Pal Grave
Pal Grave
Pal Grave
David Held
Centre for Global Governance, London School of Economics, Houghton Street,
London W2A 2AE, UK.
Abstract Thinking about the future of humankind and the basis of political
association in the early years of the twenty-first century does not give grounds for
optimism. In particular, 9/11 has become a moment associated with a return to
empire, geopolitics, political violence and the primacy of sovereignty. Yet, it is easy
to overstate the meaning of 9/11 and exaggerate from one set of historical
experiences. This article explores the ways in which the twentieth century set down
key political and legal ‘cosmopolitian steps’ toward a transformation of the global
order. These steps are explored and defended, and it is shown how they created the
grounds for a very different response to 9/11 to the one persued by President Bush
and Prime Minister Blair. Although clearly this opportunity has been temporarily
lost, the failure of the Blair–Bush War on Terror reaffirms strong reasons for
further developing a cosmopolitian global order.
International Politics (2010) 47, 52–61. doi:10.1057/ip.2009.27
It’s the worst thing that’s happened, but only this week. Two years ago,
an earthquake in Turkey killed 17 000 people in a day, babies and
mothers and businessmen y The November before that, a hurricane hit
Honduras and Nicaragua and killed even more y Which end of the
world shall we talk about? Sixty years ago, Japanese airplanes bombed
Navy boys who were sleeping on ships in gentle Pacific waters. Three and
a half years later, American planes bombed a plaza in Japan where men
and women were going to work, where schoolchildren were playing, and
more humans died at once than anyone thought possible. Seventy
thousand in a minute. Imagine y
There are no worst days, it seems. Ten years ago, early on a January
morning, bombs rained down from the sky and caused great buildings in
r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1384-5748 International Politics Vol. 47, 1, 52–61
www.palgrave-journals.com/ip/
Cosmopolitanism after 9/11
This is an unsettling and challenging passage. When I first read it, I felt
somewhat angered and unconvinced by its call to think systematically about
9/11 in the context of other disasters, acts of aggression and wars. A few days
later I found it helpful to connect these remarks to my own cosmopolitan
leanings.
Thinking about the future of humankind on the basis of the early years of
the twenty-first century does not give grounds for optimism. From 9/11 to the
2006 war in the Middle East, terrorism, conflict, territorial struggle and the
clash of identities appear to define the moment. The wars in Afghanistan, Iraq,
Israel/Lebanon and elsewhere suggest that political violence is an irreducible
feature of our age. Perversely, globalization seems to have dramatized the
significance of differences between peoples; far from the globalization of
communications easing understanding and the translation of ideas, it seems to
have highlighted what it is that people do not have in common and find
dislikeable about each other (Bull, 1977). Moreover, the contemporary drivers
of political nationalism – self-determination, secure borders, geo-political and
geo-economic advantage – place an emphasis on the pursuit of the national
interest above concerns with what it is that humans might have in common.
Yet, it is easy to overstate the moment and exaggerate from one set of
historical experiences. While each of the elements mentioned poses a challenge
to a rule-based global order, it is a profound mistake to forget that the
twentieth century established a series of cosmopolitan steps toward the
delimitation of the nature and form of political community, sovereignty
and ‘reasons of state’. These steps were laid down after the First and Second
World Wars that brought humanity to the edge of the abyss – not once but
twice. At a time as difficult as the start of the twenty-first century, it is
important to recall why these steps were taken and remind oneself of their
significance.
From the foundation of UN system to the EU, from changes to the laws of
war to the entrenchment of human rights, from the emergence of international
environmental regimes to the establishment of the International Criminal
Court, people have sought to reframe human activity and embed it in law,
r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1384-5748 International Politics Vol. 47, 1, 52–61 53
Held
important that no single power or group should act as judge, jury and
executioner. They could have decided that global hotspots like the Middle
East that help feed global terrorism should be the main centre of international
attention. They could have decided to be tough on terrorism and tough on
the conditions that lead people to imagine (falsely) that Al-Qaeda and
similar groups are agents of justice in the modern world. But they
systematically failed to pursue this agenda. In general, the world after 9/11
became more polarized, international law weaker, and multilateral institutions
more vulnerable.
The wars that began in Afghanistan in 2002 and in Iraq in 2003 gave priority
to a narrow security agenda that was at the heart of the Bush administration’s
security doctrine. This doctrine contradicted many of the core tenets of
international politics and international agreements since 1945 (Ikenberry,
2005). It set out a policy that was essentially hegemonic, that sought order
through dominance, that pursued the pre-emptive and preventive use of force,
that relied on a conception of leadership based on a coalition of the willing and
that aimed to make the world safe for freedom and democracy – by globalizing
American rules and conceptions of justice. The doctrine was pursued as the
War on Terror. The language of interstate warfare was preserved intact and
projected onto a new enemy. As a result, the terrorists of 9/11 were dignified as
soldiers and war prosecuted against them. But this strategy was a distortion
and simplification of reality and a predictable failure. In pursuing dominance
through force, the War on Terror killed more innocent civilians in Iraq than
the terrorists on 9/11, humiliated and tortured many Iraqis, created numerous
innocent victims, and acted as a spur to terrorist recruitment (see Soros, 2006).
It showed little, if any, understanding of the dignity, pride and fears of
others, and of the way the fate and fortune of all peoples are increasingly tied
together in our global age. And it unleashed an orgy of sectarian killing among
the Sunni and Shia in Iraq, and the displacement of over 300 000 people.
Instead of seeking to extend the rule of law, ensuring that no party – terrorist
or state – acts as judge, jury and executioner, seeking dialogue with the Muslim
world, strengthening the multilateral order, and developing the means to
deal with the criminals of 9/11, the United States and its allies (notably the
United Kingdom) pursued old-war techniques and has made nearly everyone
less secure.
An alternative approach existed, lets call it a cosmopolitan security agenda.
This agenda requires three things of governments and international institutions
(Held and Kaldor, 2001). First, there must be a commitment to the rule of law
and the development of multilateral institutions – not the prosecution of war as
the first response. Civilians of all faiths and nationalities need protection.
Terrorists and all those who systematically violate the sanctity of life and
human rights must be brought before an international criminal court that
r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1384-5748 International Politics Vol. 47, 1, 52–61 57
Held
parts of the world today (‘old Europe’, Latin America, Africa and Asia). These
include:
K relinking the security and human rights agenda in international law – the
two sides of international humanitarian law that, together, specify grave and
systematic abuse of human security and well-being, and the minimum
conditions required for the development of human agency;
K reforming UN Security Council procedures to improve the specification of,
and legitimacy of, credible reasons for, credible threshold tests for, and
credible promises in relation to, armed intervention in the affairs of a state –
the objective being to link these directly to a set of conditions that would
constitute a severe threat to peace, and/or a threat to the minimum
conditions for the well-being of human agency, sufficient to justify the use of
force, and which would lock the deployment of force into a clear framework
of international humanitarian law;
K recognizing the necessity to dislodge and amend the now-outmoded 1945
geo-political settlement as the basis of decision-making in the Security
Council, and to extend representation to all regions on a fair and equal
footing;
K expanding the remit of the Security Council, or creating a parallel Social and
Economic Security Council, to examine and, where necessary, intervene in
the full gambit of human crises – physical, social, biological, environmental
– that can threaten human agency.
limits and determines the moral worth of individuals and their capacity
for freedom. Cosmopolitanism builds on this insight, that is, on the basic
principles of equal dignity, equal respect, and the priority of vital need in its
preoccupation with what is required for the autonomy and development of
all human beings. It also builds on the way these principles have been
entrenched in significant post-Second World War legal and political develop-
ments. The response to 9/11 could have followed in the footsteps of these
achievements and strengthened our multilateral institutions and international
legal arrangements. In fact, it took us further away from these fragile gains
toward a world of further antagonisms and divisions – a distinctively uncivil
society.
At the heart of a cosmopolitan conception of global order is the idea that
citizenship can be based not on an exclusive membership of a territorial
community but on general rules and principles that can be entrenched and
drawn upon in different settings. The meaning of citizenship thus shifts from
membership in a community that bestows, for those who qualify, particular
rights and duties to an alternative principle of world order in which all persons
have equivalent rights and duties – in this case, to uphold and maintain the law
of war and human rights law – in the cross-cutting spheres of decision-making
that can affect their vital needs and interests. As Habermas has written, ‘only
a democratic citizenship that does not close itself off to in a particularistic
fashion can pave the way for a world citizenship y State citizenship and world
citizenship form a continuum whose contours, at least, are already being
becoming visible’ (1996, pp. 514–515). There is only a historically contingent
connection between the principles underpinning citizenship and the national
community; as this connection weakens in a world of overlapping communities
and fate, the principles of citizenship must be rearticulated and re-entrenched.
Moreover, in the light of this development, the connection between patriotism
and nationalism becomes easier to call into question, and a case built to bind
patriotism to the defence of core civic and political principles – not to the
nation or country for their won sake (Heater, 2002). Only national identities
open to diverse solidarities, and shaped by respect for general rules and
principles, can accommodate themselves successfully to the challenges of the
global age (see Held, 2002; Brunkhorst, 2005). The global challenges we face,
from 9/11 to the global financial crisis, are better met in a cosmopolitan legal
framework.
Acknowledgement
This text was presented as a plenary lecture at the Political Studies Association,
Manchester, 8 April 2009.
60 r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1384-5748 International Politics Vol. 47, 1, 52–61
Cosmopolitanism after 9/11
David Held is Co-Director of the Centre for Global Governance and Graham
Wallas Professor of Political Science in the Department of Government at the
London School of Economics. His main research interests include rethinking
democracy at transnational and international levels, and the study of
globalization and global governance. He has strong interests both in political
theory and in the more empirical dimensions of political analysis. His books
include Globalization/Anti-globalization: beyond the great divide (2007, co-
author) and Cultural Politics in a Global Age: Uncertainty, Solidarity, and
Innovation (ed., 2008).
References
Barnett, A., Held, D. and Henderson, C. (eds.) (2005) Debating Globalization. Cambridge: Polity.
Brunkhorst, H. (2005) Solidarity: From Civic Friendship to a Global Legal Community. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Bull, H. (1977) The Anarchical Society. London: Macmillan.
Crawford, J. and Marks, S. (1998) The global democracy deficit: An essay on international law and
its limits. In: D. Archibugi, D. Held and M. Köhler (eds.) Re-imagining Political Community:
Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 72–90.
Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and
Democracy. Cambridge: Polity.
Habermas, J. (1999) Bestialität und Humanität. Die Zeit 18 April.
Heater, D. (2002) World Citizenship. London: Continuum.
Held, D. (1995) Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan
Governance. Cambridge: Polity.
Held, D. (2002) Law of states, law of peoples: Three models of sovereignty. Legal Theory 8(1):
1–44.
Held, D. (2004) Global Covenant: The Social Democratic Alternative to the Washington Consensus.
Cambridge: Polity.
Held, D. and Kaldor, M. (2001) What hope for the future? http://www.lse.ac.uk/depts/global/
maryheld.htm, accessed 8 December 2008.
Hoffmann, S. (2003) America goes backward. New York Review of Books 50(10): 74–80.
Ikenberry, J. (2005) A weaker world. Prospect November.
Kaldor, M. (1998) New and Old Wars. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Kingsolver, B. (2001) A pure, high note of anguish. Los Angeles Times 23 September.
Kirgis, F. (2001) Terrorist attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon. The American
Society of international Law, September 2001, http://www.asil.org/insights/insigh77.htm.
Solana, J. (2003) The future of transatlantic relations. Progressive Politics 2(2), http://www
.policy-network.net/uploadedFiles/Publications/Publications/pp2.2%2060-67_SOLANA.pdf.
Soros, G. (2006) The Age of Fallibility: Consequences of the War on Terror. New York: Public
Affairs.
Weller, M. (1997) The reality of the emerging universal constitutional order: Putting the pieces
together. Cambridge Review of International Studies X(Winter/Spring): 40–63.
r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1384-5748 International Politics Vol. 47, 1, 52–61 61