Hegel and History
Hegel and History
Hegel and History
AND
HISTORY
Karin de Boer
Andrew Buchwalter
Pierre Chételat
Jason J. Howard
Allegra de Laurentiis
Glenn Magee
William Maker
John McCumber
Sûrya Parekh
Nathan Ross
Mark Tunick
Mario Wenning
Edited by
WILL DUDLEY
This page intentionally left blank.
Hegel and History
This page intentionally left blank.
Hegel and History
Edited by
WILL DUDLEY
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany
D16.8.H454 2009
901—dc22 2009007384
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
Introduction 1
Will Dudley
Contributors 247
Index 249
Acknowledgments
The original versions of the essays collected in this volume were presented
at the nineteenth biennial meeting of the Hegel Society of America,
held at DePaul University, October 6–8, 2006. I wish to thank Kevin
Thompson and the Philosophy Department for organizing and hosting
the conference. Portions of the essay contributed by Allegra de Laurentiis
appeared in her book, Subjects in the Ancient and Modern World: On
Hegel’s Theory of Subjectivity (2005) and are reproduced with the per-
mission of Palgrave Macmillan.
vii
This page intentionally left blank.
Introduction
Will Dudley
1
2 Will Dudley
The four chapters in the first section of the volume engage, in differ-
ent ways, the various interpretations and implications of Hegel’s claim
that history has an end, toward which it necessarily progresses, and at
which it has already arrived. This claim immediately calls into ques-
tion the status of the present and the future in Hegel’s philosophy
of history. If the actualization of freedom brought history to an end
in the nineteenth century, what is the significance of that which has
since transpired, is currently transpiring, or has yet to transpire? What,
if anything, can Hegel contribute to the comprehension of ongoing
human events and development?
William Maker, in “The End of History and the Nihilism of Becom-
ing,” argues that a proper interpretation of Hegel’s claim that history has
been completed leads not to nihilistic resignation in the face of closure
and stasis, but rather to an appreciation of the openness and dynamism
of the modern era. The end of history coincides with the beginning of
modernity, with the insight that freedom involves radical self-criticism
4 Will Dudley
aspects of each culture, those aspects that are in accordance with, and
those that are contrary to, the requirements of freedom.
Although Hegel’s philosophy of history cannot presuppose the
superiority of Europe, it does of course conclude that European
modernity actualizes freedom more fully than any other historical
culture. Buchwalter points out, however, that Hegel regards freedom
as universally and essentially human, not as the special prerogative of
Europe. Moreover, Hegel remains critical of European societies, none
of which is perfectly rational, and all of which pose economic and
political challenges that threaten the freedom of their people. Finally,
Buchwalter adds, Hegel understands freedom, at both the individual
and the cultural level, to require recognition of the autonomy of others,
and so to be a principle that demands mutual respect and openness,
while precluding unilateral domination.
Sûrya Parekh grants that Hegel claims his philosophy of history is
governed by impartial norms of rationality and freedom, but wonders
whether geography and race are in fact merely contingent factors in
the narrative. More generally, he challenges us to consider whether it
is possible for philosophy to distinguish between those factors to which
it attributes historical necessity, and those that it relegates to the sphere
of contingency. In “Hegel’s New World: History, Freedom, and Race,”
Parekh focuses on two particular ways in which Hegel appears to vio-
late his own claim to impartiality by grounding historical judgments on
considerations of race.
First, Parekh argues, Hegel denies to inhabitants of the New World
the rationality that he purportedly regards as universally human. This
is indicative, Parekh contends, of a metaphysical distinction Hegel pre-
supposes between the Old and New Worlds, and upon which he bases
his belief in the intrinsic inferiority of the inhabitants of the latter. This
inferiority includes, on Parekh’s reading, an incapacity for education,
which makes it impossible for Hegel to believe that those born and
raised in the New World could ever be rational or free.
Second, Parekh turns to two passages in which Hegel links freedom
to blood. In the first of these, Hegel ascribes the impulse to freedom
only to those native Americans who have at least some European blood.
In the second, Hegel connects the failure of Catholic lands in Europe
to accept the Reformation to the Roman blood of their inhabitants.
By bringing these issues to our attention, Parekh aims to place
the burden on those who defend Hegel’s impartiality to explain the
passages in question. If Hegel’s philosophy of history is neither racist
nor Eurocentric, then how, Parekh forces us to ask, can it link ancestral
8 Will Dudley
The third section of the volume contains four chapters, all of which are
concerned with Hegel’s accounts of the ways in which the elements of
“subjective spirit” and “objective spirit” undergo, and contribute to,
historical development. The essays treat, respectively, the historicity of
selfhood, moral imputation, ethical life, and political organization.
Allegra de Laurentiis, in “Spirit without the Form of Self: On
Hegel’s Reading of Greek Antiquity,” traces the evolution of self-knowl-
edge and subjectivity from ancient Greece to the Medieval and Modern
eras. She argues both that the transformation of subjectivity is linked to
advances in self-knowledge, and that it was just such an advancement
and transformation of selfhood that led to the downfall of the Greek
way of life.
The primary deficiency in the ancient Greek self-understanding,
as de Laurentiis reads Hegel, was ignorance of subjective freedom and
the ethical institutions appropriate to it. The Greeks therefore had only
limited knowledge, based on intuition rather than concepts, of the truth
of what it is to be human, and so failed to attain selfhood in the full-
est sense.
This failure of the ancient Greeks is understandable, de Laurentiis
argues, for Hegel demonstrates that truly adequate self-knowledge and
subjectivity are intrinsically historical achievements, which could not
emerge at such an early stage of human development. The consequences
of this failure are therefore also understandable: Greek society made sharp
distinctions of caste and class, on the basis of which it enslaved some
and denied property rights to others, because it failed to recognize the
universality of free human subjectivity. The ancient Greeks, and their
chief philosophical representative, Plato, could see such freedom only
as a threat to the success and happiness of their communities. This
insight proved to be correct, de Laurentiis concludes, for the emerging
awareness of, and insistence upon, the universal freedom of individual
subjects proved to be incompatible with, and so helped bring to an end,
the form of life in ancient Greece.
In “The Historicity of Ethical Categories: The Dynamic of Moral
Imputation in Hegel’s Account of History,” Jason Howard attempts
to determine exactly how Hegel understands the development of
self-knowledge and subjectivity to take place. In particular, Howard is
Introduction 9
The two chapters in the fourth and final section of the volume inves-
tigate, in quite different ways, the relationship between religion and
Hegel’s philosophy of history.
In “Hegel’s Philosophy of World History as Theodicy: On Evil and
Freedom,” Pierre Chételat evaluates alternative interpretations of Hegel’s
claim that the philosophy of history is also theodicy. Chételat argues
that Hegel does not claim to have solved the classical problem of evil
in the monotheistic tradition—that of explaining how evil is compatible
with the existence of an omnipotent and benevolent deity—but rather to
have shown how evil can be reconciled with the goodness of the world.
Hegel does this, according to Chételat, by demonstrating that the world
is governed by reason, and thus that history is not a merely contingent
series of events, but a necessary development toward the actualization
of freedom, which is the ultimate good. “God,” on Chételat’s reading
of Hegel, is a religious term intended to personify the idea that reason
is at work in history, and that the goodness of freedom can enable the
transcendence of evil.
Chételat emphasizes, however, that transcending evil is not the
same thing as justifying it. Hegel does not, on his view, believe that evil
is justified in virtue of being a necessary means to the end of freedom.
This position, Chételat points out, is neither philosophically compel-
ling—because much of the evil in the world clearly fails to advance
freedom at all—nor proposed in Hegel’s texts.
Freedom can transcend evil without justifying it, Chételat con-
tends, by enabling us to rise above our own particularity, and thereby
to overcome suffering by accepting its necessity. Chételat distinguishes
this position, which he attributes to Hegel, from Stoic resignation. The
chief difference, on Chételat’s reading, is that Hegel holds that the
12 Will Dudley
William Maker
Hegel’s claim that history has ended and that he has comprehended
this ending has generated considerable discussion. It is also among
his more notorious assertions. For some, to hold that history is over
and that final philosophical truth has been achieved must mean that
a radical transcendence of human finitude had been attained; that
we and the world are beyond time and change, and that Hegel, the
Great Comprehender, stands omniscient as the individualized telos of
history. According to Alexander Kojeve, only when “the real dialectic
of History is truly completed” with the “”end of time’ ” and “the
definitive stopping of history” can “a Wise Man . . . named Hegel” lay
claim to “Absolute Knowledge” which consists in revealing “being in
the completed totality of its spatial-temporal existence.”1 Barry Cooper
contends that Hegel’s idea of “a perfected knowledge” necessitates “an
end to the tiresome business of living as a human being.” It is only
achievable in an inalterable homogeneous state where there is nothing
15
16 William Maker
significant left to achieve, where all desires are fulfilled, all possibilities
are exhausted, and nothing can be gone beyond. The whole idea con-
stitutes “an aggressive attack on human dignity.”2 Stanley Rosen puts it
bluntly: in offering us a “science of totality,” Hegel made the mistake
of “confusing himself with God.”3 It would seem that nothing could
be more arrogant, blasphemous, absurd, and indicative of the totalizing,
authoritarian—and erroneous—nature of Hegel’s thought, then his claim
to have articulated the unconditional comprehension of time, being, and
truth. In opposition to this reading, my exploration of Hegel’s linking
of the end of history and the completion of philosophy aims to show
that his notion of history’s end and philosophy’s completion present
closure and completion not as terminal finality but as inseparable from
dynamic openness.
Part I outlines the interpretive problems associated with Hegel’s
idea that history ends in modernity’s attainment of freedom. Part II
argues that this attainment is linked with Hegel’s completion of philoso-
phy in that both require a transformation of our relation to the past as
what is given. To flesh this out, Part III presents Hegel’s completion
of philosophy as a resolution of the problem philosophy inherited from
Parmenides: what to do about nothingness as that which disrupts the
given. This leads to my key claim in Part IV: Hegel succeeds in intel-
ligibly reincorporating nothingness and completes philosophy by conceiv-
ing being and truth dynamically, as the becoming of self-determining
freedom. The end of history is not a termination of our relation to
the past, but a transformative reconfiguration of it. History ends as
the new beginning of freedom. Part V critiques Nietzsche’s alternative
posthistorical philosophy of becoming as will to power.
How are we to understand Hegel’s claim that history has ended and
that his system has comprehended this?6 This much is clear: according
to Hegel reason and the real have come to coincide in modernity in
that the world of historical becoming has been brought finally into
accord with the absolute being of reason, and history, the succession of
events involved in the struggle to overcome their separation, is over. The
confluence of timeless philosophical truth and worldly events has been
attained.7 The rational is now real and the real is now rational, and thus
Parmenides’ insight, that logos and being are one, is vindicated.
What does this mean? With some exceptions the prevailing approach
has been to read the end of history and the completion of philosophy
in a postdialectical fashion as predominantly signifying closure, termina-
tion, finality; it means the abrogation of the future and the inception
of decline and decay. For, if the history of the world and of philosophy
have culminated in the coincident attainment of humanity’s practical
and conceptual goals, must not this entail stasis, the end of all change
and development, both in action and thought? It would seem that an
end to change is necessary if absolute, complete, and final truth is to
be attained, and further, that future change must be precluded if abso-
lute truth is not to be relativized. Complicating matters is the fact that
the completion Hegel envisions consists in the realization of freedom.8
How can the closure of a final resolutive ending be reconciled with the
openness of the human prospect and the potential for development and
change which seem inseparable from freedom? G. A Kelly, Raymond
Plant,9 and Daniel Berthold-Bond find the completeness of history’s end
incompatible with the openness crucial for both dialectic and freedom.
According to Berthold-Bond this incompatibilty “cannot plausibly be
swept away or ‘aufgehoben’ by Hegel’s notorious synthetic method of
unifying opposites.”10
Pace Berthold-Bond I will show how to reconcile the openness of
dialectic and freedom with the systemic completeness that grasps how
being and logos are one at the end of history. When we understand
just how modernity marks the end of history and the opening for the
completion of philosophy, we will see that Hegel’s conception of abso-
lute being and truth as self-determining concept means that systematic
completeness is linked, not with the foreclosure of the future, but with
a historically unprecedented conceptual and practical openness. In taking
this view I am in general agreement with and have profited from the
work of Richard Winfield, Stephen Houlgate, and Will Dudley.11 What
I will present here is intended to complement their efforts by indicating
how openness is fundamental to systematic thought.
18 William Maker
In sum, if freedom is not just the achieved spirit of the age, but
is more fundamentally the truth of reality, then only that which accords
with freedom can play a legitimate determining role in the (individual
and social) life of freedom. Freedom requires that we do not simply
accept that who and what we are can be unreflectively determined by
anything but the activity of freedom itself.20 In this sense, history must
be ended, for making freedom’s self-determination effective requires
a change in our active and interpretive relation to the past, in the
broadest since of what “the past” is, namely, whatever we find given
as always already fully determinate. Houlgate puts it succinctly: “Hegel
understands history precisely as the passage from determination by
given, external, i.e., natural forces, to free self-determination.”21 How
then does philosophy finally achieve self-legitimation and completion by
liberating itself from its past? More specifically, how is establishing the
truth of being as freedom the fulfillment of Parmenides’ insight that
logos and being are one?
given object; and it must do this because it holds that being is just what
is found present as what is already fully determinate.26
Locating Parmenides in this format will show how he initiated
philosophy as the love of wisdom: a succession of failed attempts to
show that what we take the absolute to be is just what the absolute is.
This will also show why an overcoming of consciousness opens the way
to the completion of philosophy.
Note that Parmenides’ approach fits the framework of phenom-
enological consciousness. He too asserts the need to legitimate his
claim that being is what is knowable by further articulating what the
determinacy of being in accord with logos is, trying to show that being
in itself and being for consciousness are one.27 Whence the difficulty?
In Hegelian terms, Parmenides’ problem consists in construing the
demands of logos in terms of consciousness. Parmenides attempted to
think being minimally, and without further qualification, just in terms
of its sheer knowability as a given object. For Parmenides, nothing else
may constrain, qualify, or determine being save its being pure, complete,
and undifferentiated Gegenständlichkeit: absolute being must just be that
which can be construed purely and simply as what is already fully present
to awareness, that which totally occupies intentional space.28 Parmenides
construed logos’ constraint on what being can be precisely in terms of
consciousness’ understanding that being is a given object. He has the
simplest take on what always already present as fully determinate may
mean. For, when being means full presence to awareness, then being
cannot permit of anything not fully present. This is precisely how Par-
menides describes being: it does not permit of any break, disruption, or
fissure; being excludes all nonbeing, where nonbeing means the absence
or diminishment or interruption of all-encompassing, undifferentiated
presence. Parmenides’ problem emerges as he makes consciousness’ move
to demonstrate that what he takes being to be accords with logos: dem-
onstrating that being is nothing but full presence—what consciousness
takes it to be—involves articulating why nothing may be permitted to
disrupt being. This very act thereby brings nonbeing into the thinkable
and into being’s determinacy. In phenomenological parlance, Parmenides
compares two “moments,” what is “for it the in-itself, and knowledge,
or the being of the object for consciousness.”29 The latter moment is
the contribution of consciousness acting in accord with logos to specify
what logos demands of being as full presence through its active exclusion
of nonbeing from the presence of being. However, just this activity on
the part of consciousness thereby introduces nonbeing as the other which
it must, but cannot successfully exclude. Nonbeing as absence or void
must be excluded for being to truly be full presence, but it cannot be
22 William Maker
What has been said can also be expressed by saying that Rea-
son is purposive activity . . . purpose is what is immediate and
at rest, the unmoved which is also self-moving, and as such is
Subject. Its power to move, taken abstractly, is being-for-self
or pure negativity. . . . The realized purpose, or the existent
actuality, is movement and unfolded becoming31
which logic cannot include in, or reduce to, itself, is precisely how logic
completes itself. Completed identity is attained through a nonreductive
relationship of differentiation. A general point for Hegel and his system
is that there is no completion that is not also an opening—to reach a
true limit we must think both sides of it—and no ending that is not
also a beginning. Reaching genuine completeness is inseparable from the
recognition of that which is not included, and attaining genuine closure
requires opening up to that which lies beyond and is other than that
which has reached closure.38 (9) The philosophical nature of truth can
be grasped since the concept of freedom is timeless as the self-grounding
truth about absolute being. But in the completion of conceiving truth
as the dynamic of freedom, thought opens up to and points beyond
itself. As Realphilosophie indicates, the content of the truth of freedom
is the reality of an activity that lies outside of thought, in the given
world. In addition, the actualization of freedom is not guaranteed by
thought but requires action that is open and subject to disruption, to
external necessities and contingencies beyond thought’s control.39 The
Realphilosophie’s conception of truth as freedom is at the same time
the articulation of the limits of it as concept; the very truth of what it
articulates as a concept points beyond the conceptual. What freedom
requires is necessary and unchanging, but that we will continue to be
aware of this, and that we will continue to will and act in accordance
with what freedom requires is and must be open just for the truth of
freedom to be actualized as freedom. The concept of freedom indicates
that openness and uncertainty must be present because—among other
things—free willing of freedom is required for actual freedom to accord
with its concept. (10) Since absolute, timeless truth as freedom is irre-
ducibly dynamic, the eternal emerges in time not as its end, but as a
present, ongoing activity that relates to the past as to the completed,
and to the future as the open condition of its possibility. As attained
truth, freedom is infinite because the ground of its activity lies within
itself, and because its self-constitutive activity continually actualizes
itself in reaching beyond itself. It is timeless because the determining
constitutive framework of the activity remains unchanging as the basis
for its outward extending activity in which change is the realization of
the unchanging. (11) The “absolute” of absolute knowledge does not
signify “complete and all-encompassing” in the sense of the full pres-
ence to awareness of the totality of objects. Correlatively, the end of
history does not signify the complete set of the totality of events, which
would require the end of all time and change. Rather, as the truth
of all genuine being is self-determination, history’s end as involving
this discovery means that for this dynamic truth to sustain itself, the
26 William Maker
Notes
Hegel’s Philosophy of History,” The Owl of Minerva 22, no.1 (Fall 1990):
69–80; Will Dudley, “Freedom in and Through Hegel’s Philosophy,” Canadian
Philosophical Review 39, no. 4 (Fall 2000): 683–704. In “Circulation and
Constitution at the End of History,” David Kolb describes Hegel’s end as “an
unblocking of circulation. Barriers would have been removed that restricted the
movement of something whose flow creates society. . . . Hegel’s ‘end of history’
can be described as the unbinding of a circulation. In it, the movement of mutual
recognition and/as Spirit’s self-comprehension finally overcomes otherness and
completes the circle of Spirit’s becoming.” In Endings: Questions of Memory
in Hegel and Heidegger, ed. Rebecca Comay and John McCumber (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1999), 59. Unlike me, Kolb is skeptical about
Hegel’s success at marrying the unblocking with a philosophical completion.
While I concur in seeing Hegel’s end as an unblocking, I will argue that it
does not involve overcoming otherness in a reductive sense.
12. Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans.
F. G. Lawrence (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990), 7.
13. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, I, 95. See also 380.
14. Speaking of modern philosophy, Hegel wrote, “The principle is hereby
gained, but only the principle of freedom of spirit; and the greatness of our
time rests in the fact that freedom . . . is recognized. . . . This however is merely
abstract, for the next step is that the principle of freedom is again purified and
comes to its true objectivity.” Lectures on the History of Philosophy III, 423.
15. See especially the Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit and to the
first edition of the Science of Logic.
16. “Besides it is not difficult to see that ours is a birth-time and a period
of transition to a new era. Spirit has broken with the world it has hitherto
inhabited and imagined, and is of a mind to submerge it in the past, and in the
labour of its own transformation. Spirit is indeed never at rest but engaged in
moving forward. . . . The gradual crumbling that left unaltered the face of the
whole is cut short by a sunburst which, in one flash, illuminates the features
of the new world. But this new world is no more a complete actuality than is
a new-born child”Phenomenology, 6–7.
17. “The most perfect method of knowledge proceeds in the pure form
of thought: and here the attitude of man is one of entire freedom.” “In logic
a thought is understood to include nothing else but what depends on thinking
and what thinking has brought into existence.” G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Logic:
Being Part One of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans.
William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), §24, Zusatz, 41–42, 39.
18. Insofar as both philosophy and modernity instantiate self-determination,
philosophy can illuminate how modernity constitutes its normativity out of
itself.
19. As I will discuss below, in the will to power Nietzsche explores
the former option of taking the structure of asserting or postulating as
foundational.
20. G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1952), §27.
The End of History and the Nihilism of Becoming 31
21. “World History as the Progress of Consciousness,” 77. I would add that
those given external forces may include established modes of understanding about
what makes us what we are, modes of understanding to which we have become
historically conditioned and which we accept as given and authoritative.
22. Lectures on the History of Philosophy, I, 254.
23. “[T]he living Substance is being which is in truth Subject, or, what
is the same, is in truth actual only in so far as it is the movement of positing
itself, or is the mediation of its self-othering with itself,” “the spontaneous
becoming of itself.” Phenomenology, 10, 11. Importantly, for Hegel this means
that even the nature of the subject cannot be taken as a given. Hence his many
cautionary remarks in the logic about the error of assuming we already know
and may begin with a determinate model of subjectivity.
24. In the Phenomenology the framework of heteronomous determination
is captured in terms of consciousness’ oppositional relation to being as an
object or Gegenstand: Consciousness captures the essence of heteronomy as
other-determining in that consciousness always understands being minimally and
irreducibly as what is always found already formed in its field of awareness as
the determining ground of truth.
25. Phenomenology, 49.
26. It cannot omit what it contributes, as that is part of what is present,
but it cannot fully thematize or incorporate it either. First, that requires
another contributory act. Second, such incorporation would deviate from the
assumption that being is what is found fully present as already given. Even when
consciousness does thematize its own activity, it never makes it fully present; and
when it is finally fully present in absolute knowing, consciousness disappears as
a determinate presencing framework.
27. Parmenides, Fragments # 342, 346, pp. 266–67, 271 in G. S. Kirk
and J. E. Raven, The Presocratic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1957.) “For consciousness is, on the one hand, consciousness of the
object, and on the other, consciousness of itself; consciousness of what for it is
the True, and consciousness of its knowledge of the truth. Since both are for
the same consciousness, this consciousness is itself their comparison; it is for the
same consciousness to know whether its knowledge of the object corresponds
to the object or not.” Phenomenology, 54.
28. Parmenides, Fragments # 347 and 348, pp. 273, 275.
29. Phenomenology, 54.
30. “Hence it comes to pass for consciousness that that what it previously
took to be the in-itself is not an in-itself, or that it was only an in-itself for
consciousness. . . . We see that consciousness now has two objects: one is the first
in-itself, the second is the being-for-consciousness of this in-itself. The latter appears
at first sight to be merely the reflection of consciousness into itself, i.e., what
consciousness has in mind is not an object, but only its knowledge of that first
object. But . . . that first object, in being known, is altered for consciousness;
it ceases to be the in-itself, and becomes something that is the in-itself only
for consciousness. And this then is the True. . . . The new object contains the
nothingness of the first.” Phenomenology, 54.
32 William Maker
46. “The world with which we are concerned is false, i.e., is not a fact
but a fable and approximation on the basis of a meager sum of observations; it
is ‘in flux,’ as something in a state of becoming, as a falsehood always changing
but never getting near the truth: for—there is no ‘truth.’ ” The Will to Power,
§616.
47. The Gay Science, §109.
48. “ ‘Truth’ is therefore not something there, that must be found or
discovered—but something that must be created and gives a name to a process,
or rather to a will to overcome that has in itself no end—introducing truth,
as a processus in infinitum, an active determining—not a becoming conscious
of something that is in itself firm and determined. It is a word for the ‘will to
power.’ ” The Will to Power, §552. So unlike Hegel’s becoming, Nietzsche’s
is weighted toward nothingness. This can be seen in Nietzsche’s repeated
assurance that becoming is devoid of order, structure, lawfulness, purpose, goal,
and meaning.
49. The very attempt to distinguish one from another, to create a coherent
framework of past, present, and future, would require lapsing to a foundational
postulation of some enduring being.
50. “[T]he basic fact of the human will, its horror vacui: it needs a
goal—and it will rather will nothingness than not will.” On the Genealogy of
Morals, III, §1, 97.
51. “[N]ow one realizes that becoming aims at nothing and achieves
nothing . . . that becoming has no goal and that underneath becoming there is
no grand unity.” The Will to Power, §12, see §§25, 55.
52. “It [nihilism] places the value of things precisely in the lack of any
reality corresponding to these values and in their being merely a symptom of
strength on the part of the value-positers.” “That it is the measure of strength
to what extent we can admit to ourselves, without perishing, the merely
apparent character, the necessity of lies. To this extent nihilism, as the denial
of a truthful world, of being, might be a divine way of thinking.” The Will to
Power, §§ 13. 15.
53. The Will to Power, §55.
54. “Capitalism . . . not only never is but never can be stationary. . . . [It]
incessantly revolutionizes the economic structure from within, incessantly
destroying the old one, incessantly creating a new one. This process of Creative
Destruction is the essential fact about capitalism. It is what capitalism consists
in.” Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York:
Harper, 1975), 82. “The ‘eternal now’ of modern urban existence, for which
everything that happened more than ten minutes ago is ancient history, has
eroded that precious medium of experience, tradition.” Terry Eagleton, London
Review of Books, June 23, 2005, 23.
55. See R. D. Winfield, “Hegel’s Challenge to the Modern Economy,” in
Hegel On Economics and Freedom, ed. William Maker, 29–63 (Macon: Mercer
University Press, 1987) and R. D. Winfield, Reason and Justice (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1988), 160ff.
34 William Maker
Mario Wenning
35
36 Mario Wenning
diagnoses that the Romantics are not committed enough (or at least not
in the correct way) to their normative ideals. They do not link them to
a critical understanding of the present and the past. Thus, they deprive
themselves from making these ideals historically effective. Apart from
some of his own early ideas, which drew on Schiller’s and Hölderlin’s
account of love and aesthetic unification, Hegel’s critique is addressed
at Friedrich Schlegel’s conception of irony and utopian novels such as
Novalis’s Heinrich von Ofterdingen.19 In Novalis’s Bildungsroman, contrary
to Goethe’s Wilhelm Meister, the protagonist strives for the fantastic and
structurally unreachable place of his dreams. Heinrich’s striving for the
blue flower, the symbol of a golden age, logically outrules the possibil-
ity of reconciliation through historical learning processes in favour of
a universal and ahistorical utopia that can only be conceived of as an
apocalyptic futural escape from history and thus a place outside imma-
nent historical horizons. The problem of such utopian depictions is not
so much their claims about the future or desirable states, but that they
do not have anything meaningful to contribute to the understanding
of the present and its past apart from the fact that it is miserable when
measured against the promise exerted by the “blue flower.”
More sophisticated normative theory with a utopian intent should
not just settle with an impotent ought, but needs to point out rational
tendencies within the present reality and its history.20 Hegel advocates
an ought, which like Kant’s good will, “shines like a jewel.” Contrary
to concretely and critically questioning reality by tracing normative ten-
dencies, the Romantics dreamed of a beyond that was a mere possibility
(ein nur Mögliches). On the Romantic account, possibility and actuality
are conceived as mere opposites with no living connection. Any chance
of change is denigrated to the status of an infinitely postponed ideal, a
postulate of reason, which can never be even remotely realized through
historical agents and actions. A goal that cannot be realized, however,
is no goal worth aspiring to at all. One easily succumbs to self-pity in
light of one’s distance to allegedly higher purposes. A pondering on
possibilities commits one to a form of inwardness of being locked in
one’s subjective will.
If abstract ratiocination treats possibility as detached and logically
prior to actuality, Hegel states in the Encyclopedia Logic,21 everything
becomes possible: “that tonight the moon will fall on the earth . . . [or]
that the Turkish Kaiser will become pope, because it is a human being
who can convert to Christianity and become a catholic Priest.”22 In
other words, all standards to measure the feasibility of one’s normative
aspirations are lost when one engages in pondering about possibility
detached from concrete, even if only rudimentary manifestations of this
44 Mario Wenning
Outlook
Notes
1. Cf. the chapters “Die absolute Freiheit und der Schrecken,” “Das Gewis-
sen. Die schöne Seele, das Böse und seine Verzeihung,” and “Das unglückliche
Bewußtsein.”
2. For an account of Hegel’s diagnosis of modernity cf. Michael N.
Forster’s account of the eight dualisms Hegel identified, largely in following
Schiller, as the major crises of modernity. Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of
Spirit (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 17–125.
3. In Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics, ed. J. M. Bernstein
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 186 ff.
4. The important exceptions proving the rule are Ernst Bloch, Subjekt und
Objekt (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1962); Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1960); and Adrien Peperzak, Le jeune Hegel et la vision
Hegel, Utopia, and the Philosophy of History 49
An Open-Ended History
Karin de Boer
Introduction
51
52 Karin de Boer
Hegel’s views on world history and the modern state have often been
dismissed as uncritical defenses of a particular theological worldview or a
particular political system. I hold that neither of these claims is justified.
Although Hegel sometimes draws on religious images to clarify what he
means by the concept, the idea, or reason, he does not assume that a
divine power consciously governs the world. The subject of his philosophy
of world history—spirit—is neither a substance nor a subject in any current
sense of the terms. The concept of spirit rather refers, I would contend,
to the efforts of thought to comprehend itself.5 As far as its occurrence
in world history is concerned, the concept of spirit exclusively refers to
the mode of thought that underlies the efforts of successive civilizations
both to organize themselves in a rational way and to comprehend the
Hegel’s Account of the Present 53
Economy
When, within a large nation, need and labor are elevated into
this universality, they form on their own account a tremen-
dous system of communality and mutual interdependence, a
self-moving life of what is dead, a life which, in its motion,
blindly moves back and forth like the elements and, like a wild
beast, requires continual strict dominance and taming.15
modern state. We will see that this state is not only vulnerable insofar
as its relation to the market is concerned, but also with regard to the
political realm itself.
Politics
Hegel, we have seen, considers the modern state to rest on the prin-
ciple that the human being as such is free. This means for Hegel that
the state should allow its citizens freely to develop their talents, yet
without therefore letting its ends be determined by their arbitrary will
(Philosophy of Right, §207). As I noted in the beginning, the Philosophy
of Right is exclusively concerned with the essential determinations that
follow from this basic principle, that is, with the idea of the modern
state. Precisely because Hegel’s account of the modern state is not
limited to this principle alone, but embraces its necessary moments, the
difference between the essential actuality of the state and its empirical
existence is not always easy to tell. Hence the deliberate ambiguity of
Hegel’s equation of actuality and rationality in the preface (Philosophy
of Right, 24/20).
I would like to emphasize that Hegel always attempts to expose
the implications of a particular mode of thought from within. In order
to articulate the “spirit” of the modern state, Hegel equally goes along
with the insight of the modern state into its proper principle. The Phi-
losophy of Right makes it clear that he holds this insight to have been
achieved primarily by the moderate reformers who between 1807 and
1815 attempted to emancipate the Prussian state from its feudal institu-
tions without, on the other hand, completely abolishing the traditional
forms of local and national political participation.18 Hegel draws on the
enlightened views of these thinkers, but he distinguishes itself from them
by comprehending their ideas in light of the actualization of freedom
at stake in the history of spirit as such. Since the principle of freedom
entails the urge to actualize itself, Hegel can maintain, following Rous-
seau, that these ideas respond to the universal or rational will:
cities. Between 1807 and 1815, various efforts were made to abolish
the feudal structure of these estates and to transform them into modern
institutions representing the interests of citizens at the level of local,
regional, and national politics. Due to the resistance of the nobility and,
after 1816, the defeat of Napoleon, most of these efforts at reform were
never carried out or were quickly abandoned.20 The traditional system
of corporations, at odds with the idea of a free market, was dismantled
around the same time.21 According to an addition to the Philosophy of
Right, Hegel considers these developments a great loss:
Thus, Hegel holds that the collision between the government and
those who are governed must be resolved by mediating institutions
that represent the interests of particular groups, yet in such a way that
their “legitimate power” remains subordinated to the rational end of
the society as a whole. He does not suggest, however, that modern
societies will actually be able to organize themselves in accordance with
this essential actuality. Whereas “the rational concept of the state” has
overcome the opposition between government and people, actual states
continue to be defined by this very opposition. As long as this is the
case, Hegel notes, “it cannot be said that the state—which is the unity
of the universal and the particular will—has already become actual”
(Reason in History, 142/119).
According to Hegel, the participation of citizens in local and national
politics is to be achieved through estates and corporations rather than
through democracy.23 He would not oppose the view that democracy
is meant to protect a society against the arbitrary will of its monarch.
Hegel did not embrace democracy as the right way of achieving this aim,
however, because in his view it gives free rein to an arbitrariness even
more difficult to control than the one it was supposed to overcome:
Hegel’s Present
Freedom finds its concept in the actual world and has trans-
formed the worldly sphere into an objective system that is
concrete and structured organically. . . . It is the goal of world
history that spirit create for itself a nature and world conform
to itself. (256–57/208; translation modified)
History, for Hegel, proves that this goal has been attained in
principle. That is why he relegates “the work which still needs to be
done” to “the empirical side.”26 Although the actualization of freedom
in the element of externality may still take time,
Plato, aware that the ethics of his time were being penetrated
by a deeper principle, which, within this context, could
appear . . . only as a destructive force, . . . imagined he could
counter [this] destructive force, and he thereby inflicted the
gravest damage on the deeper drive behind it, namely free
infinite personality.28
it can longer be taken for granted that the modern world will succeed
in reconciling such contrary moments as freedom and power, hospitality
and security, universality and particularity, the individual and the com-
munity, progress and tradition, prosperity and oppression, technology
and ethics, reason and faith. If such contrary moments do not neces-
sarily yield their reconciliation, and if contemporary philosophy is to
comprehend its own time, then it should attempt, in my view, to affirm
their tragic entanglement. Rather than opposing the tragic essence of
such conflicts as a destructive force, it should attempt to incorporate
this essence into its very principle. Whereas the principle of speculative
science did not allow Hegel to do this, it cannot be done, in my view,
without returning to Hegel.
Notes
1. See Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. II: The High
Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx, and the Aftermath (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1945), 27–80. Among the authors who have opposed this identification
I mention only T. M. Knox, “Hegel and Prussianism,” in Hegel’s Political Phi-
losophy, ed. W. Kaufmann (New York: Atherton, 1970), 13–29, and S. Avineri,
Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1972). See also A. Wood’s Introduction to Elements of the Philosophy of Right
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
2. Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte Band I, Die Vernunft
in der Geschichte (1822/1831), ed. J. Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner 1994) /
Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Introduction: Reason in History, trans.
H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1975), 48/42–43, trans-
lation modified. Cf., Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte (1822–31),
ed. E. Moldauer and K. M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1986) /
The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991),
28/15.
3. See Avineri, 154; T. E. Wartenberg, “Poverty and Class Structure in
Hegel’s Theory of Civil Society,” in Philosophy and Social Criticism 8 (1981):
169–82; John McCumber, “Contradiction and Resolution in the State: Hegel’s
Covert View,” in Clio 15, no.4 (1986): 379–90; A. Wood, Hegel’s Ethical
Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 237–55. Contrary to
McCumber, I will not consider the differences between Hegel’s published works
and the various lecture courses devoted to the philosophy of right.
4. I have argued elsewhere that Hegel’s own conception of tragic con-
flicts can be deployed for this purpose. K. de Boer, “Tragic Entanglements:
Between Hegel and Derrida,” in Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain
48 (2003): 33–48.
5. Spirit “makes itself into its own object and its own content. Knowl-
edge is its form and function, but its content is the spiritual itself.” Reason in
64 Karin de Boer
on the other hand, argues convincingly that Hegel’s explicit conception of the
threefold structure of civil society is at odds with his implicit acknowledgment of
the emerging opposition between owners and workers. I agree with Wartenberg
that Hegel’s Philosophy of Right could not incorporate this latter class structure
into his philosophical account of the modern state.
18. When the Philosophy of Right was published, the conservative reaction
against the reform movement was gaining the upper hand. Hegel, who was
indirectly involved with representatives of the reform movement, tried to get
round the censors—and to preserve his position at the university—by including
some ambiguous remarks on the modern state and an unambiguous attack of
Fries in its preface. During these years, Hegel received some protection from
the reformed minister of culture Von Altenstein, to whom he owed his appoint-
ment. For a detailed account see T. Pinkard, Hegel: A Biography (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2000) ch. 10–11, and G. Heiman, “The Sources
and Significance of Hegel’s Corporate Doctrine,” in Hegel’s Political Philosophy:
Problems and Perspectives, ed. Z. A. Pelczinski (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1972), 111–35. H. Klenner, “Preussische Eule oder gallischer Hahn? Hegels
Rechtsphilosophie zwischen Revolution und Reform,” in Preussische Reformen: Wir-
kungen und Grenzen, Sitzungsberichte der Akademie der Wissenschaften der DDR
(Akademie-Verlag Berlin, 1982), 125–36, argues that Hegel’s ideas concerning
the rationally structured state are compatible with the constitution proposed
by the reformers Humboldt and Stein. He refers to many elements of Hegel’s
account that deviate from the effort to reinforce an absolutist organization of
the state. See also Avineri (70, 161–75) and Wood (12–14).
19. Reason in History, 147/123; cf. 143/119–20.
20. Hegel’s use of the term Stand (estate) covers various ways in which
people with particular interests might organize themselves and have their rights
represented in local, regional, or national politics. Whereas the term estate
traditionally referred to the representative organs of the nobility and the cities
of a particular province, reformers such as Stein tried to emancipate these rep-
resentative organs from their feudal origin. Stein also tried—unsuccessfully—to
extend this reformed system of political representation to national politics. See
R. Kosselleck, Preussen zwischen Reform und Revolution. Allgemeines Landrecht,
Verwaltung und soziale Bewegung von 1791 bis 1848 (Stuttgart: Ernst Klett
Verlag, 1975) for a detailed account of these developments. Hegel basically
distinguishes between the estates belonging to civil society (social classes) and
the estates participating in national politics (cf. Philosophy of Right, §298–315,
in particular §303 Remark; “The System of Ethical Life,” 495/170).
21. Hegel notes in an “addition” that in modern times the corporations
had been abolished, since everybody was now supposed to take care of him-
self. Hegel consents that the traditional system of self-contained guilds should
not be revived. He holds, however, that modern corporations, uniting citizens
according to their trade, profession, or confession, were a necessary means to
ward off the atomism promoted by modern liberal theories (Philosophy of Right,
§255 Addition). See Pinkard, 420.
Hegel’s Account of the Present 67
John McCumber
Hegel taught us all that one of the most important things we have
to do in order to be rational animals—perhaps the most important
thing—is comprehend our own history. We cannot be truly human
unless we understand history, not merely “from outside,” but as our
history—as a series of developments from which we have resulted and
to which we must connect by seeking to carry some of them forward
and stymie others.
This lesson is now accepted to such a degree that the refusal to
examine one’s own history regularly turns out to have a pathological
basis, as in the case of mainstream American philosophy.1 It is, in other
words, not even normal, to say nothing of rational or decent. Such is
what we might call the post-Hegelian consensus in global culture.
But if Hegel taught us that we must comprehend our own history,
there is another lesson which many people think he did not teach us,
and that is how to go about doing so. Certainly Hegel’s own view of
history, as usually viewed, is hardly a model for such comprehension. It
is what Jean-François Lyotard called a “master narrative,”2 which begins
by rejecting Africa as, literally, prehistoric; thrusts something called “the
Orient” under the juggernaut of what can only be called “colonial rea-
son”; and disposes of Hellenic and post-Hellenic Western history, that is,
all of Western history, by burying it under reams of praise. Everything
finally comes to rest in the Rector’s Office of the University of Berlin,
inhabited by Herr Doktor Hegel, “secretary to the World-Spirit.”
We can all agree, I take it, that this is not the right way to under-
stand history. I believe as well that it is not the right way to understand
Hegel. In this chapter, I will sketch what I think is the right way and
then use it to try and illuminate something Hegel knew nothing about:
the contemporary world situation.
69
70 John McCumber
Hegel, to be sure, does not tell us. But his thought has resources that
enable us to understand what has happened since the fall of the wall in
1989. The basic principle of my reconstruction of this will be what I
call “minimal negation,” or what Hegel called “determinate negation”:
76 John McCumber
we make only the smallest possible change in the previous stage to get
to the next one.21
The problem with the 1989 victory of closed-minded, whimsical
individualism was that it had not overcome the Fichtean opposition that
defined it. It still needed to be what the other was not—only now, the
other really was not. This meant two things:
other than they are: they would have to abandon their basic principles
of arbitrary decision and divine submission. Each of them, to resume a
quote from Part I, “is not what it ought to be. It contradicts its con-
tent, the Idea; it must perish.” Both the Decider and the Submitter are
doomed, over the long term, because they cannot be what they are and
still accommodate to what they both need. The future thus belongs to
their common ground, the infrastructure.
But according to a fifth Hegelian resource, the infrastructure will
at some point cease to be an “infra” structure, an undifferentiated and
indistinct background formation, and “pass forward into existence”: it
must come forward as a distinct entity, a Sache, in opposition to what
else is there.30 At that point, the infrastructure will show up as a cohe-
sive community of its own—with modern airports, high-speed trains,
cell phones, and superconnectivity. If the previous paragraph is correct
this cannot come to pass in the United States or in the Middle East as
they are now constituted, but there are two obvious candidates: Europe
and China.
Consider: an officer worker in Shanghai goes to the bathroom on
the eighty-fifth floor of an office tower, flushes the toilet, and washes
her hands. The water from the toilet and the water from the sink flow
into two different municipal sewage systems, one leading to a purification
plant and the other to a water system used for things such as watering
lawns and washing cars. For Shanghai has three different sewage systems;
no American city has more than two.
Or consider: a lawyer in Paris finishes work at five p.m. and heads
for the subway. She lives at the other end of France, in Aix-en-Provence,
but she will be home for supper; the subway goes direct to the bullet
train, which traverses the country in less than three hours.
Or consider: a businessman in Munich goes to the park to eat
his lunch. While eating his sandwich, he downloads some documents,
works on them, and e-mails them to his boss in Prague; his computer
is wirelessly linked to a satellite.
Such infrastructural developments, except perhaps for the final one,
are no more likely in the United States than they are in the mountains
of Afghanistan. But they exist today, along with many others like them,
in Europe and in China.
Hegel famously said that a Volk, a people, appears only once in
history. Europe has been there all along, but not as a Volk, China,
according to Hegel, has been a unified Volk as long as there has been
a Chinese state; but he might be willing to say that it has changed so
much in the last century that it is really not the same Volk at all.
82 John McCumber
Notes
1. Cf. my Time in the Ditch: American Philosophy and the McCarthy Era
(Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2000).
2. Jean-François Lyotard The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowl-
edge, trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massoumi (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1984), 27–31.
3. Cf. Pierre Hadot, “Être, Vie, Pensée chez Plotin et avant Plotin,”
Entretiens Hardt V (Geneva: Fondation Hardt, 1960) 107–37.
4. Hegel, letter to Sinclair of early 1813, in Hegel, Briefe von und an
Hegel, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 4 vols., 1952–1960) II 4
(#218); Hegel: The Letters, trans. Clark Butler and Christiane Seiler (Blooming-
ton: Indiana University Press, 1984), 292.
5. All references, unless otherwise noted, will be to Hegel, Werke, ed. Eva
Moldenhauer and Karl Markus Michel (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 20 vols. 1970–71)
XIII 138; English translations will be given after the slash; that of this volume,
Hegel, Aesthetics, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 vols.
with consecutive pagination, 1975), 100.
6. On the impotence of nature cf. Emil Fackenheim, The Religious Dimen-
sion in Hegel’s Thought (Boston: Beacon Press, 1967), 109n, 112–15.
7. Werke XII, 35/ Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans.
Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett 1988), 24.
8. Hegel, Einleitung in die Geschichte der Philosophie, Hrsg. Johannes
Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1940), 126/ Hegel, Introduction to the Lectures
on the History of Philosophy, trans. T. M. Knox and A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1985), 94.
9. Cf. Werke XII, 81–85/60–65; translation altered.
10. On the revisability of Hegel’s System, see my The Company of Words:
Hegel, Language, and Systematic Philosophy (Evanston: Northwestern University
Press, 1993), 127f, 165f, 177f.
11. McCumber, The Company of Words, 15–18.
12. Werke II, 413f/ Hegel, Faith and Knowledge, trans. Walter Cerf
and H. S. Harris (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977), 172.
Reinhard Lauth argues that Hegel is wrong to claim that Fichte conflates the
two levels; indeed, Fichte himself denied this doubleness, claiming that his
Wissenschaftslehre never claimed that the ego as found and perceived was its
principle: the principle of Fichte’s philosophy was instead the ego as a free, a
priori construction. But Hegel’s deeper point remains: even a “pure” ego, if
used as the sort of principle that Fichte uses it as, must be at once plenary and
Hegel and the Logics of History 83
Andrew Buchwalter
Of the many criticisms leveled against Hegel, one of the most persistent
and least contested concerns his purported Eurocentrism.1 This criticism
is directed with special force at his theory of history. Not only does
Hegel’s philosophy of world history have as its principal subject matter
events and developments largely specific to European social, political,
cultural, and religious traditions. World history itself is presented as a
teleological process culminating in an affirmation and even apotheosis of
European or, as Hegel says, Christian-Germanic societies. True, Hegel
does include in his account of world history the cultures of non-Western
societies. He is said to do so, however, not because he is committed to
a genuinely inclusive account of world history but only because such
cultures are viewed as germinally possessing traits that find realized
expression in the cultures of modern Western societies. In the words of
one critic: Hegel “goes so far as to think of every culture as a means
in the furtherance of the ultimate goal that, of course, is, for Hegel,
the European-Christian culture.”2
In what follows, I shall not dispute the presence of a centrally
Western or even Eurocentric focus to Hegel’s conception of history.
Nor do I deny that his writings on history may exhibit a certain
Eurochauvinism and what has been called “a certain prejudice against
non-European cultures.”3 What I do challenge is the assumption that
Hegel’s idea or “logic” of world history is itself Eurocentric, at least in
the pejorative sense commonly associated with that term. My argument
revolves around the following six theses: (1) while Hegel does fashion
a developmental account of world history, he does so not through an
87
88 Andrew Buchwalter
Thesis 1
Thesis 2
Thesis 3
in turn annuls this opposition, takes its other, the manifold, back into
itself, in its unitary nature.”40 At least in principle, the European spirit
is a principle not of domination but mutuality.41 What Hegel says of
the individual self is applicable to the relationship of communities as
well: “[T]he concrete return of me into me in externality is that I,
the infinite self-relation, . . . have the existence of my personality in the
being of other persons, in my relation to them, and in my recognition
by them, which is thus mutual.”42
Those critical of the Eurocentric character of Hegel’s philosophy of
history may focus less, however, on cross-cultural dialogue than on his
account of the relationship of earlier stages of development to history’s
presumed final culmination in “Christian-Germanic” societies. It is here
that Hegel appears to assert that such cultures have value, not in them-
selves, but only as a means to the realize a modern social order. Yet
this view also misrepresents the very idea of a developmental account
of freedom. A history of freedom cannot regard individual cultures as
mere tools needed to realize a final end. At least as regards those fea-
tures of a culture distinctly expressive of the principle of spirit—Hegel
names “morality, ethics, and religiosity”—these have an “infinite right”
and must be assigned intrinsic value.43 Central to a history of freedom
is the proposition that earlier cultures must be valorized as autonomous,
as ends in themselves rather than mere stepping stones for the realiza-
tion of a later stage.44
To be sure, this is not to suggest that Hegel seeks to champion
the irreducible and self-sufficient uniqueness of an earlier culture. As
already suggested, cultural identity, for Hegel, is not a wholly indigenous
property but one achieved only through reference to other cultures, to
those—future cultures included—alien to itself. Moreover, cultural identity
itself depends on the availability of institutional structures allowing for
genuinely collective processes of self-interpretation and self-definition—
and these for Hegel are most fully developed in modern constitutional
societies. Yet if in this sense Hegel does ascribe historical superiority
to modern societies, he does so not to denigrate the claims of earlier
cultures but to accommodate their realization. Hegel’s critics are not
wrong to assert that on his view an earlier culture can serve as a means
to realize a social order understood as the endpoint of history. But it
is also the case that a higher stage itself serves as a means to actualize
more fully a principle of identity associated with earlier culture.45 In this
regard, “the relation of a mere means to an end disappears.”46
In the same way that Hegel claims that the past cannot be tossed
aside in the march of history, he also claims that the historical present
depends for its own reality on recourse to the past. Directed to the
Is Hegel’s Philosophy of History Eurocentric? 97
Thesis 4
Thesis 5
Thesis 6
Two points follow from this account of the role of moral cultivation
in the realization of world history, and both involve a commitment to
global openness. First, it further questions the notion that Hegel advances
a monolithic, singular, or exclusionary conception of world history. To
say that philosophizing about history has a normative-practical function
aimed at the knowledge and action capacities of contemporary agents
means that world history is fashioned from a particular perspective. Like
philosophy generally (“its own time apprehended in thought”), the phi-
losophy of history is directed to the “present standpoint,”75 addressing
individuals, including lecture attendees, from the perspective of “their
time and their world.”76 But if philosophical world history does have
this perspectival dimension, then it allows, precisely in its character as
world history, for other accounts of development, those written at dif-
ferent times and directed to different audiences. Hegel may do little to
detail such accounts;77 and his own has an undeniably European dimen-
sion. There is little in his thought explicitly directed to “provincializing
Europe,” the expression proffered by Dipesh Chakrabarty to relativize
Eurocentric approaches.78 Still, understanding Hegel’s philosophy of
world history as a type of normative reconstruction conceived with
practical intent permits ascribing to it an openness not only to diverse
accounts of history, but to what Charles Taylor, invoking Chakrabarty,
calls a “multiform world” of historical development.79
Second, to say that world history for Hegel is a normative-practical
undertaking directed to the conditions of agency on the part of his
contemporaries also suggests that the latter can be expected to display
sensitivity to other cultures, one that may facilitate realization of a
global culture and even the idea of globality itself. To expect compa-
triots to play a role in the worldly realization of freedom means that
they must contribute to the reality not just of free institutions but of
an ethico-political community conscious of itself as free.80 However, a
realized form of self-conscious freedom cannot be circumscribed by the
boundaries of a particular political community.81 As we know from Hegel’s
Is Hegel’s Philosophy of History Eurocentric? 103
Notes
33. See, for instance, Claude Ake, “The African Context of Human Rights”;
Roger T. Ames, “Rites as Rights: The Confucian Alternative”; and Kenneth K.
Inada, “A Buddhist Response to the Nature of Human Rights,” all in Larry
May et al., Applied Ethics: A Multicultural Approach, 3rd ed. (Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 2002).
34. Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977),
51.
35. PR, §343.
36. Lectures, 56; amended.
37. Susan Buck-Morss concludes the critique of Hegel she advances in
“Hegel and Haiti” with the following question: “What if every time that the
consciousness of individuals surpassed the confined of the present constellations
of power in perceiving the concrete meaning of freedom, this were valued as
a moment, however transitory, of the realization of absolute spirit?” (op. cit.,
865). Without disputing her assertions either about Hegel’s blindness to the
historical realities of slavery or the limitations in his general treatment of world
history, I would simply note that attention to processes whereby individuals do
surpass the confines of the present is a component in his own account of the
logic of a history.
38. Enc., §394.
39. PR, §248.
40. Ibid.
41. See Erzsébet Rózsa, “ ‘Versöhnlichkeit’ als europäisches Prinzip: Zu Hegels
Versöhungskonzeption in der Berliner Zeit,” in Vermittlung und Versöhnung: Die
Aktualität von Hegels Denken für ein zusammenwachsendes Europa, ed. Michael
Quante and Erzsébet Rózsa (Münster: LIT, 2001), 21–52. This point will be
addressed more fully in the final section of this paper. Here, though, it can be
noted that, the very appeal to mutuality may itself reaffirm Western values. This
is so not just for the obvious reason that mutuality is a two-way street, one that
involves as much openness on the part of non-Western to Western cultures as
the converse. It is also so in the sense that the very structure of mutuality may
itself enforce a Western bias. Not only does reciprocal recognition, for Hegel,
center, in origin as in goal, on the idea of subjective freedom; the very idea of
reciprocity is rooted in a notion of freedom—bei sich Selbst sein—that for Hegel
finds articulated expression in modern societies. Nor can this form of Western
dominance be easily contested, since any challenge, be it in declarations of inde-
pendence or claims to recognition, arguably affirms the structures of recognition
in question. In this regard Hegel anticipates the analyses of contemporary social
theorists who assert that, under conditions of globalization, Western categories
have become inescapable. Still, in also asserting the inescapability of structures of
dialectical mediation, Hegel allows for a measure of cross-cultural dialogue that
goes beyond any one-sided imposition of Western values on other cultures. On
the inescapably of Western categories, see Depesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing
Europe: Post Colonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton: Princeton
University Press 2000).
108 Andrew Buchwalter
67. PR, §297. Hegel also refers to the corps of civil servants as “the
intelligence and educated self-consciousness of a people.” See Vorlesungen über
Rechtsphilosophie 1818–1831, ed. Karl-Heniz Ilting (Stuttgart: Frommann-Hol-
zboog, 1973), 334.
68. G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen Über Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft:
Heidelberg 1817/18, transcribed by P. Wannenmann, ed. C. Becker et al. (Ham-
burg: Felix Meiner, 1983), §170, 265 (hereafter Wannenmann).
69. Alexandre Kojève, Outline of a Phenomenology of Right, ed. Bryan-Paul
Frost (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000).
70. See my “Hegel’s Concept of an International ‘We,’ ” in Identity and
Difference in Hegel’s Logic, Philosophy of Spirit, and Politics, ed. Philip Grier
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007).
71. For a discussion of this point with reference to current issues in
international law and diplomacy, see Bryan-Paul Frost and Robert Howse’s
“Introductory Essay” in Kojève’s Outline of a Phenomenology of Right, op. cit.,
especially pp. 18–24.
72. PR, §209; for the relationship of restricted and unrestricted accounts
of spirit, see PR, §340.
73. Wannenmann, §170.
74. Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s ‘Philosophy of Right’ (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1970), 41–54.
75. Lectures on the History of Philosophy III, 552.
76. Compare The Philosophy of History, 442. In this regard Hegel’s position
bears interesting resemblance to that of Max Weber, whose theory of history is
also often perceived as advancing objectivistically universalist claims about global
development. He writes: “A product of modern European civilization studying
the problem of universal history is bound to ask himself, and rightly so, to
what combination of circumstances the fact should be attributed that in Western
civilization, and in Western civilization only, cultural phenomena have appeared
(at least as we like to think [emphasis added]) to lie on a line of development
having universal significance and validity. See The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit
of Capitalism (New York: Scribner’s, 1958), 13.
77. However, he does claim that the “Oriental” image of the Phoenix pro-
vides a different model of historical development, one that—employing categories
of nature rather than spirit—notes how the destruction of one culture contains
the seeds for the transition to a new stage of development. See Lectures, 32.
78. Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe.
79. Modern Social Imaginaries (Durham: Duke University Press, 2004),
195f. For one example, deriving from Taylor, see Xin Liu, The Otherness of Self:
A Genealogy of Self in Contemporary China (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press, 2002). I thank Marek Hrubec for this reference.
80. PR, §347.
81. I have dealt with these issues at greater length in “Hegel’s Concept
of an International ‘We,’ ” op. cit.
82. Philosophy of History, 342.
83. In contrast to divine wisdom, Weltweisheit denotes human reason
unaided by revelation and directed to the realities of finite experience. As Hegel
110 Andrew Buchwalter
notes, the term derives from the Middle Ages and was revived by Friedrich Schle-
gel and others, who sought to contrapose philosophy to religion and theology.
Hegel himself utilizes the term, but rejects any rigid distinction between the
spiritual and the secular. Such distinction is incompatible both with his view of
the relationship of reason and revelation and his understanding of the divine,
for which the infinite can and must find expression in finite reality, particularly
in human knowledge and self-consciousness. As a result, Hegel advances a par-
ticularly rich conception of worldly wisdom, one based on the comprehensive
integration of spiritual and secular considerations. On his view Weltweisheit entails,
among other things, a conception of cross-cultural understanding that ascribes,
at least in part, intrinsic or “infinite” worth to every particular culture. It also
entails the concept of Weltgeist, according to which every specific culture not
only can express with others a common principle, but can be seen as contribut-
ing to a shared global culture, one that tendentially takes the form of a global
consciousness. For Hegel’s discussion of the concept of “worldly wisdom,” see
Lectures on the History of Philosophy I, 60f.
84. PR, §339.
85. Ibid., §337.
86. Ibid., §340.
87. Ibid.
88. Philosophical historiography “has not to do with what is gone but with
the living present.” Lectures on the History of Philosophy I, 39; see also p. 3.
6
Sûrya Parekh
Introduction
111
112 Sûrya Parekh
Hegel’s account of the New World has a place in the polemic that
Antonello Gerbi has titled, in the book with the same name, La disputa
del Nuovo Mondo (The Dispute of the New World).14 Within the many
vicissitudes and contradictions of this polemic are two theses, the first
of which is the driving force: the inferiority of the New World in every
way to the Old; and the New World as a future to the Old World.
Gerbi locates in Hegel’s account both an apex to the polemic, because
his account powerfully articulates these two theses, synthetically uniting
them, and at the same time anachronistic, the polemic having by this
time been systematically refuted.15
The thesis of inferiority was first systematically developed by Buffon
in the context of developing a classificatory system of global distribution
114 Sûrya Parekh
of fauna. From the start, Buffon’s thesis was untenable and counter to
empirical observation: he suggested that the cold and humid climate of
the Americas made it unsuitable for species to thrive there. This climatic
theory supported another thesis, which had already been associated with
the inferiority with the inhabitants: a perverse sexuality of the New World
inhabitants, characterized by a lesser ability to procreate.
Although Buffon did not extend his scientific thesis to humans, he
speculated that “Nature had treated him [the New World inhabitant] less
as mother than as stepmother, withholding from him the sentiment of
love or the strong desire to multiply.”16 The Prussian philosopher, the
abbe Cornelius de Pauw extended this thesis to humans and added the
vices of gluttony, drunkenness, ingratitude, and pederasty.17 From these
ignoble beginnings, this thesis of absolute inferiority expressed in a lesser
ability to copulate developed, further supported by claims of lactating
men, non-menstruating women, small penises, and other fictions.
I briefly situate Hegel’s place in the history of this polemic, in the
persistence of this thesis of inferiority in a line of philosophers, from
Buffon to Hegel and including Kant. I consider the persistence of this
thesis, which from its inception in Buffon was already facing empirical
counterevidence, a historico-philosophical problem, which I will call the
problem of the New World.
Philosophical anthropologies of the eighteenth century grappled
with the problem of how to formulate a unity of the human. Unlike
polygenetic theories, which could rationalize human differences as bio-
logical differences arising from multiple origins, monogenetic theories
required the formulation of a common origin that could still account
for human difference. This led to the use of theories of climatic and
geographic determinism to formulate accounts that commenced from a
common genus but then hierarchized human differences in nonoriginary
natural differences, namely, some composite of climate and geography.
The biologization of these natural differences, as in Kant, produced a
scientific conception of race and the development of the science of natural
history.18 In Kant, a theory of human migration, whether motivated by
nature or autonomy, is held responsible for the divergence from a single
origin, which subsequently leads to the formation of races.
Nonetheless, these monogenetic accounts inherited a problem that
had earlier confronted Christian theologians: How to account for life
in the New World?
The tension is between the division of the world into Old and New,
a division that is metaphysical, and seems to require an absolute newness
to the New World, and the incorporation of the inhabitants of the New
Hegel’s New World 115
II
terrestrial divisions of the Earth. Two are mentioned in the thesis itself.
The first is the difference between continents: “The universal planetary
life of the natural spirit particularizes itself in the concrete differences
of the Earth and separates into particular natural spirits, which express
as a whole the nature of the geographic continents and constitute
racial diversity” (PSS, 44–45; translation modified). The second is the
polarity of North and South: “The opposition of terrestrial polarity,
through which the land in the north is more concentrated . . . brings
into the difference between continents a modification” (PSS, 44–45,
translation modified).
The determination of racial diversity is constituted by the differ-
ences between continents and modified by the terrestrial expression of
the polarity of North and South, namely, a concentration of the land
in the North. There is, however, a third necessary, terrestrial division
of the Earth, one that is only introduced in the Zusatz: “The main
dividing of the Earth is that into the old and new world” (“Die Haup-
tunterscheidung der Erde ist die in die alte und in die neue Welt”). For
a division that is here called the main division, and in the PWH “no
mere external difference . . . the division is essential” (“kein bloß äußerli-
cher Unterschied . . . die Einteilung ist wesentlich”) (PWH, 162; VPW,
199; translation modified), it is peculiar that Hegel does not treat it
directly—if only to determine and minimize its influence. Instead, he
seems to devalue its importance, stating, “we are concerned here with
the determinateness constituting the distinctive character of the conti-
nents” (PSS, 48–49).
That Hegel wishes to draw our attention away from this differ-
ence should, therefore, draw our attention. And, if on the one hand,
he seems to draw our attention away from it, the very next sentence
treats this division. A curious parallel is introduced.
He says, “It must be said in this regard, that America has a younger
appearance than the Old World and falls behind it in its historical for-
mation [Bildung]” (PSS, 48–49; my translation). America here has the
signification of a specific location on the Earth (whether the New World
has continents or not is never clarified) and a metonym for the New
World. As we shall see, this is in line with Hegel’s general argument
concerning the division of the worlds: whereas in the Old World, spirit
particularizes itself into determinate difference, in the New World, these
differences never become determinate.
In the Philosophy of Nature, in the section titled “Organic Nature,”
Hegel posits that after the division of the world into an Old and New,
there is “the further division of former into continents distinguished from
one another and from the new world by their physical, organic, and
118 Sûrya Parekh
III
population comes for the most part from Europe, and everything that
happens in America has its origin there” (PWH, 165; VPW, 203).
In the PSS: “Finally, we have however to observe with regard
to the original Americans, that they constitute a vanishing and feeble
Geschlecht . . . It is clear therefore that the Americans are unable to hold
their own against the Europeans, who will initiate a new American culture
in the land they have conquered from the natives” (PSS, 62–63).
How are we to understand this vanishing? In the dialectical process
of history, the vanishing of a peoples is part of the immanent movement
of spirit, their essence preserved in the “depths of its [spirit] present”
(PWH, 151; VPW, 183). The passing of life becomes meaningful through
this progression.
The vanishing of the New World inhabitants is not dialectical. The
vanishing is an immediate effect of the encounter of the Europeans and
the Americans, without any struggle.
Hegel incorporates one of the main themes of the polemic. Like
Kant, the New World inhabitant cannot be incorporated into Hegel’s
racial anthropology. The solution to this is to cast the inhabitants
as vanishing.
IV
What is the relationship of this account of the New World to the unity
of the human? As we have seen, the dialectical unity of the Old World
seems to depend on the immaturity of the New World. In Hegel’s
anthropology, the determination of a dialectical unity of race as a totality
is coterminous with the racial indetermination of the New World.
The destiny of the New World inhabitants as vanishing seemingly
secures the unity of the Old World human as the unity of all humans.
The movement of the anthropology, from a natural unity of the human
in the genus to a spiritual unity in the Old World, would then depend
on the vanishing of the New World inhabitant. If this constitutive
moment depends on vanishing, it is mediated by another type of dif-
ference, which incorporates these inhabitants into the unfolding of
freedom. Hegel says:
free” (“der Mensch ist durch sich selbst bestimmt, frei zu sein”) (PH, 417;
VPW, 882; translation modified).
A question troubles Hegel: Why did the Reformation originate
and not extend outside of the Germanic nations?
What has happened here until now [Was bis jetzt sich hier
ereignet] is only [nur] an echo of the Old World and the
expression of an alien liveliness [fremder Lebendigkeit]; and as a
land [Land] of the future, it is of no interest to us here. The
philosopher has nothing to do with prophecy [Der Philosoph
hat es nicht mit dem Prophezein zu tun]. In history, we are
concerned with what has been and what is; in philosophy,
however, we are concerned not with what belongs exclusively
to the past or future, but with what is and eternally is [was
ist und ewig ist] with reason. And with that we have more
than enough to do. (PWH, 170–71; VPW, 209–10; transla-
tion modified)30
Conclusion
I have shown that the inhabitants of the New World form a type of
limit to the determination of racial diversity, unable to be and unable
to become, a race. The precise nature of this limit is difficult to specify,
on account of this “difference” irreducible to dialectics: inferior in every
particular, too diffuse to constitute a sharp difference.
I have also isolated the constitution of two “limits” of Hegel’s
determination of race in an appeal to blood, in the movement from the
natural unity of the genus to the spiritual unity of the human. On the
one hand, the determination of race in Hegel’s thought in some ways
marks an advance over Kant: within its limits, that is, within the hierarchy
plotted from the Africans to the French, there is room for movement.
Natural determinations are not immutable, changes can occur. Africans
and Asians, it would appear, could be free in the New World. History
can occur as well in this space, without any relationship to race. But at
the limits of these progressions, there is an appeal to blood.
Thus, the Hegelian break is in effect a displacement, which at
its “limits” constrains the progression of history and predetermines
the movement of freedom. The movement constituting the transition
from a natural unity in the genus to a spiritual unity of the human in
reason is thus dependent on the exclusion of the “pure” inhabitants of
the New World, who are consigned to vanish. The telos of freedom
in Hegel is accessible only to the Old World human. In the Aesthetics,
Hegel says:
Notes
senses. I would willingly renounce the European beef that Hegel tells us is so
superior to American beef, and I would love to dwell beside these weak and
inoffensive crocodiles of his which are however, unfortunately, twenty-five feet
long” (Gerbi, 417).
27. These examples have frequently been cited by commentators as evi-
dence that Hegel’s philosophy accords the potential for freedom to all people.
That this example is situated in his account of the New World reveals a selec-
tive reading on the part of his commentators. See McCarney, 143 and Sandra
Bonetto, “Race and Racism in Hegel—An Analysis,” Minerva—An Internet
Journal of Philosophy 10 (2006): 47.
28. There are at least three distortions in this account, which is taken
from Henry Koster’s Travels in Brazil (microform). Koster writes, “The priest-
hood is open to them [Indians]; but they do not take advantage of it*. I never
saw an Indian mechanic in any of the towns; there is no instance of a wealthy
Indian; rich mulattos and negroes are by no means rare” (120). The asterisked
footnote reads, “I heard, from good authority, that there are two instances of
Indians having been ordained as secular priests, and that both these individuals
died from excessive drinking.” The distortions are as follows: (1) the assertion
that there are negro clergymen when Koster is clear that the clergy is not open
to negroes; (2) the omission of the term mulatto from Hegel’s account; and
(3) the shifting from two individuals to a single one. It is not clear whether
Hegel read Koster’s book directly or the review in the “Quarterly Review” that
included the passage above (PSS, 460).
29. The inclusion of Africans in this unity is not certain. Hegel omits
any mention of mulattoes, or for that matter, any union that involves an Afri-
can. In the PWH, Hegel refers to Creoles as offspring of Europeans or Asian
with Americans. This is not consistent with the various usages of the term
by his sources. Koster and Maximilian will both describe a complex system
of classification. Maximilian uses the terms Portuguezes (natives of Portugal),
Brazileiros (“Brazilians, or Portugese born in Brazil, of more or less purity in
origin”), mulattoes (“union of whites with negroes”), mamalucos (“whites and
Indians, also called Mestics”), Negroes (“pure African Negroes”), Creoles (“born
of Negroes in Brazil”), Caribocos (“born of Negroes and Indians”), Caboclos
(“civilised” Indians), and Tapuyos (wild Indians) (28, 9). Koster describes a
similar schema except: he substitutes Creole whites for Brazileiros; Caboclos
refers to domestic instead of “civilised” Indians; Creole Negroes refers to free
Negroes; and mestizo is substituted for Caribocos (Koster [abridged], 174). I
should add that Koster’s account concerns only Caboclos, for he does not meet
any Tapuyos (Koster [microform], 395). Further, the only reference I have
found concerning the relations between Asians and Americans is a reference by
Maximilian to nine Chinese day laborers who were brought to Rio de Janeiro.
He indicates that “some of them have been converted and married to young
Indians” (243, 110).
30. Commentators have understood Hegel to be here dismissing proph-
ecy as if they knew what Hegel meant by the term. See G. A. Kelly, “Hegel’s
America”; Paul Franco, Hegel’s Philosophy of Freedom (New Haven: Yale Univer-
Hegel’s New World 131
Allegra de Laurentiis
Introduction
135
136 Allegra de Laurentiis
Aristotle, neither Cicero nor the Roman jurists, and still less
the Greek and Roman peoples, possessed this concept although
it alone is the source of Right. They knew well enough that
an Athenian, or a Roman citizen, an ingenuus, is free and that
there are free men and slaves; therefore they did not know
that man as man is free . . . that is, man as apprehended in
thought and as he apprehends himself in thought.9
While living matter is nature’s analog to the logical Concept, only think-
ing is the element proper to it—from its simplest form as self-feeling
soul to absolute knowing. Already in the closing pages of the Phenom-
enology, the Concept is referred to as spirit “in the form of Self [in
selbstischer Form].”13
In the lectures on ancient philosophy, Hegel argues that pre-Socratic
philosophizing already contains intuitions of the self-referential nature
of human thinking. For instance, the ancient thesis that knowledge is
a kind of reminiscence indicates awareness that all knowledge depends
logically upon self-knowledge, or that “the Concept remains at home
with itself in the course of its process.” And yet, from Anaximander to
Aristotle and the Roman philosophers we search in vain for a properly
conceptual grasp of the self. With the dissolution of Western antiquity,
those ancient intuitions metamorphose into the representational thinking
of religious monotheisms. Only modern philosophy would be able to
engage in the labor of grasping the self in the self’s own terms—that
is, conceptually.
As is well known, Hegel interprets the transition from Antiquity to
the Middle Ages and Modernity as a “becoming subjective” of spirit. This
does not indicate an increasing individualization but rather a growing
universalization of subjectivity away from mere singularity. For example,
the recognition of a right to individual satisfaction (as defined in the
“Morality” section of the Philosophy of Right)14 amounts to a universal-
ization of the singular will. This right to subjective particularity is then
characterized a few sections later as “the turning- and center-point in
the difference between antiquity and modern times.”15
To be sure, Hegel detects in Plato’s work early forms of the
conception of a necessary universalization of mere particularity. Yet he
also points out that this notion plays there always a negative role. Plato
would recognize subjective freedom only as a threat to the harmony of
ethical life. Since the kallipolis is supposed to embody universality, and
since singularity is in Plato’s eyes its logical contradiction, the affirmation
of individual interests cannot but represent a strident dissonance in the
universal harmony. Dikaiosune is only guaranteed by purging the state
of all singular and particular claims. Subjective freedom in Plato’s polis
is the enemy within.
Despite this, Hegel does encounter in the Republic signs of
Plato’s awareness of a potential compatibility between universality and
Spirit without the Form of Self 139
If indeed the ruler and the ruled in any city share the same
belief about who should rule, it is in this one [the temperate
140 Allegra de Laurentiis
Far from being a place of harmony and unbroken continuity with the
past, classical Athens is described by historians as a relatively self-contained
world of antagonism and strife. This both bears the unmistakable marks
of class struggle—not the essence Hegel focuses upon—and closely
resembles forms of antagonism that define modern civil society, that
is, the competition among particular interests and the conflict between
these and the common good.
While Hegel largely ignores Plato’s references to class struggle,
historians have often called attention to them. Some have called these
references “obsessive.”25 For example, Plato repeatedly characterizes oli-
Spirit without the Form of Self 141
Notes
which in turn consists of the fact that “the particularity of the agent is contained
and implemented in the action.”
15. W 7, §124, Remark.
16. Even Allan Bloom, in The Republic of Plato (New York: Basic Books,
1968), seems to consider Plato’s argumentative strategy in this case baffling. He
both stresses the fundamental role of the parallelism in the overall argument of
the Republic (344) and admits that the book contains no satisfactory justification
for it: “A city, like a man, desires wealth, needs food, and deliberates. But a city
cannot reproduce or philosophize. . . . In this sense a city cannot be properly
compared to a man” (376).
17. See Republic 368d-369, 434d-435b, and 435e-436. At 368e Socrates
argues that, since “a city is larger than a single man . . . perhaps . . . there is more
justice in the larger thing, and it will be easier to learn what it is.” At 435e we
learn that “[i]t would be ridiculous for anyone to think that spiritedness didn’t
come to be in cities from such individuals as the Thracians, Scythians, and oth-
ers who live to the north of us . . . or that the same isn’t true of the love of
learning, which is mostly associated with our part of the world, or the love of
money which . . . is conspicuously displayed by the Phoenicians and Egyptians.”
The quotations are from Grube’s and Reeve’s translation in J. M. Cooper, ed.,
Plato. Complete Works (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997).
18. GW 18, 48.
19. W 7, 26.
20. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. A. W. Wood, trans., H.
B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
21. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. and trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clar-
endon, 1952).
22. W 7, 24.
23. Republic 431e-432.
24. Enz., §114.
25. See in particular: A. Fuks, “Plato and the Social Question: The Problem
of Poverty and Riches in the Republic,” Ancient Society 8 (1977): 49–83; M.
H. Jameson, “Agriculture and Slavery in Classical Athens,” Classical Journal 73
(1977–78): 122–45; G. E. M. de Ste. Croix, The Class Struggle in the Ancient
Greek World (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981). De Ste Croix (p. 70)
refers approvingly to Fuks’s talk of Plato’s “obsessive conviction” that “the tense
political atmosphere and acute civil strife of his day were the direct consequence
of increasing contrasts between wealth and poverty. In particular Plato realized
that an oligarchy . . . will actually be two cities, one of the poor and the other
of the rich, ‘always plotting against each other’([Republic] 551d).”
26. Republic, 555d.
27. Ibid. 565–57.
28. Ibid., 414c-d.
29. Ibid.
30. W 7, §206, Remark.
31. Ibid., §299, Remark.
32. Ibid., §206, Remark.
152 Allegra de Laurentiis
Jason Howard
History may be moved by many things in Hegel, but few would single
out ethical obligations as a core contributing factor. I propose to recon-
sider this assumption by examining the role of moral imputation in
Hegel’s conception of historical progress, and by “moral imputation” I
mean, very briefly, those experiences whereby agents confront their own
culpability.1 I believe taking up this issue will help answer two important
questions. First, in what sense do ethical obligations “move” history’?
Second, in what sense can these obligations have any substantial ethi-
cal import if they are destined to change as the historical actuality of
self-conscious communities alter? Simply put: Are ethical commitments
of only instrumental worth for Hegel, stepping stones of ancillary
value through which history reveals its own absolute telos, or are they
something more, and if so, what could this “more” signify? What does
Hegel mean in his lectures on history when he says that world history
“occupies a higher ground” (VpG, 67/90) than that of morality, yet
also insists at the same time that “the responsibility and moral value of
the individual [Schuld und Wert des Individuums], remains untouched,”
and is shut away from the clamor of history (VpG, 37/54).2 One of the
first things that needs to be clarified here is the extent to which ethi-
cal obligations are an inevitable aspect of our historicity. This chapter
addresses this issue by demonstrating how Hegel balances the necessity
155
156 Jason Howard
description whose focus is not simply the state but also the underlying
duties that moor the state as a determinate kind of cultural existence.
Moreover, I believe the scope as well as the necessity of this moral
dynamic of disintegration and transformation can be seen most clearly in
the struggles of ancient Greece and developing Europe to contend with
the reality of individual accountability.8 And so, far from contradicting
his later orientation in the Lectures on the Philosophy of History, I believe
the Phenomenology specifies a level of normative experience and perspec-
tive that Hegel valued throughout his career, and which is necessary to
appreciate the full scope of his account of history.
Before turning to Hegel’s Phenomenology, I want to offer a few
brief clarifying remarks on how the notion of moral imputation, or what
Hegel calls Schuld or böse Gewissen, operates in Hegel’s texts.9 As Hegel
states much earlier in his System of Ethical Life, the experience of guilt
refers to an “inner negation.”10 It surfaces from the defiance of a com-
mandment whose violation brings the subject immediately into conflict
with the sources of his or her own objective existence. The sense of
guilt arises on behalf of an outer negation, an actual defilement of the
“real” as it exists in the norms of culture. The objective negation then
returns as an inward negation of the subject. In the System of Ethical
Life Hegel describes this moment of inner negation as the implicit arrival
of freedom insofar as negativity appears here in its transformation from
real negation to “ideal” negation, or negativity as a mode of thinking.
I want to describe how this individual experience of negativity disrupts
both the security of Greek ethical life, as well as the boundless confidence
of Enlightenment rationality. It is important to realize at the outset that
what I propose to chart, the experience of moral imputation, is experi-
enced in different ways by agents depending on the historical world they
dwell within. The most substantial distinction is that between objective
and subjective guilt. The objective experience of guilt is defined by the
virtual absence of any rationalizing role for subjective intentions—that
one’s fate is determined tout court by the will of the Gods or the state.
The subjective sense of guilt, which is the modern sense of guilt we are
familiar with, locates the experience of guilt solely at the level of sub-
jective intentions and the personal knowledge of one’s circumstances.11
As our discussion of Antigone in Ancient Greece and the perils of the
French Revolution will make clear, although the experience of guilt is
expressed differently depending on what historical world we examine, its
relevancy for the consciousness of freedom as historical self-determination
is indispensable, and the most visceral way in which agents come to real-
ize the implications of their own singular individuality. Quoting Stephen
Houlgate: “History is thus the process whereby human beings come
The Historicity of Ethical Categories 159
II
Hegel begins his analysis of spirit in the Phenomenology with the histori-
cal word of the ancient Greek city-state.13 The significant aspect to note
here is how ethical life rests upon and reaches actualization through
natural characteristics; for example, age, character, and most signifi-
cantly gender. These natural distinctions are endowed with a sense that
is directly related to the larger organization of social/ethical existence,
the intelligibility of which is seen as an extension of the larger cosmos
and the natural order intrinsic to it.14
What is being examined here, as Hegel points out, is not the
subjective consciousness of singular agents per se, but the constitutive
elements that determine the “meaning” of one’s existence as this is
forged in the inseparable binds of intersubjective (living) communities,
or self-consciousness in general: “Absolute spirit realized in the plurality
of distinct consciousnesses definitely existing” (PhG, 466/292). The first
thing to recognize at this level of natural ethical life is that issues of
moral adjudication rarely, if ever, reach explicit thematization. However,
it would be a serious mistake to assume from this lack of thematization
that moral concerns are absent. Rather, these concerns are embedded in
one’s social identity, shaping the certainty of one’s existence as cultural
agent (PhG, 467/293).15
Natural ethical life flourishes through the continued interaction
of the “family” and the “state” as organizations of one social totality.
Although it is true that each sphere has its own priorities and purposes,
the first being the exclusive preserve of women and the other that of men,
these spheres do not exist in separation but as two facets of the same
world that “confirm” and “substantiate” one another (PhG, 481/303).
The state subsists on behalf of members who knowingly participate in
all the concerns of objective social organization (the sphere of human
law), while the life of the family persists through the folk wisdom of
familial traditions handed down from generation to generation (the
sphere of divine law).
These two spheres of human and divine law work to ground the
meaning or point of all natural differences through stipulating, in two
160 Jason Howard
elemental ways, what these differences mean for beings who also think
the difference and do not just live it.16 As Hegel specifies, these natural
determinations supply the “operative individuality” (betätigenden Individu-
alität), while the “universal actuality” (allgemeinen Wirklichkeit) of this
individuality is lived in the duties of nation and family (PhG, 479/302).
As a result, the ethical concerns that underwrite ancient Greece are never
explicit as distinct moral obligations since cultural existence is itself a
totality of harmonious norms whose index runs so deep its vehicle is
biological facticity itself. Consequently, reflection on these norms is not
only superfluous, but would be construed as sacrilegious.
In their allegiance to human and divine laws, the state and the
family rely on subjects in different ways. The real difficulty lies in the
fact that each recognizes the duties of individual agency in only one way,
which prohibits any robust notion of a mediated social identity from
being fulfilled within the day to day concerns of cultural existence. The
fault does not lie with either the family or the state, but the identity
of both as a single functioning world: each recognizes singular agents
in different ways, one as an explicit vehicle of universality, while the
other as the preserve of individual agency through familial piety. It is
when human beings seek to negotiate or mediate the demands of both
spheres to accommodate their own experience as singular agents, their
existence as either this man or this woman, that irreconcilable difficul-
ties emerge. As Wilfried Goossens puts it, with natural ethical life we
have two forms of self-consciousness (man and woman) that determine
themselves according to only one facet of their substantiality, and so
“not only the knowledge of but also the ignorance of a part of their
own substance (the other law),” is embodied in each which creates the
conditions for a “fatal internal contradiction.”17
In order to press home his point about the potential problem of
(natural) attribution and social organization, Hegel turns to the classic
tale of Sophocles’ Antigone. As a woman, Antigone must venerate her
brother’s death to fulfill the customs of the family, for as keeper of the
familial order she recognizes that the death of her brother demands
acknowledgment. However, in Antigone’s case such action is prohibited
by the state, the law of men, since her brother is seen as a traitor to
the state; consequently, his body is to be left unburied as a sign of his
transgression. What, then, is Antigone to do? Her identity as woman
demands she do her duty and bury her brother. To refuse would be
to relinquish the intelligibility of her own identity, since as woman her
gender transcribes her into an order that directly supervenes upon the
truth of whom she recognizes herself to be. This has the effect of forcing
the simple immediacy of her duty as woman, the truth of her essential
The Historicity of Ethical Categories 161
III
IV
Notes
1. I use the term moral imputation rather than ethical because I want
to draw attention to the peculiar difficulty that arises when agents are forced
to assess the measure of their own accountability, rather than the security and
meaning they experience when fulfilling the duties imposed by cultural life
(which I take Sittlichkeit to indicate). For an account of some of the different
roles the concept of morality plays for Hegel, consider the following: B. Bitsch,
Sollensbegriff und Moralitätkritik bei Hegel. Interpretationen zur “Wissenschaft
der Logik,” “Phänomenologie,” und “Rechtsphilosophie” (Bonn: Bouvier, 1977);
Roland Pelzer, “Studien über Hegels ethische Theoreme,” Archiv für Philosophie
13 (1964): 3–49; Allen Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought (NewYork: Cambridge
University Press, 1990); and Robert Williams, Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on
the Other (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992).
2. Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree (Amherst, NY: Pro-
metheus Books, 1991). Hereafter referred to as VpG with the English pagination
preceding the German, Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte, Werke 12
(Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1999).
3. See Lewis P. Hinchman, “On Reconciling Happiness and Autonomy:
An Interpretation of Hegel’s Moral Philosophy,” The Owl of Minerva 23
(1991–92): 29–48. Hinchman points out that the various shapes in Hegel’s
Phenomenology all disintegrate because they sense, but are unable to articulate,
the missing moral dimension of their identity, 39–40. My own interpretation
tries to make this idea more explicit at the level of historical transitions from
one world of spirit to another.
4. Saul Tobias explores the limitations with taking Hegel’s master and
slave dialectic as a model of recognition in his article “Hegel and the Politics of
Recognition,” The Owl of Minerva 38 (2006–07): 101–26. I agree with Tobias
that recognition should not be separated from a process of self-determination;
a fact that becomes even clearer once the importance of moral imputation for
Hegel is discerned.
The Historicity of Ethical Categories 171
Vol. I, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), 188. For
the German see volume 13 of Hegel’s Sämmtliche Werke, 247.
12. Stephen Houlgate, Freedom, Truth, and History: An Introduction to
Hegel’s Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 1991), 27.
13. Hegel is quite explicit about the fact that that all of the other forms
of conscious experience up to spirit have been abstractions of sorts, which
presuppose the reality of spirit as the originary ground of their existence (PhG,
459/288). I agree with John O’Donohue that these previous forms of spirit
cannot be seen as actual presuppositions of spirit, but are “decisive moments” in
the unfolding of experience that are unable to successfully stabilize themselves,
pushing beyond themselves toward their underlying reality, spirit proper. Each is
an attempt to thematize an element of spirit’s development, which is necessary
to show the extent to which spirit is self-grounding, yet they do not “exist,”
per se, in their own right, but are reflective moments that illustrate the inability
of restricting the vitality of spirit to a single moment. See John O’Donohue,
Person als Vermittlung: Die Dialektik von Individualität und Allgemeinheit in
Hegels “Phänomenologie des Geistes” (Mainz: Matthias-Grünewald, 1993), Part
III, section 11, 278–87, esp. 284. O’Donohue argues that the concept of “per-
son” is the conceptual cornerstone of the Phenomenology, mediating the poles
of universality and individuality in the development of spirit into concreteness.
I largely agree with this approach to the Phenomenology and take a similar per-
spective in my own reading.
14. This process of spiritual development is not, contrary to what Kojève
thinks, only a recapitulation of the master-slave dialectic (ch. IV, section A,
“Independence and Dependence of Self-consciousness: Lordship and Bondage”).
First, from the point of view of how spirit actually experiences its own unfold-
ing, although it is true that elements of this “struggle to the death” periodically
emerge, notably in the section on the French Revolution, the agents involved
in this movement do not see themselves as either “slaves” or “masters,” but
as fitting into a meaningful totality from which they discover the import of
their own singularity. The conflict is one of self-alienation, and not a fight to
the death, since every affirmation of singularity (being-for-itself) also singular-
izes the spiritual community, forcing self-conscious agents into making sense of
their essence on their own terms. It is the impossibility of doing so that sets
the stage for self-consciousness to transcend its own singularity through the act
of forgiveness, in which the move to religion as the awareness of spirit as an
absolute totality is made (ch. VII). See Alexandre Kojève, Introduction to the
Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. J. H. Nichols
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1980).
15. Terry Pinkard summarizes this point well by stating that the Greeks
did not confuse “is” and “ought.” “For them, what they ought to do followed
from the way things are, from the background understanding that this is ‘the
way things are done,’ which for them was a fact about social life.” See Terry
Pinkard, Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1994), 140. Although I agree with Pinkard’s initial description
of this phase of spirit, he downplays the role of guilt in effecting the transition
The Historicity of Ethical Categories 173
I care about making the good choice because it matters to me personally. The
underlying thematic concern is the attempt to unearth how and why it is that
these concepts matter. It is this search that acts to differentiate the two poles,
that of pure universality and moral imputation, whose unsuccessful resolution
will result in the terror of the French Revolution.
23. Initially the “good” is what is universal, unquestioned and objective,
stipulating the right way to live from the wrong, whereas the “bad” is identified
with what is contingent, subjective, and relative. Thus, the good is what defines
the meaning of objective reality, while the bad is what contradicts this reality,
that which calls it into question (PhG, 519–20/327–28). Within this opposi-
tion, which permeates the entirety of self-conscious existence, the acceptable
is distinguished from the unacceptable; the good is seen as that which appeals
directly to all, while the bad exists as a force of exclusion, promoting personal
welfare at the expense of social harmony.
24. Kainz makes the remark that “good” and “bad” function in this sec-
tion as equivalent judgments to what does or does not cultivate subjectivity, yet
it should be added that in the beginning of culture both good and bad contain
their own warrants, they are “objective” and viewed as inherently meaningful;
they are not attributes of the subject. They do eventually become “terms” of the
subject, and with this identification lays the ruin of their conceptual legitimacy.
See Howard P. Kainz, Hegel’s Phenomenology, Part II. The Evolution of Ethical
and Religious Consciousness to the Absolute Standpoint (Ohio: Ohio University
Press, 1983), 44.
25. Pure insight and belief succeed in reestablishing the primacy of the true
and the good through the rudimentary conceptual scheme of self and not-self:
belief takes inwardness as good and externality as bad, while pure insight takes
inwardness as true and externality as false. The compact solidity of the good
and the true from which our analysis of culture began, has become completely
separate domains of experience, each of which approach finite existence only in
reference to its own pure vocabulary of universality (PhG, 578/370).
26. What should not be overlooked is how each universal shape of the pure
I (that of belief and pure insight) arises out of an ethical crisis of commitments,
reducing the truth of this existence to structures of pure consciousness. These
two molds of universality totalize the lives of self-conscious agency, trading the
reality of singular existence for an explanation of what it means to exist.
27. As Axel Honneth explains: “For Hegel, then, the real challenge posed
by the age must have been the question generated by the Revolution, namely,
how that sphere of abstract freedom which had been won through political
struggle could itself be embedded in an overarching context so that it would
not unleash its atomizing capacity ad infinitum, but rather become a positive
formative element in an ethical community.” See Axel Honneth, “Atomism and
Ethical Life: On Hegel’s Critique of the French Revolution,” Philosophy and
Social Criticism 14 (1988): 359–68, 361–62.
28. Hegel describes this frightful process in his Lectures on the Philosophy
of History as follows: “The principle of the Freedom of the Will, therefore,
asserted itself against existing right. . . . The political condition of France at that
The Historicity of Ethical Categories 175
Nathan Ross
177
178 Nathan Ross
meaning that they isolate the activity of individuals from the pervasive
teleological organization of their common existence;1 his (mechanistic
understanding of labor) places these pursuits in contrast to Hegel’s
organic grasp of “ethical life” during this era. And yet I will argue that
Hegel comes to the paradoxical insight in these writings that the modern
state is a more pervasively organic form of ethical life to the degree that
it includes and does not negate or stifle this mechanism. Thus, it will be
necessary to consider this mechanism thesis from three perspectives:
first, it must be clarified how labor is inherently mechanistic; then I
will demonstrate how Hegel includes this mechanism in his historical
conception of ethical life, and hence grasps it as contributing to the
actualization of freedom; finally, I will consider how this force has the
tendency to “become positive” according to Hegel and thus embody a
one-sided form of historical development that is destructive of ethical
life. The strength of Hegel’s historical vision here in the Jena texts, as
opposed to his later philosophy of history, is perhaps the very fact that
he leaves this possibility open, that he sees in the forces of the modern
economy both the possibility for a deeper and more pervasive kind of
social freedom than that of previous historical epochs, as well as the
possibility for a profoundly alienating form of progress that is destructive
of any vision of human society in which we could be at home.
Modern Ethicality
In both of these 1802 texts, Natural Right and Ethicality, Hegel devotes
extensive attention to the notion of civil society,5 that is, to the place of
The Mechanization of Labor 181
ideality of the concept, the un-free class dwells in the bifurcated extremes
of the concept, “the reflection of absolute unity.”
As Hegel makes clear in his discussion of the structure of the con-
cept of ethicality, the structure is whole only in this entire process, that
is, the concept consists in the bifurcation of its moments and the taking
back of these moments into a vision of their unity. In Greek ethical life,
the speculative form of the concept implies that the un-free class only
takes part in the ethical thanks to the free class, and the free class only
through the un-free class. But although both classes make up integral
moments in the creation of ethicality, of a functioning social whole in
which there is a vision of freedom, only one of the classes enjoys the
“intuition” of such freedom. Freedom, here in this context, means giving
up one’s individuality for the sake of the whole, subsisting as much as
possible in the moment of universality within the concept. “A free death,”
the willingness to die for the city and the courage that goes along with
such a stance, are the virtues that stem from such a freedom.8
Hegel’s description of the nature of the political class in ancient
Greece and his identification of this class with “Tapferkeit” demonstrates
the manner in which his conception of ancient ethicality is essentially
based in an account of “political virtue.” However, it will become clear
in what follows that by the time that Hegel wrote this text, he no longer
believes that such political virtues as the Greek Tapferkeit could serve as
the constitutive force of modern political life.9 This shift in his thought
departs from the realization that this class and the form of ethicality
that it represents is inferior to that of the modern state, precisely to the
degree that the modern state includes the notion of bourgeois freedom,
that is, the development of a more universal form of freedom that stems
from the pursuit of economic activities that stood within Greek society
under the aspect of the un-free class.
For Hegel, the departure of the ancient city-state means a funda-
mental change within “ethicality,” and a shift in what it means to be
free. He calls this change the “tragedy within the ethical.” He writes:
“In the loss of absolute ethicality and the degradation of the noble class,
the two hitherto separate classes have become equal, and with the end of
slavery comes the end of freedom as well” (GW IV, 456).10 But Hegel
argues in the course of this essay that the rise of bourgeois equality does
not represent a simple death of the ethical life. The notion of tragedy
does not imply a simple loss of the ethicality expressed in the ancient
Greek state, but a movement of “sacrifice” aimed at regaining whole-
ness. The soul dies to make itself one with the body, but in so doing
it imbues the body with a life of its own. Hegel borrows a phrase from
Plato in calling ethicality “an immortal animal in which body and soul
The Mechanization of Labor 183
are eternally giving birth to each other” (GW IV, 462). This mixing of
the “free” and the “un-free” classes represents not just a moment of
leveling, but a moment of further, more developed and pervasive dif-
ferentiation within the syllogistic whole called ethicality. In the hitherto
developed conception of ethicality in terms of two classes, the concept
had two moments, one of pure unity (the intuition of freedom) and
one of bifurcated unity (the governed life of the worker or merchant).
This form of ethicality must cease, “sacrifice itself,” in order to generate
a more pervasive unity between the moment of unity and difference.
Hegel poses the question: What would happen if the organizing
principle of the second, un-free class were allowed to divide itself off and
posit itself as autonomous? Could such a social whole ever organize itself
in such a way as to become a form of ethicality? In becoming indepen-
dent in this manner, this class makes one of the conceptual extremes into
the unifying medium of ethical life. The negative unity of the concepts,
“desire-work” and “work-enjoyment,” remains the governing principle
of this class, but this principle is allowed to organize itself as much as
possible into a rational whole (what Hegel would later call a “system of
needs”). This results in the concept of “bourgeois freedom,” a kind of
freedom that no longer consists in the sacrifice of the individual to the
universal, but in the protection of individuality as a “universal” right.
Such a freedom “has the unity of the concept only as an imitated, nega-
tive independence, namely as the freedom of the individual” (GW IV,
461). In such a conception, freedom would mean the absolute right of
the individual to work and own, the right to life and property and to
pursue prosperity. Hegel makes it clear that he considers such a form
of freedom a mere shadow of the form of freedom represented by the
Greek model of ethicality, and yet he writes, “[E]ven if the essence of
ethicality views this [bourgeois freedom] as something foreign, still it
intuits it and is in spirit one with it” (GW IV, 461). This cryptic phrase
seems crucial to understanding what Hegel views as the relation between
“ethicality” and bourgeois freedom within civil society. But what does
he mean by calling the latter a negative reflection of the former? How
does this clearly lesser form of modern freedom relate to the model of
ethicality he has developed up to this point?
We have up to now two conceptions of freedom, the freedom of
the individual to give up its singularity and think and act as part of a
unified social fabric, and the freedom of the individual to pursue its own
interests and see its achievements protected as a form of right. He tells
us that the first form must learn to recognize itself in the latter and be
“in spirit one with it.” For Hegel already in this period, this is only pos-
sible in and through a state that allows civil society to develop itself by
184 Nathan Ross
In the two texts that I have treated up to now, Hegel treats the
genesis of civil society under two different methods, the System of Ethi-
cality developing the concept of labor first outside of the ethical whole,
the Natural Right essay treating civil society as a historical force arising
out of the decline of ancient civilization. But there are certain common
methodological points that connect these two texts from the same year.
In describing work as tending toward “mechanization,” Hegel describes
the way that work, by its own dialectic, leads to a kind of concep-
tual externality: the extremes of “desire-work” and “work-enjoyment”
(which were unified in the first potency) only relate together through
some kind of external mediation. As the division of labor progresses,
the labor process is only “whole” in a mediating term that escapes the
consciousness of the person engaging in work. Labor stands for a form
of teleology that is increasingly divided against itself and in need of some
external conceptual mediation. Thus, we have a key to understanding
what Hegel means in Natural Right when he describes the working
and trading class as the “inorganic nature of ethicality” and argues that
this class dwells in the “extremes of the concept” (GW IV, 461). Since
this class dwells in the extremes of the concept, it lacks the “intuition
of freedom” inherent to the political class in the ancient world. For
work to be mechanical thus means for it to represent an abstract, or
one-sided, form of mediation within the conceptual whole that Hegel
calls ethicality. And yet it is one of Hegel’s most important discoveries
of these writings, both into the nature of the speculative concept and
into the nature of social wholes, that the intuition of freedom can only
grow in an organic sense through “sacrificing” itself to the divided form
of externality and creating a new, more fundamental unity out of this
bifurcation. This means that the kind of teleology present in political
action, its ability to accomplish its goals in a way that arises out of and
is immanent to the movement of society, will be greater if this mechani-
cal, divided teleology of the laboring aspect of society becomes a free
factor within the state.14
Up to now, I have discussed the Jena writings mostly in such a
manner as to illustrate the positive ethical importance that Hegel attributes
to the mechanistic aspect of civil society, its contribution to the state as
a form of ethicality. But at the same time, these texts articulate a sharp
critique of the contradictions that Hegel sees as latent in the modern
economy, and these contradictions will also be diagnosed through con-
sidering civil society as a mechanistic aspect within the cohesive whole
that Hegel calls ethicality. In order to arrive at Hegel’s critique of these
contradictions, I will turn toward the notion of positivity that Hegel
develops in the Natural Right essay.
186 Nathan Ross
and such a misrecognition will then allow one part of the ethical fabric
to dominate another and stifle the organism. Thus, Hegel embraces the
“formalism” of the legal sciences out of his notion of the organic: a
living whole is one in which the “form” supersedes the content, where
the form assimilates its content to it. But even in a living whole there
is a tendency toward positivity, when, in the growth of the whole, the
customs and laws drift apart and no longer reflect each other. This mani-
fests itself in a set of laws that contradict the actual lives of the people
governed by them. Hegel argues that such a system of laws becomes
mechanical, in that it relates parts to a whole in such a way that these
parts do not have an understanding of their relation to the whole.16
Hegel even anticipates Marx in arguing that such positive laws become
a means by which one class in society dominates another.
But for Hegel, such positivity does not simply result out of the
misformulation of laws, or out of scientific errors; it results also out
of the “material” of society itself. This becomes clear in the ensuing
discussion of where such legal positivity comes from. He claims that
positivity of laws comes not just from the past, that is, from a society
clinging to outdated laws, but also from new developments that do not
proceed in a properly organic way:
I will argue that Hegel means here to claim, adding to his earlier notion
of positivity, that false positivity dwells not just in the maintenance of
the feudal order in German states, but also in the very tendencies of
the new industrial economy. Positivity, or the legal form that does not
adequately express the ethical dimension of a society, can result not just
from a people outgrowing its laws, but also from a one-sided form of
development inherent in civil society. Civil society has a tendency to posit
as absolute the rights of a class that has a merely negative, individualistic
conception of right. In doing so, it posits a subordinate moment of the
social development as an absolute purpose of the development. The form
of right is positive, or mechanical, to the degree that it posits a purely
quantitative factor of economic life as a politically determinative force
188 Nathan Ross
within the social whole; this latter aspect will become clearer through
a discussion of Hegel’s analysis of modern class structures in the System
of Ethicality.
In this text, Hegel’s thesis on the positivity of civil society takes
on a new, more specific dimension. In a later passage from the text
(GW V, 349–57) Hegel gives a discussion of the class structures that
arise out of the modern economy, analyzing how the dialectic of labor
in a free market economy creates a measureless degree of inequality. In
the Natural Right essay, Hegel has simply spoken of the “commercial
class” (Erwerbestand), but in this latter section of System of Ethical
Life, he argues that when this commercial aspect of society is allowed to
develop in a relatively autonomous manner, it engenders distinct classes
within itself, classes that are determined not by the political agency of
individuals, but by their quantity of ownership. But the initially quanti-
tative differences within the commercial class convert into “relations of
dominance” between its members. Differences in the quantitative level
of wealth between free citizens in a free market economy will lead to
distinct relations of power and agency, an owning class and a working
class.17 This class differentiation is different from the two classes of ancient
Greek society distinguished in the Natural Right essay, in that here the
distinction does not take place according to conceptual moments, for
the classes have the same political rights and the same basic motivating
principle in their activities. And yet the purely quantitative difference
within the commercial class leads to a kind of domination that is all the
more blind and ethically alienating. In the Natural Right essay, it was
posited that the commercial class represented the separated “extremes of
the concept” and that the extremes were only mediated by the activity
of labor, rather than in an ethical intuition. But now in the System of
Ethical Life, it seems that Hegel would claim that through the formation
of quantitative inequalities within the commercial sector, this relative
conceptual unity could become sundered, and lose even the external
mediation described earlier.
In this state of affairs the well-off bring forth riches that are
connected to the deepest poverty; for in the separation, labor
on both sides becomes universal, objective; on the one side is
ideal universality; on the other side it is real, mechanical, and
this purely quantitative, conceptually individuated inorganic
aspect of labor is the most elevated brutishness [die höchste
Roheit]. (GW V, 354)
the owning class, such as what Hegel describes here, these conceptual
extremes no longer describe separate subjective aspects of a cohesive
labor process, but separate social functions. Individual groups of human
beings become pinned, as it were, to one side of the whole teleology of
the labor process and pursue this one side with a measureless intensity.
One class in society is completely absorbed by speculation upon the
cultivation of new forms of luxury, while another group is immersed
in the mechanical production of the materials needed to fulfill such
speculations. The physical aspect of labor becomes increasingly mechani-
cal, that is, subjectively detached from the enjoyment of the product of
labor. The mental aspect of the production process, on the other hand,
takes on the aspect of an infinite speculation on the creation of needs,
which Hegel calls a completely “empty ideality” that can be cultivated
to infinity.
Hegel sees potentially disastrous political consequences in this
quantitative inequality within the commercial class. When groups within
society become so confined to one side of the labor process, they become
incapable of any intuition of the whole as an organic system. In ancient
Greek ethical life, Hegel writes, at least the commercial class and the
aristocracy could pray to the gods of the city;18 but in modernity, with
the progressive development of economic inequality on purely economic
grounds the commercial class becomes incapable of submitting itself to
any divinity outside of its sphere.19 And with this inability, Hegel argues,
the very possibility of a common ethicality disappears, in that separate
members of society become so occupied with a socially mediated material
prosperity that they are not capable of cultivating the kind of political
institutions that make for fulfilling their desires.
It is clear from the dialectic Hegel describes here in this section
of Ethicality that the political problem of the positivity of civil society
emerges from within the very dialectic of labor. The tendency of the
labor process to lead to increasingly mechanical forms of labor leads
to the creation of a class structure in which political consciousness is
destroyed and replaced by a kind of blind pursuit of economic devel-
opment. Hegel turns this incapacity of civil society into a defense of a
higher political moment in society that hinders the measureless pursuit
of wealth and the development of excessive inequalities primarily through
a system of taxation. As in the Natural Right essay, he views the role
of the state in relation to the commercial activities of its citizens not
only as that of protecting the property rights that make commerce pos-
sible, but that of limiting or hindering commerce so as to keep it from
propagating socially destructive levels of inequality between citizens.
But for Hegel the state’s limitation of economic development is not a
merely negative or restrictive factor, for it is the giving of a measure to
190 Nathan Ross
Notes
in the direction of some repeatable labor process that transcends the actual
consumption of the worked on object.
3. It would be easy to compare the two conceptions of labor here to the
analysis of labor in the master-slave dialectic of Hegel’s Phenomenology (1807).
The first form of work from Ethicality is taken up there in the analysis of the
master, who merely negates the object as something immediate, while the second
form of work is taken up there in the case of the slave, who subordinates his
desire to negate the object in working upon it. The Phenomenology makes clear
moreover that the formation of spirit, its acquiring of a conception of its own
freedom and of its right, is based in the work of the slave. This seems parallel
to the manner in which Hegel here develops the notion of “right” out of the
second conception of labor.
4. In discussing “right” within this section on work, Hegel does not
think that he is giving an exhaustive account of what right is. He will make clear
later in the text that these relations do not yet belong to the sphere of “ethical-
ity.” Instead, what Hegel does here is to demonstrate how human involvement
with nature leads to certain determinate social relations, and to the formation
of a primitive conception of right. Only later, in discussing industrial pursuits
(cf. GW V, 350–57) as a part of “ethicality” will Hegel demonstrate how this
basic conception of equality and security in one’s possessions can exist as part
of a sustainable social body. Thus, in the language of Hegel’s later philosophy
of objective spirit, this dialectic of labor belongs to the realm of abstract right
rather than “civil society.” But nevertheless, this basic account of how human
labor transforms itself from a simple teleological activity into a mechanical and
social process will remain implicit in Hegel’s account of the nature of civil
society as a “potency of the ethical.” Later in the Ethicality essay, he discusses
civil society (a “system of needs”) as a moment in ethical life, and here too he
speaks of the increasing mechanization of the labor process and of a one-sided
notion of bourgeois right. Civil society begins, as it were, not with natural labor
but with labor that has already attained to the second potency, and its correct
account assumes the results of this dialectic of natural labor.
5. Hegel did not yet use the term civil society (bürgerliche Gesellschaft)
until the 1817 Encyclopedia. However, since these texts are largely occupied with
the issue of economic activities and the sphere of social involvements, rights,
and institutions entailed by them, I have chosen to use this term here for the
sake of expediency, since it makes clear the contrast between social/economic
aspects and political aspects that Hegel is working with in these texts.
6. Throughout Hegel’s Bern and Frankfurt writings, he often compares
the organic structure of ancient political community to the mechanistic nature
of modern social relations. However, it seems to me that the new element here
in these Jena texts is the manner in which he grasps the logic of mechanism
and organism not as utterly antinomical, but as two forms of processuality that
can coexist.
7. When Hegel here explains that the “un-free” or laboring class dwells
in the separated “extremes” of the concept, I believe this can be explained
by reference to the prior treatment of work in the System of Ethicality, where
192 Nathan Ross
able insofar as it can actually be viewed as a factor that leads to more cohesive
integration within society.
12. In a rather parenthetical context, Ludwig Siep gives an excellent articu-
lation of this sense in which Hegel uses the term organism within the Natural
Right essay: “Paradoxerweise enthält gerade der Begriff des Organischen—der
immer wieder als romantisch und totalitaer kritisiert wurde—die ‘liberalen’ Züge
der hegelschen Staatsphilosophie” (Praktische Philosophie im deutschen Idealismus,
168). In the footnote Siep expands upon the meaning of the organic within
Hegel’s political thought: “Im Begriff des Organischen hat Hegel nicht nur die
Einheit, sondern stets auch die Selbstständigkeit der Teile und das Vermögen, das
Ganze gerade in ihrer besonderen Funktion zu repräsentieren, zu denken versucht.”
Needless to say, this conception of the organic is completely consonant with the
notion that I am developing here. Since, however, my work is primarily interested
in a definition of the mechanistic, rather than the organic, the point remains to
be made that the organic must be thought of as containing or integrating the
mechanistic forms of social existence within it.
13. Hegel admits that there are two ways in which the state limits civil
society (GW IV, 451): advertent and inadvertent. An example of an inadvertent
limitation would be the fighting of a war, which conscripts members of the
working class and absorbs taxes. An example of an advertent limitation would
be taxation of the wealthy intended to improve the lives of the poor. Hegel’s
point is that any action of the state that limits the development of bourgeois
interests is one that serves to give measure to the inherent measurelessness of
the civil society, which tends toward ever greater social disparity.
14. In the work of Herder and perhaps also the earlier works of Hegel
the figure of mechanism stood for the danger of the state in interfering with
the “organic” development of society. Frederick Beiser gives an excellent account
of this aspect of Romantic political theory. Cf. Enlightenment, Revolution, and
Romanticism (Cambridge; Harvard University Press, 1992), 236–39. But here
for Hegel the figure of mechanism stands for a principle of development latent
in society; the state can only become organic by allowing this mechanism to
subsist and yet drawing determinate limits on its activities. Hegel’s critique of
mechanism, from henceforth in his writings, will revolve around an attempt
to distinguish the functions of the state from the “measureless” developments
associated with the modern economy.
15. Hegel’s term potency is derivative of Schelling’s nature philosophy,
which uses this term to designate a developmental phase within the genesis
of a systematic whole, a fragment in which the whole is visible at some phase
of its organization. Hegel seems to use the term here in a somewhat different
manner to designate each of the subsystems that make up a social whole, such
as the family, the economy, and political institutions.
16. “The historical recognition of laws demonstrates . . . that there is now
lacking in the living present an understanding [of the laws] and the meaning is
lacking, even if through the form of law, and by way of the fact that the laws
still represent the interests of some factions and these factions have attached their
existence to these laws, these [laws] still have force and power” (GW IV, 481).
194 Nathan Ross
17. “This necessary inequality that establishes itself inside the commercial
class and within all of the specialized branches of commerce brings forth a rela-
tion of dominance [Herrschaftsverhältnis] by way of its quantitative make-up,
which only relates to degrees and is not capable of any other determination
than that of degree; the individual, immensely wealthy one becomes a power,
he sublates the form of pervasive physical dependence, to be of a particular and
not a universal nature” (GW V, 353–54).
18. Cf. Natural Right III; GW IV, 462.
19. “The foremost character of the commercial class, that it is capable
of an organic, absolute intuition, and of respect for an albeit foreign divin-
ity, falls away; and the bestiality of disdain for everything higher emerges; the
wisdom-less, the purely universal, the mass of wealth is determinative; and the
absolute bond of the people, the ethical has disappeared, and the people dis-
solved” (GW V, 354).
10
Mark Tunick
Introduction
Hegel claims that democracy was necessary for the ancient Athenians but
is inappropriate for a modern state. My purpose is to clarify this claim
by spelling out its underlying assumptions. I also hope to indicate how
Hegel’s views on democracy draw us into a larger controversy concern-
ing Hegel’s philosophy of history.
The larger controversy is about the extent to which Hegel’s approach
to history is empirical. On the one hand, Hegel is critical of original
historians who merely describe the events they experience or witness,
without reflection or having transcended the events (RH, 4); he advo-
cates a philosophical method of history that does not seek just to record
brute facts. Yet Hegel rejects as one-sided the view that a philosophy of
history produces its own ideas without regard to given data (RH, 10).
Hegel claims his approach to history is in some sense empirical:
Only the study of world history itself can show that it has
proceeded rationally, that it represents the rationally necessary
course of the World Spirit. . . . This [m]ust be the result of
history. History itself must be taken as it is; we have to proceed
historically, empirically [empirisch]. (RH, 12; VPG, 22)
195
196 Mark Tunick
Aristotle does not place the individual and his rights first, but
recognizes the state as what in its essence is higher than the
individual and the family, for the very reason that it consti-
tutes their substantiality. . . . This is directly antagonistic to the
modern principle in which the particular will of the individual,
as absolute, is made the starting point, so that all men by
giving their votes, decide what is to be the law, and thereby
a commonweal is brought into existence. (HP, 208)
for the Athenians is puzzling, given the existence of city states contem-
porary with Athens with similar features such as a “common culture”
and small size (PH, 255) but that were not democratic.5
There are two ways we might understand Hegel’s claim. Democracy
may have been necessary in order for humans to advance beyond the
limits of Greek culture and society. Hegel says that the “justification and
absolute necessity of the democratic constitution of the Greeks rests on
the still immanent, objective ethical life” that lacks the corrupting ele-
ment of particular interests that have not yet developed (VPG, 308). He
argues that the democratic, along with the aristocratic and monarchical
structures of government,
free: man, unlike animals, raises “himself above the singleness of sensa-
tion to the universality of thought, to self-knowledge, to the grasp of his
subjectivity, of his ‘I’ ” (PM, §381Z). By virtue of this capacity, humans
can realize they are spirit. But subjectivity must not be totalized. A state
that adopts institutions that give play only to subjectivity and particularity
fails to help its citizens develop an adequate self-understanding, leaving
them with an abstract or incomplete, and untrue form of consciousness.
Because the Athenians lacked subjectivity, they could have democracy.
But, on Hegel’s view, because modern democracy necessarily expresses
only subjectivity and particularity, modern democratic states fail to satisfy
the demands of the Idea.
with all of his rights, to the entire community” (SC 1:6, 148). Hegel
was unable to conceive of democracy as capable of coexisting within a
corporatist structure in which citizens had civic consciousness and could
be mediated with the universal. Why did he assume democracy neces-
sarily is governed by the principle of individual sovereignty and leads
to the dissolution of the state? Hegel points to empirical evidence of
how individuals express their wills through the vote, but his evidence
is anecdotal and meager, and so it is hard to believe that he was led to
his conclusions about democracy in a modern state by his observations
of political behavior.
Hegel’s weakness as an empiricist political scientist is apparent
by comparing one of his arguments against elective and for hereditary
monarchy with Thomas Paine’s objection to hereditary monarchy.
Hegel argues that hereditary monarchy is rational because by having
the monarch decided by “nature” and not by political deliberations or
in-fighting, conflicts among factions are avoided (PR, §281, Rem.).
This is by no means Hegel’s only defense of hereditary monarchy,
and he explicitly disavows that this is its primary ground.16 But it is
an important one, and an argument that Paine anticipates and rejects
with a far more effective empiricism. Paine observes that there are
more civil wars resulting from contested hereditary claims than ever
arose from elections. Paine provides the example of Poland, which
“though an elective monarchy, has had fewer wars than those which
are hereditary.”17 Even Paine’s woefully slim data set is more impressive
than what Hegel assembles for establishing a correlation between elec-
tions and regime breakdown. Hegel points only to intuitive arguments
about the effect of a vote when there is a large electorate, and anecdotal
evidence about corruption, indifference, and competence, without ever
establishing that democratic polities are more likely to fail. Indeed, he
fails to explain how the particularism to which democracy gives play
would still effectively destroy the unity of the state if voters are, as he
claims, indifferent and disengaged. Paine at least compares observable
outcomes of democratic and nondemocratic regimes.
Despite Hegel’s claim that the historian should proceed empiri-
cally, and that we should not imagine how the world ought to be but
instead reflect on what has already transpired, he did not convincingly
base his claim about the failure of democracies in modern states on
observations of democratic practices in England or elsewhere. Hegel’s
criticism of modern democracy is left to rest on his rejection of the
principle of individual sovereignty:
that it conformed to his ideal. But it would not have been inconsistent
with his philosophy of history for Hegel to rework his understanding of
an ideal, rational state if institutions such as democracy, which he does
not regard as rational, had historically developed instead.21
Notes
The Philosophy of
History and Religion
This page intentionally left blank.
11
Hegel’s Philosophy of
World History as Theodicy
Pierre Chételat
215
216 Pierre Chételat
This passage leaves us with the impression that Hegel’s theodicean project
is essentially the same as Leibniz’s. In other words, it seems that, like
Leibniz, Hegel intends his theodicy to address the problem of evil. It is
certainly true that for Hegel there are particular events that are a neces-
sary part of history’s development and are therefore justified. However,
I will argue that when Hegel claims that the philosophy of history is
theodicy, he does not pretend to have resolved the problem of evil but
has a different philosophical project in mind. For Hegel, the philosophy
of history is theodicy first and foremost because it demonstrates that
God is at work in the world and that this work leads ultimately to a
state in which evil or suffering can be overcome.
At first glance, it is puzzling that Hegel would claim that the philoso-
phy of history is theodicy. One might expect him to associate theodicy
with theology or metaphysics, since God is an object of study in these
disciplines, but normally the focus of history is not on God but on
human events. Hegel helps to resolve this puzzle when he tells us that
God is at work in history. As he writes, “History is the unfolding of
God’s nature in a particular, determinate element.”4 For Hegel the task
of the philosophy of history is to show how God is active in history’s
development. This explains why the philosophy of history can be theo-
dicy: insofar as it deals with the role of God in history, the philosophy
of history has God’s activity as its subject matter.
What does Hegel mean by the term God when he claims that his-
tory is the unfolding of God’s determinate nature? I cannot address this
question here in detail, but I must take a position on it. As a number
of scholars have already argued effectively, the God that Hegel is refer-
ring to here is not the transcendent, autonomous creator of traditional
Christianity.5 Hegel’s God is not one who plays a role in history by
determining the course of historical events from beyond as a puppet
master determines the actions of his marionettes.6 In Hegel’s philosophy
of history, God is reason both as Idea and as spirit. As the latter, God is
reason as it manifests itself in the events of world history. When Hegel
Hegel’s Philosophy of World History as Theodicy 217
can be accounted for. But not all evil in the world is caused by humans,
since there is also natural evil, the harm and suffering that results, for
example, from natural disasters, disease, the infirmities of old age, etc.
Traditionally the job of theodicy has been to justify or account for not
only the evil that is caused by humans, but also for this natural evil. But
the philosophy of history is unable to do this if it is theodicy in the way
that has been suggested. Since spirit does not advance the progress of
history in the events of nature, and since diseases and natural disasters
are merely contingent occurrences, they cannot be justified as necessary
events on the road toward freedom.
Finally, according to the means/end interpretation, theodicy can
only serve effectively as a justification for evil that has occurred in his-
tory, since this justification is dependent on the fact that such evil has
a necessary role in history, and so must be viewed in the context of
history’s complete development. But alongside the conditions of freedom
that have been attained in the modern world, evil continues to be a
reality: wars are still fought, people are still oppressed, etc. These evil
events cannot be justified by this form of theodicy, first, because the good
toward which they could potentially contribute has for Hegel already
been reached, and, second, even if there was a higher goal toward which
they could contribute, their necessity and hence their justification would
only be apparent in retrospect. Hegel’s theodicy in this interpretation
has no bearing on the evil in our own lives, but is only able to give an
account of evils that are already long past.
Thus, we see in these three ways that according to the means/end
interpretation Hegel’s philosophy of history provides only a weak reply
to the problem of evil. The fact that Hegel’s theodicy may be weak
is not in and of itself a problem for interpreters, since this is perhaps
what Hegel intended. For those who defend the means/end interpre-
tation, this weakness of Hegelian theodicy may even be viewed as its
strength, since it shows that Hegel does not try to deny or play down
the full reality of the world’s pain and suffering.13 However, I believe
that the means/end interpretation on its own is insufficient. If we look
closely at what Hegel writes in the 1830 manuscript about the role of
philosophy of history as theodicy, Hegel appears to have a significantly
stronger form of theodicy in mind. In the passage that I read at the
outset of this chapter, Hegel tells us that his theodicy encompasses not
only some evil but all evil. “It should enable us to comprehend all the
ills of the world, including the existence of evil.”14 Here Hegel clearly
distinguishes human or moral evil (Böse) from evil in general (Übel) or
what Nisbet translates as “ill.” When he claims that theodicy should
allow us to grasp “all the ills of the world,” he is referring not just to
220 Pierre Chételat
the evil that results from human action, but to all suffering whatsoever,
including that brought on by acts of nature. The means/end interpre-
tation cannot explain why Hegel thinks that the philosophy of history
functions as a theodicy in this way.
Furthermore, from what Hegel tells us in his discussion of theodicy,
we see that it does more than just justify evil as a means to an end.
It shows, rather, that evil is itself overcome in history. Here he writes
about the reconciliation that theodicy must bring about between spirit
and the negative aspects of existence.
From this passage we see that there is some sense for Hegel in
which the good wins out against evil or in which the problems associated
with evil and suffering are resolved for us. Once again, the means/end
interpretation of Hegel’s theodicy is unable to account for why Hegel
might be saying this. The means/end interpretation shows that certain
evil occurrences in history are necessary, but, on its own at least, it does
not explain how evil is overcome. History could lead necessarily to the
advent of freedom without having any effect on the place of evil in the
world or our relationship to it.
The passages that I have just presented give us good reason to look more
closely at how Hegel’s philosophy of history is theodicy. The starting
point for such a reconsideration is to be found in the manuscript pas-
sages that I have already considered above. Hegel’s initial explanation
of theodicy is that it ought to allow us to grasp the evil (Übel) of the
world in general and that it ought to allow thinking spirit to be recon-
ciled with the negative. Elaborating on this reconciliation, Hegel says a
little farther that it requires the perception (Recentness) of an affirmative
in which the negative (i.e., evil) is subordinated and overcome. When
Hegel speaks of an affirmative in which evil is transcended, what is he
referring to? The answer is given in what follows, where he goes on to
Hegel’s Philosophy of World History as Theodicy 221
spell out three points through which this perception of the affirmative is
achieved. First, this perception requires that we be conscious of what the
final purpose of the world is. Although Hegel does not say so explicitly
here, we have seen that this final purpose is freedom. Second, it demands
consciousness that this purpose, or freedom, is actualized in the world.
Third, this perception involves a recognition that evil does not count
alongside this purpose. In other words, in freedom evil is overcome; it
no longer has force. Thus, the affirmative in which evil is transcended
is freedom itself.16 Hegel is suggesting that for the individual freedom
is itself a type of solution to the problem posed by evil, that with the
advent of freedom evil is in some way overcome. The philosophy of
history is theodicy because it shows that history progresses necessar-
ily toward freedom in which evil is transcended, and that this state of
freedom has been realized in modern European culture.
The claim that freedom allows us to transcend evil is one that
does not fit well either with ordinary conceptions of freedom or with
conceptions of freedom normally attributed to Hegel. Although scholars
agree strongly that the concept of freedom is of central importance in
Hegel’s thinking, there is still a lot of debate over what this freedom
involves. Some stress that freedom is ultimately the capacity to make
decisions that are truly independent or self-determined.17 This means
that our decisions are not merely determined by our natural impulses
or desires, but are rationally justified by us insofar as they are actions
that we are able to support with good reasons. For others, Hegelian
freedom is ultimately self-actualization,18 and in yet other cases the
emphasis is put on freedom as reconciliation with the other.19 None of
these views gives us an obvious explanation of why Hegel thinks that
freedom allows us to overcome evil. If interpreted in any of these ways,
freedom is undoubtedly a good. Moreover, being a member of a society
in which freedom is promoted might arguably shield someone from evil
more than being a member of another type of society would. But it is
not apparent on any of these readings why freedom would allow us to
overcome evil in the way that Hegel is suggesting. Whether freedom
means having the capacity to make independent decisions or being fully
self-actualized or being at home in the world, it does not, in and of
itself, spare a person from evil and does not offer any obvious way of
dealing with evil. Further explanation is required.
Hegel has claimed that the advent of freedom involves a transcending
of evil, and I believe that there is other textual evidence to suggest at
least that Hegel does see freedom as a state in which evil is overcome.
As I will argue, freedom for Hegel ultimately involves liberation, and
this is rooted in the fact that freedom not only allows us to supersede
222 Pierre Chételat
our particular existence but even requires that we do so. In the 1830
manuscript Hegel closely associates freedom with the capacity to think
or to act as a universal, and, in turn, with the ability to renounce one’s
particular or natural self.
Hegel is saying quite simply that the free individual can recognize pain
as just another one of its particular determinations, one that the mind
is able to distance itself from, or one that is ideal just like any other
determination and so can be taken in stride. As with abstract freedom,
the agent that is concretely free is ultimately able to achieve a form of
liberation from suffering. However, she does so not by stamping out
all desire and inclination, but by accepting the negation of particular
desires whenever this occurs.
This acceptance of suffering need not be viewed merely as a state
of resignation. Not only does the free individual reduce the effect of
suffering by being able to let go of what she cannot have, but she also
benefits from the good that freedom itself brings, a good that works
to offset the negative aspects of suffering.33 This good is the feeling of
blessedness that results from identifying with the universal and from
acting in accordance with one’s own rational nature. Nor should the
overcoming of evil be viewed as a capacity that can be immediately
exercised. The overcoming of evil that is present in freedom needs to be
understood as mediated by ethical life. Hegel is not proposing that we
are automatically able to endure any pain simply because we decide to
accept it. Rather, this aspect of freedom is one made gradually possible
by habit (Gewohnheit), and, more specifically, by participation in ethical
life.34 A detailed discussion of how ethical life shapes this capacity for
freedom cannot be undertaken here, but I can give a brief outline of
what I think this explanation would be like. An ethical life for Hegel
is a modern life. It involves possessing property, marrying and raising
a family, having a career, acting morally, being a member of the state,
etc. Far from being ascetic, ethical life gives the individual a lot of room
in which she can, indeed ought to, pursue her own particular desires.
However, for Hegel ethical life is governed first and foremost by duty.
It is a life in which all of a person’s actions or activities are justified by,
or are at least consistent with, the achievement of the highest good,
namely freedom. The individual’s particular subjective existence—her own
personal subjective identity with all her likes and dislikes, needs, talents,
experiences, expectations, etc.—is a necessary moment of who she is as
a free individual, and it needs to be developed and nurtured. But as a
moment, it is also sublated or ideal; it can be affected or changed without
affecting her universal nature. By living a life of duty, a life in which
she ultimately subordinates her particular interests to the imperatives of
her universal, rational side, the agent’s capacity to act and view herself
as the universal is strengthened gradually, and with it her ability to rise
above or to bear pain is also strengthened. To put it in Hegel’s terms,
she develops the capacity to eliminate the otherness of the negative and
226 Pierre Chételat
to be at home with herself in it. It is in this way that the ethical life
allows one to be reconciled slowly with life’s adversity.
Let us return to the main topic of this chapter, namely, Hegel’s claim
that the philosophy of history is theodicy. I have argued that the means/
end view does not account for all the claims that Hegel makes about
his theodicy, and I have explored Hegel’s claim that theodicy involves
recognizing that evil is overcome in freedom. It should be noted that
even if evil for Hegel is overcome in freedom, this fact does little to
strengthen Hegel’s response to the problem of evil. Freedom as over-
coming of evil is perhaps good news for those who are free or part of
a free society: it can contribute to the individual’s own struggle with
suffering because it suggests that in freedom the reality or full force
of evil can be mitigated. This also can contribute to addressing the
problem of evil in a small way, since it shows for one group of people
in history that evil need not be the problem that it initially appears to
be. However, this does nothing to justify the unmitigated suffering of
those in both the past and present who are not free. It may be the
case that in truth evil is ideal, but this of little comfort or use to those
who cannot benefit from this truth. If we recognize this, then we see
that we are not much farther ahead than the means/end interpretation
in our justification of evil.
We make better sense of Hegel’s claim that the philosophy of
history is theodicy if we abandon the view that it is a theodicy as a
response to the problem of evil. The Lectures on the Philosophy of World
History do demonstrate that certain evil events in history are neces-
sary, but the primary task of Hegel’s theodicy is not to try to provide
a rational justification for the world’s suffering. A strong case can be
made for the fact that Hegel often employs his religious terminology
in unconventional ways. I have in mind here terms such as immortality,
eternity, creation, proof as in the proofs for God’s existence, the mystical,
and, perhaps most importantly but also most controversially, the term
God itself. If Hegel is employing such terms in unusual ways, there is
no reason to assume that his use of the term theodicy could not also be
unusual. In considering the few other instances where Hegel speaks of
theodicy in his Berlin writings, we see that philosophy is theodicy for
Hegel in a more general sense, insofar as it simply demonstrates to the
philosophical observer that spirit is present in the world, or demonstrates
that the world or history is governed by reason.35 If we assume that
Hegel’s Philosophy of World History as Theodicy 227
this is what Hegel means by “theodicy,” then theodicy need not be first
and foremost an explanation of why there is evil in the world. In this
interpretation of theodicy, the demonstration that God is at work in
the world allows the observer to comprehend evil or to be reconciled
with the negative, not because it shows that all of this evil had to be or
because it justifies all the suffering in history in the way that full theo-
dicy ordinarily demands, but because it shows the individual that evil is
ultimately overcome by free spirit. On this reading, theodicy allows the
individual to be reconciled with the negative insofar as it demonstrates
that evil by its very nature is ultimately ideal.
At the very least, the view that freedom for Hegel involves an
overcoming of evil gives the philosophy of history a more optimistic feel
from Hegel’s point of view than it might otherwise have. It shows more
than the fact that history develops in a necessary way toward its final
purpose, the goal of freedom. Freedom is not a good that simply exists
for the individual alongside the evil that she continues to suffer. Freedom
itself is a form of response to evil. It is a state in which one has the
knowledge and social context necessary to live a life in which suffering
can be handled. In the free individual’s own life at least, good wins out
against evil, not because evil is completely eliminated but because it is
possible for her in her freedom to accept and be reconciled with it.
Notes
full freedom, and its promotion for Patten is what ultimately justifies the norms
of ethical life.
18. See Allen Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995), 36.
19. McCarney takes reconciliation and the overcoming of alienation as
central to Hegel’s concept of freedom. See McCarney, Hegel on History, 77–79.
In the philosophy of world history, this reconciliation is understood as finding
oneself at home in one’s political setting, Ibid., 80. For Will Dudley, com-
plete freedom involves various forms of reconciliation. See Will Dudley, Hegel,
Nietzsche, and Philosophy: Thinking Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002), 111. These forms of reconciliation include being at home in one’s
social and political situation, as well as having a theoretical understanding of
the fact that the natural world is not an other. Dudley’s account of freedom as
reconciliation and as liberation is closest in spirit to my own. However, I have
found no evidence that Dudley interprets Hegel’s concept of freedom as the
capacity to endure suffering.
20. LPW, 144; my italics.
21. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 3 vols., trans. R.
F. Brown, P. C. Hodgson, and J. M. Stewart (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1984–87), 1:362 (hereafter LPR1-3).
22. Ibid., 223. Hegel also associates freedom with the loss of particular-
ity in the following passages: LPR-1, 342–43; LPR-2, 623, 634; VPW, 501,
519. The theme of overcoming of particularity is one that thoroughly pervades
Hegel’s work in the Berlin period. It is a central part not only of Hegel’s phi-
losophy of religion, but plays a role for Hegel in education, art, philosophy,
and ethical life.
23. Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought, 44, belongs to the former, while Patten,
Hegel’s Idea of Freedom, 51, and Richard Schacht, Hegel and After: Studies in
Continental Philosophy: Between Kant and Sartre (Pittsburgh: University of Pitts-
burgh Press, 1975), 76, have a more Kantian reading of Hegel’s freedom.
24. For example, in the preface to his Lectures on the Philosophy of Reli-
gion—perhaps the most rhetorical and passionate couple of pages that the mature
Hegel wrote—Hegel gives the impression that religion offers a type of liberation
or escape from suffering. “Finite purposes, disgust at petty interests, the pain
of this life, even if only in isolated moments that are themselves unhappy, the
troubles, burdens, and cares of ‘this bank and shoal of time,’ pity and compas-
sion—all this, like a dream image, seems to float away into the past like the
soul that drinks from the waters of forgetfulness, its other, mortal, nature fading
into a mere semblance, which no longer causes it anxiety and on which it is
no longer dependent,” LPR1, 85. Moreover, in a remarkable passage from the
Science of Logic, Hegel indicates that a person ought not to care about the state
of his particular existence. Replying here to Kant’s famous argument against the
ontological proof for the existence of God, Hegel states that the Christian ought
to be indifferent whether he does or does not possess the infamous one hundred
dollars, and Hegel goes on to say that “it ought to be a matter of indifference
to him whether he is or is not, that is, in finite life,” G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s
230 Pierre Chételat
Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press
International, 1993), 89. In this passage Hegel’s ideal Christian is suggestive of
the Stoic: he does not care about the particulars of his existence or does not
cling to the satisfaction of his own desires, and so does not suffer when these
desires are not met. In the Philosophy of Spirit, Hegel tells us that a person is
able to overcome pain or is able to be liberated from sensation through habit
(Gewohnheit), G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, 3 vols., trans.
M. J. Petry (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978), 2:§410, Remark. Hereafter PSS1-3.
Habit or custom makes it possible for a person to harden his body against
external sensations such as heat, cold, or fatigue, and to harden the mind against
unhappiness. Habit also makes it possible for a person to become indifferent
with regard to whether or not his desires are satisfied. It is not entirely clear
to what extent Hegel thinks we can inure ourselves through habit to pain and
deprivation. However, all of this evidence indicates that for Hegel it is possible,
at least to some degree, to be indifferent to loss and to rise above pain.
25. PSS-1, §382.
26. In his discussion of stoicism in Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der
Philosophie, Teile 1–4, Vols. 6–10, ed. Pierre Garniron and Walter Jaeschke
(Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1986–1996), 3:114, hereafter VGP1-4, Hegel confirms
his view that the free individual is able to resist pain, and he claims that this
understanding of freedom is what is great in Stoic philosophy.
27. G. W. F. Hegel, Berliner Schriften: 1818–1831, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister
(Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1956), 45–51. One also finds a very similar critique
of Catholic holiness in LPR-1, 473; LPR-3, 341–42, 455–56.
28. G. W. F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen W.
Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004),
§154; §261, Remark.
29. VPG, 14.
30. PSS-1, §382, Addition.
31. Ibid.
32. G. W. F. Hegel, The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part I of the Encyclopaedia of
Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, trans. T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, and
H. S. Harris (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1991), §147, Addition (hereafter EL).
33. This point was suggested to me by Ken Westphal.
34. PSS-2, §410.
35. G. W. F. Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree (New York:
Dover, 1956), 457; G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie
III, Werke vol. 20, ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Markus Michel (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1971), 455; VGP-4, 6. For other references to theodicy,
see LPR-1, 147; EL, §147, Addition.
12
Hegel’s Philosophy of
History and Kabbalist Eschatology
Glenn Magee
Introduction
231
232 Glenn Magee
This and other passages seem to be saying that the living presence
of God, Shekhinah, truly came to be only in the Temple of Jerusalem,
the religious center of the Israelites.
A well-known Kabbalistic epigram states: “Israel forms the limbs
of the Shekhinah.”13 The Jewish Gnostics held to a doctrine of the
“exile of the Shekhinah,” which maintained that God’s presence in
the world is like a “divine spark” which must be ignited in order that
the world be filled with divine presence. This is the task of the knes-
set Yisrael, which came in the works of the Kabbalists to be identified
with Shekhinah.14 Christian Kabbalists, whom I shall treat in the next
section, accordingly identified Shekhinah with the third person of the
trinity, the Holy Spirit.
In contrast to conventional or orthodox Christianity, however,
Jewish Kabbalism views redemption as something that will take place
in time and within the world. As Scholem expresses it, “[R]edemption
is expressed as the end of the ‘exile of the Shekhinah,’ the restoration
of the Divine unity throughout all areas of existence.”15 And this is the
basic Kabbalist eschatology. God develops and unfolds through cre-
ation and history, but creation (and thus God) must be completed or
perfected by the faithful. Daniel Matt writes, “God is not static being,
but dynamic becoming. Without human participation, God remains
Hegel’s Philosophy of History and Kabbalist Eschatology 235
Conclusion
My objective in this chapter has been to show that some of the more
famous claims of Hegel’s philosophy, including his philosophy of his-
tory, are to be found in the Kabbalist and Joachimite mystical traditions.
Further, I have argued that these strains fuse in the tradition of Swabian
speculative pietism, and that there is some reason to believe that this
tradition was a formative influence on both Hegel and Schelling.
However, I am not claiming that Swabian pietism was the sole source
of certain ideas in Schelling and Hegel. The question of influence is an
extremely difficult one to disentangle. The most reasonable approach
is to understand both thinkers as having been influenced by multiple
sources—philosophical and nonphilosophical—which they saw, in many
cases, as mutually supporting and confirming each other. I am merely
arguing that there is a further possible source to be explored, one that
has so far received little attention from scholars. Nevertheless, to argue
for such influences has, I believe, extremely important implications.
Though it seems obvious that regional traditions, attitudes, and
intellectual fashions must have had an influence on the Swabian Ideal-
ists, this is actually seldom considered by philosophically trained scholars,
especially Americans, who feel themselves on surer ground situating their
subjects exclusively in the context of the philosophical canon. This is a
highly artificial way to understand a thinker’s development, and highly
ironic when it is applied to a thinker such as Hegel, who was so attuned
to how every man is a product of his time and place. I offer this chapter,
in part, as an invitation to scholars to understand Schelling and Hegel
in the context of their homeland, and in doing so I am following in
the footsteps of the German scholars Ernst Benz and Robert Schneider,
and, more recently the American Laurence Dickey.49
What is needed is a study of the Swabian Idealists that situates
them in the context of the speculative traditions of their native land.
For example, a systematic comparison of the writings of Schelling and
Hegel to those of Oetinger and other Swabian mystics and theologians
might yield important new discoveries. The present essay has, I believe,
merely scratched the surface.
Notes
247
248 Contributors
and the Hermetic Tradition, The Hegel Dictionary, and editor of The
Cambridge Handbook of Western Mysticism and Esotericism.
249
250 Index
Boehme, Jacob, 12, 235, 237–40, conscience, 74, 157, 167–68, 171,
242 175, 210
bourgeoisie, 28, 34, 55, 181–84, consciousness, 1, 3, 10, 18, 20–23,
186, 190–93 27–28, 31, 35–37, 40–41, 44,
Buchwalter, Andrew, 210–11 48, 61, 65, 77, 90, 93, 95,
Buck-Morss, Susan, 105–07 97–104, 106–10, 116, 124, 142,
Büchner, Georg, 37 144, 147–48, 158–69, 173–74,
Buffon, George, 113–14, 128 178, 180, 185, 189–90, 196–97,
Butler, Clark, 244 203–04, 207, 210, 221–22
constitutions, 36, 40, 66–67, 92, 96,
Caesar, Julius, 169–218 196–202, 205, 210
caste, 8, 140–41 contingency, 6–7, 11, 25, 32, 39,
categories, 6, 39, 65, 77–78, 89, 105, 111–13, 115, 125, 162–63, 165,
107, 109, 112, 162, 215, 233 174, 203, 217, 219
Catholicism, 7, 43, 124–25, 224, Cooper, Barry, 15, 29
230 corporations, 58–60, 66, 199, 203,
Chakrabarty, Dipesh, 102, 107, 109 211
China, 81–82, 109, 130 cosmopolitanism, 101, 103–04
Christianity, 12, 43, 87, 89, 92–93, culture, 2, 4, 6–7, 9, 62, 64, 69, 73,
96, 114, 123, 131, 164, 216, 80, 87–89, 92–97, 99, 101–04,
229–32, 234, 236–40, 242 107, 109–10, 119–22, 124,
citizens, 5, 36, 52, 54–55, 57–60, 135–36, 156–58, 162, 164–65,
62, 66, 90, 103–04, 120, 123, 167–68, 173–74, 190, 198–99,
137, 145–48, 166, 186, 188–89, 217, 221
196–97, 199, 202, 204, 207 cunning of reason, 2
city-state, 135, 159, 163, 167, 173, custom, 1, 92, 144, 160, 164,
182 186–87, 230
civil servants, 100–01, 109
civil society, 9–10, 54–56, 65–66, Dagger, Richard, 210
94, 140–41, 147, 149, 177, 180– Dahl, Robert, 211
81, 183–89, 191, 193, 196–97, Dallmayr, Fred R., 108
199, 202–03, 211 death, 32, 77, 79–80, 160, 166,
civilizations, 51–54, 56, 109, 111, 172, 181–82, 187, 210, 218
135–36, 148, 185, 218 de Boer, Karin, 63
Clark, Wendy Lynn, 176 de Lubac, Henri, 244–45
class, 8, 10, 34 54–55, 66, 100–01, de Ste Croix, G.E.M., 151
139–41, 181–85, 187–89, 191–94, democracy, 10–11, 59–60, 141,
201 195–211
Cold War, 5–6, 72, 75, 78 Descartes, 36
colonialism, 95 desire, 2, 16, 35, 45, 77, 79, 124,
comedy, 147–48 125, 145–48, 151, 156, 166,
communitarianism, 94, 184 179–80, 183, 185, 189–91,
concept, the, 24, 52–53, 57, 62, 64, 221–25, 230, 238
67, 71–72, 74, 90–91, 99, 137– Dickey, Laurence, 180, 192, 243–44,
38, 142, 144, 178–79, 181–85, 246
188–91, 201 Dierauer, Walter, 245
Index 251
diversity, 97, 99, 101, 113, 115–17, family, 9, 78, 100, 144, 159–61,
126 193, 197, 211, 224–25
Dove, Kenley R., 175–76 fate, 54, 112, 137, 141, 158, 161,
Dover, J.K., 152 168
Dudley, Will, 17, 30, 32, 229 feudalism, 57–59, 66, 149, 164,
Dussel, Enrique, 105 167, 187
duties, 74, 121, 156–58, 160–65, Fichte, 6, 72–76, 82–83, 98, 171,
170–71, 204, 225 186, 240
Forbes, Jack, 128
Forster, Michael, 48
East, 3, 141
Foucault, Michel, 47
education, 7, 40, 45, 74, 76, 83,
foundationalism, 23, 26–27
100–02, 108–09, 112, 119, 148,
Franco, Paul, 130–31
152, 162, 165, 167, 177, 179,
freedom, 2–9, 11–12, 16–20, 22–23,
201, 229, 245
25–26, 28–30, 36, 38, 40–42, 45,
Egerman, F., 152
52–54, 56–65, 73, 88, 90–100,
ego, 73, 78, 82, 116, 149
102–04, 106–07, 111–13, 115–16,
Ehrenberg, V., 152
120, 122–26, 130, 135–38, 142,
empiricism, 207, 209
144–47, 149–50, 157–59, 163,
end of history, 3–4, 12, 16–20,
165–66, 168–69, 173–75, 177–78,
23–25, 30, 40, 231
181–85, 191–92, 199–200, 203,
English Reform Bill, 200–02, 204
205, 217–30, 238, 242
Enlightenment, 37, 158, 164,
free will, 25, 29, 135, 145
166–69, 231, 237, 242
French Revolution, 4, 35–38, 42,
Erlanger, Steven, 210
157–58, 165–67, 172, 174–75,
eschatology, 4, 232, 234–35, 238
205
estates, 58–60, 66, 101, 141, 145,
Fritzman, J.M., 176
149, 181, 201–02
Frost, Bryan-Paul, 109
eternal return, 28
Fuks, A., 151
ethical life, 8–10, 12, 62, 138–40,
Fukuyama, Francis, 93
147–48, 158–64, 167–69, 173–74,
fundamentalism, 5–6, 77
177–92, 198–99, 225–26, 229
future, the, 3, 5–6, 12, 16–17, 19,
Eurocentrism, 6–7, 87–88, 96, 99,
25–26, 33, 37, 41, 43–45, 47–48,
102, 104–05, 127
56, 60, 62, 79, 81, 96, 113, 115,
Europe, 3, 7, 9, 34, 81–82, 87–89,
121, 125–26, 131, 166, 168
92–93, 95–97, 99, 102–04, 109,
115, 120–23, 125–26, 128–30,
Gaier, Ulrich, 245
157–58, 164–69, 190, 208, 217,
Gallie, W.B., 210
221, 237, 245
Gaonkar, Dilip, 108
evil, 3, 11, 39, 156–57, 170, 173,
Gauthier, Jeffrey A., 173
176, 215–21, 223–28
genealogy, 4, 36, 38, 41, 46, 48, 72
exclusion, 21–22, 24, 78, 100, 102,
genocide, 115, 121
126, 145, 174, 197
geography, 7, 98, 112, 114, 117–18,
201
Fackenheim, Emil, 72, 82 geology, 118
Faivre, Antoine, 244–45 Gerbi, Antonello, 113, 116, 128–30
252 Index
Nietzsche, 4, 16, 26–30, 32–34, 37, 96–97, 125, 140, 169, 187, 219,
51 226, 228–29
nihilism, 3–4, 27–29, 33 Patten, Alan, 228–29
non-being, 21–22, 24 Pelzer, Roland, 170
normative reconstruction, 6, 88–93, Peperzak, Adrien, 48, 136, 150
99–100, 102, 105 personhood, 135, 140, 142–43, 145
normativity, 4, 18, 30, 35–38, Pico, Giovanni, 236
40–44, 46–48, 111, 123, 139, Pietism, 12, 231, 237, 240, 242–43,
158, 164 246
norms, 4, 7, 37–38, 41–42, 44–46, Pinkard, Terry, 66, 172, 227
91, 94, 104, 156, 158, 160, 164, Pippin, Robert, 228
173, 229 Plant, Raymond, 29
nothingness, 16, 24, 27–28, 31, 33, Plato, 8, 37, 54, 62, 131, 135–36,
184, 232 138–42, 144–45, 181–82, 199,
Novalis, 43, 49 210
Popper, Karl, 63, 70
O’Brien, George Dennis, 227 possibility, 4–5, 25, 27, 43–44, 48,
O’Donohue, John, 172–73 56, 80, 112–13, 115–16, 142,
O’Regan, Cyril, 244–45 162, 167, 178, 180, 189, 205
Oedipus, 136–37, 150 poverty, 5, 52, 56, 65, 151, 188,
Oetinger, Friedrich Christoph, 12, 224
232, 237–43, 245–46 present, the, 1, 3, 5, 12, 19–21,
Old World, 7–8, 113–15, 117–20, 23–28, 31, 33, 35–36, 38–46, 48,
122–23, 125–26, 129 61, 67, 79–80, 95–98, 100, 102,
oligarchy, 141, 151, 210 107, 110, 146, 187, 193, 215,
ontology, 64, 89–90, 103, 113, 233 226, 232
organism, 10, 137, 144, 181, 187, presuppositions, 4, 38–39, 78, 90,
190–91, 193 172
Orient, 38, 64, 69, 109, 136, 156, property, 8, 29, 54, 56, 92, 96,
169 140, 143–45, 180, 183, 186, 189,
Ormiston, Alice, 176 195–96, 201, 205, 225
Ortega y Gasset, Jorge, 128 Protestantism, 92, 100, 125, 237
otherness, 24, 30, 32, 91, 97–98, providence, 2, 39–41, 206, 217, 228
100, 225 Prussia, 42, 51, 57–58, 108
Ottmann, Hennig, 108
quietism, 5
pain, 3, 219, 223–25, 229–30
Paine, Thomas, 207, 211 race, 7, 93, 111–16, 119–20,
panlogism, 41 122–23, 125–27, 129
Parmenides, 4, 16–17, 20–24, 27, 31 rationality, 7, 57–58, 71, 73, 76, 91,
particularity 11, 32, 56, 60, 63, 67, 93, 95, 126, 158, 192, 201, 206,
98–99, 138, 142, 146–48, 150– 208
51, 166–67, 180, 197, 203–05, Rausher, Frederick, 176
223–24, 229 Rawls, John, 37
past, the, 5, 16, 18–20, 25–26, 28, Raz, Joseph, 50
30, 33, 37, 39, 43–46, 51, 61–62, Realphilosophie, 25, 89
Index 255
State University of
New York Press
www.sunypress.edu