter the finite
ego will approach the Infinite Ego 'with the irreplaceable singleness of
his individuality.'
2 This is, in fact, translation of the Qur' anic text: wa Iii taziru wiiziratan
wizra ukhrii which appears in verses 6: 164; 17: 15; 35: 18; 39: 7 and 53: 38.
Chronologically the last verse 53: 38 is the earliest on the subject. The
implication of this supreme ethical principle or law is three-fold: a
categorical rejection of the Christian doctrine of the 'original sin',
refutation of the idea of 'vicarious atonement or redemption', and
denial of the possibility of mediation between the sinner and God (d.
M. Asad, The Message of the Qur'an, p. 816, note 31).
3 Again, translation of the Qur'anic verse 53:39 which is in continuation
of the verse last referred to above.
4 Cf. O. Spengler, The Decline of the West, 1, 306-07. Also Lecture V, p. 114
where Allama Iqbal makes the important statement: 'Indeed my main
purpose in these lectures has been to secure a vision of the spirit of
Islam as emancipated from its Magian overlaying' (italics mine). This
may be read in conjunction with Allama's reply to a Parsi gentleman's
letter published in Statesman. This reply makes it clear that: 'Magian
thought and religious experience very much permeate Muslim
theology, philosophy and Sufism. Indeed, there is evidence to show that
certain schools of Sufism known as Islamic have only repeated the
Magian type of religious experience ... There is definite evidence in the
Qur' an itself to show that Islam aimed at opening up new channels not
only of thought but the religious experience as well. Our Magian
inheritance, however, has stifled the life of Islam and never allowed the
Notes and References 177
creation' is also alluded to in such verses as 10: 4; 27: 64; 30: 11. See also
56: 61.
65 Qur'an, 17: 13.
66 Reference here is to the Qur' anic description of life hereafter such as is
to be found in verses 37: 41--49 and 44: 51-55 for the state of life promised
to the righteous, and 37: 62-68 and 44: 43--49 for the kind of life to be
suffered by the wicked. See also 32: 17.
67 Qur'an, 104: 6-7.
68 Reference is to the Qur'anic expression hiiwiyah (for hell) in 101: 9.
69 See the Qur' anic verse 57: 15 where the fire of hell is spoken of as man's
friend (mawlii), i.e. 'the only thing by which he may hope to be purified
and redeemed' (d. M. Asad, The Message of the Qur'an, p. 838, note 21).
70 Qur'an, 55: 29.
25: 73 and 17: 72 which in the present context clearly make it as much a
religious duty of the 'true servants of the Most Gracious God' to ponder
over these apparent signs of God 'as revealed to the sense-perception of
man' as to ponder over the Divine communications (iiyat al-Qur'an)
revealed to the Holy Prophet- this two-way God-consciousness alone
ensures man's physical and spiritual prosperity in this life as well as in
the life hereafter.
10 Cf. G. H. Lewes, The Biographical History of Philosophy (1857), p. 306, II.
4-8, where Lewes says: 'It is this work ("Revivification of the Sciences of
Religion") which M. Schmolders has translated. It bears so remarkable a
resemblance to the Discours de la methode of Descartes, that had any
translation of it existed in the days of Descartes, everyone would have
cried against the plagiarism'. The second sentence of this passage was
quoted by Allama Iqbal in his doctoral dissertation: The Development of
Metaphysics in Persia (1908), p. 73, note (1), in support of his statement
that GhazalI 'anticipated Descartes in his philosophical method'.
It is to be noted that Schmolders' Essai sur les ecoles philosophiques chez les
Arabes (Paris, 1842) was not the French translation of GhazaH's
voluminous 'Revivification' (Ihyii 'Ulum aI-Din in forty books) but that
of his autobiographical work AI-Munqidh min al-Daliil with its earliest
edited Arabic text. It seems that the remarkable originality and boldness
of GhazalI's thought in the French version of al-Munqidh led Lewes to
confuse it with the greater, the more famous 'Revivification' (Ihyii'). For
the 'amazing resemblance' between GhazaH's AI-Munqidh min al-(llliil
(Liberation from Error) and Descartes' Discourse de la methode (Discourse
on Method), see Professor M. M. Sharif, 'The Influence of Muslim
Thought on the West', 'Section: D', A History of Muslim Philosophy, II,
1382-84.
11 Cf. AI-Qistiis al-Mustaqim, trans. D. P. Brewster (The Just Balance),
chapters ii-vi and translator's Appendix III: 'AI-GhazaH and the
Syllogism', pp. 126-30; d. also Michael E. Marmura, 'GhazaH's Attitude
to the Secular Sciences and Logic', Essays on Islamic Philosophy and
Science, ed. G. F. Hourani, Section II, pp. 102-03, and Susanna Diwald's
detailed review on AI-Qistiis in Der Islam (1961), pp. 171-74.
12 Shihab aI-Din Suhrawardi Maqtiil.
13 For an account of Ishraqi's criticism of Greek logic contained in his
Hikmat al-Ishriiq, d. S. Hossein Nasr, 'Shihab ai-Din Suhrawardi Maqtiil',
A History of Muslim Philosophy, I, 384-85; a fuller account of Ishraqi's
logic, according to Nicholas Rescher, is to be found in his Kitiib al-
Talwihiit and Kitiib al-Lamahiit d. Development of Arabic Logic, p. 185). It is
to be noted that the earliest explanation of Ishraqi's disagreement with
Aristotle that logical definition is genus plus differentia, in terms of
modem (Bosanquet's) logic, was given by Allama Iqbal in his
186 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
prove this fifth postulate on the one hand and the development of the
non-Euclidean geometries on the other are as many tributes to Euclid's
wisdom', says Sarton (ap. cit. I, 153). A long note on the postulate by
Spengler- well versed in mathematics- in his Decline of the West, 1,176,
admirably brings out its deep philosophical import.
These non-Euclidean geometries were developed in the nineteenth
century by certain European mathematicians: Gauss (1777-1855) in
Germany, Lobachevski (1792-1856) in Russia, Bolyai (1802-1860) in
Hungary and Riemann (1826-1866) in Germany. They abandoned the
attempt to prove Euclid's parallel postulate for they discovered that
Euclid's postulates of geometry were not the only possible postulates
and that other sets of postulates could be formulated arbitrarily and
self-consistent geometries based on them. They further discovered that
the space assumed in Euclidean geometry is only a special case of a
more general type. These non-Euclidean geometries assumed immense
scientific significance when it was found that the space-time continuum
required by Einstein's theory of gravitation is non-Euclidean.
This in short is the movement of the idea of parallel postulate from
Euclid to Einstein; Allama Iqbal with his seer-like vision for ideas was
very much perceptive of this 'movement' and also of the scientific and
philosophical significance of the non-Euclidean geometries. It is to be
noted that Allama's keenly perceptive mind took full notice of the
scientific developments of his days, for example, of anti-mechanistic
biologism (neo-vitalism) of Hans Driesch and J. S. Haldane and of
quantum theory as well as of relativity-physics especially as expounded
by Eddington, Louis Rougier, Lord Haldane, Wildon Carr and other
philosopher-scientists. Among other things, one may notice a score of
books on the 'Philosophy of Contemporary Science', more than half of
which are on relativity-physics (mostly published between 1920 and
1928) in his personal library alone. See M. Siddiq, Descriptive Catalogue of
Allama Iqbal's Personal Library, pp. 4-7 and 71-76, as well as Plates Nos.
22 and 23 giving the facsimiles of Allama's signatures dated July 1921
and September 1921 on his own copies of Einstein's work: Relativity: The
Special and the General Theory: A Papular Exposition (1920) and Edwin E.
Slosson's Easy Lessons in Einstein (1920); d. also Dr Ahmad Nabi Khan,
Relics of Allama Iqbal (Catalogue), books listed at IV. 41 and IV. 46. The
first book The Mystery of Space by Robert T. Browne by its very sub-title:
, A Study of the Hyperspace Movement in the Light of the Evolution of
New Psychic Faculties and an Inquiry into the Genesis and Essential
Nature of Space' suggests that it was probably this book which was
foremost in Allama's mind when he spoke of highly mathematical
notion of 'hyperspace movement' in connection with Tiisi's effort to
improve the parallel postulate here as well as in his 'Plea for Deeper
190 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
After that such rapid advances took place in mathematics that within,
say, fifty years it was completely metamorphosed into its modern form
or, as Spengler puts it: 'Once this immense creation found wings, its rise
was miraculous'. Being well versed in mathematics, Spengler gives an
exciting account of the new discoveries of the Western mathematicians
and their impact on European science and arts (op. cit., I, 74-90). Two of
his statements are to be noted. 'Not until the theory of functions was
fully evolved', says Spengler, 'could this mathematics be unreservedly
brought to bear in the parallel sphere of our dynamic Western physics'.
Generally speaking, this means that Nature speaks the subtle and
complex language of mathematics and that without the use of this
language the breath-taking progress of science in the West, since the
seventeenth century, would have been a sheer impossibility. Spengler,
however, did not care to know that the mathematical idea of function
originated, not in the West, but in the East, more particularly with the
most brilliant AI-BInlni's AI-Qanun al-Mas'udi in 1030, i.e. six hundred
years before Fermat and Descartes.
The second statement to be noted is that, according to Spengler, 'The
history of western knowledge is thus one of progressive emancipation
from classical thought' (op. cit, p. 76). As it is, Allama Iqbal has the least
quarrel with Spengler on the truth of this statement for he says: 'The
most remarkable phenomenon of modern history, however, is the
enormous rapidity with which the world of Islam is spiritually moving
towards the West. There is nothing wrong in this movement, for
European culture, on its intellectual side, is only a further development
of some of the most important phases of the culture of Islam' (Lecture I,
p. 6: italics mine). And further, 'Spengler's view of the spirit of modern
culture is, in my opinion, perfectly correct' (p. 114). What Allama Iqbal,
however, rightly insists is 'that the anticlassical spirit of the modern
world has really arisen out of the revolt of Islam against Greek thought'
(ibid.). This revolt consists in Islam's focussing its vision on 'the
concrete', 'the particular' and 'the becoming' as against the Greeks'
search for 'the ideal', 'the universal' and 'the being'. Spengler failed to
see these Islamic ingredients of modern culture because of his seJf-
evolved thesis 'that each culture is a specific organism, having no point
of contact with cultures that historically precede or follow it'. Spengler's
thesis has its roots, not in any scientifically established dynamics of
history, but in his uncompromising theory of cultural holism (note the
sub-title of the first volume of his work: Gestalt and Wirklichkeit). Cf. W.
H. Dray's article, 'Spengler, Oswald', in Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, VII,
527-30 for critical evaluation of Spengler's philosophical position.
23 Cf. M. A. Kazim, 'AI-BIrllni: and Trignometry', AI-Biruni
Commemoration Volume, esp. pp. 167-68, for the English translation of the
192 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
Plate No. 33) or his highly valuable one-page private study notes
preserved in Allama Iqbal Museum, Lahore (d. Relics of Allama Iqbal:
Catalogue, I. 26). It is, however, in one of his greatest poems 'Iblis ki
Majlis-i Shura' ('Satan's Parliament') included in the posthumous
Armughiin-i Hijiiz that one is to find his final verdict on this baseless
scholastic controversy:
k .!.J\p. L ..ill (tf'
..:-If t.f.. '-;? if'f- J(j' /.=)I
t.f.. ml./lv,i J( L V
r;:.::..i;.-o,.::..u L .::..f'I-:
Are the words of the Qur'an created or untreated?
In which belief does lie the salvation of the ummah?
Are the idols of Uit and Manat chiselled by Muslim theology
Not sufficient for the Muslims of today?
10 Cf. Ibn Qutaibah, Ta'wil Mukhtalif al-Hadith, p. 19.
11 Cf. Development of Metaphysics in Persia, p. 54, where it is stated that
rationalism 'tended to disintegrate the solidarity of the Islamic Church';
also W. M. Watt, 'The Political Attitudes of the Mu'tazilah', Journal of the
Royal Asiatic Society, (1962), pp. 38-54.
12 Cf. Muhammad al-Khudari, Tiirikh al-Tashr!' al-Isliimi, Urdu trans.
'Abd aI-Salam Nadvi, p. 323; Ibn Qutaibah, Ma'iirif, p. 217, and J.
Schacht, The Origins of Muhammadan Jurisprudence, p. 242. According to
A. J. Arberry, Sufyan al-Thauri's school of jurisprudence survived for
about two centuries; d. Muslim Saints and Mystics, p. 129 translator's
prefatory remarks.
13 On the distinction of ziihir and biitin, see Allama Iqbal's article "Ilm-i
Zahir wa 'Ilm-i Batin" (Anwiir-i Iqbiil, ed. B. A. Dar, pp. 268-77) and also
the following passage from Allama Iqbal's article captioned as 'Self in
the Light of Relativity' (Thoughts and Reflections of Iqbal, ed. S. A. Vahid,
pp. 113-14): 'The mystic method has attracted some of the best minds in
the history of man-kind. Probably there is something in it. But I am
inclined to think that it is detrimental to some of the equally important
interests of life, and is prompted by a desire to escape from the arduous
task of the conquest of matter through intellect. The surest way to
realize the potentialities of the world is to associate with its shifting
actualities. I believe that Empirical Science- association with the visible-
is an indispensable stage in the life of contemplation. In the words of
the Qur'an, the Universe that confronts us is not biitil. It has its uses, and
the most important use of it is that the effort to overcome the
obstruction offered by it sharpens our insight and prepares us for an
insertion into what lies below the surface of phenomena.
Notes and References 199
14 The founder of Zahirl school of law was Dawud b. 'All b. Khalaf (c.
200-270/c. 815-884) who flourished in Baghdad; Ibn Hazm (384-
456/994-1064) was its founder in Muslim Spain and its most illustrious
representative in Islam. According to Goldziher, Ibn Hazm was the first
to apply the principles of the Zahirite school to dogmatics (The Ziihiris:
Their Doctrine and their History, p. 112); cf. also Goldziher's articles:
'Dawud B. 'All B. Khalf' and 'Ibn Hazm' in Encyclopaedia of Religion and
Ethics, V, 406 b and VII, 71 a.
15 Cf. Serajul Haque, 'Ibn Taimiyya's Conception of Analogy and
Consensus', Islamic Culture, XVII (1943), 77-78; Ahmad Hasan, The
Doctrine of Ijmii' in Islam, pp. 189-92, and H. Laoust, 'Ibn Taymiyya',
Encyclopaedia of Islam (New edition), III, 954.
16 Cf. D. B. Macdonald, Development of Muslim Theology, p. 275.
17 SuyuU, Husn al-Muhadarah 1, 183; also' Abd al-Muta'al al-Sa'idl, Al-
Mujaddidun fi 'l-Isliim, pp. 8-12. Cf. also Allama Iqbal's 'Rejoinder to The
Light' (Speeches, Writings and Statements of Iqbal. pp. 167-68) wherein,
commenting on the tradition that mujaddids appear at the head of every
century (AbU Dawud, Malahim: 1), he observed that the tradition 'was
probably popularised by Jalal-ud-Dln Suyuti in his own interest and
much importance cannot be attached to it.'
Reference may also be made here to Allama's letter dated 7 April 1932
addressed to Muhammad Ahsan wherein, among other things, he
observes that, according to his firm belief ('aqidah), all traditions relating
to mujaddidiyat are the product of Persian and non-Arab imagination
and they certainly are foreign to the true spirit of the Qur'an (cf.
Iqbiilniimah, II, 231).
18 For Allama Iqbal's statements issued from time to time in clarification
of meanings and intentions of pan-Islamic movement or pan-Islamism
see: Letters and Writings of Iqbal, pp. 55-57: Speeches, Writings and
Statements of Iqbal. p. 237; Guftiir-i Iqbiil, ed. M. Rafiq Afdal, pp. 177-79
and 226- the earliest of these statements is contained in Allama's letter
dated 22 August 1910 to Editor: Paisa Akhbiir reproduced in Riaz
Hussain, '1910 Men Dunya-i Islam ke Halat' (Political Conditions of the
Islamic World in 1910), Iqbal Review, XIX/ii Ouly 1978), 88-90.
In three of these statements Allama Iqbal has approvingly referred to
Professor E. G. Browne's well-grounded views on 'Pan-Islamism', the
earliest of which were published (s.v.) in Lectures on the History of the
Nineteenth Century, ed. F. Kirpatrick (Cambridge, 1904).
It may be added that Allama's article 'Political Thought in Islam',
Sociological Review, I (1908), 249-61 (reproduced in Speeches, Writings and
Statements, pp. 107-21), was originally a lecture delivered by him in a
meeting of the Pan-Islamic Society, London, founded by Abdullah
Suhrawardy in 1903- the Society also had its own journal: Pan-Islam.
200 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
The Life and Teachings of Ziya G6kalp, pp. 102-03, and Allama Iqbal's
statement 'On the Introduction of Turkish Prayers by Ghazi Mustafa
Kemal Pasha' published in the Weekly Light (Lahore), 16 February 1932,
reproduced in Rahim Baksh Shaheen (ed.), Mementos of Iqbal, pp. 59-60.
29 On Ibn Tumart's innovation of introducing the call to prayer in the
Berber language, d. Ibn AbI Zar', Raud al-Qirtas, Fr. trans. A. Beaumier,
Histoire des souverains du Magreb, p. 250; I. Goldziher, 'Materalien zur
Kenntniss der Almohadenbewegung in Nordafrika', ZDMG, XLI
(1887),71, and D. B. Macdonald, Development of Muslim Theology, p. 249.
This practice, according to Ahmad b. Khalid al-SalawI, was stopped and
call to prayer in Arabic restored by official orders in 621/1224; d. his AI-
Istiqsa Ii Akhbar Duwal al-Maghrib 'I-Aqsa, 11,212.
30 Cf. Ziya Gokalp kulliyati, p. 133. The word 'sun' in the second
sentence of this passage stands for GOnum in Turkish which, we are
told, could as well be translated as 'day'; some allowance, however, is to
be made for translation of poetical symbols from one language into
another.
31 Cf. ibid., p. 161. It is interesting to note how very close is late Professor
H. A. R. Gibb's translation of this passage as well as of the one
preceding it (Modern Trends in Islam, pp. 91-92), to that of Allama's, even
though his first reference is to the French version of them in F.
Ziyaeddin Fahri's Ziya Gi G6kalp: sa vie et sa sociologie, p. 240.
32 Cf. BukharI, 'I'tisam'; 26; 'Hm'; 39; 'Jana'iz'; 32; 'Marada'; 17, and
Muslim, 'Jana'iz'; 23 and 'Waslyyah'; 22.
33 For further elucidation of Allama's observations on Luther and his
movement here as also in a passage in his 'Statement on Islam and
Nationalism in Reply to a Statement of Maulana Husain Ahmad'
(Speeches, Writings and Statements of Iqbal, p. 254), see his most famous
and historical 'All-India Muslim League Presidential Address of 29
December 1930', ibid., pp. 4-5. Cf. also the closing passages of the article;
'Reformation' in An Encyclopaedia of Religion, ed. Vergilius Farm, p. 642.
34 Cf. SubhI MahmasanI, Falsafah-i Shari'at-i Islam, Urdu trans. M.
Ahmad RidvI, pp. 70-83.
35 This acute observation about the development of legal reasoning in
Islam from the deductive to the inductive attitude in interpretation is
further elaborated by Allama Iqbal on pp. 140-41. It may be worthwile
to critically examine in the light of this observation the attempts made
by some of the wellknown western writers on Islamic law to
analytically trace the historical development of legal theory and practice
in Islam, viz. N. J. Coulson, A History of Islamic Law, chapters, 3-5; J.
Schacht, Introduction to Islamic Law, chapters, 7-9 and his earlier
pioneering work: Origins of Muhammadan Jurisprudence, by General
Index especially under 'Medinese' and 'Iraqians'.
Notes and References 203
Hashimis Tasiinifi Iqbiil kii Tahqiqi -o-Tauzmi Mutiili'ah throw light on the
immediate impact that Aghnides's book had on Allama's mind. It seems
that Aghnides's book did interest Allama and did play some part in
urging him to seek and study some of the outstanding works on UsOI
al-Fiqh such as those by Amidi, Shatibi, Shah Wali Allah, Shaukani, and
others. This is evident from a number of Allama's letters to Sayyid
Sulaiman Nadvi (Iqbiilniimah, I, 128-36, 160-63) as also from his letters
from 13 March 1924 to 1 May 1924 to Professor Mauiavi M. Shafi'
(Oriental College Magazine, LIII (1977), 295-300). It is to be noted that
besides a pointed reference to a highly provocative view of Ijma'
alluded to by Aghnides, three passages from part I of Mohammedan
Theories of Finance are included in the last section of the present Lecture,
which in this way may be said to be next only to the poems of Ziya
Gokalp exquisitely translated from Fischer's German version of them.
47 This is remarkable though admittedly a summarized English version
of the following quite significant passage from Shah WaH Allah's
magnum opus Hujjat Allah al-Biilighah (I, 118):
').,s'.i.l.1 Jr"'J 1 .r.i- l5J"'1 Jr"1 JI ;..\.>-1) ;J... J.>- ['-''11 l5"u1 rl,.'JII.L. )
'-'I fr'" :JL.i oj; Y' ) J\.i'J1 .) ) ./)'J I j->I .uG..."i <>-},,..
) ')r""- .r.i- ['-'I '.ulos; "'" Jl;;, 'J .......;,; rl,.'J 1 I.L. 0'1 SJ; ) (u"WJ ":""f l
cJ\,;'J1 j->'J .,.....i.l.1 lJr" Y' l,. """'? "l,. .)1 -.,...>") SJ:s .)\.51;1
)S1 "'; ",..\;. ) ":"\';\'.ii) '11 ) r-WI ;,r ....; = l,. ( ) rAJ" U.L.a.l1
.r''J 1 01 JI J.,.- '1 .;'1 SJ.; lLiI J.>- L..,r. u"UI ( ,......r.i- ;,r
) r; J5 = l,. 01 JI 'JI ) ')\..pI '.AJ\.i "'" j.....; 'J ;1 r'" J5WI JI
..u, j")\.:>.1 J.>- 1""'= l,. ) r-ibt..., :;,be.. '1 1;1 "'-l? J-(j H I*'" % u")""
..s:J; W ;..\.>-1) "'-l? .,,1» , f ,1))1 r-s- .li ) r-i4,1 J.Y ) r11
...,JI rs- J.,J., 'J ,J.,. ) ,"'" 'JI J.J"''J I ,y;1 'J .;1 ;5"'J1 )
r+sT)I;,r ;,rl l,. .:.,.,....LJ.I) l5}.....JI ) 0\.i 0'J1 "Y"}I tllrJl .) c!) LS 4)1
) )I....!JI .) fr-" .)1 ;,r )""'!I 'J ) ,:.r->-I ")\.i SJ, J./"t1 1".....,1 ( '11
. ..u., 0f\,
This is the passage quoted also in ShibH Nu'mani's AI-Kaliim (pp. 114-
15), a pointed reference to which is made in AJlama Iqbal's letter dated
22 September 1929 addressed to Sayyid Sulaiman Nadvl. There are in
fact three more letters to Sayyid Sulaiman Nadvi in September 1929,
which all show Allama's keen interest in and perceptive study of Hujjat
Allah al-Biilighah at the time of his final drafting of the present Lecture
206 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
.5J1 }u 01 ) cJ r-WI Jot ,-""I I.,. J"; r}.J1 .y .J 011 C:"'" .y r-WI
Jw .y ,.J,.y <'1.;Jo y.y " I.,. c}J .11 ,)1 1.l.4i
;;)4>0- d' J ""J\kUI Jk<t .y c>y> ,-4-> j}... ..u >U.•.:...)lI) ..50>)11 ij.i )
) j-J J r-WI ;...,; .5J1 0\5' 01 )
From the study of the section of Irshad al-Fuhul dealing with the
'possibility of there being a period of time without a mujtahid, it
becomes abundantly clear that the views embodies in the above
passage are those of the Shafi'Ijurist Badr aI-DIn ZarkashI of the
eight century of Hijrah and not of SarkashI, nor of ZarkashI of the
tenth century. For an account of the life and works of Badr aI-DIn
ZarkashI, Cf. Muhammad Abu'I-Fadl aI-RahIm's 'Introduction' to
ZarkashI's well-known, AI-Burhiin fi 'Ulum al-Qur'iin.
It may be added that the Persian translator of the present work Mr.
Ahmad Aram considers 'SarkashI' to be a misprint for 'SarakhsI', Le.
the Hanafi jurist Shams al-A'immah AbU Bakr Muhammad b. AbI
Sahl al-Sarakhi, the author of the well-known thirty-volume al-
Mabsut who dies in near about 483/1090; and referring to 'many
errors and flaws' that have unfortunately crept into the Lahore
edition of the present work, he is inclined to think that 'tenth
centruy' is another misprint for 'fifth century' (Cf. Ihyii-i Fikr-i Dini
dar Isliim, pp. 202-03, note)
Ahmad Aram admittedly takws his clue from a line in Madame Eva
Meyero-vitch's French translation: Reconstruire la pen see religious de
I'Islam (p. 192) and perhaps also from the Urdu translation: Tashkil-I
Tadi'd Il iihiyat-I Isliimi'yah (p 274) by the late Syed Nadhir NiyazI who
corrects the name (SarakhsI) but not the date. This is, however,
better than the Arabic translator who retains both the misprints
without any commects (Cf. 'Abbas Mahmud, Tajdid al-Tafkir al-Dini
fi'l Isliim, p 206).
58 Cf. article 'Turkey' in Encyclopaedia Britannica, XXII, 606-08. the French
writer alluded to by Allama Iqbal is Andre Servier whose work L'Islam
Notes and References 209
expression in Allama's verse, viz. Kulliyiit-i Iqbiil (Urdu), Biil-i Jibn1, Pt.
II, Ghazal 60, v. 4:
nalism and race-hatred (as) a scabies of the heart and blood poisoning',
also The Twilight of the Idols, chapter viii where he pronounces
nationalism to be 'the strongest force against culture'.
13 Cf. pp. 145-46.
14 Reference here is to the misguided observations of the orientalists to
be found in such works as A. Sprenger, Des Leben and die Lehre des
Mohammed (1861), I, 207; D. S. Margoliouth, Mohammed and the Rise of
Islam (1905), p. 46; R. A. Nicholson, A Literary History of the Arabs (1907),
pp. 147-48; and D. B. Macdonald, Religious Attitude and Life in Islam
(1906), p. 46.
15 C. Jung, Contribution to Analytical Psychology, p. 225.
16 Idem, Psychology of the Unconscious, pp. 42-43.
17 Cf. Shaikh Ahmad Sirhindi', Maktubat-i Imam Rabbani, vol. I, Letter 253,
also Letters 34, 257 and 260. In all these Letters there is listing of the five
stations: Qalb (the 'heart'), Ruh (the 'spirit'), Sirr (the 'inner'), Khafi (the
'hidden'), and Akhfa (the 'hidden most'); together they have also been
named as in Letter 34 Jawiihir-i Khamsah-i 'Alam-i Amr ('Five Essences of
the Realm of the Spirit'). Cf. F. Rahman, Selected Letters of Shaikh Ahmad
Sirhindi, chapter iii (pp. 54-55).
18 Cf. Stray Reflections, ed. Dr. Javid Iqbal, p. 42, where Nietzsche has
been named as a 'great prophet of aristocracy'; also article: 'Muslim
Democracy' (Speeches, Writings and Statements of Iqbal, pp. 123-24), where
a critical notice of Nietzsche's' Aristocracy of Supermen' ends up in a
very significant rhetorical question: 'Is not, then, the Democracy of early
Islam an experimental refutation of the ideas of Nietzsche?'
19 Cf. Kulliyat-i Iqbal (Persian), Javid Namah, p. 741, verses. 4 and 3.
.:;..,-1
:.
7?
. (;)Jy')1 .J:?)? J; .:;..,-1
:..
7? (;)JJI
.
..: I) J?
A
Jr.y' J J!.? (;)li"1 JI; .L I) oW j .&
if. J .:;..,-1 J / Jr.y' <v!1
(A) Works
, Abd aI-Qadir, 'All Hasan, Nazarah Ammah fi TanKh al-Fiqh al-
Islami, Cairo, 1942.
'Abd al-Quddus GangohI, Lata'if-i Quddusi, ed. by Shaikh
Rukn aI-Din, Delhi, 1311 A. H.
'Abd aI-Salam KhurshId, Dr., Sargudhasht-i Iqbal, Lahore,
1977.
Abdullah Anwar Beg, The Poet of the East, Lahore, 1939.
I Abdullah Chaghata'I, Dr., Iqbal ki Suhbat Men, Lahore, 1977.
Abu Dawud, Sulaiman b. al-Ash'ath al-SijistanI, Kitab al-
Sunan, 4 vols. in 2, Cairo, 1935; English trans. by Ahmad Hasan,
Sunan Abu Dawud, 3 vols., Lahore, 1984.
Abu RashId Sa'Id b. Muhammad b. SaId al-NaisaburI, Kitab
al-Masa'il fi-Khilafbain Basriyyin wa 'l-Baghdadiyyin ed. and trans.
into German by Arthur Biram: Die atomistische Substanzenlehre
aus dem Buch der Streitfragen Bavensern und Bagdadensern, Leyden,
1902.
Aghnides, Nicolas P., Mohammedan Theories of Finance (with
an Intro. to Mohammedan Law and a Bibliography), New York,
1916; rep. 1969.
Ahmad b. Hanbal, Musnad, 6 vols., Beirut, n. d.
218 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
1369/1950.
Ashnawi, Shaikh Taj aI-Din Mahmud b. Khudadad, Ghtiyat al-
Imktin fi Ma'rifat al-Zamiin wa 'l-Makiin, ed. by Nadhr Sabiri,
Campbellpur, 1401 A. H.
Ashraf Ali Thanawi, Maulana, Al-Hilat al-Niijizah li 'l-Haliilat
I
Sprenger, Aloys, Dos Leben and die Lehre des Mohammed, vol. I,
Berlin, 1861.
Steinberg, S. H. (ed.), Cassell's Encyclopaedia of Literature, vol. I,
London, 1953.
SWckl, Albert, Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, vol. II,
Bonn, 1865.
AI-Suyuti, Jalal aI-DIn, Husn al-Muhiidarah fi Akhbiir Misr wal
Qiihirah, vol. I, Cairo, 1299 A H.
Tauqan, Qadri: Hafiz, Turiith al-'Arab al-'Ilmi, Cairo,
1382/1963.
Thadani, Nanikram Vasanmal, The Garden of the East, Karachi,
1932.
AI-Tirmidhi, Muhammad b. 'Isa, AI-Tiimi' al-Sahih, ed. by
Ahmad Muhammad Shakir, 3 vols., Cairo, 1356/1937.
Toumeau, R. Le, The Almohad Movement in North Africa in the
Twelfth and Thirteenth Centuries, Princeton, 1969.
Toynbee, A, A Study of His tory, vol. III, London, 1934.
Tsanoff, Radoslav A, The Problem of Immortality: Studies in
Personality and Value, London, 1924.
AI-Tusi, NasIr aI-Din, AI-Risiilat al-Shiifiyah 'an al-Shakk fi '1-
KhutUt al-Mutawiizziyah in (Tusi's) Rasii'il, vol. II, Hyderabad
(Deccan), 1359 A H
Tyan, Emile, Institutions du droll public musulman, Tome II:
Sultanat et califat, Paris, 1956.
Vaihinger, Hans, The Philosophy of liAs If'; trans. by C. K.
Ogden, London, 1924.
Wahid-ud-DIn, FaqIr Sayyid, Ritzgiir-i Faqir, Lahore, 1963.
Wall Allah, Shah, Hujjat Allah al-Biilighah, vol. I, Cairo, 1322
A H, Urdu trans. by Maulana' Abd aI-RahIm, Lahore, 1961.
Whinfield, E. H (tr.), Masnavi-i Ma'navi (Spiritual Couplets of
Maulana Jalalud-DIn Muhammad Rumi: trans. & abridged),
London, 1898.
Whitehead, Alfred North, The Concept of Nature, Cambridge,
1920; -, Religion in the Making (Lowell Lectures in Boston in
1926), New York & Cambridge, 1926; -, Science and the Modem
World (Lowell Lectures in Boston in 1925), New York, 1925.
Yunus Farangi Mahalli, Muhammad, Ibn Rushd, A'zamgarh,
1324 A H
Zahid al-KautharI, Husn al-Taqiidi fi Sirat ai-Imam Abi Yiisuf al-
Qiidi, Cairo, 1948.
230 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
(B) Articles
Arendonk, C. van, 'Ibn Hazm', The Encyclopaedia of Islam, II,
384-86.
Arnaldez, Roger, & A Z. Iskander, 'Ibn Rushd', Dictionary of
Scientific Biography, XII, 1-9.
Arnheim, R, 'Gestalt', Encyclopaedia of Psychology, II, 58-60.
Barker, Henry, 'Berkeley', section: 'Metaphysics of
Immaterialism', Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, II, 526b-528b.
Bassett, R, 'Ibn Tumart', The Encyclopaedia of Islam, II, 425-27;
also Shorter Encyclopaedia of Islam, pp. 152-54.
Bausani, A, 'Concept of Time in the Religious Philosophy of
Muhammad Iqbal', Die Welt des Islams, N. 5., III (1954), 158-86.
Beare, Mary, 'Faust' in S. H. Steinberg (ed.), Cassell's
Encyclopaedia of Literature, 1, 217-19.
de Boer, T. J., 'Atomic Theory (Muhammadan)" Encyclopaedia
of Religion and Ethics, II, 202b-203b.
Bohr, Niels, 'Atom', Encyclopaedia Britannica, II, 642-47.
Broad, C. D., 'Time', Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, XII,
334a-345a.
Browne, E. G., 'Pan Islamism' in F. Kirkpatrick (ed.), Lectures
on the History of the Nineteenth Century.
Butler, R A, "Kitab aI-Tawasin of al-HalIaj', Journal of the
University of Baluchistan, 1/2 (Autumn 1981),49-117.
Carr, H. Wildon, 'The Idealistic Interpretation of Einstein's
Theory', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. N. 5., XXII (1921-
22), 123-27.
Carra de Vaux, B., 'Averroes, Averroism', Encyclopaedia of
Religion and Ethics. II, 2666; 'Ibn Rushd,' The Encyclopaedia of
Islam, II, 410-13.
Dar, Bashlr Ahmad, 'Iqbal Aur Mas'ala-i Zaman-o-Makan,' in
Salim Akhtar (ed.), Fikr-i-Iqbiil ke Munawwar Goshay (Lahore,
1977), pp. 141-51.
Bibliography 231
XXI/ii, (1947),264-302.
Taylor, Alfred Edward, 'Continuity', Encyclopaedia of Religion
and Ethics, IV, 89b-98a (inter alia Zeno of Elia's notion, 91-92 and
Cantor's theory, 96b-98a).
Thomson, W., 'Kharijitism and the Kharijites' in R. W.
Barstrow (ed.), The Macdonald Presentation Volume, pp. 371-89.
Vemet, Juan, 'Mathematics, Astronomy, Optics', in J. Schacht
(ed.), The Legacy of Islam, pp. 461-89.
Watt, W. Montgomery, 'The Political Attitudes of the
Mu' tazilah', Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society, 1962, pp. 38-54.
Yazdani, Dr. Khwajah Hamid, 'RisaIah dar Zaman-o-Makan',
AI-Ma'a-rif, XVII/7 (Lahore, July 1984), 31-42, 56 (Urdu trans. 'of
Khwaja Muhammad Parsa's tractate on space and time based on
the unique MS 707, Majami' Tal'at, Dar al-Kutub. Cairo).
Zedler, B. H., 'Averroes and Immortality', New Scholasticism,
1954, pp. 436-53.
QUR' ANIC INDEX
Note: - The first figure in the first column represents the number of the Surah
and the second the number of the verse(s). A roman numeral in parentheses in
the second column denotes the number of the Lecture and the figure following it
the number of note in that Lecture.
AI-Baqarah AI-Nisii
Yusuf Kahf
12:21 70 18:29 87
18:49 (IV 63)
AI-Ra'd 18:59 110 (V 41)
13:11 10 Maryam
13:39 60 (III 36)
19:66-67 96
Ibriihim 19:80 76 (IV 1), 93 (IV 52)
19:88-92 51 (III 3)
14:5 110 19:93-95 93
14:19 8 (122)
Tii Hii
Al-Hijr
20:14 45 (II 38), 57 (III 26)
15:5 111 (V 412) 20:118-19 67 (III 60)
15:16 (I 8) 20:120 66 (III 52)
15:19-20 66 (III 56) 20:120-22 68 (II 61), 69
238 The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
20:122 76 25:73 102 (V 9)
20:123 70 (III 68)
AI-Qasas
AI-Anbiya'
28:7 100 (V 3)
21:11 110 (V 41) 28:77 8 (1 21)
21:16 8 (I 22)
21:33 3 (I 9) AI-'Ankabut
21:35 68
21:37 69 (III 67) 29:6 45 (1137)
21:94 (IV 63) 29:20 8,98 (II 65)
21:103 94 (IV 55) 29:44 8 (122)
21:108 (III 3) 29:69 118 (VI 6)
AI-Hajj AI-Rum
AI-Hadid AI-Naba'
87:2-3 40 (II 0)
AI-Ghiishiyah
88:17-20 11
AI-Balad
AI-Shams
91:7-10 95
AI-TIn
AI-Zi/ziil
99:5 100 (V 3)
AI-Qiiri'ah
AI-Humazah
AI-Ikhliis
112:14 50
INDEX
Note:- Throughout the Index Roman and Arabic numerals
within parentheses indicate the number of the Lecture and
that of the note respectively where the entry may be seen.
of, is self-revelation and not good and evil, Qur' anic view of,
the pursuit of an ideal, 48; 65-68
loyalty to, amounts to man's Government, republican form of,
loyalty to his own ideal not only consistent with the
nature, 117; metaphor of light spirit of Islam, but a
as applied to, 51-52; necessity, 125
omnipotence as related to
Great European War, 129, 142
Divine wisdom, 64-70;
perfect individuality and 'Great I am', 57 (II 38, III 26)
unity of, as enunciated in the Greek lOgic, Muslim criticism of,
Qur'an, 50-52 (III 3); Qur'an's 102-03 (V 13)
emphatic denial of the Greek philosophy, intellectual
sonship of, 51 (III 3); revolt of Islam against, 3, 47,
rationalistic arguments for 102, 113, 114 (V 22)
the existence of, 23-25;
relation to the universe as Greek thought, character of
soul's relation to the body Muslim culture not
('Iraqi), 110; scholastic determined by, 104
arguments for the existence Greeks, influence of, tended to
of, 23-25; teleological obscure Muslims' vision of
argument for the existence of, the Qur'an, 3, 104
24; thought and deed, the act Guide of the Perplexed
of knowing and the act of (Maimonides), 54 (III 12)
creating identical in, 62 see Hadith, and life-value of the
also Ultimate Ego and legal principles enunciated in
Ultimate Reality the Qur' an, 137; as a source
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von of Muhammadan Law, 135-
(1749-1832), and the legend 37; attitude of AbU Hanlfah
of Faust, 65 (III 47); on the towards, of purely legal
teachings of Islam, quotes 7 import perfectly sound, 137;
Gokalp, Ziya (c. 1292-1343/c. Goldziher's examination of,
1875-1924), critical in the light of modem canons
assessment of the views of, of historical criticism, 135;
on equality of man and intelligent study of, to be
woman, 134-35; ideal of used as indicative of the
womanhood, 128; inspired by spirit in which the Prophet
the philosophy of Comte, himself interpreted his
126-27; religio-political views Revelation, 137; modem
of, 126-28; science and (Western) critics of, 135 (VI
religion, 127 45); pre-Islamic usages in,
our writers do not always
Glodziher, Ignaz (1850-1921), (V
refer to, 136; quoted in the
15, VI 14); on hadith, 135 (VI
present work: 'Actions shall
45)
be judged only by intention'
Index 251