Norms, Values, Society:: A Brief Phenomenological
Norms, Values, Society:: A Brief Phenomenological
Norms, Values, Society:: A Brief Phenomenological
abstract
In our paper we introduce three main areas of social ontology that correspond with the
sections structuring the current issue of “Phenomenology and Mind”: non-institutional
life, institutional life and ethical-political life. We argue three points about these areas,
which are represented in the accounts published in this issue: levels of social life and
reality; normative levels of life and reality; hierarchical levels of life and reality. Finally,
we introduce two interviews, to which the last special section of the issue is devoted.
The interviews were conducted by the editors with Martha Craven Nussbaum and by
Valentina Bambini, Cristiano Chesi and Andrea Moro with Noam Chomsky.
keywords
1. The current issue (vol. 3) of “Phenomenology and Mind” deals with social
Our Purposes facts. Social facts include many different subjects: persons, groups, norms,
values, political systems, economical powers, etc., that are the domain of
different theoretical and practical disciplines, such as social and developmental
psychologies, empirical sociologies (both quantitative and qualitative), political
sciences, legal theories, ethics, economics, etc.
1 Some phenomenologists (like Scheler) spoke about individual essences, such as the essence
of a nations or a person, going far beyond the ontological assessment that personhood implies
absolute individuality (haecceitas). His pretension to have direct access to the metaphysical obscure
individualities of Germany, Britain, or Europe cast a cloud over his bright ontology of the individual
person, justifying more skeptical approaches in cultural studies and Schutz’s mistrust of ontology.
Husserl’s methodological distinction (finally edited in Hua XL) between ontology and the essence
of individuals, however, stressing that eidetic, the ontological study of essences (greek ‘eidos’, ‘eide’),
deals with classes and not with individuals, as well as his distinction between ontological eidetics and
monadological metaphysics could reset long-lasting prejudices about the role of ontologies in cultural
and social sciences.
10
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
Still, in the last few decades, apart from these influential debates, analytical
philosophers began to struggle with the (formal) nature of social facts,
looking for their constitutive features, their invariants, and their properties
and trying to systematize the results of these meticulous analyses into a
particular branch of general metaphysics: social ontology. In doing so they
found unexpected echoes among scholars working on and furthering the
phenomenological projects, through the pioneering work of the “Seminar
for Austro-German-Philosophy” and the reassessment of “realistic
phenomenology” (especially Kevin Mulligan and Barry Smith).
In the last three years, the Research Center in Phenomenology and Sciences
of the Person has invited several scholars working in this field to discuss
their current research. The discussions were held in the lecture halls of
the San Raffaele University (Milan), and on the virtual platform of this
research laboratory (www.phenomenologylab.eu). The main goal of the
lab is to give voice to an authentic phenomenological spirit in both its
analytic (in the sense of conceptual clarity and of the attention for formal
logic and ontology) and synthetic (in the sense of openness to the best
of the philosophical traditions, including the contemporary intellectual
debates and the material or regional ontologies). The best contributions
on social ontology that preceded and followed the Spring School 2011, and
the International Conference Making the Social World, devoted to John R.
Searle’s Making the Social World. The Structure of Human Civilization (2010), are
collected in this issue of the journal under the title “Norms, Values, Society:
Phenomenological and Ontological Approaches”.
11
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
The working hypothesis of our Lab was that the individual person is the last
bearer of properties in the ontological region of the social. She is individuated
in her intentional positions and attitudes (both theoretical, axiological
and practical) toward her social environment, which is necessary, but not a
sufficient condition for her concrete personal development. On one hand, she
relies on her natural, biological and psychological faculties, which, together
with her material and social environment, give her the possibility to develop
her individual personality in early childhood socialization. On the other hand,
the mature and autonomous flourishing of her being-person requires the free
capability to emerge from the level of her social environment through the
execution of spontaneous and rational acts, both shaping her individuality
as well as offering her personal contribution to social and institutional
life. Personhood, therefore, is at the same time rooted in and transcending
sociality. Moreover, the individual person, as the last bearer in the region
of social ontology, does not coincide with her natural and psychological
support, although she is founded on it. As highlighted by Norberto Bobbio
(1948), a human being is definable by three traits, which coincide with its
progressive levels of individuation: human being as natural being or biological
individual, human being as social being or socius, human being as personal
2 Nam In-Lee (2006) claims, that we don’t have any phenomenological attempts of
transcendental sociology. Maybe Schutz and his heirs Berger and Luckmann (Berger and
Luckmann 1966, Schutz and Luckmann 1975/1984) could be considered as transcendental
sociologists, although they didn’t. Yet since they looked for invariant but dynamic structures
of the life-world, and Husserl considered the description of these the phenomenological way to
transcendental philosophy, as the research on the condition for the possibility for something
(in our case, social facts), we can consider them in these frame. Thereby Berger and Luckmann’s
metaphysical sympathies for constructionism could be revisited within Husserl’s approach to the
realism and constructivism debate.
12
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
Further, individual persons are not the only objects of the ontological
region of the social, which is inhabited also by organizations consisting
of a plurality of persons (such as clubs, states, churches, universities…),
immaterial objects (such as promises, marriages, juridical persons, titles,
…), and social subjects (such as documents, money, monuments and meeting
halls for clubs, parliaments and governments, churches and universities),
whose material founders cannot explain their irreducible social meaning,
although the constitution of social objects is limited by materiality (Roversi
2012, Terravecchia 2012). Hartmann (1933) defined these three domains
as the domain of the person or subjective mind (Person bzw. subjektiver
Geist); the domain of the common mind or objective mind (Gemeingeist bzw.
objektiver Geist); and the domain of the cultural objects or objectified mind
(Kulturwerke bzw. objektivierter Geist).
2. Three main topics emerge from the accounts presented here. They
Three Topics correspond to three main areas of social reality:
1. Non-institutional life
2. Institutional life
3. Ethical-political life
13
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
The question of whether social ontology should admit intentional but not
social forms of life is to be left open4.
2.2 Non-institutional life, institutional life, ethical-political life are not only
Social Life as a different areas of social life, they are also normative levels of life. What we
Normative Level mean is that social reality as such is a normative dimension of life.
of Life
In particular, we make two claims:
3 As Francesca De Vecchi says, social entities do not depend on solitary intentionality; they
involve “heterotropic intentionality” (De Vecchi 2012, pp. 17-18).
4 Gilbert claims for such a position, Williams addresses in the present issue his criticism to
her opinion.
14
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
1. Social reality has its own eidetic laws, which differ from the
causal laws of nature and the motivational structures of mere
individual minds (if they exist).
2. Social reality is characterized by different types of normativity,
which vary depending on the level of social life we meet5.
2.3 Non-institutional life, institutional life, and ethical-political life are not
Hierarchical Levels only levels of social life, nor are they only normative levels of life. They
of Social Life are also hierarchical levels of life: non-institutional life, institutional life,
and ethical-political life are levels of social life in ascending order of
complexity. This implies that social-ontology has also to answer the formal-
ontological question about the type of relation among its components.
In the contemporary debate, different solutions have been proposed
to formalize the inner hierarchy of social reality (e.g. Supervenience
Theory, Constitution Theory, Emergentism). We distinguish at least three
hierarchical domains of social life: non-institutional, institutional life and
ethical-political life.
Non-institutional life is the basic level of social life. It is the domain of social
life precedent or besides its institutional normation. The first section of this
issue is devoted to the topic of non-institutional life.
Ethical-political life is the level of social life that implies the translation of
values and duties in political and juridical systems. It represents, in some
sense, the apex of the phenomenon of normativity. It is concerned with
the level of both social and institutional life regarded in their ontological,
deontic and axiological components. Meta-ethical and political topics are
discussed in the third section.
3.1 The first section presents contributions exploring the social world besides
First Topic: its institutional types, focusing on early imitation (Zhok), the embodied
Non-Institutional constitution of normality (Spina), the relations between individual persons and
Life personal groups (Ssonko, Williams), and the nature of cultural objects (Salice).
15
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
Spina’s paper Norm and Normatility. Starting from Merleau-Ponty shows the
conceptual tension and ambiguity of Merleau-Ponty’s description of
normality and norm by analysing his phenomenology of perception and
facing the task of abnormality.
16
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
3.2 The second topic, “Institutional Life”, is concerned with the level of social
Second Topic: life characterized by the phenomenon of norms or rules stricto sensu.
Institutional Life
Although the distinction between the institutional level of social life and
the non-institutional level of social life is not always adequately pointed out
in the literature, we consider it very important.
According to us, the distinction between the institutional level of social life and the
non-institutional level of social life is illuminated by the fundamental distinction
between nomic regularity and anomic regularity, pointed out by Amedeo G. Conte (2004,
2011)7. Anomic regularity is the regularity of actions which are performed regularly,
but without a rule – anomic regularity is a regularity without rules – nomic regularity
is the regularity of the actions which are performed regularly with a rule – nomic
regularity is a rule-related regularity.
17
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
On the opposite side, typical examples of nomic regularities are the habit of a
community to pray for the sake of a rule; the habit of a person to remove the cap
entering the church because of the fear of social blame or the habit of a person
to observe traffic rules because of the fear of police sanctions (to perform
action according to a rule)8; the habit of the cheat to cheat as a function of a rule
– a rule of a game – to which he does not conform his behavior, etc.9.
18
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
acts are those rules without which the game of chess or Parliamentary
acts would not exist. They differ from regulative rules, which simply rule
behaviors pre-existing to them, such as the rule that prohibits smoking.
According to Searle, social entities are essentially status functions, i.e.
entities created by constitutive rules or, according to some revisions of his
theory, by Status Function Declarations (Searle 2010).
The distinction between constitutive rules and regulative rules gave rise to a
great deal of research on the topics of constitutive rules, such as, in Italy,
those of Gaetano Carcaterra and those of Amedeo G. Conte’s School10, which
distinguished between eidetic constitutive rules and anankastic constitutive rules
(Conte 2007). While eidetic-constitutive rules are a necessary condition for
their object, anankastic-constitutive rules impose a necessary condition for
their object. Eidetic-constitutive rules create the type of their object, such as
the type of the game “chess” and its praxems (example of rule: “one cannot
castle when the king is under the check”); anankastic-constitutive rules
determine the tokens of pre-existing types, such as the tokens of the type
“wills” (example of rule: “wills ought to be signed by the Testator” (Conte
2001, 73).
10 The distinction between regulative rules and constitutive rules (Searle 1969) have an important
precursor in the Polish philosopher Czesław Znamierowski’ s distinction between “coercive
norms” (normy koercytywne) and “constructive norms” (normy konstrukcyjne). See Znamierowski
(1924).
19
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
The second section of this issue, “Institutional Life”, regards the question of
what essentially characterizes institutional entities. Differently from the previous
section, which primarily involves research on modalities of the constitution
of non-institutional life, the present section does not correspondently involve
research on modalities of the constitution of institutional life. Contributions
of this section welcome institutional reality as already constituted and focus
on what essentially characterizes it.
We would like to mention each contribution, which points out very relevant
aspects about institutional reality, as well as about the phenomenon of
constitutive rules. Some of them are also critical of the classical paradigm of
constitutive rules and of Searle’s institutional reality account.
20
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
Values are not a specific object of social ontology. Other regional ontologies
show values: unorganic material and natural life, for example, can carry
own values. Every realm of reality can be a bearer of values. Concerning
the nature of values, phenomenology stands within metaethics for a
realistic, objectivistic and cognitivistic position. There are plausible
phenomenological reasons to argue for an enlargement of the rationality
sphere to emotional life, which provides the possibility of an ethics of
values, integrating the Kantian formal rational view of ethics (see Scheler
1913-1916, Hartmann 1925). Although values, as such, are not specific to
social ontology, to this region correspond specific regional values, such as
sincerity, fidelity, fairness, human dignity, etc. and their corresponding
normative features, such as duties, commitments, claims. Furthermore,
specific values emerge at the level of institutional life: institutional life
21
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
coincides with the social life step in which the constitution of norms or
rules – obligations, duties, rights, permissions, prohibitions, authorizations,
licenses, etc., is given. Norms are, in opposition to values, specific social
ontological objects. The constitution of norms could be given without any
relation to an order of values, like the rules of a game: norms are ideally
independent from values, as Hume teaches. Otherwise, peculiar duties
correspond to every value, since the nature of values founds affordances in
the form of “to-be-ought”, and therefore motivates and justifies actions. If
norms are independent from values, duties are not.
The contributions of this section have the merit to reconstruct the classical
paradigm of rationalism, in ethics and politics, and to criticize or integrate it,
providing interesting directions of research, worth of developments.
11 The opposite point of view is argued by Max Weber, who claims that ethical-normative
beliefs have the status of ultimate value axioms (letzte Wertaxiome), which enjoy critical
immunity and so they are not liable to discussion. See Weber (1917) and see Fittipaldi (2003, 263).
22
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
4 Finally, we are very happy to present in the last, special section of the
Interviews current issue two interviews that were conducted by the editors with
23
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
4.1 Martha Craven Nussbaum and by Valentina Bambini, Cristiano Chesi and
Martha Nussbaum Andrea Moro with Noam Chomsky.
on Political
Emotions In her interview, Nussbaum gives us some insight into her current research
project, that will be published as “Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for
Justice” by Harvard University Press in 2013. Moving to her liberal account,
she stresses the role of emotions and liberal arts in the educations of the
citizens of a decent liberal society. Rationality and reasonability are not
enough in her account, since every person has to learn to master her passions
and to educate her sensitivity in order to have cognitive access to social
values. This project is linked with the general Nussbaum’s attempt to discern
human capabilities in order to formulate the fundamental constitutional
principles, that are always liable to be reviewed and improved. Here the role
of emotions and liberal arts stands out: they refine human sensitivity and
allow us to have cognitive access to renewable interests and claims, playing a
role in their recognition through rights, in the limits of what is ought by each
to everyone. The interview was held in Cologne, at the time of her Albertus
Magnus Lectures 2012 (June 19th-21st). For this opportunity, we would like to
thank the a.r.t.e.s. Graduate School for the Humanities Cologne (http://artes.phil-
fak.uni-koeln.de/), which is an international partner of our Research Centre
PERSONA.
24
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
References:
Berger, P. L. and Luckmann, T. (1966), The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise
in the Sociology of Knowledge, Anchor Books, Garden City (New York), 1966;
Bobbio, N. (1948), Introduzione alla filosofia del diritto, Torino, Giappichelli, 1948;
Conte, A. G. (2001), “Dimensions of Nomic Freedom”, in I. Carter, M. Ricciardi
(eds.), Freedom, Power, and Political Morality. Essays for Felix Oppenheim, Palgrave,
New York, 2001, pp. 69-78;
Conte, A. G. (2004), “Kanon. Filosofia della regolarità”, Sociologia del diritto, 3,
2004, pp. 5-22;
Conte, A. G. (2007), “Regola eidetico-costitutiva vs. regola anankastico-
costitutiva”, in L. Passerini Glazel (ed.), Ricerche di filosofia del diritto,
Giappichelli, Torino, 2007, pp. 48-68;
Conte, A. G. (2011), “Tetracotomia della regolarità”, in Amedeo G. Conte,
Sociologia filosofica del diritto, Giappichelli, Torino, 2011, pp. 73-86;
De Vecchi, F. (2012), “Making the Social World, or on making our Everyday
life World”, Phenomenology and Mind 3, 2012, pp. 14-21;
Fittipaldi, E. (2003), Scienza del diritto e razionalismo critico. Il programma
epistemologico di Hans Albert per la scienza e la sociologia del diritto, Giuffrè,
Milano, 2003;
Garfinkel, H. (1967), Studies in Ethnomethodology, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1967;
Hartmann, N. (1933), Das Problem des geistigen Seins. Untersuchungen zur
Grundlegung der Geschichtsphilosophie und der Geisteswissenschaften, De Gruyter,
Berlin, 1933;
Hartmann, N. (1925), Ethik, De Gruyter, Berlin-Leipzig, 1925;
Hersch, Jeanne (1990), “Le droits de l’homme d’un point de vue
philosophique”, in J. Hersch, L’exigence absolue de la liberté. Textes sur le droits
humains, 1973-1995, Genève, MetisPresses, 2008, pp. 103-125;
Husserl, E. (1950), (Hua), Husserliana: Edmund Husserl – Gesammelte Werke,
Springer, Dordrecht, 1950ff.;
Luckmann, T. and Schütz, A. (1975), Die Strukturen der Lebenswelt,
Luchterhand, Darmstadt und Neuwied, 1975 (New Edition: Suhrkamp,
Frankfurt am Main, 1979);
Mulligan, K. (2004), “Husserl on the ‘logics’ of valuing, values and norms”,
in B. Centi & G. Gigliotti (eds.), Fenomenologia della Ragion Pratica. L’Etica di
Edmund Husserl, Bibliopolis, Napoli, pp. 177-225;
Nam-Im-Lee (2006), The future of Phenomenologica Sociology, http://www.newschool.
edu/nssr/husserl/Future/Part%20One/PartOneFrames/PartOne.html;
Roversi, C. (2012), “Mimetic Constitutive Rules”, Phenomenology and Mind 3,
2012, pp. 144-151;
25
Norms, Values, Society: A Brief Phenomenological Overview
E. caminada Universität zu Köln, b. malvestiti Università degli Studi di Milano
Scheler, M. (1913-1916), Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik.
Neuer Versuch der Grundlegung eines ethischen Personalismus, in Gesammelte
Werke, vol. II (1954, 2000);
Searle, J. R. (1969), Speech Acts. An essay in the Philosophy of Language,
Cambridge University Press, London, 1969;
Searle, J. R (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, Penguin Press,
Harmondsworth, 1995;
Searle, J. R. (2010), Making the social world. The structure of human civilization,
Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010;
Smith, B. and Zaibert, L. (2007), “The Varieties of Normativity: An Essay on
Social Ontology”, in S. L. Tsohatzidis (ed.), Intentional Acts and Institutional Facts:
Essays on John Searle’s Social Ontology, Springer, Dordrecht, 2007, pp. 155–174;
Spiegelberg, H. (1933), Sinn und Recht der Begründung in der axiologischen
und praktischen Philosophie, in E. Heller, F. Loew (eds.), Neue Münchener
philosophische Abhandlungen, Barth, Leipzig, 1933, pp. 100-142;
Spiegelberg, H. (1937), Sollen und Dürfen. Philosophische Grundlagen der ethischen
Rechte und Pflichten, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1989;
Spiegelberg, H. (1939), “Justice Presupposes Natural Law”, Ethics, 49, 3, 1939,
pp. 343-348;
Spiegelberg, H. (1947), “What Makes Good Things Good? An Inquiry into the
Grounds of Value”, Philosophy And Phenomenological Research, 7, 4, 1947, pp. 578-611;
Stein, E. (1922), “Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie
und der Geisteswissenschaften”, in E. Husserl (ed.), Jahrbuch für Philosophie
und phänomenologische Forschung, Jg. 5, Niemeyer Verlag, Halle, pp. 1-284. New
Edition: Stein, E., Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der
Geisteswissenschaften (edited by B. Beckmann-Zöller), in E. Stein, Edith Stein
Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 6, Herder, Freiburg 2010;
Terravecchia, G. P. (2012), “Emergent Rules and Social Reality”, Phenomenology and
Mind 3, 2012, pp. 166-173;
Weber, M. (1917), Der Sinn der “Wertfreiheit” der soziologischen und ökonomischen
Wissenschaftlichen, in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, Mohr, 1988;
Znamierowski, C. (1924), Podstawowe poȩcia teorji prawa. I. Układ prawny i
norma prawna, Fiszer i Majewski, Poznań, 1924. Italian partial translation
of G. Lorini: “Atti tetici e norme costruttive”, in A. G. Conte, P. Di Lucia, L.
Ferrajoli, M. Jori (eds.), Filosofia del diritto, Raffaello Cortina, Milano, 2002, pp.
75-80 (new edition forthcoming).
26