Vygotsky Mind in Society PDF
Vygotsky Mind in Society PDF
Vygotsky Mind in Society PDF
35
tIL, .;J(~ ".';
!!!,;>-:;).'
(r alae c./}-., ;(£a-t:ifj
0 ' . •
,,14' •
"Lt£!.,a~pi/(4 I ~~~~.
jui.J~1I 'I'll ~J~ I,.ff!,/UU(.. Fragment of Vygotsky's note
UdA..y.z:tU~ d--IcJf1\ ~
HUlSt answer the following
questions: 1. How does one
remember stimulus 81 with the
h Utr/4..iA · (nm-fLUfUf.t. ~ . aid of stimulus 82 (where SI is
the object and S2 is the instru..
/t<L-~k ~ 2cfh~ &1.(/ nlent).2. How is attention
directed to 51 with the aid of 82.
Mind in Society/
The Development :7
of Higher
Psychological Processes
.VCf3
1978
c.. ~
Introduction 1
Michael Cole and Sylvia Scribner
Biographical Note on L. S. Vygotsky 15
Educational Implications
6. Interaction between Learning and Development 79
7. The Role of Play in Development 92
8. The Prehistory of Written Language 105
Afterword 121
Vera [ohn-Steiner and Ellen Souberman
Notes 135
Vygotsky's Works 141
Index 153
The spider carries out operations reminiscent of a weaver and the
boxes which bees build in the sky could disgrace the work of many
architects. But even the worst architect differs from the most able bee
from the very outset in that before he builds a box out of boards he
has already constructed it in his head. At the end of the work process
he obtains a result which already existed in his mind before he began
to build. The architect not only changes the form given to him by
nature, within the constraints imposed by nature, he also carries out
a purpose of his own which defines the means and the character of
the activity to which he must subordinate his will.
Karl Marx, Capital
NINETEENTH-CENTURY BEGINNINGS
Until the latter half of the nineteenth century the study of man's
nature was the province of philosophy. The intellectual descendants of
John Locke in England had developed his empiricist explanation of
mind, which emphasized the origin of ideas from environmentally
produced sensations. The major problem of psychological analysis for
these British empiricists was to describe the laws of association by
which simple sensations combine to produce complex ideas. On the
continent the followers of Immanuel Kant argued that ideas of space
and time and concepts of quantity, quality, and relation originate in the
human mind and cannot be decomposed into simpler elements. Neither
side budged from its armchair. Both of these philosophical traditions
were operating under the assumption, dating from the work of Rene
Descartes, that the scientific study of man could apply only to his
physical body. To philosophy was assigned the study of his soul.
While the conflict between these two approaches reaches down to
the present day, in the 1860s the terms of this discussion were changed
irrevocably by the almost simultaneous publication of three 'books. Most
famous was Darwin's Origin of Species, which argued the essential
continuity of man and other animals. One immediate consequence of
this assertion was an effort by many scholars to establish discontinuities
that set human adults off from their lower relatives (both ontogenetically
and phylogenetically). The second book was Gustav Fechner's Die
Psuchophqsik, which provided a detailed, mathematically sophisticated
description of the relation between changes in specifiable physical
events and verbalizable "psychic" responses. Fechner claimed no less
than an objective, quantitative description of the contents of the human
mind. The third book was a slim volume entitled Reflexes of the Brain,
written by a Moscow physician, I. M. Sechenov. Sechenov, who had
studied with some of Europe's leading physiologists, had advanced
understanding of simple sensory-motor reflexes by using techniques that
isolated nerve-muscle preparations from the living organism. Sechenov
was convinced that the processes he observed in the isolated tissue of
frogs were the same in principle as those that take place in the central
nervous systems of intact organisms, including humans. If responses of
leg muscles could be accounted for by processes of inhibition and exci-
tation, might not the same laws apply to the operations of the human
cerebral cortex? Although he lacked direct evidence for these specula-
tions, Sechenov's ideas suggested
.- the physiological basis for linking
the natural scientific study of animals with the heretofore philosophical
Introduction
3
Vygotsky and many other Soviet theorists of the day were also
heavily influenced by the work of western European sociologists and
anthropologists, like Thurnwald and Levy-Bruhl.t who were interested
in the history of mental processes as reconstructed from anthropological
evidence of the intellectual activity of primitive peoples. The scant
references in this book are a pale reflection of the extent of Vygotsky's
interest in the development of mental processes understood historically.
This aspect of his work received special attention in a publication
titled Studies in the History of Behavior published jointly with A. R.
Luria in 1930. It served as the impetus for Luria's two expeditions to
Central Asia in 1931 and 1932, the results of which were published
long after Vygotsky's death,"
This historical emphasis was also popular in Soviet linguistics,
where interest centered on the problem of the origin of language and its
influence on the development of thought. Discussions in linguistics dealt
with concepts similar to Vygotsky's and also similar to the work of Sapir
and Whorf, who were then becoming influential in the United States.
While an acquaintance with academic issues of the 1930s is helpful
to understanding Vygotsky's approach to human cognition, a considera-
tion of sociopolitical conditions during this time in the Soviet Union is
essential as well. Vygotsky worked within a society that put a premium
on science and had high hopes for the ability of science to solve the
pressing economic and social problems of the Soviet people. Psycho-
logical theory could not be pursued apart from the practical demands
made on scientists by the government, and the broad spectrum of Vygot-
sky's work clearly shows his concern with producing a psychology that
would have relevance for education and medical practice. For Vygotsky,
the need to carryon theoretical work in an applied context posed no
contradiction whatsoever. He had begun his career as a teacher of litera-
ture, and many of his early articles had dealt with problems of educa-
tional practice, especially education of the mentally and physically
handicapped. He had been a founder of the Institute of Defectology in
Moscow, with which he was associated throughout his working life. In
such medical problems as congenital blindness, aphasia, and severe
mental retardation Vygotsky saw opportunities both for understanding
the mental processes of all people and for establishing programs of
treatment and remediation. Thus, it was consistent with his general
theoretical view that his work should be carried out in a society that
sought the elimination of illiteracy and the founding of educational
programs to maximize the potential of individual children.
Vygotsky's participation in the debates surrounding the formulation
Introduction
10
not a stimulus-response learning theorist and did not intend his idea
of mediated behavior to be thought of in this context. What he did
intend to convey by this notion was that in higher forms of human be-
havior, the individual actively modifies the stimulus situation as a
part of the process of responding to it. It was the entire structure of this
activity which produced the behavior that Vygotsky attempted to de-
note by the term "mediating."
Several implications follow from Vygotsky's theoretical approach
and method of experimentation. One is that experimental results will
be qualitative as well as quantitative in nature. Detailed descriptions,
based on careful observation, will constitute an important part of
experimental findings. To some, such findings may seem merely anec-
dotal; Vygotsky maintained that if carried out objectively and with
scientific rigor, such observations have the status of validated fact.
Another consequence of this new approach to experimentation is
to break down some of the barriers that are traditionally erected be ..
tween "laboratory" and "field." Experimental interventions and obser..
vations may often be as well or better executed in play, school, and
clinical settings than in the psychologist's laboratory. The sensitive ob-
servations and imaginative interventions reported in this book attest
to this possibility.
Finally, an experimental method that seeks to trace the history of
the development of psychological functions sits more comfortably than
the classical method alongside other methods in the social sciences con-
cerned with history-including the history of culture and society as
well as the history of the child. To Vygotsky, anthropological and
sociological studies were partners with observation and experiment in
the grand enterprise of accounting for the progress of human conscious-
ness and intellect.
Biographical Note on
L. S. Vygotsky
Basic Theory
and Data
Tool and Symbol in
Child Development
jects, their ability to make detours while pursuing a goal, and the
manner in which they use pr!niitive tools: ·These observations, as well
as his experiment in which a youngchild i;'" asked to remove a ring from
a stick, illustrate an approach akin to Kohler's. Buhler interpreted the
manifestations of practical intelligence in children as being of exactly
the same type as those we are familiar with in chimpanzees. Indeed,'
there is a phase in the life of the child that Buhler designated the
"chimpanzee age" (p. 48). One ten-month-old infant whom he studied
was able to pull a string to obtain a cookie that was attached to it. The
ability to remove a ring from a post by lifting it rather than trying to
pull it sideways did not appear until the middle of the second year."
Although these experiments were interpreted as support for the analogy
between the child and apes, they also led Buhler to the important dis-
covery, which will be explicated in later sections, that the beginnings
of practical intelligence in the child (he termed it "technical thinking"),
as well as the actions of the chimpanzee, are independent of speech.
Charlotte Buhler's detailed observations of infants during their
first year of life gave further support to this conclusion." She found the
first manifestations of practical intelligence took place at the very
young age of six months, However, it is not only tool use that develops
at this point in a child's history but also systematic movement and
perception, the brain and hands-in fact, the child's entire organism.
Consequently, the child's system of activity is determined at each specific
stage both by the child's degree of organic development and by his or
her degree of mastery in the use of tools.
K. Buhler established the developmentallyimportant principle that
the beginnings of intelligent speech are preceded by technical thinking,
and technical thinking comprises the initial phase of cognitive develop-
ment. His lead in emphasizing the chimpanzee-like features of children's
behavior has been followed by many others. It is in extrapolating this
idea that the dangers of zoological models and analogies between human
and animal behaviors find their clearest expression. The pitfalls are
slight in research that focuses on the preverbal period in the child's
development, as Buhler's did. However, he drew a questionable conclu-
sion from his work with very young children when he stated, "The
achievements of the chimpanzee are quite independent of language
and in the case of man, even in later life, technical thinking, or think-
ing in terms of tools, is far less closely bound up with language and
concepts than other forms of thinking."?
Buhler proceeded from the assumption that the relationship be-
tween practical intelligence and speech that characterizes the ten-
Mind in Society
.2.2
sumed that the child's mind contains all stages of furore intellectual
development; they exist in complete form, awaiting the proper moment
to emerge.
Not only were speech and practical intelligence assumed to have
different origins, but their joint participation in common operations
was considered to be of no basic psychological importance (as in the
work of Shapiro and Gerke). Even when speech and the use of tools
were closely linked in one operation, they were still studied as separate
processes belonging to two completely different classes of phenomena.
At best, their simultaneous occurrence was considered a consequence
of accidental, external factors.
The students of practical intelligence as well as those who study
speech development often fail to recognize the interweaving of these
two functions. Consequently, the children's adaptive behavior and sign-
using activity are treated as parallel phenomena-a view that leads to
Piaget's concept of "egocentric" speech.P He did not attribute an
Important role to speech in the organization of the child's activities,
nor did he stress its communicative functions, although he was obliged
to admit its practical importance.
Although practical intelligence and sign use can operate inde-
pendently of each other in young children, the dialectical unity of these
systems in the human adult is the very essence of complex human be-
havior. Our analysis accords symbolic activity a specific organizing
function that penetrates the process of tool use and produces funda-
mentally new forms of behavior.
Prior to mastering his own behavior, the child begins to master his
surroundings with the help of speech. This produces new relations with
the environment in addition 'to the new organization of behavior itself.
The creation of these uniquely human forms of behavior later produce
the intellect and become the basis of productive work: the specifically
human fonn of the use of tools.
Observations of children in an experimental situation similar to
that of Kohler's apes show that the children not only a.¢Jn attempting
to achieve a goal but also speak. As a rule this speech arises spontane-
ously and continues almost without interruption throughout the experi-
ment. It increases and is more persistent every time the situation be-
comes more complicated and the goal more difficult to attain. Attempts
to block it (as the experiments of my collaborator R. E. Levina have
shown) are either futile or lead the child to "freeze up."
Levina posed practical problems for four- and five-year-old children
such as obtaining a piece of candy from a cupboard. The candy was
placed out of reach so the child could not obtain it directly. As the child
got more and more involved in trying to obtain the candy, "egocentric"
speech began to manifest itself as part of her active striving. At first
this speech consisted of a description and analysis of the situation, but
it gradually took on a "planful" character, reflecting possible paths to
solution of the problem. Finally, it was included as part of the solution.
For example, a four-and-a-half-year-old girl was asked to get candy
from a cupboard with a stool and a stick as possible tools. Levina's
description reads as follows: (Stands on a stool, quietly looking, feeling
along a shelf with stick.) "On the stool." (Glances at experimenter. Puts
stick in other hand.) "Is that really the candy?" (Hesitates.) cCI can get it
from that other stool, stand and get it." (Gets second stool.) "No, that
doesn't get it. I could use the stick." (Takes stick, knocks at the candy.)
C'It will move now." (Knocks candy.) celt moved, I couldn't get it with
the stool, but the, but the stick worked."13
In such circumstances it seems both natural and necessary for
children to speak while they act; in our research we have f~und that
speech not only accompanies practical activity but also plays a specific
role in carrying it out. Our experiments demonstrate two important
facts:
(1) A child's speech is as important as the role of action in attaining
the goal. Children not only speak about what they are doing; their
speech and action are part of one and the same complex psychological
function, directed toward the solution of the problem at hand.
(2) The more complex the action demanded by the situation and
Mind in Society
26
the less direct its solution, the greater the importance played by speech
in the operation as a whole. Sometimes speech becomes of such. vital
importance that, if not permitted to use it, young children cannot ac-
complish the given task.
These observations lead me to the conclusion that children solve
practical tasks with the help of their speech, as well as their eyes and
hands. This unity of perception, speech, and action, which ultimately
produces internalization of the visual field, constitutes the central sub-
ject matter for any analysis of the origin of uniquely human forms of
behavior.
To develop the first of these two points, we must ask: What is it that,
really distinguishes the actions of the speaking child from the actions
of an ape when solving practical problems?
The first thing that strikes the experimenter is the incomparably
greater freedom of children's operations, their greater independence
from the structure of the concrete, visual situation. Children, with the
aid of speech, create greater possibilities than apes can accomplish
through action. One important manifestation of this greater flexibility
is that the child is able to ignore the direct line between actor and goal.
Instead, he engages in a number of preliminary acts, using what we
speak of as .IDstrumental, or mediated (indirect), methods. In the process
of solving a task the child is able to include sti;muli that do not lie within
the immediate visual field. Using words (one class of such stimuli) to
create a specific plan, the child achieves a much broader range of
activity, applying as tools not only those objects that lie near at hand,
but searching for and preparing such stimuli as can be useful in the
solution of the task, and planning future actions.
Second, the practical operations of a child who can speak become
much less impulsive and spontaneous than those of the ape. The ape
typically makes a series of uncontrolled attempts to solve the given
problem. In contrast, the child who uses speech divides the activity into
two consecutive parts. She plans how to solve the problem through
speech and then carries out the prepared solution through overt ac-
tivity. Direct manipulation is replaced by a complex psychological
process through which- inner motivation and intentions, postponed in
time, stimulate their own development and realization. This new kind
of psychological structure is absent in apes, even in rudimentary forms.
Finally, it is decisively important that speech not only facilitates the
child's effective manipulation of objects .but also controls the child's own
behavior. Thus, with the help of speech children, unlike apes, acquire
the capacity to be both the subjects and objects of their own behavior.
\
Tool and Symbol in Child Development
27
early stage speech accompanies the child's actions and reflects the
vicissitudes of problem solving in a disrupted and chaotic form. At
a later stage speech moves more and more toward the starting point of
the process, so that it comes to precede action. It functions then as an
aid to a plan that has been conceived but not yet realized in behavior.
An interesting analogy can be found in children's speech while drawing
(see also chapter 8). Young children name their drawings only after
they have completed them; they need to see them before they can decide
what they are. As children get older they can decide in advance what
they are going to draw. This displacement of the naming process signifies
a change in the function of speech. Initially speech follows actions, is
provoked by and dominated by activity. At a later stage, however, when
speech is moved to the starting point of an activity, a new relation be-
tween word and action emerges. Now speech guides, determines, and
dominates the course of action; the planning function of speech comes
into being in addition to the already existing function of language to
reflect the external world."
Just as a mold gives shape to a substance, words can shape an
activity into a structure. However, that structure may be changed or
reshaped when children learn touse Ianguage in ways that allow them
to go beyond previous experiences when planning future action. In
contrast to the notion of sudden discovery popularized by Stern, we
envisage verbal, intellectual activity as a series of stages in which the
emotional and communicative functions of speech are expanded by the
addition of the planning function. As a result the child acquires the abil-
ity to engage in complex operations extending over time.
Unlike the ape, which Kohler tells us is "the slave of its own visual
field," children acquire an independence with respect to their concrete
surroundings; they cease to act in the immediately given and evident
space. Once children learn how to use the planning function of their
language effectively, their psychological field changes radically. A
view of the future is now an integral part of their approaches to their
surroundings. In subsequent chapters, I will-describe the developmental
course of some of these central psychological functions in greater detail.
To summarize what has been said thus far in this section: The
specifically human capacity for language enables children to provide
for auxiliary tools in the solution of difficult tasks, to overcome impulsive
action, to plan a solution to a problem prior to its execution, and to
master their own behavior. Signs and words serve children first and
foremost as a means of social contact with other people. The cognitive
and communicative functions of language then become the basis of a
Tool and Symbol in Child Development
29
tion equally with words and sticks, demonstrating the fundamental and
inseparable tie between speech and action in the child's activity; this
unity becomes particularly clear when compared with the separation of
these processes in adults.
In summary, children confronted with a problem that is slightly too
complicated for them exhibit . a complex variety of responses including
direct attempts at attaining the goal, the use of tools, speech directed
toward the person conducting the experiment or speech that simply
accompanies the action, and direct, verbal appeals to the object of
attention itself.
If analyzed dynamically, this alloy of speech and action has a very
specific function in the history of the child's development; it also demon-
strates the logic of its own genesis. From the very first days of the child's
development his activities acquire a meaning of their own in a system of
social behavior and, being directed towards a definite purpose, are re-
fracted through the prism of the child's environment. The path from
object to child and from child to object passes through another person.
This complex human structure is the product of a developmental process
deeply rooted in the links between individual and social history.
2
The Development of
Perception and Attention
The linkage between tool use and speech affects several psycho-
logical functions, in particular perception, sensory-motor operations,
and attention, each of which is part of a dynamic system of behavior.
Experimental-developmental research indicates that the connections
and relations among functions constitute systems that change as radically
in the course of a child's development as do the individual functions
themselves. Considering each function in turn, I will examine how
speech introduces qualitative changes in both its form and its relation to
other functions.
Kohler's work emphasized the importance of the structure of the
visual field in organizing the ape's practical behavior. The entire process
of problem solving is essentially determined by perception. In this
respect Kohler had ample grounds for believing that these animals are
bound by their sensory field to a much greater extent than adult humans.
They are incapable of modifying their sensory field by means of volun-
tary effort, Indeed, it would probably be useful to view as a general law
the dependence of all natural forms of perception on the structure of
the sensory field.
However, a child's perception, because it is human, does not develop
as a direct continuation and further perfection of the forms of animal
perception, not even of those animals that stand nearest to humankind.
Experiments conducted to clarify this problem led us to discover some
basic laws that characterize the higher human forms of perception.
The first set of experiments concerned developmental stages of
picture perception in children. Similar experiments describing specific
aspects of young children's perception and its dependence On higher
31
Mind in Society
32
ments within it. The child evaluates the relative importance of these
elements, singling out new CCfigures" from the background and thus
widening the possibilities for controlling her activities."
In addition to reorganizing the visual-spatial field, the child, with
the help of speech, creates a time field that is just as perceptible and
real to him as the visual one. The speaking child has the ability to
direct his attention in a dynamic way. He can view changes in his
immediate situation from the point of view of past activities, and he can
act in the present from the.viewpoint of the future.
For the ape, the task 'is unsolvable unless the goal and the object
needed to reach it are both simultaneously in view. For the child, this
gap is easily overcome by verbally controlling her attention and thereby
reorganizing her perceptual field. The ape will perceive a stick one
moment, but cease to pay attention to it after its visual field has changed
and the goal comes into view. The ape must see his stick in order to pay
attention to it; the child may pay attention in order to see.
Thus, the child's field of attention embraces not one but a whole
series of potential perceptual fields that form successive, dynamic
structures over time. The transition from the simultaneous structure of
the visual field to the successive structure of the dynamic field of atten-
tion is achieved through the reconstruction of the separate activities that
are a part of the required operations. When this occurs, we can say that
the field of attention has detached itself from the perceptual field and
unfolded itself in time, as one component of a dynamic series of psycho-
logical activities.
The possibility of combining elements of the past and present visual
fields (for instance, tool and goal) in one field of attention leads in turn
to a basic reconstruction of another vital function, memory. (See chapter
3.) Through verbal formulations of past situations and activities, the
child frees himself from the limitations of direct recall; he succeeds in
synthesizing the past and present to suit his purposes. The changes that
occur in memory are similar to those that occur in the child's perceptual
field where centers of gravity are shifted and figure and ground rela-
tionship are altered. The child's memory not only makes fragments of the
past more available, but also results in a new method of uniting the
elements of past experience with the present.
Created with the help of speech, the time field for action extends
both forward and backward. Future activity that can be included in an
ongoing activity is represented by signs. As in the case of memory and
attention, the inclusion of signs in temporal perception does not lead to
a simple lengthening of the operation in time; rather, it creates the
The Development of Perception and Attention
37
38
Maste1'Y of Memory and Thinking
39
s R
x
Figure 1
was forbidden to use, and no color name could be used twice. The third
task had the same rules as the second, but the child was given nine
colored cards as aids to playing the game ("these cards can help you to
win"). The fourth task was like the third and was used in cases where
the child either failed to use the color cards or began to do so only late
in the third task. Before and after each task we asked the child questions .
to determine if she remembered and understood the instructions.
A set of questions for a typical task is the following (in this case
green and yellow are the forbidden colors): (1) Have you a playmate?
(2) What color is your shirt? (3) Did you ever go in a train? (4) What color
are the railway-carriages? (5) Do you want to be big? (6) Were you
ever at the theater? (7) Do you like to play in the room? (8) What color
is the floor? (9) And the walls? (10) Can you write? (11) Have you seen
lilac? (12) What color is lilac? (13) Do you like sweet things? (14) Were
you ever in the country? (15) What colors can leaves be? (16) Can you
swim? (17) What is your favorite color? (18) What does one do with a
pencil?
For the third and fourth tasks the following color cards were pro-
vided as aids: black, white, red, blue, yellow, green, lilac, brown, and
gray.
The results for thirty subjects ranging in age from five to twenty-
seven years are summarized in table 1, which contains the average
number of errors on tasks 2 and 3 and the difference between the two
tasks. Looking first at the data from task 2, we see a slight decrease in
errors from ages five to thirteen and a sharp drop in adulthood. For
task 3 the sharpest drop occurs between the Hve-tc-six and eight-to-nine-
year-old groups. The difference between tasks 2 and 3 is small for both
the preschool children and the adults. The difference is largest for the
school-age children.
The processes that give rise to the summary figures are most readily
revealed by looking at transcripts representative of children in the difler-
Mind in Society
42
ent groups. The preschool children (age five to six years) were generally
unable to discover how to use the auxiliary color cards and had a great
deal of trouble with both tasks. Even when we tried to explain to them
how the color cards could help them, children at this age were incapable
of using these external stimuli in order to organize their own behavior.
The following transcript is from a five-year-old boy;
This transcript suggests that the "aids" actually hindered this child.
His repeated use of "white" as a response occurred when his attention
was fixed on the white card. The aids are only an accidental feature of
the situation for him. Still, there is no doubt that preschool children
sometimes demonstrate precursors of the use of external signs. From this
point of view certain cases are of special interest. For example, after we
suggested to a child that he use the cards to carry out his task ("take the
cards, they will help you to win"), he searched for the forbidden colors
and put all such cards out of his sight, as if trying to prevent himself
from naming them.
In spite of their apparent variety, methods for using the cards can
be reduced to two basic types. First the child may put forbidden colors
out of sight, display the remainder, and, as he answers the questions,
place the colors already named to one side. This is the less effective but
Mastery of Memory and Thinking
43
the earliest method used. The card in this case serves only to register the
named color. Initially, children often do not turn to the cards before they
answer the question about color, and only after it is named do they
search among the cards, turn over, move, or put away the one named.
This is undoubtedly the simplest act of memorization with the help of
external means. It is only later that the conditions of the experiment .
bestow a new, second function on the cards. Before naming a color the
child makes a selection with the help of the cards. It makes no difference
whether the child looks at the cards so far unused or whether she attends
to the colors she has already named. In either case the cards are inter-
posed in the process and serve as a means of regulating her activity. The
preliminary hiding of forbidden colors, which is a distinguishing char-
acteristic of the first method for using the cards, does not yet lead to the
complete substitution of a less mature operation by a more complex one;
it represents merely a step in that direction. Its occurrence is explained
partly by the greater simplicity of this operation in mastering memory
and partly by a "magical" attitude toward various potential problem-
solving aids that children frequently display.
The following examples from a thirteen-year-old schoolgirl illus-
trate these points:
when being shown- the auxiliary stimulus. Rather, the sign evokes a
new associative or syncretic series represented by the following scheme:
A~
X
Figure 2
The operation has not yet progressed to the more advanced level which
is mediated in form using culturally elaborated features. In contrast with
figure 2, the usual scheme for mediated memorizing can be represented
by the following:
Figure 3
cases, children linked the figures to the word stimuli by changing the
meaning of the sign instead of using the mediating link offered by the
experimenter. The introduction of these meaningless figures encouraged
the children to engage in active mnemonic activity instead of relying on
already formed links, but it also led them to treat the sign stimulus as
the direct representation of the object to be remembered. When this
proved impossible, the child refused to memorize.
A similar phenomenon is apparent in u. C. Yussevich's unpublished
study with small children. The auxiliary stimuli, which were pictures
that bore no direct relation to the word presented, were rarely used as
signs. The child looked at the picture and tried to see in it the object
she had to remember. For example, when asked to remember the word
"sun" with the help of a picture showing an axe, one child did it very
easily; she pointed to a small yellow spot in the drawing and said, "There
it is, the sun." This child replaced potentially complex instrumental
memorization by a search for a direct representation of the stimulus
(akin to an eidetic image). The child sought an eidetic-like representation
in the auxiliary sign. In both the Zankov and Yussevich examples, the
child reproduced the required word through a process of direct repre-
sentation rather than mediated symbolization.
The laws describing the role of sign oper~tions at this stage of de-
velopment are completely different from the laws describing how the
child links up a word with a sign in fully developed sign operations.
Children in the experiments just described illustrate a stage of de-
velopment between the elementary and the completely instrumental
process from which fully mediated operations will later develop.
Leontiev's work on the development of sign operations in memory
provides examples supporting the theoretical points discussed above
as well as later stages in the development of sign operations in memory.P
He gave a set of twenty words for recall to children of different ages and
levels of mental ability. The materials were presented in three ways.
First, the words were simply spoken at intervals of about three seconds
and the child was told to recall them, In a second task the child was
given a set of twenty pictures and told to lise them to help recall the
words. The pictures were not replicas of the words but were associated
with them. In the third series twenty pictures bearing no obvious rela-
tion to the to-be-remembered words were used. The basic questions
in this research were to what extent can children convert their remem-
bering into a mediated activity using pictures as auxiliary memory aids
and how does their success depend upon the different degrees of diffi-
culty represented by the two, potentially mediated, series.
As we might expect, the results differed depending upon the group
Mastery of Memory and Thinking
49
of children and the difficulty of the recall task. Normal children (ten
to twelve years of age) recalled twice as many words when the pictures
were available as memory aids as they did without them. They were
able to make use of both picture series equally well. Mildly retarded
children of the same age benefited little, if at all, from the presence of
the pictures; and for severely retarded children, the auxiliary stimuli .
actually interfered with performance.
The original transcripts from this study clearly show intermediate
levels of functioning in which the child attends to the auxiliary picture
stimulus and even associates it with the word to be recalled but cannot
integrate the stimulus into his system of remembering. Thus, one child
selected a picture of an onion to recall the word "dinner." When asked
why she chose the picture, she gave the perfectly satisfactory answer,
"Because I eat an onion." However, she was unable to recall the word
"dinner" during the experiment. This example shows that the ability to
form elementary associations is not sufficient to ensure that the associa-
tive relation will fulfill the instrumental function necessary to produce
recall. This kind of evidence leads us to conclude that the development
of mediated psychological functions (in this case, mediated memory)
represents a special line of development that does not wholly coincide
with the development of elementary processes.
I should mention also that the addition of pictures as memory aids
did not facilitate recall of adults. The reason for the "failure" is directly
opposite to the reasons underlying the failure of memory aids to affect
the severely retarded children. In the case of adults, the process of
mediated memorizing is so fully developed that it occurs even in the
absence of special external aids.
The memory of older children is not only different from the memory
of younger children; it also plays a different role in the older child's
cognitive activity. Memory in early childhood is one of the central
psychological functions upon which all the other functions are built.
OUf analyses suggest that thinking in the very young child is in many
respects determined by his memory, and is certainly not the same thing
as the thinking of the more mature child. For the very young child, to
think means to remember; at no time after very early childhood do
we see such a close connection between these two psychological func-
tions.
I will give three examples. The first is the definition of concepts in
children, which are based on their recollections. If you ask a child to tell
you what a snail is, he will say that it is little, it slithers, and it sticks
out its foot; if you ask him to tell you what a grandmother is, he is likely
to reply, "She has a soft lap." In both cases the child gives a very clear
summary of the impressions which the topic has made upon him and
which he recollects~ The content of the thinking act in the child when
defining such concepts is determined not so much· by the logicai struc-
ture of the concept itself as by the child's concrete recollections. It is
syncretic in ch~racter and reflects the fact that the child's thinking de-
pends first of allan his memory.
Another example is the development of visual concepts in very
young children. Investigations of children's thinking when they are re-
quired to transpose a relation learned with one set of stimuli to a similar
set have shown that their transfer is nothing more than remembering
with respect to isolated instances. Their general representations of
the world are based on the recall of concrete instances and do not yet
possess the ch'aracter of an abstraction."
The last example concerns the analysis of word meaning. Investi-
gations in this area show that the connections underlying words are
fundamentally different in the young child and in the adult. Children's
concepts relate to a series of examples and are constructed in a manner
similar to the way we represent family names. To name words for
them is not so much to indicate familiar concepts as to name familiar
families or whole groups of visual things connected by visual ties. In
this way the experience of the child and the "unmediated" influence of
the child's experience are documented in his memory and directly deter-
mine the entire structure of the young child's thought.
All these facts suggest that, from the point of view of psychological
development, memory rather than abstract thought is the definitive
Mastery of Memory and Thinking
51
Internalization of Higher
Psychological Functions
I Mediated activity I
ISign/""
I ITool I
Figure 4
That concept, quite justly, was invested with the broadest general
meaning by Hegel, who saw in it a characteristic feature of human
reason: "Reason," he wrote, "is just as cunning as she is powerful. Her
cunning consists principally in her mediating activity which, by causing
objects to act and react on each other in accordance with their own
nature, in this way, without any direct interference in the process, car-
ries out reasons' intentions."! Marx cites that definition when speaking of
working tools, to show that man "uses the mechanical, physical, and
chemical properties of objects so as to make them act as forces that affect
other objects in order to fulfill his personal goals."2
This analysis provides a sound basis for assigning the use of signs
to the category of mediated activity, for the essence of sign use consists
in man's affecting behavior through signs. In both cases the indirect
(mediated) function comes to the forefront. I shall not define further the
relation of these jointly subsumed concepts to each other, or their rela-
tion to the more generic concept of mediated activity. I should only
Internalization of High~ Psychological Functions
55
like to note that neither can, under any circumstance, be considered iso-
morphic with respect to the functions they perform, nor can they be
seen as fully exhausting the concept of mediated activity. A host of
other mediated activities might be named; cognitive activity is not
limited to the use of tools or signs.
On the purely logical plane of the relation between the two con- .
cepts, our schema represents the two means of adaptation as diverging
lines of mediated activity. This divergence is the basis for our second
point. A .most essential difference between sign and tool, and the basis
for the real divergence of the two lines, is the different ways that they
orient human behavior. The tool's function is to serve as the conductor
of human influence on the object of activity; it is externally oriented;
it must lead to changes in objects. It is a means by which human external
activity is aimed at mastering, and triumphing over, nature. The sign, on
the other hand, changes nothing in the object of a psychological opera-
tion. It is a means of internal activity aimed at mastering oneself; the
sign is internally oriented. These activities are so different from each
other that the nature of the means they use cannot be the same in both
cases.
Finally, the third point pertains to the real tie .between these activi-
ties and, hence, to the real tie of their development in phylo- and onto-
genesis. The mastering of nature and the mastering of behavior are
mutually linked, just as man's alteration of nature alters man's own
nature. In phylogenesis we can reconstruct this link through fragmentary
but convincing documentary evidence, while in ontogenesis we can
trace it experimentally.
One thing is already certain. Just as the first use of tools refutes the
notion that development represents the mere unfolding of the child's
organically predetermined system of activity, so the first use of signs
demonstrates that there cannot be a single organically predetermined
internal system of activity that exists for each psychological function.
The use of artificial means, the transition to mediated activity, funda-
mentally changes all psychological operations just as the use of tools
limitlessly broadens the range of activities within which the new
psychological functions may operate. In this context, we can use the
term higher psychological function, or higher behavior as referring to
the combination of tool and sign in psychological activity.
Several phases in the use of sign operations have been described
thus far. In the initial phase reliance upon external signs is crucial to the
child's effort. But through development these operations undergo radi-
cal changes: the entire operation of mediated activity (for example,
Mind in Society
56
Problems of Method
58
Problems of Method
59
for the millionth time and have become mechanized. They have lost
their original appearance, and their outer appearance tells us nothing
whatsoever about their internal nature. Their automatic character 'cre-
ates great difficulties for psychological analysis.
The processes that have traditionally been referred to as voluntary
and involuntary attention provide an elementary example that demon-
strates how essentially different processes acquire outer similarity as
a result of this automation. Developmentally speaking, these two pro-
cesses differ very profoundly. But in experimental psychology it is con-
sidered a fact, as formulated by Titchener, that voluntary attention,
once established, functions just like involuntary attention." In Titchener's
terms, "secondary" attention constantly changes into "primary" attention.
Having described and contrasted the two types of attention, Titchener
then says, "There exists, however, a third stage in the development of
attention, and it consists in nothing less than a return to the first stage."
The last and highest stage in the development of any process may
demonstrate a purely phenotypic similarity with the first or primary
stages, and if we take a phenotypic approach, it is impossible to dis-
tinguish between higher and lower forms of this process. The only way
to study this third and highest stage in the development of attention is to
understand it in all its idiosyncrasies and differences. In short, we need
to understand its origin. It follows, then, that we need to concentrate
not on the product of development but on the very process by which
higher forms are established. To do so the researcher is often forced
to alter the automatic, mechanized, fossilized character of the higher
form of behavior and to turn it back to its source through the experiment.
This is the aim of dynamic analysis.
Inactive, rudimentary functions stand not as the living remnants of
biological evolution but as those of the historical development of be-
havior. Consequently, the study of rudimentary functions must be the
point of departure for evolving a historical perspective in psychological
experiments. It is here that the past and the present are fused and the
present is seen in the light of history. Here r~e find ourselves simultane-
ously on two planes: that which is and that which was. The fossilized
form is the end of the thread that ties the present to the past, the higher
stages of development to the primary ones.
The concept of a historically based psychology is misunderstood
by most researchers who study child development. For them, to study
something historically means, by definition, to study some past event.
Hence, they naively imagine an insurmountable barrier between his-
toric study and study of present-day behavioral forms. To study some-
Problems of Method
65
behavior; at each new stage the child changes not only her response
but carries out that response in new ways, drawing on new "instruments'
of behavior and replacing one psychological function by another. Psy-
chological operations that were achieved through direct forms of adapta-
tion at early stages are later accomplished through indirect means. The
growing complexity of children's behavior is reflected in the changed.
means they use to fulfill new tasks and the corresponding reconstruction
of their psychological processes..
Our concept of development implies a rejection of the frequently
held view that cognitive development results from the gradual accumu-
lation of separate changes. We believe that child development is a
complex dialectical process characterized by periodicity, unevenness in'
the development of different functions, metamorphosis or qualitative
transfo;rmation of one form into another, intertwining of external and
internal factors, and adaptive processes which overcome impediments
that the child encounters. Steeped in the notion of evolutionary change,
most workers in child psychology ignore those turning points, those
spasmodic and revolutionary changes that are so frequent in the history
of child development. To the naive mind, revolution and evolution seem
incompatible and historic development continues only so long as it
follows a straight line. Where upheavals occur, where the historical
fabric is ruptured, the naive mind sees only catastrophe, gaps, and dis-
continuity. History seems to stop dead, until it once again takes the
direct, linear path of development.
Scientific thought, on the contrary, sees revolution and evolution as
two forms of development that are mutually related and mutually
presuppose each other. Leaps in the child's development are seen by the
scientific mind as no more than a moment in the general line of
development.
As I have repeatedly emphasized, an essential mechanism of the
reconstructive processes that take place during a child's development is
the creation and use of a number of artificial stimuli. These play an
auxiliary role that permits human beings to master their own behavior,
at first by external means and later by more complex inner operations.
Our approach to the study of cognitive functioning does not require
the experimenter to furnish subjects with ready-made, external or arti-
ficial means in order that they may successfully complete the given
task. The experiment is equally valid if, instead of giving children
artificial means, the experimenter waits until they spontaneously apply
some new auxiliary method or symbol that they then incorporate into
their operations.
The specific area to which we apply this approach is not important.
Mind in Society
74
but they are limited to the study of external responses that are usually
in the subject's repertoire to begin with. We believe that our approach
to objectifying inner psychological processes is much more adequate,
where the goals of psychological research are concerned, than the
method of studying preexisting, objective responses.'! Only the objecti-
fication of the inner process guarantees access to specific forms of higher
behavior as opposed to subordinate forms.
Part Two / Mind in Society
Educational
Implications
6
Interaction between
Learning and Development
79
Mind in Society
80
particular subjects for daily living, they were of the greatest value for
the pupil's mental development. A variety of studies have called into
question the soundness of this idea. It has been shown that learning in
one area has very little influence on overall development. For example,
reflex theorists Woodworth and Thorndike found that adults who, after
special exercises, had achieved considerable success in determining the
length of short lines, had made virtually no progress in their ability to
determine the length of long lines. These same adults were successfully
trained to estimate the size of a given two-dimensional figure, but this
training did not make them successful in estimating the size of a series
of other two-dimensional figures of various sizes and shapes.
According to Thorndike, theoreticians in psychology and education
believe that every particular response acquisition directly enhances
overall ability in equal measure.' Teachers believed and acted on the
basis of the theory that the mind is a complex of abilities-powers of
observation, attention, memory, thinking, and so forth-and that any
improvement in any specific ability results in a general improvement in
all abilities. According to this theory, if the student increased the atten-
tion he paid to Latin grammar, he would increase his abilities to focus
attention on any task. The words "accuracy," "quick-wittedness,' "ability
to reason," "memory,' "power of observation," "attention," "concentra-
tion," and so forth are said to denote actual fundamental capabilities
that vary in accordance with the material with which they operate; these
basic abilities are substantially modified by studying particular subjects,
and they retain these modifications when they tum to other areas. There-
fore, if someone learns to do any single thing well, he will also be able
to do other entirely unrelated things well as a result of some secret
connection. It is assumed that mental capabilities function indepen-
dently of the material with which they operate, and that the development
of one ability entails the development of others.
Thorndike himself opposed this point of view. Through a variety of
studies he showed that particular forms of activity, such as spelling,
are dependent on the maste!y of specific skills and material necessary for
the performance of that particular task. The development of one particu-
lar capability seldom means the development of others. Thorndike
argued that specialization of abilities is even greater than superficial
observation may indicate. For example, if, out of a hundred individuals
we choose ten who display the ability to detect spelling errors or to
measure lengths, it is unlikely that these ten will display better abilities
regarding, for example, the' estimation of the weight of objects. In the
Interaction between Learning and Development
83
same way, speed and accuracy in adding numbers are entirely unrelated
to speed and accuracy in being able to think up antonyms.
This research shows that the mind is not a complex network of
general capabilities such as observation, attention, memory, judgment,
and so forth, but a set of specific capabilities, each of which is, to some
extent, independent of the others and is developed independently.
Learning is more than the acquisition of the ability to think; it is the
acquisition of many specialized abilities for thinking about a variety of
things. Learning does not alter our overall ability to focus attention but
rather develops various abilities to focus attention on a variety of things.
According to this view, special training affects overall development only
when its elements, material, and processes are similar across specific
domains, habit governs us. This leads to the conclusion that because
each activity depends on the material with which it operates, the
development of consciousness is the development of a set of particular,
independent capabilities or of a set of particular habits. Improvement
of one function of consciousness or one aspect of its activity can affect
the development of another only to the extent that there are elements
common to both functions or activities.
Developmental theorists such as KoHka and the Gestalt School-who
hold to the third theoretical position outlined earlier-oppose Thorn-
dike's point of view. They assert that the influence of learning is never
specific. From their study of structural principles, they argue that the
learning process can never be reduced simply to the formation of skills
but embodies an intellectual order that makes it possible to transfer
general principles discovered in solving one task to a variety of other
tasks. From this point of view, the child, while learning a particular
operation, acquires the ability to create structures of a certain type,
regardless of the diverse materials with which she is working and regard-
less of the particular elements involved. Thus, Koffka does not conceive
of learning as limited to a process of habit and skill acquisition. The
relationship he posits between learning and development is not that of
an identity but of a more complex relationship. According to Thorndike,
learning and development coincide at all points, but for Koffka, develop-
ment is always a larger set than learning. Schematically, the relationship
between the two processes could be depicted by two concentric circles,
the smaller symbolizing the learning process and the larger the develop-
mental process evoked by learning.
Once a child has learned to perform an operation, he thus assimilates
some structural principle whose sphere of application is other than just
Mind in Society
84
the operations of the type on whose basis the principle was assimilated.
Consequently, in making one step in learning, a child makes two steps in
development, that is, learning and development do not coincide. This
, concept is the essential aspect of the third group of theories we have
discussed.
stop at this point, people would imagine that the subsequent course of
mental development and of school learning for these children will be
the same, because it depends on their intellect. Of course, there may be
other factors, for example, if one child was sick for half a year while
the other was never absent from school; but generally speaking, the fate
of these children should be the same. Now imagine that I do not
terminate my study at this point, but only begin it. These children seem I
varied to a high degree, it became apparent that those children were not
mentally the same age and that the subsequent course of their learning
would obviously be different. This difference between twelve and eight,
or between nine and eight, is what we call the zone of proximal develop-
ment. It is the distance between the actual developmental level as de-
termined by independent problem solving and the level of potential
development as determined through problem solving under adult
guidance or in collaboration tvith more capable peers.
If we naively ask what the actual developmental level is, or, to put it
more simply, what more independent problem solving reveals, the most
common answer would be that a child's actual developmental level
defines functions that have already matured, that is, the end products of
development. If a child can do such-and-such independently, it means
that the functions for such-and-such have matured in her. What, then,
is defined by the zone of proximal development, as determined through
problems that children cannot solve independently but only with ~s
sistance? The zone of proximal development defines those functions that
have not yet matured but are in the process of maturation, functions that
will mature tomorrow but are currently in an embryonic state. These
I functions could be termed the "buds" or "flowers" of development
rather than the "fruits' of development. The actual developmental level
characterizes mental development retrospectively, while the zone of
Interaction between Learning and Development
81
92
The Role of Play in Development
93
fact that the child satisfies certain needs in play. If we do not under-
stand the special character of these needs, we cannot understand the
uniqueness of playas a form of activity.
A very young child tends to gratify her desires immediately; nor-
mally the interval between a desire and its fulfillment is extremely short.
No one has met a child under three years old who wants to do something
a few days in the future. However, at the preschool age, a great many
unrealizable tendencies and desires emerge. It is my belief that if needs
that could not be realized immediately did not develop during the school
years, there would be no play, because play seems to be invented at the
point when the child begins to experience unrealizable tendencies. Sup-
pose that a very young (perhaps two-and-a-half-year-old) child wants
something-for example, to occupy her mother's role. She wants it at
once. If she cannot have it, she may throw a temper tantrum, but she
can usually be sidetracked and pacified so that she forgets her desire.
Toward the beginning of preschool age, when desires that cannot be
immediately gratified or forgotten make their appearance and the tend-
ency to immediate fulfillment of desires, characteristic of the preceding
stage, is retained, the child's behavior changes. To resolve this tension,
the preschool child enters an imaginary, illusory world in which the
unrealizable desires can be realized, and this world is what we call
play. Imagination is a new psychological process for the child; it is not
present in the consciousness of the very young child, is totally absent in
animals, and represents a specifically human form of conscious activity.
Like all functions of consciousness, it originally arises from action. The
old adage that child's play is imagination in action must be reversed:
we can say that imagination in adolescents and school children is play
without action.
From this perspective it is clear that the pleasure derived from
preschool play is controlled by different motives than simple sucking
on a pacifier. This is not to say that play arises as the result of every
unsatisfied desire (as when, for example, the child wants to ride in the
cab, but the wish is not immediately gratified, so the child goes into her
room and pretends she is riding in a cab). It rarely happens in just this
way. Nor does the presence of such generalized emotions in play mean
that the child herself understands the motives giving rise to the game.
In this respect play differs substantially from work and other forms of
activity.
Thus, in establishing criteria for distinguishing a child's play from
other forms of activity, we conclude that in play a child creates an
imaginary situation. This is not a new idea, in the sense that imaginary
Mind in Society
94
situations in play have always been recognized; but they were previ-
ously regarded as only one example of play activities. The imaginary
situation was not considered the defining characteristic of play in general
but was treated as an attribute of specific subcategories of play.
I find previous ideas unsatisfactory in three respects. First, if play
is understood as symbolic, there is the danger that. it might come to be
viewed as an activity akin to algebra; that is, play, like algebra, might
be considered a system of signs that generalize reality, with no char-
acteristics that I consider specific to play. The child would be seen as
an unsuccessful algebraist who cannot yet write the symbols but can
depict them in action. I believe that play is not symbolic action in the
proper sense of the term, so it becomes essential to show the role of
motivation in play. Second, this argument stressing the importance of
cognitive processes neglects not only the motivation for, but also the
circumstances of, the child's activity. And third, previous approaches
do not help us to understand the role of play in later development.
If all play is really the realization in play fonn of tendencies that
cannot be immediately gratified, then elements of imaginary situations
will automatically be a part of the emotional tone of play itself. Con-
sider the child's activity during play. What does a child's behavior in an
imaginary situation mean? We know that the development of playing
games with rules begins in the late preschool period and develops
during school age. A number of investigators, although not belonging
to the camp of dialectical materialists, have approached this issue along
the lines recommended by Marx when he said that "the anatomy of
man is the key to the anatomy of the ape." They have begun their exami-
nation of early play in the light of later rule-based play and have con-
cluded from this that play involving an imaginary situation is, in fact,
rule-based play.
One could go even further and propose that there is no such thing
as play without rules. The imaginary situation of any form of play
already contains rules of behavior, although it may not be a game
with formulated rules laid down in advance. The child imagines himself
to be the mother and the doll to be the child, so he must obey the rules
of maternal behavior. Sully early noted that, remarkably, young chil-
dren could make the play situation and reality coincide.' He described
a case where two sisters, aged five and seven, said to each other, "Let's
play sisters." They were playing at reality. In certain cases, I have found
it easy to elicit such play in children. It is very easy, for example, to have
a child play at being a chiljl while the mother is playing the role of
mother, that is, playing at what is actually true. The vital difference,
The Role of Play in Development
95
as Sully describes it, is that the child in playing tries to be what she thinks
a sister should be. In life the child behaves without thinking that she is
her sister's sister. In the game of sisters playing at "sisters," however,
they are both concerned with displaying their sisterhood; the fact that
two sisters decided to play sisters induces them both to acquire rules
of behavior. Only actions that fit these rules are acceptable to the play
situation: they dress alike, talk alike, in short, they enact whatever
emphasizes their relationship as sisters vis-a-vis adults and strangers.
The elder, holding the younger by the hand, may keep telling her about
other people: "That is theirs, not ours." This means: "My sister and I
act the same, we are treated the same, but others are treated differently."
In this example the emphasis is on the sameness of everything that is
connected with the child's concept of a sister; as a result of playing, the
child comes to understand that sisters possess a different relationship to
each other than to other people. What passes unnoticed by the child in
real life becomes a rule of behavior in play.
What would remain if play were structured in such a way that there
were no imaginary situation? The rules would remain. Whenever there
is an imaginary situation in play, there are rules-not rules that are
formulated in advance and change during the course of the game but
ones that stem from an imaginary situation. Therefore, the notion that
a child can behave in an imaginary situation without rules is simply
inaccurate. If the child is playing the role of a mother, then she has rules
of maternal behavior. The role the child fulfills, and her relation to the
object (if the object has changed its meaning), will always stem from
the rules.
At first it seemed that the investigator's only task in analyzing play
was to disclose the hidden rules in all play, but it has been demonstrated
that the so-called pure games with rules are essentially games with
imaginary situations. Just as the imaginary situation has to contain rules
of behavior, so every game with rules contains an imaginary situation.
For example, playing chess creates an imaginary situation. Why? Be-
cause the knight, king, queen, and so forth can only move In specified
ways; because covering and taking pieces are purely chess concepts.
Although in the chess game there is no direct substitute for real-life
relationships, it is a kind of imaginary situation nevertheless. The sim-
plest game with rules immediately turns into an imaginary situation in
the sense that as soon as the game is regulated by certain rules, a number
of possibilities for action are ruled out.
Just as we were able to show at the beginning that every imaginary
situation contains rules in a concealed form, we have also demonstrated
Mind in Society
96
of pleasure. The rule wins because it is the strongest impulse. Such a rule
is an internal nile, a rule of self-restraint and self-determination, as
Piaget says, and not a rule the child obeys like a physical law. In short,
play gives a child a new form of desires. It teaches her to desire by relat-
ing her desires to a fictitious "I," to her role in the game and its rules. In
this way a child's greatest achievements are possible in play, achieve-
ments that tomorrow will become her basic level of real action and
morality.
quires a pivot in the form of an action to replace the real one. While
action begins as the numerator of the acti~n structure, now the
meaning
structure is inverted and meaning becomes the numerator. Action
retreats to second place and becomes the pivot; meaning is again de-
tached from action by means of a different action. This is another exam-
ple of the way in which human behavior comes to depend upon opera-
tions based on meanings where the motive that initiates the behavior is
sharply separated from fulfillment. The separation of meaning from
objects and action has different consequences, however. Just as operat-
ing with the meaning of things leads to abstract thought, we find that
the development of will, the ability to make conscious choices, occurs
when the child operates with the meaning of actions. In play, an action
replaces another action just as an object replaces another object.
How does the child float from one object to another, from one action
to another? This is accomplished by movement in the field of meaning-
which subordinates all real objects and actions to itself. Behavior is not
bound by the immediate perceptual field. This movement in the field
of meaning predominates in play. On the one hand, it represents move-
ment in an abstract field (which thus makes an appearance in play prior
to the appearance of voluntary operation with meanings). On the other
hand, the method of movement is situational and concrete. (It is an
affective, not a logical change). In other words, the field of meaning
appears, but action within it occurs just as in reality. Herein lies the
main developmental contradiction of play.
CONCLUSION
I would like to close this discussion of play by first showing that
play is not the predominant feature of childhood but it is a leading
factor in development. Second, I want to demonstrate the significance of
the change from predominance of the imaginary situation to predomi-
nance of rules in the development of play itself. And third, I want to
point out internal transformations in the child's development brought
about by play,
The child moves forward essentially through play activity. Only in this
sense can play be considered a leading activity that determines the
child's development.
How does play change? It is remarkable that the child starts with
an imaginary situation that initially is so very close to the real one. A
reproduction of the real situation takes place. For example, a child play-
ing with a doll repeats almost exactly what his mother does with him.
This means that in the original situation rules operate in a condensed
and compressed form. There is very little of the imaginary. It is an
imaginary situation, but it is only comprehensible in the light of a real
situation that has just occurred. Play is more nearly recollection of some-
thing that has actually happened than imagination. It is more memory
in action than a novel imaginary situation.
As play develops, we see a movement toward the conscious realiza-
tion of its purpose. It is incorrect to conceive of playas activity without
purpose. In athletic games one can win or lose; in a race one can come in
first, second, or last. In short, the purpose decides the game and justifies
the activity. Purpose, as the ultimate goal, determines the child's affective
attitude to play. When running a race, a child can be highly agitated
or distressed and little pleasure may remain because she finds it physi-
cally painful to run, and if she is overtaken she will experience little
functional pleasure. In sports the purpose of the game is one of its domi-
nant features, without which there would be no point-like examining
a piece of candy, putting it into one's mouth, chewing it, and then
spitting it out. In such play, the object, which is to win, is recognized
in advance.
At the end of development, rules emerge, and the more rigid they
are the greater the demands on the child's application, the greater the
regulation of the child's activity, the more tense and acute play becomes.
Simply running around without purpose or rules is boring and does
not appeal to children. Consequently, a complex of originally unde-
veloped features comes to the fore at the end of play development-
features that had been secondary or incidental in the beginning occupy
a central position. at the end, and vice versa.
In one sense a child at play is free to determine his own actions. But
in another sense this is an illusory freedom, for his actions are in fact
subordinated to the meanings of things, and he acts accordingly.
From the point of view of development, creating an imaginary
situation can be regarded as a means of developing abstract thought.
\ The corresponding development of rules leads to actions on the basis
Mind in Society
104
The Prehistory of
Written Language
Until now, writing has occupied too narrow a place in school prac-
tice as compared to the enormous role that it plays in children's cultural
development. The teaching of writing has been conceived in narrowly
practical terms. Children are taught to trace out letters and make words
out of them, but they are not taught written language. The mechanics of
reading what is written are so emphasized that they overshadow written
language as such.
Something similar has happened in teaching spoken language to
deaf-mutes. Attention has been concentrated entirely on correct produc-
tion of particular letters and distinct articulation of them. In this case,
teachers of deaf-mutes have not discerned spoken language behind these
pronunciation techniques, and the result has been dead speech.
This situation is to be explained primarily by historical factors:
specifically, by the fact that practical pedagogy, despite the existence
of many methods for teaching reading and writing, has yet to work out
an effective, scientific procedure for teaching children written language.
Unlike the teaching of spoken language, into which children grow of
their own accord, teaching of written language is based on artificial
training. Such training requires an enormous amount of attention and
effort on the part of teacher and pupil and thus becomes something
self-contained, relegating living written language to the background.
Instead of being founded on the needs of children as they naturally
develop and on their own activity, writing is given to them from without,
from the teacher's hands. This situation recalls the development of a
technical skill such as piano-playing: the pupil develops finger dexterity
105
Mind in Society
106
and learns to strike the keys while reading music, but he is in no way
involved in the essence of the music itself.
Such one-sided enthusiasm for the mechanics of writing has had an
impact not only on the practice of teaching but on the theoretical state-
ment of the problem as well. Up to this point, psychology has conceived
of writing as a complicated motor skill. It has paid remarkably little
attention to the question of written language as such, that is, a particular
system of symbols and signs whose mastery heralds a critical tuming-
point in the entire cultural development of the child.
A feature of this system is that it is second-order symbolism, which
gradually becomes direct symbolism. This means that written language
consists of a system of signs that designate the sounds and words of
spoken language, which, in turn, are signs for real entities and relations.
Gradually this intermediate link, spoken language, disappears, and
written language is converted into a system of signs that directly sym-
bolize the entities and relations between them. It seems clear that
mastery of such a complex sign system cannot be accomplished in a
purely mechanical and external manner; rather it is the culmination of a
long process of development of complex behavioral functions in the
child. Only by understanding the entire history of sign development in
the child and the place of writing in it can we approach a correct solution
of the psychology of writing.
The developmental history of written language, however, poses
enormous difficulties for research. As far as we can judge from the avail-
able material, it does not follow a single direct line in which something
like a clear continuity of forms is maintained. Instead, it offers the most
unexpected metamorphoses, that is, transformations of particular forms
of written language into others. To quote Baldwin's apt expression re-
garding the development of things, it is as much involution as evolution.'
This means that, together with processes of development, forward
motion, and appearance of new forms, we can discern processes of
curtailment, disappearance, and reverse development of old forms at
each step. The developmental history of written language among chil-
dren is full of such discontinuities. Its line of development seems to
disappear altogether; then suddenly, as if from nowhere, a new line
begins, and at first it seems that there is absolutely no continuity between
the old and the new. But only a naive view of development as a purely
evolutionary process involving nothing but the gradual accumulation of
small changes and the gradual conversion of one form into another can
conceal from us the true nature of these processes. This revolutionary
type of development is in no way new for science in general; it is new
The Prehistory of Written Language
107
might point to the numbers on the face and say, "This is medicine in the
drugstore"; another might point to the ring and say, "This is the en-
trance." Referring to a bottle that is playing the part of a wolf, a child
will point to the neck and say, "And this is his mouth." If the experi-
menter asks, pointing to the stopper, "And what is this?" the child an-
swers, "He's caught the stopper and is holding it in his teeth."
In all these examples we see the same thing, namely, that the cus-
tomary structure of things is modified under the impact of the new
meaning it has acquired. In response to the fact that a watch denotes a
drugstore, a feature of the watch is isolated and assumes the function
of a new sign or indication of how the watch denotes a drugstore, either
through the feature of medicine or of the entrance. The customary
structure of things (stopper in a bottle) begins to be reflected in the new
structure (wolf holds stopper in teeth), and this structural modification
becomes so strong that in a number of experiments we sometimes in-
stilled a particular symbolic meaning of an object in the children. For
example, a pocket watch denoted a drugstore in all our play sessions.
whereas other objects changed meaning rapidly and frequently. In
taking up a new game, we would put down the same watch and explain,
in accordance with the new procedures, "Now this is a bakery." One
child immediately placed a pen edgewise across the watch, dividing it
in half, and, indicating one half, said, "All right, here is the drugstore,
and here is the bakery." The old meaning thus became independent and
functioned as a means for a new one. We could also discern this acqui-
sition of independent meaning outside the immediate game; if a knife
fell, a child would exclaim, "The doctor has fallen." Thus, the object
acquires a sign function with a developmental history of its own that is
now independent of the child's gesture. This is second-order symbolism,
and because it develops in play, we see make-believe playas a major
contributor to the development of written language-a system of second-
order symbolism.
As in play, so too in drawing, representation of meaning initially
arises as first-order symbolism, As we have already pointed out, the
first drawings arise from gestures of the (pencil-equipped) hand, and
the gesture constitutes the first representation of meaning. Only later on
does the graphic representation begin independently to denote some
object. The nature of this relationship is that the marks already made on
paper are given an appropriate name.
H. Hetzer undertook to study experimentally how symbolic repre-
sentation of things-so important in learning to write-develops in three-
to-six-year-old children," Her experiments involved four basic series. The
The Pl'ehisto.,y of Written Language
111
is only around age seven that all children master this completely. At the
same time, our analysis of children's drawings definitely shows that, from
the psychological point of view, we should regard such drawings as a
particular kind of child speech.
SYMBOLISM IN WRITING
In connection with our general research, Luria undertook to create
this moment of discovery of the symbolics of writing so as to be able to
study it systematically." In his experiments children who were as yet
unable to write were confronted with the task of making some simple
fonn of notation. The children were told to remember a certain number
of phrases that greatly exceeded their natural memory capacity. When
each child became convinced that he would not be able to remember
them all, he was given a sheet of paper and asked to mark down or
record the words presented in some fashion.
Frequently, the children were bewildered by this suggestion, saying
that they could not write, but the experimenter furnished the child with
a certain procedure and examined the extent to which the child was
able to master it and extent to which the pencil-marks ceased to be
simple playthings and became symbols for recalling the appropriate
phrases. In the three-to-four-year-old stage, the child's notations are
of no assistance in remembering the phrases; in recalling them, the child
does not look at the paper. But we occasionally encountered some seem-
ingly astonishing cases that were sharply at variance with this general
observation. In these cases, the child also makes meaningless and un-
differentiated squiggles and lines, but when he reproduces phrases it
seems as though he is reading them; he refers to certain specific marks
and can repeatedly indicate, without error, which marks denote which
phrase. An entirely new relationship to these marks and a self-reinforc-
The Prehistory of Written Language
115
ing motor activity arise: for the first time the marks become mnemo-
technic symbols. For example, the children place individual marks on
different parts of the page in such a way as to associate a certain phrase
with each mark. A characteristic kind of topography arises-one mark
in one comer means a cow, while another farther up means a chimney-
sweep. Thus the marks are primitive indicatory signs for memory
purposes.
We are fully justified in seeing the first precursor of future writing
in this mnemotechnic stage. Children gradually transform these undif-
ferentiated marks. Indicatory signs and symbolizing marks and scribbles
are replaced by little figures and pictures, and these in turn give way to-
signs. Experiments have made it possible not only to describe the very
moment of discovery itself but also to follow how the process occurs as a
function of certain factors. For example, the content and forms intro-
duced into the phrases in question first break down the meaningless
nature of the notation. If we introduce quantity into the material, we
can readily evoke a notation that reflects this quantity, even in four-
and- Bve-year-olds. (It was the need for recording quantity, perhaps, that
historically first gave rise to writing.) In the same way, the introduction
of color and form are conducive to the child's discovery of the principle
of writing. For example, phrases such as "like black," "black smoke
from a chimney," "there is white snow in winter," "a mouse with a long
tail,' or "Lyalya has two eyes and one nose" rapidly cause the child to
change over from writing that functions as indicatory gesture to writing
that contains the rudiments of representation.
It is easy to see that the written signs are entirely first-order symbols
at this point, directly denoting objects or actions, and the child has yet
to reach second-order symbolism, which involves the creation of written
signs for the spoken symbols of words. For this the child must make a
basic discovery-namely that one can draw not only things but also
speech. It was only this discovery that led humanity to the brilliant
method of writing by words and letters; the same thing leads children to
letter writing. From the pedagogical point of view, this transition should
be arranged by shifting the child's activity from drawing things to
drawing speech. It is difficult to specify how this shift takes place, since
the appropriate research has yet to lead to definite conclusions, and the
generally accepted methods of teaching writing do not permit the
observation of it. One thing only is certain-that the written language
of children develops in this fashion, shifting from drawings of things to
drawing of words. Various methods of teaching writing perform this in
various ways. Many of them employ auxiliary gestures as a means of
Mind in Society
116
uniting the written and spoken symbol; others employ drawings that
depict the appropriate objects. The entire secret of teaching written
language is to prepare and organize this natural transition appropriately.
As soon as it is achieved, the child has mastered the principle of written
language and then it remains only to perfect this method.
Given the current state of psychological knowledge, our notion that
make-believe play, drawing, and writing can be viewed as different
moments in an essentially unified process of development of written
language will appear to be very much overstated. The discontinuities
and jumps from one mode of activity to another are too great for the
relationship to seem evident. But experiments and psychological analysis
lead us to this very conclusion. They show that, however complex the
process of development of written language may seem, or however
erratic, disjointed, and confused it may appear superficially, there is in
fact a unified historical line that leads to the highest forms of written
language. This higher form, which we will mention only in passing,
involves the reversion of written language from second-order symbolism
to first-order symbolism. As second-order symbols, written symbols
function as designations for verbal ones. Understanding of written
language is first effected through spoken language, but gradually this
path is curtailed and spoken language disappears as the intermediate
link. To judge from all the available evidence, written language be-
comes direct symbolism that is perceived in the same way as spoken
language. We need only try to imagine the enormous changes in the
cultural development of children that occur as a result of mastery of
written language and the· ability to read-and of thus becoming aware
of everything that human genius has created in the realm of the
written word.
PRACTICAL IMPLICATIONS
An overview of the entire developmental history of written lan-
guage in children leads us naturally to three exceptionally important
practical conclusions.
The first is that, from our point of view, it would be natural to
transfer the teaching of writing to the preschool years. Indeed, if
younger children are capable of discovering the symbolic function of
writing, as Hetzer's experiments have shown, then the teaching of
writing should be made the responsibility of preschool education, In-
deed, we see a variety of, circumstances which indicate that in the
The Prehistory of Written Language
111
Soviet Union the teaching of writing clearly comes too late from the
psychological point of view. At the same time, we know that the teach-
ing of reading and writing generally begins at age six in most European
and American countries.
Hetzer's research indicates that eighty percent of three-year-oIds
can master an arbitrary combination of sign and meaning, while almost
all six-year-olds are capable of this operation. On the basis of her ob-
servations, one may conclude that development between three and six
involves not so much mastery of arbitrary signs as it involves progress
in attention and memory. Therefore, Hetzer favors beginning to teach
reading at earlier ages. To be sure, she disregards the fact that writing is
second-order symbolism, whereas what she studied was first-order
symbolism.
Burt reports that although compulsory schooling begins at age five
in England, children between three and five are allowed into school if
there is room and are taught the alphabet," The great majority of chil-
dren can read at four-and-a-half. Montessori is particularly in favor of
teaching reading and writing at an earlier age." In the course of game
situations, generally through preparatory exercises, all the children in
her kindergartens in Italy begin to write at four and can read as well as
first-graders at age five.
But Montessori's example best shows that the situation is much
more complex than it may appear at first glance. If we temporarily
ignore the correctness and beauty of the letters her children draw and
focus on the content of what they write, we find messages like the
following: "Happy Easter to Engineer Talani and Headmistress Montes-
sori. Best wishes to the director, the teacher, and to Doctor Montessori.
Children's House, Via Campania," and so forth. We do not deny the
possibility of teaching reading and writing to preschool children; we
even regard it as desirable that a younger child enter school if he is
able to read and write. But the teaching should be organized in such a
way that reading and writing are necessary for something. If they are
used only to write official greetings to the staff or whatever the teacher
thinks up (and clearly suggests to them), then the exercise will be
purely mechanical and may soon bore the child; his activity will not be
manifest in his writing and his -budding personality will not grow.
Reading and writing must be something the child needs. Here we have
the most vivid example of the basic contradiction that appears in the
teaching of writing not only in Montessori's school but in most other
schools as well, namely, that writing is taught as a motor skill and not
Mind in Society
118
one can draw not only objects but also speech. If we wished to sum-
marize all these practical requirements and express them as a single one,
we could say that children should be taught written language, not just
the writing of letters.
The great basic idea that the world is not to be viewed as a complex of
fully fashioned objects, but as a complex of processes, in which appar-
ently stable objects, no less than the images of them inside our heads (our
concepts), are undergoing incessant changes . . .
In the eyes of dialectical philosophy, nothing is established for all
time, nothing is absolute or sacred. On everything and in everything it
sees the stamp of inevitable decline; nothing can resist it save the un-
ceasing process of formation and destruction, the unending ascent from
lower to the higher-a process of which that philosophy itself is only a
simple reflection within the thinking brain.
Friedrich Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach
Afterword
VERA JOHN-STEINER AND ELLEN SOUBERMA~
121
Afterw01'd
122
adaptive processes" (chapter 5). And indeed, in this sense, his views of
the history of the individt)al~,Jhe-history_Qf_cultur_e_ were similar. In
both cases Vygotsky rejects the concept of linear development and in-
corporates into his conceptualization both evolutionary and revolution-
ary change. The recognition of these two interrelated forms of develop-
ment is for him a necessary component of scientific thought.
Because it is not easy to conceptualize a dialectical process of
change, we found that his concepts did not make their full impact until
we attempted to combine our own research with his seminal ideas.'
This process required working through, again and again, the expansion
of his condensed but powerful concepts and applying them either to
our work or to daily observations of human behavior. The cryptic nature
of Vygotsky's writing, though it can be explained by the conditions of
his life during his last years, forced us to search deeply for his most sig-
nificant concepts. In this way we isolated those ideas that were strikingly
original and which, forty years after his death, still offer new and un-
fulfilled promise for both psychology and education.
CONCEPTS OF DEVELOPMENT
Each chapter of this volume deals with some aspect of developmen-
tal change as Vygotsky conceived it. Although he is clearly committed
to a theoretical position distinct from those of his influential contem-
poraries-Thorndike, Piaget, Koffka-he constantly returns to and ana-
lyzes their thinking in order to enrich and sharpen his own. While his
contemporaries also addressed the issue of development, Vygotsky's
approach differed from theirs in that he focused upon the historically
shaped and culturally transmitted psychology of human beings. His
analysis also differs from that of the early behaviorists. Vygotsky wrote:
In spite of the significant advances attributable to behaviorist method-
ology, that method nevertheless is seriously limited. The psychologist's
most vital challenge is that of uncovering and bringing to light the hidden
mechanisms underlying complex human psychology. Though the be-
haviorist method is objective and adequate to the study of simple re-
flexive acts, it clearly fails when applied to the study of complex psycho-
logical processes. The inner mechanisms characteristic of these processes
remain hidden.
The naturalistic approach to behavior in general does not take into
account the qualitative difference between human history and that of
animals. The experimental ramification of this kind of analysis is that
human behavior is studied without regard to the general history of human
development.P ..
Afterword
123
126
EDUCATIONAL IMPLICATIONS
Throughout this volume Vygotsky explores the various temporal
dimensions of human life. He never equates the historical development
of humankind to the stages of individual growth, since he is opposed to
the biogenetic theory of recapitulation. Rather, his concern is with the
consequences of human activity as it transforms both nature and so-
ciety. Although the labor of men and women to improve their world is
rooted in the material conditions of their era, it is also affected by their
capacity to learn from the past, to imagine, and to plan for the future.
These specifically human abilities are absent in newborns, but by the
age of three young children may already experience the tension between
desires that can be fulfilled only in the future and demands for immedi-
ate gratification. Through play this contradiction is explored and tem-
porarily resolved. And so Vygotsky places the beginnings of human
imagination at the age of three: "Imagination is a new formation which
is not present in the consciousness of the very young child, is totally
absent in animals, and represents a specifically human form of con-
scious activity. Like all functions of consciousness, it originally arises
from action. The old adage that child's play is imagination in action can
be reversed: we can say that imagination in adolescents and school-
children is play without action" (chapter 7).
In their play children project themselves into the adult activities
of their culture and rehearse their future roles and values. Thus, play is
in advance of development, for in this manner children begin to acquire
the motivation, skills, and attitudes necessary for their social participa-
tion, which can be fully achieved only with the assistance of their
peers and elders.
During preschool and school years the conceptual abilities of chil-
dren are stretched through play and the use of their imagination. In the
course of their varied games they acquire and invent rules, or as Vygot-
sky describes it, "In playa child is always above his average age, above
his daily behavior, in play it is as though he were a head taller than
himself" (chapter 7). While imitating their elders in culturally pat-
terned activities, children generate opportunities for intellectual de-
velopment. Initially, their games are recollections and reenactments of
real situations; but through the dynamics of their imagination and the
recognition of implicit rules governing the activities they have repro-
duced in their games, children achieve an elementary mastery of ab-
stract thought. In this sense, Vygotsky argued, play leads development.
Similarly, school instruction and learning is in advance of chil-
Afterword
130
use upon humans is fundamental not only because it has helped them
relate more effectively to their external environment but also because
tool use has had important effects upon internal and functional rela-
tionships within the human brain.
Although Engels and Vygotsky based their theories on the limited
archaeological findings available to them during the years in which they
wrote, contemporary archaeologists and physical anthropologists such
as the Leakeys and Sherwood Washburn have interpreted more recent
findings in a manner consistent with Engels' and Vygotsky's point of
View. Washburn states, "It was the success of the simplest tools that
started the whole trend of human evolution and led to the civilization
of today." Most likely Vygotsky would have agreed with Washburn,
who views the evolution of human life from our primate ancestors as
resulting in "intelligent, exploratory, playful, and vigorous primates ...
and that tools, hunting, fire, complex social speech, the human way and
the brain evolved together to produce ancient man."'15 These archaeo-
logical discoveries support Vygotsky's concepts of what it is to be
human.
The impact of Vygotsky's work-as that of great theoreticians
everywhere-is both general and specific. Cognitive psychologists as
well as educators are interested in exploring the present-day implica-
tions of his notions, whether they refer to play, to the genesis of scien-
tific concepts, or to the relation of language and thought. The men and
women who were his students forty years ago still debate his ideas with
the intensity and vigor due a contemporary-and we who worked as
his editors found many possible, sometimes contradictory, interpreta-
tions of his work. But there is a powerful tlplead drawing together Vy-
gotsky's diverse and stimulating writings: it is the way in which his
mind worked. His legacy in an increasingly destructive and alienating
world is to offer through his theoretical formulations a powerful tool for
restructuring human life with an aim toward survival."
Notes
INTRODUCTION
1. K. N. Kornilov, "Psychology and Marxism," in K. N. Kornilov, ed.,
Psychology and Marxism (Leningrad: State Publishing House, 1925), pp. 9-
24. L. S. Vygotsky, "Consciousness as a Problem in the Psychology of Be-
havior," in Komilov, ed., Psychology and Marxism, pp. 175-198. See also
K. N. Kornilov, "Psychology in the Light of Dialectical Materialism," in C.
Murchison, ed., Psychologies of 1930 (Worcester: Clark University Press,
1930; rpt., New York: Arno Press, 1973).
2. Friedrich Engels, Dialectics of Nature (New York: International Pub-
lishers, 1940), p. 40.
3. P. P. Blonsky, Studies in Scientific Psychology (Moscow: State Pub-
lishing House, 1911).
4. R. Thumwald, "Psychologic des primitiven Menschen," in Handbuch
der uergleichenden Psychologie (Munich, 1922). L. Levy-Bruhl, Primitive
Mentality (New York: Macmillan, 1923).
5. A. R. Luria, Cognitive Development: Its Cultural and Social Founda-
tions (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1976).
6. Z. M. Istomina, "The Development of Voluntary Memory in Pre-
school Age Children," Soviet Psychology, 13, no. 4 (1975): 5-64.
7. M. Cole and I. Maltzman, eds., A Handbook of Contemporary Soviet
Psychology (New York: Basic Books, 1969). A. V. Zaporozhets and D. B.
Elkonin, eds., The Psychology of Preschool Children (Cambridge: MIT Press,
1971).
CHAPTER,l
1. K. Stumpf, "Zur Methodik der Kinderpsychologie," Zeitsch. f. pddag.
Psychol., 2 (1900).
2. A. Gesell, The Mental Growth of the Preschool Child (New York:
Macmillan, 1925; Russian ed., Moscow-Leningrad: Gosizdat., 1930).
135
Notes to Pages 20-37
136
CHAPTER 2
1. A. Binet, "Perception de'enfants," Revue Philosophique, 30 (1890):
582--611. Stern, Psychology of Early Childhood.
2. A. A. Potebnya, Thought and Language (Kharkhov, 1892), p. 6.
3. K. KoHka, The Growth of the Mind (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1924).
4. R. Lindner, Gas Taubsiumme Kind in Vergleich mit vollstandigen
Kinder (Leipzig, 1925).
Notes to Pages 37-66
137
CHAPTER 3
1. E. R. Jaensch, Eidetic Imagery (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1930).
2. Vygotsky is referring here to the technique of using knotted rope as a
mnemonic device among Peruvian Indians. No reference is given in the text,
but from other manuscripts it appears that the writing of E. B. Taylor and
Levy-Bruhl provided these examples.
3. These observations are taken from an article by A. N. Leontiev,
"Studies on the Cultural Development of the Child," Journal of Genetic
Psychology, 40 (1932): 52-83.
4. A fuller description of this technique may be found in A. R. Luria,
"The Development of Mental Functions in Twins," Character and Personality,
5 (1937): 35-47.
5. L. V. Zankov, Memory (Moscow: Uchpedgiz., 1949).
6. A. N. Leontiev, "The Development of Mediated Memory," Problemi
Defektologiga, no. 4 (1928).
7. See H. Werner, Comparative Psychology of Mental Development
(New York: Science Editions, 1961), pp. 216ff.
8. See Vygotsky, Thought and Language, chapter 6, for a more extensive
discussion of the distinction.
CHAPTER 4
1. G. Hegel, "Encyklopadie, Erster Theil. Die Logik" (Berlin, 1840),
p. 382, cited in K. Marx, Capital (Modem Library Edition, 1936).
2. Marx, Capital, p. 199.
CHAPTER 5
1. Engels, Dialectics of Nature, p. 172.
2. H. Werner, The Comparative Psychology of Mental Development
(New York: International Universities Press, 1948).
3. K. Lewin, A Dynamic Theory of Personality (New York: McGraw-
Hill, 1935).
4. Stern, Psyclwlogy of Early Childhood.
5. Exact references are not included, but in his other writings, Vygotsky
quotes extensively from Capital, vol. 1.
6. E. Titchener, Textbook of Psychology (Moscow, 1914, in Russian).
7. P. P. Blonsky, Essays in Scientific Psychology (Moscow: State Publish-
ing House, 1921).
8. For an extended discussion of the importance of reaction time experi-
ments in early twentieth-century psychology, see E. G. Boring, "The Psychol-
ogy of Controversy," Psychological Review, 36 (1929): 97-121.
9. Several of Cattell's papers on the reaction time study are reprinted in
W. Dennis, Readings in the History of Psychology (New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts, 1948).
Notes to Pages 67-121
138
CHAPTER 6
1. Piaget, Language and Thought.
2. William James, Talks to Teachers (New York: Norton, 1958), pp.
36-37.
3. Koffka, Growth of the Mind.
4. E. L. Thorndike, The Psychology of Learning (New York: Teachers
College Press, 1914).
5. Dorothea McCarthy, The Language Development of the Pre-school
Child (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1930).
6. Kohler, Mentality of Apes.
7. Piaget, Language and Thought.
CHAPTER 7
1. J. Sully, Studies of Childhood (Moscow, 1904, in Russian), p. 48.
2. Lewin, Dynamic Theory of Personality, p. 96.
3. See K. Goldstein, Language and Language Disorders (New York:
Greene and Stratton, 1948).
4. Koffka, Growth of the Mind, pp. 381ff.
CHAPTER 8
1. J. M. Baldwin, Mental Development in the Child and the Race (New
York, 1895; Russian ed., 1912).
2. Wurth (reference not available).
3. H. Hetzer, Die Symbolische Darstelling in der fruhen Windhert,
(Vienna: Deutscher Verlag fur Jugend und Yolk, 1926), p. 92.
4. K. Buhler, Mental Development of the Child.
5. J. Sully, Studies of Childhood (London, 1895).
6. A. R. Luria, "Materials on the Development of Writing in Children,"
Problemi Marksistkogo Vospitaniya, I (1929): 143-176.
7. C. Burt, Distribution of Educational Abilities (London: P. S. King
and Sons, 1917).
8. M. Montessori, Spontaneous .Activity in Education (New York:
Schocken, 1965).
AFTERWORD
1. See Nan Elsasser and Vera John-Steiner, (CAn Interactionist Approach
to Advancing Literacy," Harvard Educational Review, 47, no. 3 (August
1977): 355-370. ..
Notes to Pages 122-126
139
IN RUSSIAN
1915
"The Tragedy of Hamlet, Prince of Denmark." Private archives of L. S. Vy-
gotsky. Manuscript.
1916
"Literary Remarks on Petersburg by Andrey Biely." The New Way, 1916, no.
47, pp. 27-32.
Review of Petersburg by Andrey Biely. Chronicle, 1916, no. 12, pp. 327-328.
Review of Fumnos and Bounds by Vyacheslav Ivanov published in (Musatet,
1916). Chronicle, 1916, no. 10, pp. 351-352.
"The Tragedy of Hamlet, Prince of Denmark." Private archives of L. S. Vy-
gotsky. Manuscript.
1917
Review of loy Will Be (a play) by D. Merezhkovsky (published in The Lights,
1916). Chronicle, 1917, no. 1, pp. 309-310.
Foreword to and remarks on "The Priest" (a poem) by N. L. Brodsky.
Chronicle, 1917, nos. 5-6, pp. 366-367.
1922
"About the Methods of Teaching Literature in Secondary Schools."
Report on the District Scientific Methodological Conference, Aug. 7,
1922. Private archives of L. S. Vygotsky. Manuscript, 17 pp.
1923
"The Investigation of the Processes of Language Comprehension Using Mul-
tiple Translation of Text from One Language to Another." Private
archives of L. S. Vygotsky. Manuscript, 8 pp.
141
Vygotsky's Works
142
1924
Vygotsky, L. S., ed. Problems of Education of Blind, Deaf-Dumb and Re-
tarded Children. Moscow: SPON NKP Publishing House, 1924.
"Methods of Reflexological and Psychological Investigation." Report of
the National Meeting of Psychoneurology, Leningrad, Jan. 2, 1924. In
The Problems of Contemporary Psychology, 11,26-46. Leningrad: Gov-
ernment Publishing House, 1926.
"Psychology and Education of Defective Children." In Problems of Education
of Blind, Deaf-Dumb and Retarded Children, pp. 5-30. Moscow: SPON
NKP Publishing House, 1924.
Foreword to Problems of Education of Blind, Deaf-Dumb and Retarded Chil-
dren. Moscow: SPON NKP Publishing House, 1924.
"The Principles of Education of Physically Defective Children." Report of
the Second Meeting of SPON, Dec. 1924. Public Education, 1925, no. 1,
pp. 112-120.
1925
Review of The Auxiliary School by A. N. Graborov. Public Education, 1925,
no. 9, pp.17Q-171.
'Foreword to Beyond the Pleasure Principle by S. Freud. Moscow: Contempo-
rary Problems, 1925. (With A. R. Luria.)
Foreword to General and Experimental Psychology by A. F. Lasursky. Lenin-
grad: Government Publishing House, 1925.
"The Principles of Social Education of Deaf-Dumb Children." Private arch..
ives of L. S. Vygotsky. Manuscript, 26 pp.
The Psychology of Art. Moscow: Moscow Art Publishing House, 1965 (379
pp.); 2nd ed., 1968 (576 pp.).
"The Conscious as a Problem of the Psychology of Behavior." In Psychology
and Marxism, I, 175-198. Moscow-Leningrad: Government Publishing
House, 1925.
1926-1927
Graphics of Bikhovsky. Moscow: Contemporary Russia Publishing House,
1926.
"Methods of Teaching Psychology." (Course program.) The State Archives of
Moscow District, fo!' 948, vol. I, set 613, p. 25.
"About the Influence of Speech Rhythm on Breathing." In Problems of Con-
temporary Psychology, II, 169-173. Leningrad: Government Publishing
House, 1926.
Pedagogical Psychology. Moscow: The Worker of Education Publishing
House, 1926.
"Introspection" by Koffka. In Problems of Contemporary Psychology, pp. 17~
178. Moscow-Leningrad: Government Publishing House, 1926.
Foreword to Principles of Learning Based upon Psychology by E. L. Thorn-
dike (tr, from the English), pp. 5-23. Moscow: The Worker of Education
Publishing House, 1926.
Foreword to The Practice of Experimental Psychology, Education and Psy-
chotechnics by R. Schulz (tr. from the German), pp. 3-5. Moscow: Prob-
lems of Labor Publishing House, 1926. (With A. R. Luria.)
Vygotsky's Works
143
1928
"Anomalies of Cultural Development of the Child." Report to the Department
of Defectology, Institute of Education of the Second Moscow State Uni-
versity, April 28, 1928. Problems of Defectology, 1929, no. 2 (8), pp.
106-107.
"Behaviorism." The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 1928, vol. III, cols. 483-486.
"Sick Children." Pedagogical Encyclopedia, 1928, vol. II, cols. 396-397.
"The Will and Its Disturbances." The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 1928, vol.
V, cols. 590-600.
"The Education of Blind-Deaf-Mute Children." Pedagogical Encyclopedia,
1928, vol. II, cols. 395-396.
"Report of the Conference of Methods of Psychology Teaching in Teachers'
College," April 10, 1928. The State Archives of Moscow District, fol.
948, vol. I, pp. 13-15.
"The Genesis of Cultural Forms of Behavior." Lecture, Dec. 7, 1928. Private
archives of L. S. Vygotsky. Stenography, 28 pp.
"Defect and Compensation." Pedagogical Encyclopaedia, 1928, vol. II, cols.
391-392.
"The Instrumental Method in Psychology." In The Main Problems of Pedology
in the USSR, pp. 158-159. Moscow, 1928.
"The Results of a Meeting." Public Education, 1928, no. 2, pp. 56-67.
"Invalids." Pedagogical Encyclopaedia, 1928, vol. II, col. 396.
"The Question of the Dynamics of Children's Character. In Pedology and
Education, pp. 99-119. Moscow: The Worker of Education Publishing
House, 1928.
"The Question Concerning the Duration of Childhood in the Retarded
Child." Report to the Meeting of Defectology Department by the Insti-
Vygotsky's Works
144
- 1929
"Lectures on Abnormal Childhood." Problems of Defectology, 1929 (1930),
no. 2 (8), pp. 108-112.
"Developmental Roots of Thinking and Speech." Natural Science and Marx-
ism, 1929, no. 1, pp. 106-133.
"Genius." The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 1929, vol. VI, cols. 612-613.
"About the Plan of Research Work for the Pedology of National Minorities."
Pedology, 1929, no. 3, pp. 367-377.
Vygotsky's Works
145
1930
"The Biological Base of Affect." 1 Want to Know.Everything, 1930, nos. 15-
16, pp. 480-481.
Foreword to materials collected by workers of the Institute of Scientific Edu-
cation, April 13, 1930. Archives of the Academy of Pedagogical Sciences,
USSR, fo1. 4, vol. I, no. 103, pp. 81-82.
"Is It Possible to Simulate Extraordinary Memory?" I Want to Know Every-
thing, 1930, no. 24, pp. 700-703.
Vygotsky's 'Works
146
1931
Buhler, C., et aI. The Social-Psychological Study of the Child During the
First Year of Life. L. S. Vygotsky, ed. Moscow-Leningrad: Medgiz, 1931.
(With A. R. Luria.)
"Report of the Reactological Discussion,. 1931." Archives of the Institute of
General and Pedagogical Psychology, Academy of Pedagogical Sciences,
USSR, fol. 82, vol. I, pp. 5-15. Stenography (corrected by L. S. Vygot-
sky).
The Diagnosis- of Development and Pedological Clinics for Difficult Chil-
dren. Moscow: Publishing House of the Experimental Defectology Insti-
tute, 1936.
"The History of the Development of Higher Psychological Functions." In
Development of Higher Psychological Functions by L. S. Vygotsky,
pp. 13-223. Moscow: Academy of Pedogogical Sciences, RSFSR, 1960.
"The Question of Compensatory Processes in the Development of the Re-
tarded Child." Report to the Conference of the Workers of Auxiliary
Schools, Leningrad, May 23, 1931. Private archives of L. S. Vygotsky.
Stenography, 48 pp.
"Problems of Pedology and Related Sciences." Pedology, 1931, no. 3, pp.
52-58.
"The Collective as a Factor of Development in the Abnormal Child." In Prob-
lems of Defectology, 1931, nos. 1-2, pp. 8-17; no. 3, pp. 3-18.
"Thinking." The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 1931, vol. XIX, cols. 414-426.
The Pedology of Teenagers. Lectures 9-16. Moscow-Leningrad: Extension
Division of the Second Moscow State University, 1931.
"Practical Activity and Thinking in the Development of the Child in Con-
nection with a Problem of Politechnism." Private archives of L. S. Vygot-
sky. Manuscript, 4 pp.
Foreword to Development of Memory by A. N. Leontiev. Moscow-Leningrad:
Uchpedgiz, 1931. ..
Foreword to Essay on the Behavior and Education of the Deaf-Mute Child
by Y. K. Zvelfel. Moscow-Leningrad: Uchpedgiz, 1931.
Vygotsky's Works
148
1932
"The Problem of Creativity in Actors." In The Psychology of the Stage Feel-
ings of an Actor by P. M. jakobson, pp. 197-211. Moscow: Government
Publishing House, 1936.
"Toward a Psychology of Schizophrenia." Soviet Neuropathology, Psychiatry
and Psychohygiene, vol. 1 (1932), no. 8, pp. 352--361.
"Toward a Psychology of Schizophrenia." In Contemporary Problems of
Schizophrenia, pp. 19-28. Moscow: Medgiz, 1933.
"Lectures on Psychology." Leningrad Pedagogical Institute, March-April
1932. Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute. Stenography.
Also in Development of Higher Psychological Functions, pp. 235-363.
Moscow: Academy of Pedagogical Sciences, RSFSR, 1960.
"Infancy." Private archives of L. S. Vygotsky, Manuscript, 78 pp.
Foreword to Education and Teaching of the Retarded Child by E. K. Gra-
cheva, Moscow-Leningrad: Uchpedgiz, 1932.
Foreword to Development of Memory by A. N. Leontiev. Moscow, 1932.
(With A. N. Leontiev.)
"The Problem of Development of the Child in the Research of Arnold Gesell."
In Education and Childhood by A. Gesell, pp. 3-14. Moscow-Leningrad:
Uchpedgiz, 1932.
"Problem of the Speech andThinking of the Child in the Teachings of Pia-
get." In Language and Thought of the Child by J. Piaget, pp. 3-54.
Moscow-Leningrad: Uchpedgiz, 1932.
"Early Childhood." Lecture, Leningrad Pedagogical Institute, Dec. 15, 1932.
Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute. Stenography, 50 pp.
"Contemporary Directions in Psychology." Report to the Communist Acad-
emy, June 26, 1932. In Development of Higher Psychological Functions
by L. S. Vygotsky, pp. 458-481. Moscow: Academy of Pedagogical
Sciences, RSFSR, 1960.
1933
"Introductory Lecture about Age-Psychology." The Central House of Art
Education of Children, Dec. 19, 1933. Archives of the Leningrad Peda-
gogical Institute. Stenography, 34 pp.
"Dynamics of Mental Development of School Children in Connection with
Education.'" Report to the Meeting of the Department of Defectology
of Bubnov Pedagogical institute, Dec. 23, 1933. In Mental Develop-
ment of Children during Education by L. S. Vygotsky, pp. 33-52. Mos-
cow-Leningrad: Government Publishing House, 1935.
Vygotsky's Works
149
1934
"Dementia during Pick's Disease." Soviet Neuropathology, Psychiatry, Psy-
chohygiene, vol. 3 (1934), no. 6, pp. 97-136. (With G. V. Birenbaum
and N. V. Samukhin.)
"Development of Scientific Ideas during Childhood." In The Development of
Scientific Ideas of School Children by Zh. I. Shif, pp. 3-17. Moscow-
Leningrad: Uchpedgiz, 1935.
"Infancy and Early Age." Lecture, Leningrad Pedagogical Institute, Feb. 23,
1934. Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute. Stenography,
24pp.
Thought and Language. Moscow-Leningrad: Sozekgiz, 1934.
"The Thinking of School Children." Lecture, Leningrad Pedagogical In-
stitute, May 3, 1934. Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute.
Stenography, 11 pp.
Fundamentals of Pedology. Moscow: Second Moscow Medical Institute,
1934.
"Adolescence." Lecture, Leningrad Pedagogical Institute, March 25, 1934.
Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute. Stenography.
"Problems of Age." Private archives of L. S. Vygotsky. Manuscript, 95 pp.
Also in Problems of Psychology, 1972, no. 2, pp. 114-123.
"Problems of Education and Mental Development in School Age." I~ Mental
Development of Children during Education by L. S. Vygotsky, pp. 3-19.
Moscow-Leningrad: Uchpedgiz, 1935.
"Problem of Development in Structural Psychology." In Fundamentals of
Psychological Development by K. Koffka, pp. ix-Ixi, Moscow-Leningrad:
Sozekgiz, 1934.
"Problem of Development and Destruction of the Higher Psychological
Functions." In Development of Higher Psychological Functions by L. S.
Vygotsky, pp. 364-383. Moscow: Academy of Pedagogical Sciences,
RSFSR, 1960. (Vygotsky's last report, prepared one month before his
death.)
"Psychology and Teaching of Localization." In Reports of the First Ukranian
Meeting of Neuropathologists and Psychiatrists, pp. 34-41. Kharkov,
1934.
"Dementia during Pick's Disease." Private archives of L. S. Vygotsky, 1934.
Manuscript, 4 pp.
Fascism in Psychoneurology. Moscow-Leningrad: Biomedgiz, 1934. (With V.
A. Giljarovsky et al.)
"School Age." Private archives of D. B. Elkonin, 1934. Manuscript, 42 pp.
"School Age." Lecture, Leningrad Pedagogical Institute, Feb. 23, 1934.
Archives of the Leningrad Pedagogical Institute. Stenography, 61 pp.
"Experimental Investigation of the Teaching of New Speech Reflexes by the
Method of Attachment with Complexes." Private archives of L. S.
Vygotsky. Manuscript.
1935
"Education and Development during School Age." Report to the National
Vygotsky's Works
lSI
IN ENGLISH
153
Index
154