Derrida, Jacques - Who's Afraid of Philosophy (Stanford, 2002)
Derrida, Jacques - Who's Afraid of Philosophy (Stanford, 2002)
Derrida, Jacques - Who's Afraid of Philosophy (Stanford, 2002)
Crossing Aesthetics
Werner Hamacher
Editors
Translated by
Jan Plug
Stanford
University
Press
Stanford
California
2002
WHO'S AFRAID
OF PH I LOSOPHY?
Right to Philosophy 1
Jacques Derrida
Stanford University Press
Stanford, California
Assistance for the translacion was provided by the French Ministry of Culture.
Translator's Note ix
Notes 193
Translator's Note
ix
X Tramlator's Note
lege formed by the Socialist government that came to power in 1981, Der
rida circulated a call for proposals for potential research projects and re
ceived an overwhelming response. The College was founded on October
ro, 198 3 , and is funded by the state, though autonomous in its operation.
Its mission is to provide a place for "philosophical" research that existing
institutions either forbid or marginalize. To this end the College does not
require the same kind of teaching or research accreditation demanded by
other institutions.
To ]ean-Luc Nancy
I
2 Privilege
poses. Philosophy would be what wants to keep, by declaring it, this ulti
mate or initial privilege that consists in exposing its own privilege: to dan
ger or presentation, sometimes to the risk of presentation.
Let's make some sentences. If I say, for example, and this is the first
meaning of my title, "How does one go from right to philosophy?," we get
involved in a certain problematic. It will be a maner, for example, of the re
lations permitting one to go from juridical thought, from the juridical dis
cipline or practice, to philosophy and the quidjuris questions that have
long worked at its heart. It will be a question, more precisely, of the relation
of the juridical structures that implicitly or explicitly support philosophical
institutions (teaching or research) to philosophy itself, if such a thing exists
outside, before, or beyond an institution. In this first meaning, the title
Right to Philosophy announces a program, a problematic, and a contract: we
will deal with the relations berween right and philosophy. What is more,
every contract implies a question of right. And a title is always a contract.
That, in the unique case of philosophy, this contract be destined to more
than one paradox is here our privileged theme, privilege as our theme.
In this first type of sentence, only one of the five words [in Du droit a
Ia philosophie-Right to Philosophy], in fact, the single lener a [to], carries
the entire semantic determination. Meaning here pivots on the different
values an a can carry. We have in effect just evoked the relation of right to
philosophy as that of an articulation in general: berween rwo areas, rwo
fields, rwo structures, or rwo institutional mechanisms. But with the same
semantic determination of the to, with the same value of a relation to, an
other sentence announces another program-and another problematic.
One can in fact rightly note that, to analyze these problems (institutional
right and the philosophical institutions of research and teaching), we have
to talk about right [droit] to philosophers. We have to talk about right
[droit] to philosophy. We have to recall the questions of law [droit] , the
enormous continent of the juridical problematic about which philosophers
in general-and especially in France-talk too little, even if and no doubt
because, law [droit] talks through them so much: we have to talk about
right [droit] to philosophy. We have to talk to philosophy about right
[droit] , have to talk to philosophy and philosophers about the immense
and ramifYing question of right [droit] . The "to" still says articulation, but
this time in a different sense, that of the speech articulated in the address,
of the word that is addressed or intended for: we have to talk about right
to philosophy.
Privilege 3
But this articulatory mode does not exhaust the entire relation of the
"right to philosophy." The French syntagm du droit a can signify something
else and open another semantic access. One says "to have the right to"
[avoir droit a] to indicate the access guaranteed by the law, the right of way,
the pass, the Shibboleth, the authorized entry. Who has the right to philos
ophy today, in our society? To which philosophy? Under what conditions?
In which private or public space? Which places of teaching, research, pub
lication, reading, discussion? Through which instances and filterings of the
media? To have the "right to philosophy'' is to have a legitimate or legal
access to something whose singularity, identity, and generality remain as
problematic as what is called Philosophy [laphilosophie] . Who, then, can lay
claim legitimately to philosophy? To think, say, discuss, learn, teach, expose,
present, or represent Philosophy [la philosophie] ?
This second value of the "to" (the relation no longer as articulation but
as address) deploy s another possibility. To recapitulate; to this point we
have three typical sentences:
directly-and-reach-right-away-without-waiting-the-true-content-ofthe-urgent
and-serious-problems-that-Jace-us-all-etc. Thus, they will no doubt judge an
analysis that deploys this range of meanings and possible sentences playful,
precious, and formal, indeed futile: "Why be so slow and self-indulgent?
Why these linguistic stages? Why don't we just speak directly about the true
questions? Why not go right to the things themselves?" Of course, one can
share this impatience and nonetheless think, as I do, that not only do we
gain nothing by immediately giving in to it, but that this lure has a history,
interest, and a sort of hypocritical structure, and that one would always be
better off to begin by acknowledging it by giving oneself the time for a de
tour and analysis. At stake is precisely a certain right to philosophy.
The analysis of the potential values that sleep or play at the bottom of
the idiom "right to philosophy'' must be an exercise in vigilance and must
only "play'' to the extent that the question of the "game" is here of the
most serious kind. For at least two reasons. One stems from the question
of the title, the other from that of language.
. .
r. "The nght of... , " "the ngh t to . . " : .
to call for, upon all that depend today the most serious stakes and respon
sibilities.According to philosophers, when it is posed concerning a science
or art, the question "what is ..." always belongs to philosophy.It belongs
by rights to philosophy.T herein lies the right of philosophy.Since philos
ophy alone retains this right, according to philosophy, it is also a privilege.
Philosophy would be this privilege. It would not receive it, but would be the
power of granting it to itsel The oldest theme of philosophy is found
here once again: the question "What is phy sics, sociology, anthropology,
literature, or music?" would be philosophical in nature.
But can the same be said about the question "What is the philosophi
cal?"? T his is the most and least philosophical of all questions. We will
have to take it into account. It is in all the institutional decisions: "Who
is a philosopher? What is a philosopher? What has the right to claim to be
philosophical? How does one recognize a philosophical utterance, today
and in general? By what sign (is it a sign?) does one recognize a philosoph
ical thought, sentence, experience, or operation (say, that of teaching)?
What does the word philosophical mean? Can we agree on the subject of
the philosophical and of the very place from which these questions are
formed and legitimated?"
T hese questions are no doubt identical with philosophy itsel But in ac
cordance with this essential unrest of philosophical identity, perhaps they
are already no longer completely philosophical.Perhaps they stop short of
the philosophy they interrogate, unless they carry bey ond a philosophy that
would no longer be their ultimate destination.
A question addressed to philosophy about its identity can respond to at
least two dominantfigures. Other approaches are no doubt possible, and
here we are working to engage in them in a preliminary way. But the two
figures that have won out in the tradition seem opposed to one another as
essence and JUnction. On the one side, that of essence (which also happens
to be that of history; the origin, the event, meaning, and the etymon), one
attempts to think philosophy as such, as what it is, what it will have been,
what it will have anticipated being since its origin-and one will do this
precisely by placing oneself at the point of an event that establishes itself,
in the experience of a language, on the basis of the question ofbeing or of
the truth ofbeing. T his is the figure ofHeideggerian "destruction," defined
as schematically as possible.6 On the other side, that of function, and in a
style that is apparently more nominalist, one begins by denouncing such
an originarism: it would teach us nothing about a pragmatic truth of phi-
8 Privilege
losophy, that is, about what it does or what is done under its name, about
the use [parti] we make of it, the part [parti] or the stands
[parti] we take
in it, in speech acts, discussions, evaluations, social, political, and institu
tional practices, whose difference, above all, must be grasped, rather than
the genealogical thread that would reconnect them to some forgotten emer
gence. This functionalist pragmatism is the model, at least implicitly, for
numerous modern interrogations on the subject of philosophy, whether
they are deployed by philosophers, sociologists, or historians.
Beyond all their differences and oppositions, and they are anything but
negligible, these two figures of the question on the subject of philosophy
(What is it? What does it do? What does one do about or with it?) always
presuppose one another, to begin with or in the end. Nominalist prag
matics must give itself a rule in advance in order to set its own operations
under way and recognize its objects. That rule is always a concept ofphilos
ophy, which itself demands that one presuppose a sense or essence, the being
on the basis of which the being-philosophical of philosophy is thought.
The originarist approach (and this is also true of that ofHeidegger) itself
must presuppose an event, a chain of events, a history in which a philo
sophical thinking is no longer distinguished from a "speech act" made pos
sible by an arche-conventional or quasi-contractual condition in a given
language. It must therefore presuppose the performative moment of a so
cial and institutional "function," even if more appropriate names are given
to these "things" after having put them through "destruction."
If we were to invent and adjust another type of questioning, if that were
to be possible, we would have to start by understanding and formalizing
the necessity; if not the fatality, of this common presupposition. It is on
this path that we find ourselves. All the debates evoked in this book recall
this, whether they concern the inaugural proposals of Greph,7 the Intro
duction to the Estates General of Philosophy, the founding of the College
International de Philosophie, or the Report of the Commission on Philos
ophy and Epistemology. Each time, I joined vigorously and unequivocally
in struggles to ensure and develop what is often called the threatened "spec
ificity" of the discipline of philosophy: struggles against its fragmentation,
and even its dissolution into the teaching of the social or human sciences,
sometimes (the more traditional risk in France) into that of languages and
literatures. But at the same time, it was necessary to remind those who
would make a merely defensive and conservative, sometimes narrowly dog
matic, even corporatist use of this just argument that this "specificity"
Privilege 9
must remain of the most paradoxical kind. Its experience is also that of an
aporia across which an uncertain path must continually be reinvented. It
is not only the specificity of one discipline among others (even if it should
be recalled that it is also that), with its field of objects and its stock of trans
missible rules. If philosophy must remain open to all interdisciplinarities
without losing itself in them, that is because it does not lend itself as one
discipline among others to the peaceful and regular transaction between
kinds of knowledge with established borders or objects that can be as
signed to given territories. What has been called "deconstruction" is also
the exposure of this institutional identity of the discipline of philosophy:
what is irreducible about it must be exposed as such, that is to say, shown,
watched over, laid claim to, but in that which opens it and ex-propriates
it, as what is proper in its properness distances itself from itself in order to
relate to itself-first of all, in the least of its questions about itself Philos
ophy, philosophical identity, is also the name of an experience that, in iden
tification in general, begins by ex-posing itself: in other words, expatriat
ing itsel Taking place where it does not take place, where the place is
neither natural, nor originary, nor given.
Questions of title and right always have a topological dimension. No in
stitution does without a symbolic place of legitimation, even if assigning
this place can be overdetermined at the intersection of empirical and sym
bolic, physico-geographic and ideal givens within a homogeneous or het
erogeneous space. A seminar can take place in a specific institution (phys
ically but not without drawing from it a symbolic benefit that sets the
stakes for the transactions and contracts), a seminar given by someone
who does not belong to that institution (Jacques Lacan at the Ecole Nor
male Superieure for several years, for example) or by someone who, a for
mer student of the Ecole Normale Superieure, teaches there under the
auspices of that other public establishment that is the Ecole des Hautes
Etudes en Sciences Sociales, or even of an institution having no physical
place proper that, like the College International de Philosophie (Ciph),
founded in 1983, is by right a private association (governed by the so-called
Law of 1901), autonomous in its operation and orientations, although its
board of directors includes, by statute, the representatives of four min
istries! The map of these "places" calls for an exact description and the in
terferences of these paths favor a turbulence quite auspicious for reflection
on the historicity of institutions, notably philosophical institutions. If the
latter are thoroughly historical, that means that neither their origin nor
IO Privilege
their solidity is natural, and especially that the processes of their stabili
zation are always relative, threatened, essentially precarious. The apparent
firmness, hardness, dUiability, or resistance of philosophical institutions be
trays, first of all, the fragility of a foundation. It is on the ground of this
(theoretical and practical) "deconstructability," it is against it, that the in
stitution institutes itsel The erection of the institution betrays this ground
-signals the ground as a symptom would, and reveals it, therefore, but
deceives it as well.
received from the other. But it traces a form of strange limit between all
the determinations of the philosophical and a deconstructive thinking
that, while undertaken by philosophy, does not belong to it. Thinking is
faithful to an affirmation whose responsibility places it before philosophy
but also always before there was philosophy, thus short of and beyond phi
losophy, identifiable figures of philosophical identity, the philosophical
question about the subject of philosophy, and even the question-form of
thinking. Deconstruction, as it appears to be required by or, rather, as it
appears to require thinking, is involved in this third possibility. All I can
say, at this point in a preface, is that the common aim of the texts gathered
in this collection does not consist in recalling works published elsewhere
under the title of deconstruction but in better indicating how deconstruc
tion forces us to think differently the institutions of philosophy and the
experience of the right to philosophy. Here less than ever is thinking op
posed to science, technique, calculation, and strategy. Now is the time to
indicate once again that the line I am drawing here between thinking and
philosophy, thinking and science, etc., has never taken the form and func
tion Heidegger gives it. 10
To give right to philosophy is not to give right over [donner droit sur] phi-
I4 Privilege
losophy, at least in the sense of the authority exercised over or with regard
to-for we will be interested later in the idiomatic play between the adverb
and the noun: "to give right onto" [donner droit sur] can simply mean open
ing onto, with or without authority, power, or surveillance: a window or a
door "gives" right onto the street, yard, forum, classroom, prison courtyard.
To "give" right onto philosophy, where this right does not yet exist, whether
it is ignored or misunderstood, inhibited, refused, or forbidden, is a banal
task, since it resembles the legitimating or "entitling'' function of every in
stitution. But the form it was assigned by Ciph remains of the most para
doxical kind: it seems to assume the foreknowledge of what is still forbid
den. (I privilege for the moment the form of the "forbidden" over the other
modes of the nonexistence of philosophy in order to emphasize that phi
losophy can always be interpreted and is in no way "natural." It always has
a meaning; it betrays a counter-force, an always already "symbolic" force.)
A singular institution, for example, Ciph, should therefore locate, within
institutions or outside of them, in their margins or their interinstitutional
space, what every other institution cannot or does not want (cwan't) to le
gitimate. For that to happen, a beginning of legitimation must, in a certain
form and under certain conditions, have permitted the approaches forbid
den by existing institutions, or at least by what dominates in them (for they
are always heterogeneous and worked through by contradictions), to be de
tected, traked, and to take shape, virtuall y or implicitly. T his simple fact
is enough to threaten the very concept of legitimation to the core: it has
no opposite. Nonlegitimacy can appear as such, be its signs ever so dis
creet, only in a process of prelegitimation. In other words, in order for that
which is not yet established elsewhere to take shape through a theoretico
institutional analysis that would do justice to it, a new institution must take
advantage of a certain capacity to access what is forbidden (repressed, made
minor, marginalized, even "unthought") elsewhere. It must therefore access
a certain knowledge still deprived of all institutional manifestation. Who
can claim that such a thing, such a knowledge or foreknowledge, exists?
To the extent that it is a question of philosophy, an institution that likes
to think it is this "new" ought to take advantage-this would be its very
right-of an access to philosophy that is still made impossible or regarded
to be so elsewhere. A claim one would be right to consider exorbitant, es
peciall y if it comes together in a single person or in the unity of a homo
geneous discourse. T hat this is not the case and that this very hypothesis is
structurally untenable already complicates the very idea of such a claim,
Privilege 15
but not without also and at the same time compromising the identity,
unity, and assembling of an institution founded upon such a project. But
is it not the example of the untenable hypothesis, the impossible project,
that we ate evoking? Does Ciph not expect its unity, the unicity of its Idea,
at least, to come from the exorbitant? (All my questions in this regard, and
especially the most incredulous ones, can only come from a place that re
mains external to Ciph, regardless of the part I might have taken in found
ing it. But I have alway s thought that participation in or belonging to
Ciph ought to be like no other.) The exorbitant is immediately contami
nated or compromised. It selects using the most reassuring norms. If Ciph
claims to discover new and necessary paths, new possible legitimations,
that is because it is already inscribed in a network of legitimacy or a pro
cess of legitimation: by the form of its project and the discourse that pre
sents it, by the people who support the project and speak for it, by those
who argue for its foundation, directly or through intervening allies. Ciph
had every title to be founded; it responded to numerous, diverse, interre
lated, and overdetermined interests. Their analysis would be difficult, but
it is possible in principle.
Despite the privilege of its apparent unicity, despite the fact that, in the
general configuration of all its characteristics, Ciph is perhaps like no other
institution in the world, it still retains some resemblance to many other
modern places ofresearch. It responds to scientific, political, technical, and
economic imperatives. What is more, while leaving aside already classified
academic titles, it does not give up considering all titles; and its criteriology
or titlology is no less discriminating. In its selection it considers unsanc
tioned titles, which are more numerous and more mobile, but which can
skrit rootci, where the game of meanings unfolded is folded back and re
connected in the very idea of connection. It is gathered up in the idea of
gathering or co-adjoining. It contracts in the idea of a contract. Whence
con-vention, consent, re-union, colligation, co-institution in spirit, in the
closure or enclosure made possible by said synagogal convention; whence
also the sense of mark and re-mark, the research, the recognition, that seeks
to know while venerating and honoring, knowledge as the recognition of a
right and an authority.
Now, one of the remarkable and paradoxical structures of the philo
sophical tide, as of everything that legitimates a contract and authorizes a
so-called philosophical institution, is that for once nothing should be
posited in advance. Nothing should be presupposed by this alliance or
convention: no object or field of objects, no theme, no certitude, no dis
cipline, not even the so-called philosopher who would give himself that ti
de on the basis of his training, research identity, or horizon of question
ing. Philosophy has no horizon, if the horizon is, as its name indicates, a
limit, if "horizon'' means a line that encircles or delimits a perspective.
This is precisely not the case, by right, for other disciplines or regions of
knowledge. As such, and this is the very status of their identification or
delimitation, they can indeed think their object in an epistemology, trans
form it by transforming the founding contract of their own institution;
but, at least in the institutional act of their research or teaching, they can
not and must never doubt the pregiven and preunderstood existence of an
object or type of identifiable being. Interdisciplinarity and the institutions
that practice it never put these horizontal identities into question. They
presuppose them more than ever. This is not, this by right should not be the
case for philosophy, since there is no philosophical horizontality.
There is a privilege there, an excess and a lack of power, that complicates
principially all of philosophy's undertakings in an interdisciplinary space
that it calls for but that, more than any other discipline, it must resist.
Those who gather in the name or on account of philosophy in fact pre
suppose, of course, traditions and the knowledge of questioning. They al
ways have, infact, horizons. And numerous and diverse ones, which never
simplifies things. But by right, they must always, at every moment (and the
reference to the moment signals here the always possible rupture or inter
ruption of a discursive or historical continuum), claim to be justified in
putting into question not only every determinate knowledge (which re
searchers in other fields can also do) but even the value of knowledge and
Privilege
to the responsibility that, in its name, carries beyond its name or the
names available for it. In its rhetoric or logic, this torsion can look like a
laborious contortion. It can appear useless or avoidable, even comic, es
pecially to those who are always sure they can smooth or flatten out the
space of discourse, efface its "performative contradictions" with a sigh of
impatience and distinguish in good conscience between the philosophical
and the nonphilosophical on either side of a straight and indivisible line.
In the report I just cited, on the contrary, when it comes to the title "phi
losophy," belonging to the "philosophical" is designated as a problem,
even a problem that is still "brand new," a philosophical problem, per
haps, but not only and necessarily. The dividing line is not given. Perhaps
it is not a line. It takes shape as the experience of a paradoxical responsi
bility that others are invited to share, to give themselves the means of shar
ing. This is done in the language of a report that is not intended for pro
fessional philosophers (a situation in which our entire problem is reflected
and concentrated) and that does not hesitate to emphasize the "provi
sional" recourse to certain nonetheless decisive words, all the while retain
ing a formal reference to the "need of philosophy'' (Hegel) or to the "in
terest of reason" (Kant) , an interest that, as long and as much as possible,
would have to be kept sheltered from all preinterpretation. That this last
precaution already gives itself a certain right to philosophy is the para
doxical provocation in whose singular space we find ourselves and attempt
to come to an agreement:
on the one hand, to designate a place of thinking in which the question ofphi
losophy would be deployed: the question about the meaning or destination of
the philosophical, irs origins, irs future, irs condition. In this regard, "think
ing" for the moment only designates an interestforphilosophy, in philosophy,
bur an interest that is not philosophical first of all, completely and necessarily.
It is, on the other hand, to affirm philosophy and define what it can be and do
today in our society as regards new forms of knowledge in general, technique,
culture, the arts, languages, policies, law [droit], religion, medicine, power and
military strategy, police information, ere. The experience of thinking on the
subject ofthe philosophica no less than philosophical work, is what might be
the task of the College. A task at once classic (what philosophy has not begun
by seeking to determine the essence and destination of philosophy?) and re-
20 Privilege
qui red today to deploy itself in sin gul ar conditions. Later, we will say the same
for the values of research, science, interscience, or art.
Right [droit] is indicated twice in this passage. Once literally and specif
ically (it is a matter of the juridical science or discipline), another time im
plicitly and co-extensively with what claims to justify the entire project, the
interest for philosophy as the right to philosophy. This latter right therefore
gives itself the right to think right philosophically as institutionalized dis
cipline. The choice of the word "thinking" to designate what exceeds the
particular modes of thought that would be philosophy and science is only
justified strategically and provisionally in this context. It of course indicates
the necessity of a certain "having it out with'' Heidegger, a reference that to
me seemed, and still seems, absolutely indispensable in this context, but, as
I have explained elsewhere, and again right here a moment ago, in the form
of listening and thinking, which is also to say, of debate and deconstruc
tion. Moreover, the moment we translate a certain gesture by Heidegger
into our language, we must consider the consequences of the fact that
"thinking" belongs to a lexical system (which is always more than itself) in
which we no longer find the semantic network that Heidegger associates
with Denken. We find another lexical system, we find ourselves in another
place of meaning-and, the moment we also read German and other lan
guages, in the space and time ofa translation ofpensee [thinking] . If, at least,
one takes translation seriously and as something other than a peaceable re
coding of already-given meanings, I see no other or better definition for
what we are speaking about here: the time of a translation of "thinking. "
Which puts in motion the essential instability of that community or col
legiality, the indecision of its title, the scruple with which it demands its
right to philosophy, in the name of philosophy, its difficulty in founding it
self as philosophical. In a word, its difficulty in founding itself, if the values
of founding and foundation are also philosophemes through and through,
and philosophemes essentially associated with values of right. (We find a
simple indication of this in the fact that in its predominant contexts Be
grnndung means, above all, justification.) Under the name of the College
International de Philosophie is found, therefore, an institution that has
been quasi-founded for seven years, but on the open and still gaping ques
tion of the subject of founding power and its own self-founding power. The
day of the official inauguration of Ciph (legally we should really say in the
presence of three ministers rather than by Mr. Fabius, Mr. Lang, and Mr.
Privilege 21
in this work. And it is always redoubled by the question of its own transla
tion into Kantian language, whether that of the infinite Idea or of right. At
this point we can say that a self-foundation could not be a present event. It
cannot exist, in the strong sense of this word that implies presence, at the
moment of installation or institution. Individuals, subjects, in the strong
sense of this word that implies presence, or the community of subjects ap
parently responsible for foundation, rely directly or indirectly on a network
of powers, on legitimating forces and "interests" of all kinds, on a state of
things and on the thing the state. This is very dear for Ciph, which, how
ever, seems very close to self-foundation and to the subject we have been
able to speak about without worrying too much about it. It is even clearer
for all the other public and private foundations. I however, across the ob
vious limits of hetero-foundation, the idea of an absolute self-foundation
takes shape (without literally presenting itself), this promise is not nothing.
In certain conditions the promise constitutes a "performative" event whose
"probability'' remains irreducible-even if the promise is never kept in a
presently certain, assured, demonstrable fashion. If something like Ciph
is habitable, it is as the experience of this space of the promise. To this ex
tent, the affirmation of a concern for independence, autonomy, and self
legitimation is not necessarily, and in anyone's mouth, a "mere word," even
if no institutional reality is or can be adequate to it. The sel the autos ofle
gitimacing and legitimated self-foundation, is still to come, not as a foture re
ality but as that which will always retain the essential structure of a promise
and as that which can only arrive as such, as to come.
son, Nicomachus, although he was his disciple. " This man of gentle and
divine speech had hordes of disciples, among them Menander, the comic
poet. Over two thousand disciples, it is said, which indicates, especially at
the time, a true "popularity." What is a popular philosopher? This ques
tion will be raised again more or less directly in the essays that follow.15
Theophrasrus, at any rate, was"popular" enough among the Athenians to
risk losing his life there as much as his adversary did when Agonides dared
accuse him of impiety, just as Meletus had accused Socrates. In one form
or another, has impiety not, from time immemorial, and thus still today,
been the indictment against every disturbing thinker? The fundamental
category of every accusation? And doesn't impiety most often consist in
taking the uncertain, chance, fortune, tukhe seriously? Cicero reports (in
Tusculanae Disputationes V, 9) that Theophrastus was accused of having
said, "Fortune is queen of the world. " Sophocles, the son of Amphidides,
had a law passed: philosophers could not preside over a school without the
"consent of the people and the senate, on pain of death. " It was then that
Theophrasrus and a few other philosophers left. They returned when Soph
ocles in turn was accused of impiety: "The Athenians repealed the law,
condemned Sophocles to a fine of five talents, and voted for the return of
the philosophers."
A vote for the return of the philosophers! Must philosophy wait to be
given votes publicly? Does it need majorities (democratic or not)? In the
logic of classical discourse, such as I have reconstructed it here, the answer
would not be long in coming: no, the interdiction applies only to the
right to education, teaching, the discipline, even the doctrine, bur in no
way to philosophy itself, to the thing itsel die Sache selbst, "philosophy, "
the "business" of philosophy. If from the point of view of positive right,
laws, or the police, one can make a dent in the right to the philosophical
This logic has richer resources at its disposal than those I expose
schematically and principially here. But it can always inspire a protest of
this type: "Why the devil do you need to burden yourself with new pub
lic or private philosophical institutions? Why try to have them legitimated
by the state, society, the nation, or the people? Why these detours? Be
philosophers right where you are, you yourselves, either in silence or by
speaking to those who can understand you, who you can understand,
with whom you can come to an understanding. You do not need a social
contract for that. You might not even need anyone . . . "
A very strong temptation: such a discourse is not only seductive, it will,
precisely [justement] , just barely [de justesse] , never be lacking in j ustice
[dejustice] and legitimacy. It has on its side, by right, the absolute of right,
every right. However, without challenging this discourse, we can nonethe
less fold it back toward its presuppositions. Without even catching it in
the "performative" trap of its own pronouncements, of its own discursiv
ity, for which it would indeed have to assume philosophical responsibility,
a particular philosophy can be detected in it. It is first of all a philosophy
of langue and langage. Two apparently opposed and irreconcilable con
cepts of language [langue] can share the same "presupposition" and the
same interpretacion of the right to philosophy, that is, that of a sort of nat
ural right that is rigorously dissociable from an institutional right.
Let's reduce these concepts to their most typical characteristic. It would
be a matter, on the one hand, of a techno-semiotic, purely conventionalist
and instrumental concept of language [langue] . Everything that derives
from these formalizable signifiers belongs to technique and the institution.
But since there is in principle no indissoluble affiliation between philo
sophical thought and a natural language [langue] , this formal language
[langage] is accessible to everyone and itself remains, like the institution,
external to a kind of natural, that is, original and universal right. This tech
nologism assumes, as is often the case, a kind of originarist naturalism
from which it emerges. On the other hand, to separate language [langue]
from semio-technique, the originarity of idiom from its instrumental con
tamination, is to end up at the same result. Every speaking being, before
any institution, can have access to philosophy, one would therefore say.
That philosophy be originarily linked by privilege to this or that language
(Greek, German) can then have several consequences: such privileged id
ioms are themselves foreign to instrumentalization, conventional transla
tion, and the institution; they are quasi-natural, "naturalized," even if their
Privilege
called "conclusions" perhaps deserve another name, for precisely the order
of derivation is in question here. Beyond the great, canonical questions
about translation and the originary privilege of a natural language (Greek
or German) ,18 the problematic that interests us here affects more pointedly
what, producing itself "inside" a language upon the arrival of philosophy,
no longer has its tapas "between'' different so-called natural languages. If it
were asserted, as has often been done, especially in Germany, that because
of its "founding concepts," indeed, its original lexical and syntactic possi
bilities, the exercise of the right to philosophy, even to thinking tout court,
is conditioned by competence in and, more generally, the experience of a
language (for example, Greek or German) , if it were added, as has often
been done, especially in Germany, that competence does not consist here
in acquiring some available techniques; then the adventure whose risks
and end remain incalculable no longer concerns one or two languages
among others. It involves itineraries of translation that lead toward or away
from the aforementioned languages at the same time. It involves tramla
tiom even "imide" these languages.
This last necessity is enough to displace the entire stakes. If one says there
is no philosophy without Greek or German (etc.), that neither only norfirst
of all excludes those for whom these languages are not their "mother
tongue," but also the Greeks and Germans19 who do not speak or write
their own language in a certain manner, which is called philosophy, this
manner of speaking and writing being of the most singular kind, marked
by a shrouded history, strangely interwoven with other histories and other
threads from the same language or other languages. Philosophy is not only
linked to a natural language. The serious and massive question is not only
that of the eurocentrism, the helleno- or germano-centrism of philosophi
cal language. Within every language, European or not, what we call "phi
losophy" must be linked regularly and differently, according to eras, places,
schools, social and socio-institutional circles, to distinct discursive proce
dures among which it is often difficult to translate. The life of philosophy
is also the experience of these "intralinguistic" translations, which are some
times as perilous or prohibited as other translations. To have access effec
tively, in effect, to these discursive procedures and thus to have the right to
the philosophical such as it is spoken, for philosophical democracy, democracy
in philosophy, to be possible (and there is no democracy in general without
that, and democracy, the democracy that remains still to come, is also a
philosophical concept) , one must be trained in these procedures. One must
30 Privilege
pense: rather, i n order t o improve its chances, its rights, o r the rights it
gives, which it can allow to be thought differently.
rights; every citizen can therefore speak, write, and print freely, but must
answer for the abuse of this freedom in the cases determined by the law."21
In what way does this discourse legitimate itself by denying its perfor
mative power and rooting it in a constative self-representation, the very
self-representation of philosophy that has always claimed it is the language
of being stating what is? The proponents of this discourse, those who of
fer it, support it, and bring it out, must claim they describe what each per
son (everyone) knows to be and to be true. For them it is only a matter of
recalling that, of making it explicit, thematizing it in the element of philo
sophical consensus. This element is transparent-or destined to transpar
ency. But it is indissociable, noncontingently, from the practice and un
derstanding of language, here of the French language. On July II, 1789, La
Fayette declared to the National Assembly that the merit of a declaration
of rights consists in "truth and precision; it must say what everyone knows,
what everyone feels." It must, therefore, it must, but it must only state. It
must, by submitting itself to a theoretical prescription, to the prescription
of being theoretical and not prescriptive, take note of (by showing) what
everyone knows or feels. It is supposed to add nothing to this knowledge
other than its explicit stating. The imperative concerns the act of saying
alone: but it must still be "well" said, that is, "truthfully and precisely."
The problems of composition are no longer extrinsic. The Declaration of
the Rights of Man implies a philosophy, a reminder that will surprise no
one, but also a philosophy of philosophy, a concept of truth and its re
lations to language. And the access to the declaration, to the content of
what it says, which gives the right to all rights, assumes instruction and
the knowledge of language. Only instruction, and first of all instruction
in language, can make one aware of right, and in particular of the right to
instruction. The two "competencies" envelop one another. They are folded
onto one another.
Considering what we said above about the philosophical over-coding or
subcoding "inside" a natural language, one can easily understand that the
debates on language and education, at the time of the composition of the
rights of man, were not simply about form any more than the "composi
tion" debates were. When we "talk philosophy'' we must always (this is the
beginning of a prescriptive statement) attempt to evaluate, for example, the
number and place of all those who would understand nothing or little of
all these potential or actual stakes: billions of human beings, all but a few
thousand, and among the very few who read me at this very moment, the
34 Privilege
tion of the rights of man, as to every institution of positive laws: and, first
of all, to the constitution of a state founded on this knowledge. One of
the ambiguities of the Declaration of 1 7 8 9 is that it does not content itself
with stating or "recalling" the principles of natural right. It also posits
elements of constitutional law concerning the separation of powers, for
example. What is important here is that constitutional law should be
founded on a philosophical knowledge of natural right. This is what Mou
nier tells the National Assembly: "For a constitution to be good, it must
be founded on the rights of man, and must obviously protect them; to
prepare a constitution, therefore, the rights that natural justice grants to
all individuals must be known; all the principles that must form the basis
of every kind of society must be recalled, and every article of the constitu
tion must be the consequence of a principle." I have emphasized the word
recall. He claims to recall that the essence of a constitution (and especially
of the declaration of the rights it supposes here) consists in a declarative
act that contents itself with bringing to the light of memory what is al
ready known in principle (at its origin and by rights) . This, at the time of
the French Revolution, entails referring to a very specific concept of the
declaration. It will be difficult to make it coincide with the definition that
Guizot will give this concept in his Nouveau dictionnaire des synonymes de
Ia languefranraise, to limit ourselves to this one indication: "To declare is
not only to make known what is unknown. It is to say things expressly
and with intent, in order to instruct those to whom one does not want
them to remain unknown."
The figure of the fold, explicitation, or complication often imposes it
self upon us. It is not, we know, incompatible with that of a circular band
or invagination.23 The right to teaching assumes the knowledge and teach
ing of right. The right to, as right of access (to whatever, teaching, philos
ophy, and so forth) , assumes the access to right, which assumes the capac
ity to read and interpret, in short, instruction.
The circulation of this circle is inscribed in the great and old concept of
ability [pouvoir] . It is indicated in the grammar and semantics of the verb
can [pouvoir] , as it can be read in j urisdictional declarations, in the state
ments that pronounce the law. In the famous article n, for example: "The
free communication of thoughts and opinions is one of the most precious
rights of man; every citizen can therefore speak, write, and print freely, but
must answer for the abuse of this freedom in the cases determined by the
law." The word "can," the verb can in the third person singular of the pre-
Privilege 37
sent indicative, can and must be readable. One has the right to interpret it,
in two ways, simultaneously and indissociably. On the one hand, "can"
means "must be able": not "every citizen can" at this moment (is capable
of), but must be able (permitted) to speak, write, print (teach?) freely. Even
if he cannot do so in fact today (and this is indeed why we posit, even if to
recall, this normative or prescriptive law), he must be able to do so in prin
ciple and by right. But on the other hand, as citizen he can do so without
delay: if he is recognized as a citizen, the state ensures the present effective
ness of this ability. State power [pouvoir] should guarantee that the citizen's
ability or power [pouvoir] does not remain formal, that it no longer belongs
solely to the order of the possible, of the abstract wish or simple prescrip
tion. But how can one ensure the passage between the two meanings or
modalities of power or ability? Through an ability-to-interpret, speak, write,
decipher. This latter passes by way of the practice of language and, to the
extent that it is a matter of universal principles, by way of philosophy. By
way of the training of ability as linguistic and philosophical competence.
This latter ability is of course inscribed in the circle, but it is also the con
dition of the circulation of the circle. It is the becoming effective of right,
as right to.
This expression, "right to," with which we have already made a lot of
sentences, marks a sort of mutation in the history of right. It is difficult to
date rigorously, but it announces a difference in regime in the relations be
tween the citizen and the state, if at least, as has been the case from Kant to
Kelsen, right, distinguished from morality, is understood as a system of
norms in which the state manifests itself by exercising sanction or coer
cion.24 This difference in regime makes the passage from the right of to the
right to, even if a right to remains virtually implied in the right of In the his
tory of the declarations of the rights of man and their corollaries over the
last two centuries, much more has been said about the right to when the
aim has been to determine the contents of the social rights that should fill
in the abstract formality of the rights of 1789. Far from contenting itself
with not impeding the exercise of the right of (right of property, rights of
speech, writing, publishing, resisting oppression) , the state must also inter
vene actively to make possible the exercise of the right to and to prepare
conditions favorable for it. The example of the "right to work'' must be ca
pable of being extended to the rights to instruction and culture. It must be
capable of this. It must by right, but we encounter here a structural-and
Privilege
into this debate yet-it will take up almost this entire work. Let's note just
one of the dimensions of the disagreement. It is also a matter of a disagree
ment about the name of philosophy and of the philosophical discipline.
Those who remain content with the little philosophy that is taught in the
Terminale, like those who think that it is still too much, can respond to
those who speak of the "right to philosophy": at any rate, to the extent that
it is implied everywhere (and first of all, I have said, in the reading, under
standing, or critical interpretation, thus in the exercise, of all rights) , we
find some philosophy everywhere, in particular in the other disciplines, and
from the moment we learn to speak the language. This philosophy need
not be confused with a specialized discipline. This argument has great titles
of nobility in the philosophical tradition, and we will speak about them
laterY On the contrary, and for this very reason, those who demand that
"philosophy," as specialized discipline, be present as such before the Termi
nale fear that in the absence of a rigorous, critical, and explicit discipline,
other contents (moral, social, and political ideology, etc.) will insidiously
and dogmatically occupy the place of what they consider "philosophy."
In all these hypotheses, should the state or the social body do more or
less than institute a "philosophy in the Terminale," formally-very for
mally-ensuring each citizen the chance of encountering one of those
things that are called philosophy at least once in his or her life? Or rather,
must this go further? How far? Does that mean training the largest possi
ble number of teachers of philosophy? Who will determine the extent of
that possibility? According to what criteria? Why would it not be the right
or duty of the teachers of other disciplines-as some demand-to include
philosophical training in their own education? And why would this train
ing be reserved to future professional teachers?
These are concrete, current questions often debated beyond the circle
of those who "militate" for respecting the rights to philosophy. Whatever
their seriousness or complexity, they all envelop another question that might
be called more "radical." If the declaration of a right hides a performative
under a constative, its "convention" always assumes a philosophy. It at the
same time assumes that its own meaning is accessible to everyone "inter
ested" (or assumed to be, for this community is not yet given; it is never
given, but rather is to be constituted by this very right). The access to the
meaning of this declaration (made possible by literacy, the introduction
to a certain type of hermeneutic, that is to say, to so many other things)
is at the same ime, in one and the same movement, the access to the
Privilege
minor, to marginalize, to censor (by every means, and the means are some
times subtle and always overdetermined) other philosophical discourses or
other discourses on the subject ofphilosophy, in particular when their ques
tioning exceeds the philosophico-juridico-political machinery that sup
ports the state, the nation, and its pedagogical institutions.
From this angle, one realizes that a right to philosophy could not be
one right among others. One can, no doubt, no doubt one even must en
trust the conditions of its implementation to a state, which, as state of
right, is qualified to make effective the very right that posits or constitutes
it. But these conditions of implementation should remain external to the
philosophical as such. Is this possible, in all rigor, in all purity? No, but
externalwould here mean tendentially, ideally extrinsic: once the state is
obligated to ensure the technical, material, professional, institutional, and
so on, conditions of a right to philosophy, no contract would bind phi
losophy itself and institute this philosophy as a reciprocal and responsible
partner of the state. If this were demanded of philosophy, even implicitly,
philosophy would have the right, a right it only gets from itself, this time,
and in no way from the state, to match wits with the state, to break uni
laterally every agreement, in a brutal or cunning, declared or, if the situa
tion demands, surreptitious fashion. This irresponsibility toward the state
can be demanded by philosophy's responsibility to its own law-or the re
sponsibility of what I above called thinking, which can, in analogous con
ditions, break its contract with science or philosophy. Despite appearances,
this is not to reconstruct the essential interiority of a philosophy whose
"business" would be to j ustifY itself On the contrary, it is to carry its re
sponsibility still further: to the point of giving itself the right-or privi
lege-to go on questioning, without trusting too quickly, the limit between
the inside and the outside, the proper and the improper, what is essential
and proper to philosophy and what is not.
If we follow this kind of argumentation, the right to philosophy can be
managed, protected, facilitated by a juridico-political apparatus (and de
mocracy, insofar as its model is already given, remains in this regard the
best one); it cannot be guaranteed, still less produced, through the law as
a body of prescriptions accompanied by coercion and sanction. Jumping
some steps, let's say that the philosophical act or experience takes place
only once this juridico-political limit can be transgressed, or at least ques
tioned, perturbed, in the force that will in a certain sense have naturalized
that limit. As for what would link this transgression to the production of
Privilege
a new right, "thinking" (which "is" that very thing) must be able to pro
nounce its right beyond philosophy and science. Through philosophy and
science, as I might have said a moment ago: through the state. There is no
pure instance. "Thinking," a word that entitles only the possibility of this
"no," must even, in the name of a democracy still to come28 as the possi
bility. of this "thinking," unremittingly interrogate the de facto democracy,
critique its current determinations, analyze its philosophical genealogy, in
short, deconstruct it: in the name of the democracy whose being to come
is not simply tomorrow or the future, but rather the promise of an event
and the event of a promise. An event and a promise that constitute the de
mocratic: not presently but in a here and now whose singularity does not
signifY presence or self-presence.
which therefore can be approached but in no way reached. Thus one must
content oneself, as was the case with the metaphysics of nature, with the
"first metaphysical principles of the doctrine of right." What is here called
"right" is what, Kant tells us, derives from the system outlined a priori and
is inscribed "in the text" (in den Text), that is, the principal text, while the
rights linked to experience and particular cases find themselves relegated
to the Remarks and other annexes to the corpus.
Here, then, the question of the language of the philosopher, or rather of
his discourse, imposes itself. Must he remain "obscure" or make it his duty
to become "popular"? We should not be surprised to see this question arise
concerning right or the metaphysics of right. The philosopher's language
(the discursive implementation of a language within language) must in
fact become popular, Kant responds to a certain Garve, unless this imper
ative were to lead the philosopher to neglect, fail to recognize, or, worse,
lead his readers to ignore, rigorous distinctions, decisive divisions, essential
stakes for thinking. Kantian rigor and prudence appear so exemplary
and so appropriate to our modern debates on philosophy and the media
that a long citation imposes itself here. It is a supplementary complication
that the major, strategically determining distinction, the distinction that
cannot and must not in any case let itself be "popularized," is, in Kant's
eyes, that of the sensible and the intelligible, the very distinction that so
many deconstructive approaches have tracked down for a long time, in it
self and in the extreme diversity of its effects. It must be taken into ac
count today if one wants to reconcile the responsibilities of philosophical
and "deconstructive" rigor, new orders of public or media space, and the
imperatives of the democracy to come. The strategy of public discourse
must be more cunning than ever-and incessantly reevaluated. Although
"popularity, " as Kant, who speaks elsewhere of a "popular tone,"33 sug
gests, can today no longer mean, if it ever could have, "to be sensible," we
can draw a formal and analogous lesson from the response to Garve-and
in advance to all the Garves of modernity:
Philosophical treatises are often charged with being obscure, indeed deliber
ately unclear, in order to affect an illusion of deep insight. I cannot better an
ticipate or forestall this charge than by readily complying with a duty that
Garve, a philosopher in the true sense of the word, lays down for all writers,
but especially for philosophical writers. My ody reservation is imposed by the
nature of the science that is to be corrected and extended.
This wise man rightly requires (in his work Vermischte Aufiatze34) that every
Privilege 45
strict, only attains its proper stricture, to the extent that it is constraining,
exacting, but also to the extent that it links a "reciprocal universal coer
cion'' with the "freedom of everyone," and does so according to an "exter
nal universal" law, that is, a natural one. This value of exteriority distin
guishes pure right from morals. Right has no internal depths; its "objects"
(Objekte) must be shown in actions. It is a domain of visibility or theatri
cality without fold. Even when a certain interiority is summoned or called
to appear (questions of veracity, remorse, deep conviction, motives, etc.),
it is assumed that it can be exposed completely-in a discourse or in ex
pressive gestures. This exteriority of strict and pure right is in no way
"mixed up" with "some prescription relative to virtue."
But exteriority is not enough to found right. It does not j ustify it. Ac
cording to a sort of logico-transcendental foctum (whose wake is found in
Kelsen), the foundation of right is not j uridical but moral. "This is indeed
based [griindet sich] on everyone's consciousness of obligation [aufdem
Bewuj!tsein der Verbindlichkeit] in accordance with the law [nach dem Ge
set:z] , which also means everyone's being before the law, Vor dem Gesetz, a
being-before-the-law that is at once moral and j uridical, therefore, and
thus also anterior to this distinction between the two laws] ; but if it is to
remain pure, this consciousness may not and cannot be appealed to as an
incentive to determine one's choice in accordance with this law. Strict right
rests instead on the principle of its being possible to use an external con
straint that can coexist with the freedom of everyone in accordance with
universal laws."37
This consciousness (excluded as a "motive" for right) is nonetheless the
consciousness of strict right. Is it a moral or a j uridical consciousness?38
The consciousness of obligation is already j uridical and still moral. It is
what "founds" strict right. But Kant suggests that it does not belong to the
order ofwhat it founds. The founding of strict right would not be j uridi
cal. Not in the sense in which one could say, in a Heideggerian gesture,
that the j uridicity of right or the essence of right is in no way j uridical
(with all the didactico-institutional consequences that follow), but in the
sense in which the being-right of right is its (moral and juridical) right to
be right: the order of the law and not of being. A question of stricture.39
The possibility of an analogy between right and rectilinearity is closely
related to pedagogy, even if this relation appears principia! and virtual.
What is at stake in fact is the presentation (Darstellung) of a concept, its
presentation in a pure and a priori intuition, but following an analogy.
Privilege 47
Kant defines (before the Remark, precisely) "strict right": "the possibility
of a complete, reciprocal constraint in accordance with the freedom of
everyone following universal laws" (2 5) . Let us again recall this important
point: only a perfectly external right deserves the name of strict (narrow)
right, even if this right founds itself on the consciousness of an obligation
before the law. But such a consciousness is not the motive for a juridical
arbitration that must rely on the possibility of an external constraint, at
least to the extent that it can be reconciled with the freedom of everyone
following universal laws. If we have the right to demand the settlement of
a debt, it is not to the extent that we can persuade the debtor's reason, but
to the extent that we can constrain him, in a manner that is compatible
with the freedom of everyone "following a universal external law": "right
and the faculty of constraining are one and the same thing."
It is in order to construct this pure concept of right, that is, to present it
in a pure a priori intuition, that the question of analogy is posed. At issue
is the analogy between this pure concept of right and the possibility of the
free movement of bodies under the law of the equality of action and reac
tion. The analogy between pure right and pure mathematics is announced
by a "just as, so too [sowie] ." "But, just as" in pure mathematics, the prop
erties of its object cannot be derived immediately, directly, from a concept
(hence the necessity of "constructing" the concept) , "so too" the presenta
tion of the concept of right is not made possible directly by the concept it
self, but only by reference to a reciprocal and equal constraint under uni
versal laws. This first analogy remains too formal and belongs to the order
of pure mathematics. That is still not enough, therefore, to explain the re
course to analogies with the "right" (gerade, rectilinear) , the curved, or the
oblique. A supplementary argument, another analogy; must ensure the me
diation-and Kant must allude to the care shown by reason, to the con
cern (llersorgen) it offers, a reason that is providing, providential, giving: to
put at our disposal, within reach of our understanding, as far as possible, a
priori intuitions that help us construct the concept of right. Without such
solicitude from reason, without the system oflirnits that it procures, guar
antees, and crosses at the same time, no "presentation" would be possible,
and we can say, skipping some steps, no properly philosophical rhetoric,
pedagogy; communication, or discussion:
action], so too reason has taken care to furnish the understanding as far as pos
sible with a priori intuitions for constructing the concept of right. Straighmess
or rectitude (rectum) is opposed to what is curved on the one hand and what is
oblique on the other. In the first case, it is a question of the innerproperty of a
line such that there can only be a single one between two given points, inclin
ing no more to one side than to the other and dividing the space on both sides
equally. Analogously to this, the doctrine of right wants to determine that
what belongs to each has been determined (with mathematical exactitude).
Such exactitude cannot be expected in the doctrine ofvirtue, which cannot re
fuse some room for exceptions (latitudinem). (26)
the level of the canon. Whatever the supposedly intrinsic necessity of this
reference to the Kantian discourse on right, morals, politics, teaching in
general, the teaching of philosophy insofar as it is not one teaching among
others, etc., our relation to this necessity, the interest or pleasure we take
in recognizing and exposing it (which happens to me every time I read
Kant, and it is always for the first time), all that implies a program and a
repetition. For many of "us" ("us": the majority of my supposed readers
and myself), the authority of.Kantian discourse has inscribed its virtues of
legitimation to such a depth in our philosophical training, culture, and
constitution that we have difficulty performing the imaginary variation
that would allow us to "figure" a different one. Better, the "relation to
Kant" signals the very idea of training, culture, constitution, and espe
cially "legitimation," the question of right, that is, the element in which
we see the situation I am describing at this moment take shape. Even in
the expression "relation to," a "French philosopher" over-hears or infers
the translation of the "relation to [Beziehung auf] ," of the relation to the
object or to "something in general," a Kantian syntagm.
The Kantian heritage is not only the Kantian heritage, a thing identical
to itself. Like every heritage, it exceeds itself to provide (or lay claim to)
the analysis of this heritage and, better, the instruments of analysis for
every heritage. This "supplementary" structure must be taken into ac
count. A heritage always surreptitiously bequeaths to us the means of in
terpreting it. It superimposes itself a priori on the interpretation we pro
duce of it, that is to say, always, to a certain extent, and up to a line that is
difficult to determine, that we repeat of it.
Yet whoever says this (here me, for example) does not need to specify "I
am a Kantian'' or "I know Kant well." It is as though the "relation to Kant"
were tattooed on. It is the privileged inscription of an absolute privilege, one
quasi-naturalized right in the training, and by that training, in its programs,
its values and implicit evaluations, the modes of.argumentation and dis
cussion it authorizes, the kinds of sanction and reproduction it codifies, the
genres of exercise it favors (the essay, the thesis, the dissertation), the rhet
oric, the "style," the experience of language it privileges. This is no doubt
due in large part to the "figure" of .Kant, to this philosopher's public image
in the doxa of a socio-cultural circle determined by the French schooling
that for a long time included a "philosophy class": all young French bour
geois are supposed to have heard of this severe, difficult to read, bachelor,
civil servant philosopher. There again, let us read or reread Le Discours de
50 Privilege
angles. The question of its singularity, that is, its absolute privilege, will
only be more pointed. Kantian critique and metaphysics are inseparable
from modern teaching. They "are" this teaching, that is to say that they
"are" teaching forms untried until now.
I. They propose a pedagogy. They situate the moment and necessity of
the pedagogical: outside the pure thinking of principles, but as the neces
sity of an ascent to pure principles for the "people" as "unwitting meta
physician." I have insisted, and will do so again (later, in the chapter enti
tled "Popularities"40), on this topic of pedagogy and what it assumed
about metaphysics (the construction of the concept of the people and the
"popular" on the basis of the distinction between reason and understand
ing, imagination and sensibility, the opposition of the intelligible and the
sensible, the pure and the impure, the inside and the outside, the strict
and the nonstrict) .
2. Let's move quickly to the fact that Kantian philosophy is elaborated
and structured as a teaching discourse. More precisely, that of a professor
in a state University. This can be seen not only in the well-known fact that
Kant wrote essays and theses, that he led the life of a civil servant, and that
he had all kinds of debates with the royal power upon which he depended,
the echo of which we find in particular in The Conflict ofthe Faculties and
Religion Within the Limits ofReason Alone. This was the case, in this form
and to this degree, of no philosopher before him. On the other hand, af
ter him, rare were the noteworthy philosophers who did not find them
selves in an analogous situation. These "facts" being well known, it would
no doubt be more interesting and difficult to identifY the marks of that
situation in the logico-rhetorical form and even in the very "content" of
Kantian philosophy. This philosophy was homogeneous and predisposed
to the becoming-public-teaching of philosophy in given socio-political
conditions: classrooms, programs, evaluations, and sanctions within a sys
tem (the school and the university) holding not only a power of the trans
mission and reproduction of knowledge (which might have been consid
ered secondary by certain representatives of professional philosophy) but
above all a power of judgment, evaluation, and sanction, that is, the power
of a jurisdiction, of an instance pronouncing the law, accompanying its
declarations with an objective constraint (this is the very definition of right
according to Kant) , and deciding on the legitimacy of a discourse or a
thinking, on relevance and competence, by conferring upon it a title, in
deed, a professional right.
52 Privilege I
3 This possibility of Kamian discourse is as much a symptom (and there
I
are so many others) as a determining factor. It would be naive to choose
here between the two terms of such an alternative. It would be better to at
tempt to think this singular "history'' (the only privilege there is) in such a
way that the discourse, critique, and metaphysics of a certain Immanuel
Kant could be read at once as "cause" and "effect," meaning and symptom,
production and product, origin and repetition, so many distinctions for
malized by a graphics of iterability,41 inscribed in it as "effects" that it in
turn relativizes without, however, disqualifYing them. "Kant" is the name
of something "possible": made possible and making possible in turn. Some
thing possible that is no doubt produced, carried by the birth of the mod
ern state and its teaching systems, whose limits and precarity it therefore
shares; like the modern state, this something possible is of course also car
ried and produced by the history of earlier philosophies, as by so many
other preexisting forces, drives, and pressures. But this symptomal forma
cion is powerful, gathered together in its formalization, overdetermined and
overdetermining. It therefore possibilizes: in turn, but it is destined to this
turn. Through numerous relays of potencialization, it participates in the
most structuring, the most productive, and the most destructive operations
in the history to come of discourses, works, and European institutions. It
informs European "culture," which is also to say European "colonization,"
wherever it operates.
The possibilization of this power can also be read in the "internal" or
ganization of Kantian discourse. It works on the critical idea itself, in its
rhetorical-conceptual armature, architectonic motif, system of limits, and
machinery of semantic oppositions. What could be more indispensable
than such an architectonics for a philosophical institution charged, if one
can put it this way (although charged in complete freedom respecting aca
demic autonomy, of course), by the state, even by any civil or clerical power
whatsoever, with assuming the mission of judging, of telling the truth (but
also, and even thereby, of authorizing those who distinguish competences,
confer titles, produce and propagate legitimacies), of pronouncing the law
or, more radically, the truth42 and metaphysical principles of the doctrine of
right, of providing the very criteria for distinguishing the strict from the
nonstrict, of deducing according to rigorous and specific rules the possibil
ity of "equivocation" or "illegitimacy'' in the order of right?43 What could
be more efficient in this regard than a discursive machinery of the Kancian
type with its principia! and cutting oppositions between the sensible and
Privilege 53
The critique of pure reason (the project and the work that carry this ti
tle, whose title or rights are guaranteed by the entire juridical history of rea
son) is no doubt an institution, since it has the status of a nonnatural and
Privilege
It is idle to feign indifference to such enquiries, the object of which can never
be indifferent to our human nature. Indeed these pretended indifferentists, how
ever they may try to disguise themselves by substituting a popular tone for the
language of the schools, inevitably fall back, in so far as they think at all, into
those very metaphysical assertions which they profess so greatly to despise.
None the less this indifference, showing itself in the midst of flourishing [mit
ten in dem Flor] sciences, and affecting precisely those sciences, the knowledge
of which, if attainable, we should least of all care to dispense with, is a phe-
Privilege
nomenon that calls for attention and reflection. It is obviously the effect not
of levity bur of the mature judgment [ Urteilskraft] of the age, which refuses to
be put off any longer with illusory knowledge. It is a call to reason to under
rake anew the most difficult of all irs tasks, that of self-knowledge, and to in
stitute a tribunal. (8-9)
totality; the infinite Idea in the Kantian sense, which still plays a decisive
role in the transcendental teleology of Husserlian phenomenology) , even
if the question of the meaning of being is torn from the question of the
totality of beings for Heidegger. Even if he demonstrates the impossibility
of totalization, even if he denounces the evil of totality or totalitarianism,
even if he calls for the question beyond the whole, he is a philosopher
who, in the tradition of the quidjuris, says (something about) the totality
of beings, about the symbolic and hyperbolic, the hyper-symbolic relation
that connects the whole to what lies beyond it and permits one precisely
to speak about it, authorizes discourse about it. The philosopher autho
rizes himself to speak about the whole: and thus about everything.
Such is his mission, such his power proper, what he bequeaths or dele
gates to himself in addressing it to himsel beyond every other instance. To
say of this self-authorization that it defines the autonomous power of the
University as philosophy and philosophical concept of philosophy does not
mean that this discourse would be offered or implied only in the Univer
sity; even less in chairs of philosophy. It corresponds to the essence of the
dominant discourse in industrial modernity of the Occidental type. That,
on the one hand, it deconstructs itself in every respect and according to dif
ferent modes (the possibility of the hypersymbolic deposes what it posits,
destructs by constructing), that, on the other hand, those who can articu
late it in its magistral and philosophical form in academic institutions are
endowed with so little "real power" changes nothing of the figure and es
sence of this power. The "truth" of this university discourse pronouncing
the law oflaw is found elsewhere in other forms. We must correct our per
ception of it and recognize the university site outside the walls of the insti
tution itself: in the allegory or metonymy of the University; in the social
body that gives itself this power and this representation.
3 Leamed Ignorance. A certain nonknowledge is intimately associated
with the hypersymbolic excess of this power of.critical questioning that
s ummons every field of knowledge to appear and for that reason must re
main formal. To translate this necessity into a malicious caricature, one
could say that the philosopher authorizes himself to know about every
thing on the basis of an "I don't want to know." No effective content of
positive knowledge in any region of the encyclopedia derives from philos
ophy. A paradoxical situation whose most concrete effects we sometimes
experience. The philosopher gives himself the right (even if he does not al
ways take it, in fact) to incompetence in all the domains of the encyclope-
Privilege
dia, all the departments of the University. He does this while demanding
the right to pronounce the law about the totality of these knowledges and
about the essence of knowledge in general, about the meaning of each re
gion of beingness or objectivity. This postulation is common, despite all
their differences, to Kant and Husserl, to Hegel and Heidegger (the Hei
degger of Being and Time, at any rate) . Certain philosophers sometimes
have a particular knowledge, of course, at least in certain disciplines, and,
moreover, always to different degrees. Philosophical training of course nec
essarily implies a certain education (a scientific one, especially outside of
France; in the "humanities"-arts, literature, and the human sciences
especially in France) . This poses all kinds of interesting and serious prob
lems but changes nothing of the essential structure of the philosophical
position and of the generality of the mechanism. An essential and manda
tory incompetence, a structural nonknowledge, constructs the concept of
philosophy as metaphysics or the science of science. That does not exclude
an impressive scientific competence in certain cases (Kant, Hegel, or oth
ers). But this competence is always "historical" in the sense Kant under
stands it in The Conflict ofthe Faculties: it concerns what one learns from
others in the form of results; it is a knowledge that has already been pro
duced and accredited elsewhere, that one can only display or must relate
flawlessly. But by rights, precisely, the content of historical and positive
knowledge is not required, as shocking as this might appear. It remains ex
ternal to the philosophical act as such. This exteriority (which poses the
enormous problems of the norms of philosophical training) potentializes
the power and the powerlessness of the philosopher, in his posture armed
with a quidjuris, the powerless power of the modern University as an es
sentially philosophical place, its vital force and deconstructible precarity,
its continuous, interminable, terminable death. Most of the texts collected
in this book52 associate the old theme of our modernity (the suspended
death sentence of philosophy) with the historical situation of this privilege.
"subversion" but also the "preservation of the symbolic order" while objec
tifying-as much as possible-such a contradiction, etc.), a "complete ob
jectification," that is, an objectification that has been achieved and is no
longer maintained as a regulating idea, such a consideration should recon
stitute the metalanguage of an absolute knowledge that would place "soci
ology'' in the place of the great logic and would ensure it absolute, that is,
philosophical, hegemony over the multiplicity of the other regions of knowl
edge, of which sociology would no longer simply be a part. It should find
(as I believe every time I subscribe to its most radical projects) another
name for itsel I do not believe Bourdieu considers this objectification ef
fictively possible, even if he appears perfectly justified in doing everything
he can to approach it. And the task is infinite. But (a second type of hy
pothesis), if the task is infinite, it is not only because there will always be
more to do and because what is spread out as far as the eye can see is the
content of what is to be objectified, in particular concerning objectification
itself (a place and interests, the "habitus" of objectifying "subjects," her
itage, all kinds of affiliation, style, methods-language! etc. See the first
hypothesis) . The "objectifiable" is not objectifiable, because it always ex
ceeds the scene of visibility. But beyond all the analyses, which cannot but
remain incomplete, the task is infinite for a reason ofanother order, which,
in a certain way, folds or interrupts the homogeneous unfolding of an end
less progress-and finishes the infinite. The "necessary accident" that some
times "engenders" the "interest in truth" can also induce a supplement of
objectification that no longer belongs to the order of objectivity, no more,
therefore, than it belongs to that of subjectivity, and leaves room for the
question of the "truth" of objectivity, of the genealogy of the value of ob
jectivity, of the history of the interpretation of the truth as objectivity (a
history that eludes historians as it does all "objectifying" knowledge by de
finition). And thus leaves room for a new type of question about this very
determination of the infinite task that retains an essential relation with the
process of knowledge as process of objectification.56
July-August 199 0
Where a Teaching Body Begins
and How It Ends
(There will be more than one sign ofthis: these notes were not intended, as
the saying goes, for publication.
Nothing, however, ought to keep them sealed. What could be more public,
at its origin, and more presentable than a teaching? What could be more ex
posed than its staging orputting into question, as is the case here? That is why,
the first reason, I accepted the proposal to reproduce these notes without the
slightest modification.
There must have been other reasom, since I hesitatedfor a long time. What,
in fact, could theftagment (chopped offmore or less arbitrarily, as ifby a me
chanical knifo) ofa single class mean, thefirst class, moreover, more than oth
ers marked by the inadequacies, approximatiom, andprogrammatic general
itypronounced before an audience more anonymous and undefined than ever?
Why this class rather than another? And why my continuous discourse rather
than others, rather than the critical exchanges thatfollowed? Unable to amwer
these questiom, Ifinally decided that the struggle in which Greph (Groupe de
Recherches sur l'Enseignement Philosophique} is involved todayl made them
secondary: Since the proposed class essentially relates to Greph, why not seize
(ftom the sidelines) the opportunity to make better known what is at stake in,
and the objectives of, its work?
Another, more serious, objection: Was myparticipation in this volume com
patible with the very intention one can read, at least in part and indirectly, in
these notes? Should I be ofservice to (or make use of) one ofthe numerous un
dertakings (here in the immediateform ofpublishing) that multiply the skir
mishes (but without questioning-it hardly matters-all the intentiom ofall
their agents) agaimt the very thingftom which they draw their existence and
68 Where a Teaching Body Begim
whose alibis they maintain? More precisely, do not collecting names, selecting
figures, and displaying titles reveal one ofthe phenomena of authority (an al
ready solid counter-imtitution, even ifits unity, comideredfrom other angles,
must leave one baffled and invite the most circumspect ofinvestigatiom) nec
essmily produced by the apparatus that, on the contrary, is to be dislocated?
The connectiom between this apparatus and that ofpublishing are becoming
more and more obvious. Theyform precisely one ofthe objects ofthe work, one
ofthe targets rather, of Greph, which ought to link its activity with that ofa
research and information group about the publishing machine. Manifest
(undisguised), the intention ofwhatyou read right here is to callfor such ac
tivities, on the spot.
But I am simplifying a great deal. I have to be brief The laws ofthisfield
are tricky. we have to begin to challenge them. In short, comidering the great
est possible number ofgivem at my disposal, because the objectives of Greph
seem to me to impose this, Iprefer in the end to run the risk ofposing here (this
timefrom an internal border) spiraling questiom that concern theplaces, scenes,
andforces that stillpermit them to present themselves.
Thefragment ofthisfirst class opened a sort ofcounter-seminar ofthe Cen
tre de Recherches sur l'Emeignement Philosophique (Research Center on the
Teaching ofPhilosophy). Established at the Ecole Normale Superieure two years
ago, this center is by right distinctfrom Greph, with which, ofcourse, there is
no lack ofopportunitiesfor exchange.
On the program, for the I974-75 year, were the following questiom:
-What is a teaching body-ofphilosophy?
-What do "defeme" and "philosophy" mean today in the slogan "the de-
feme ofphilosophy"?
-Ideology and the French ideologues (the analysis ofthe concept ofideol
ogy and of the politico-pedagogical projects ofthe French Ideologues at the
time ofthe Revolution).)
One must not forget that. One must (try, first of all, just to see, a dis
course without "one must," and not just without an obvious "one must,"
one that is visible as such, but without a hidden "one must"; I propose to
bring these to light in so-called theoretical, indeed trans-ethical discourses,
even when they do not claim to be discourses of teaching; at bottom, in the
latter, the teaching discourses, the "one must"-the lesson given concinu-
Where a Teaching Body Begins
ously, from the moment the floor is taken-is perhaps, naively or not, only
more declared, which can, in certain conditions, disarm it more quickly),
one must therefore avoid naturalizing this place.
has been transformed (for security reasons and for lack of space in the so
called classrooms that were formerly reserved for the small number of stu
dents chosen for the Ecole Normale Superieure) . Here, in the Ecole Nor
male Superieure, in the place where I, this teaching body that I call mine
and that occupies a very specific function in what is called the French
philosophical teaching body today, I teach. I say now that I am teaching.
And where for the first time, at least in this direct form, I am getting
ready to speak about the teaching of philosophy.
That is to say, where, after approximately fifteen years of experience
called "teaching" and twenty-three years as a civil servant, I am only be
ginning to question, exhibit, and critique systematically. (I am begin
ning, rather, to begin in this fashion. I am beginning by beginning to do
so systematically and effectively: it is the systematic character that is im
portant if one does not want to remain content with verbal alibis, skir
mishes, or scrapes that do not affect the system in place. No fairly alert
philosopher will ever have neglected these; on the contrary, they make up
part of the predominant system, its very code, its relation to itsel its self
critical reproduction-self-critical reproduction forming perhaps the dri
ving force of the tradition and of philosophical conservation, its inces
sant sublation, along with the art of the question with which it will be
discussed below. It is the systematic character that is important, as well as
its effictiveness, which can never come down to the initiative of a single
person. And that is why, for the first time, I am here linking my discourse
to the group work engaged in under the name Greph.) I am beginning,
then, this late, to question, exhibit, and critique systematically-in view
of a transformation-the borders of that within which I have given more
than one talk.
When I say "this late," this is not (principally, at least) to make a scene
or put on a show of self-critique, mea culpa, or histrionic guilty conscience.
I could justify at length why I abstain from such a gesture. Let us say, to
cut things very short, that I have never had a taste for that and I even take
it to be a question of taste. When I say "this late," it is rather to begin the
analysis both of a belatedness that, as we know, is not mine alone, and that
therefore cannot be explained only by subjective or individual inadequa
cies, and of a possibility that is not opened by chance today or by the de
cision of a single person. The belatedness and one's awareness of it, in di
verse forms, and the beginning of (theoretical and practical, as the saying
Where a Teaching Body Begins 7I
than one of its traits and in strategically defined moments, it had to have re
course to a "style" unacceptable to a university reading body (the "allergic"
reactions to it were not long in coming), unacceptable even in places said
to be outside the university. As we know, it is not always in the university
that the "university style" dominates. It sometimes sticks to those who have
left the university, and even people who have never been there. You can see
this ftom the sidelines. This work, then, tackled the ontological or tran
scendental subordination of the signifying body in relation to the ideality
of the transcendental signified and to the logic of the sign; it tackled the
transcendental authority of the signified as well as the signifier, and there
fore that which constirutes the very essence of the philosophical. For a long
time, therefore, it has been necessary (coherent and programmed) that de
construction not limit itself to the conceprual content of philosophical ped
agogy, but that it challenge the philosophical scene, all its instirutional
norms and forms, as well as everything that makes them possible.
If it had remained at a simple semantic or conceprual deconstirution,
which it never did except in the eyes of those who profited from their in
ability to understand it, deconstruction would have formed but a-new
modality of the internal self-critique of philosophy. It would have risked
reproducing philosophical properness, philosophy's self-relation, the econ
omy of traditional putting into question.
However, in the work that awaits us, we must be suspicious of all forms
of reproduction, all the powerful and subtle resources of reproduction:
among them, if one can still say so, that of a concept of reproduction that
cannot ("simply") be used here without being "expanded" (Marx) , that
cannot be expanded without recognizing the contradiction at work in it,
and always heterogeneously, that cannot be analyzed in its essential con
tradiction without posing, in all its magnitude, the problem of contradic
tion (or dialectics) as philosopheme. Could an effective deconstruction, in
the "final instance," proceed with such a philosopheme (with something
like a "Marxist philosophy'')?
Inversely, if deconstruction had disregarded the principle of the internal
destrucruration of phallogocentric onto-theology, it would have repro
duced, in a politicist, sociologist, historicist, economistic, etc., precipita
tion, the classic logic of its surroundings. And it would have let itself be
guided, more or less directly, by traditional metaphysical schemes. That, it
seems to me, is what threatens or limits, in essence, the rare and therefore
very precious French works on the teaching of philosophy, whatever the
Where a Teaching Body Begins 73
give technical advice in the name of a jury and canons that in his eyes have
been discredited. Like the candidates, he judges severely, for example, a
given report by a given jury, and if they happen to send protests to the gen
eral inspectors or presidents of the juries, they know from experience that
they will simply go unanswered.
In his "seminar," since for several years now the repeaters have been al
lowed to conduct a seminar in addition and next to the repetition exer
cises properly speaking, the repeater reproduces the division: he tries to
help the "candidates," all the while introducing, like a long stream of con
traband, premises that no longer belong to the space of the general agn
gation, 4 that even undermine it more or less underhandedly. Such dissoci
ation is so well accepted and interiorized on both sides that I myself have
been able to abstain almost totally, in the course of the exercises, and par
tially, in the course of seminars, from implicating work that I pursue else
where and that can be consulted in publications. I act as though this work
did not exist, and only those who read me can reconstruct the network
that, although concealed, of course unites my teaching and my published
texts. Everything in the seminar must, in principle, begin at a fictive zero
point of my relation to the audience: as though we were all "complete be
ginners" the whole time. We will have to return to these two values (rep
etition and "complete beginners") to seek in them a general law of philo
sophical exchange, a general permanent law whose phenomena will have
been no less differentiated, specific, and irreducible throughout history.
This dissociating fiction is indeed accepted, but for a few ruses and de
tours, by both sides; I have heard it spoken by two students of the Ecole,
long ago and of late, whom I cite not for their anecdotal but for their
symptomatic value. While he was a student, one of them told me, "I have
decided not to read you in order to work unbiased and to simplifY our re
lations." And in fact he seems to have read me after the agregation, has
even cited me in certain of his publications (which are remarkable, by the
way), which, he told me, would have caused him trouble with this or that
commission before which he still found himself in the position of a can
didate. The other, once his education was finished and he was appointed
to a position as assistant in a Parisian university, recently told me that he
preferred one of my publications to another and asked if I shared his feel
ing; since I showed some reticence and was unable to grade my own exer
cises, he concluded in the form of an apology: "You know, I am saying
this about them most of all to show you that I now read you." Now, that
Where a Teaching Body Begim
is to say, now that I am no longer a candidate for the agregation, now that
the space of repetition in which you, repeater, had to reflect a code and a
program before me, so that I could reflect them in turn, no longer risks
(he believed) becoming distorted.
By program I do not mean only the program that, every spring, rather ar
bitrarily (at any rate, according to motivations that are never explained and
about which no one can demand any justification) picks out an individual
subject (for example, the president of a jury), himself selected by a ministe
rial decision from the teaching body of which he is a member. Neither the
teaching body nor, a fortiori, the body of candidates can take any initiative
for this private selection; and the mystery of the ministerial decision is re
produced ill the mystery of co-optation. The place of this mystery, at any
rate, can be clearly located: it is one of the points where a nonphilosophical
and nonpedagogic power intervenes to determine who (and what) will de
termine, in a decisive and absolutely authoritarian fashion, the program
and the filtering and coding mechanisms of all teaching. Given the central
ist and military structure of French National Education, one can see what
troop movements are set loose in the university and in publishing (there the
connecting mechanisms are a bit more complex, but quite dose) by the
program planner's slightest quiver. From the moment it inherits such power
from the ministry, without any consultation with the teaching body as
such, the jury or more generally the control mechanism can put on a show
of liberty or liberalism. (Even if it is elected, it is most often only partially
so, and it in fact takes into account the results of competitive examinations
assessed by an appointed jury.) It is, in fact, subject, whether directly or not,
to ideological or political constraint, the real program of power. And there
fore, it necessarily tends to reproduce that program in essence, reproducing
the conditions in which it is exercised and warding off everything that
comes to remove that order.
Under the name of program, then, I target not only the program that
appears to fall from the sky every year, but a powerful machine with com
plex works. It is made up of networks of tradition or repetition, which no
doubt function according to a particular historical or ideological configu
ration, and which have perpetuated themselves since the beginnings of
sophistry and philosophy. And not only as a sort of fundamental and con
tinuous structure that would support singular phenomena or episodes. In
fact, this profound machine, this fundamental program, is reinvested, re
informed, and reemployed in its totality by each specific configuration.
Where a Teaching Body Begins 79
One of the difficulties in analyzing it stems from the fact that deconstruc
tion must not, cannot only, choose between long or barely mobile net
works and short and quickly outdated ones, but must display the strange
logic by which, in philosophy at least, the multiple powers of the oldest
machine can always be reinvested and exploited in a new situation. That is
a difficulty, but it is also what makes a quasi-systematic deconstruction pos
sible by protecting it against any empiricist light-headedness. These pow
ers are not only logical, rhetorical, and didactic schemas. Nor are they even
essentially philosophemes. They are also sociocultural or institutional op
erators, scenes or trajectories of energy, clashes of force that use all sorts of
representatives. Consequently, when I say, in such a trivial formula, that
power controls the teaching apparatus, it is not to place power outside the
pedagogic scene. (Power is constituted inside pedagogy as an effect of this
scene itself, no matter what the political or ideological nature of the power
in place around it.) Nor is it to make us think or dream of a teaching with
out power, free from teaching's own power effects or liberated from all
power outside of or higher than itself That would be an idealist or liberal
ist representation, with which a teaching body blind to power-the power
it is subject to, the power at its disposal in the place where it denounces
power-effectively reinforces itsel
This power is rather tricky: ridding itself of its own power is not the
easiest thing for a teaching body to do, and the fact that doing so does not
completely depend on an "initiative" or "gesture," an "action" (for exam
ple, a political one, in the coded sense of the word), is perhaps inherent to
the structure of the teaching body I want to decompose here.
"Wherever teaching takes place, therefore-and in the philosophical par
excellence-there are, within that field, powers, representing forces in con
flict, dominant or dominated forces, conflicts and contradictions (what I
call effects ofdifferance). That is why work like that we are undertaking
(this is a banality whose experience shows us that we must incessantly be
reminded of it) implies a political commitment on the part of all those
who participate in it, whatever the complexity of the relays, alliances, and
strategic detours. (Our ''Avant-Projet"; is full of such detours, but it still
made some "liberals" flee.)
There could therefore never be one teaching body or one body of teach
ing (teaching/taught: we will broaden the syntax of this word, of the cor
pus taught to the body of disciples) : one homogeneous, self-identical body
suspending within it the oppositions (for example, the politics) that take
8o Where a Teaching Body Begins
One of the reasons for which I insist upon the function of the repeater
is that if the word now appears to be reserved for the Ecole Normale, with
the backward or old-fashioned air becoming to every self-respecting nobil
ity, the function remains active everywhere today. It is one of the most re
vealing and essential functions of the philosophical institution. I will read,
on this subject, a long paragraph from Canivez's thesis, "Jules Lagneau,
professeur et philosophe. Essai sur la condition du professeur de philoso
phie jusqu'a la fin du XJXe siecle,"6 one of the two or three works in France
that, to my knowledge, take up certain historical problems of the philo
sophical institution directly. Indispensable material is dealt with there, that
Where a Teaching Body Begins 8!
is also to say, read, selected, and evaluated according to the system of a phi
losophy, of a very specific ethic and ideology. We will study these here and
will attempt to identify them not only in this or that declared profession of
faith, but in the more hidden, subtle, and apparently secondary operations
that produce-or contribute powerfUlly to-the thetic effect of every dis
course; the latter, moreover, is a principal thesis for this doctorat d'Etat,
which militates for a sort of liberal spiritualism, one that is eclectic in its
liberalism, even if it sometimes condemns Cousin's eclecticism. But eclec
ticism does not exist, of course, at least never as an opening that allows
everything to pass through. & its name indicates, it always puts into prac
tice, whether openly or not, choice, filtering, selectivity, election, elitism,
and exclusion. The passage I am speaking of describes the teaching ofphi
losophy in the eighteenth century, in France: "It must not be forgotten that
instruction was accompanied by an education that was religious in inspira
tion. Pedagogical practice always lags behind mores, no doubt because
teaching is more retrospective than prospective" (82).
I interrupt my reading a moment for a first aside.
If "pedagogical practice always lags behind mores," a proposition that
perhaps neglects a certain heterogeneity in their relations, but which does
not appear, globally, very questionable, then the outdated structure of teach
ing can always be questioned as repetition. That does not make less neces
sary any other specific analysis but rather concerns a structural invariant in
teaching. It originates in the semiotic structure of teaching, the practically
semiotic interpretacion of the pedagogical relation: Teaching delivers signs.
The teaching body produces (shows and puts forward) signs or, more pre
cisely, signifiers supposing the knowledge of a prior signified. In relation to
this knowledge, the signifier is structurally second. Every university puts
language in this posicion of belatedness or derivation in relation to mean
ing or truth. That the signifier-or rather the signifier of signifiers-is now
placed in the transcendental posicion in relation to .the system changes noth
ing: the teaching structure of a language and the semiotic belatedness of a
didactics are reproduced insofar as they are given a second wind. Knowl
edge and power stay on the level of principles. The teaching body, as or
ganon of repetition, is as old as the sign and has the history of the sign. It
lives from belief (what, then, is belief in this case and on the basis of this sit
uation?) in the transcendental signified. It comes back to life, more and bet
ter than ever, with the authority of the signifier of signifiers, that of the
transcendental phallus, for example. Which amounts to remembering that
Where a Teaching Body Begim
Rollin, the famous Rollin, has no other goal than to make priests or monks,
poets or orators: that's what it's really about. . . . It's about giving the sovereign
zealous or faithful subjects; giving the empire useful citizens; society educated,
honest, and even amiable individuals; the family good husbands and fathers;
the republic arts and a few men of great taste; and religion edifYing, enlight
ened, and peaceful ministers. That is no small goal.8
At the time Diderot wrote this, the body of teachers of philosophy was
far &om being, seamlessly and homogeneously, the servile representation of
a politico-religious power itself wracked by contradictions. Already in the
seventeenth century, in the archives of the proceedings of the University of
Paris, one finds accusations against the independence of certain teachers,
for example, against those who intended to teach in French (a very impor
tant stake that we will have to consider again) . In 1 737 , Canivez recalls,
teachers were ordered to dictate their courses. That, by the way, is a rule
that is brought back more easily than it is established. Dictating was syn
onymous with teaching. "A regent could say he had 'dictated' for ten years
in a certain college." The "dictation" of the course repeated a fixed and
controlled content, but it was not confused with "repetition" in the narrow
Where a Teaching Body Begins
They passed imperceptibly from the reading and study of a text and its com
mentary to the dictated course and contact with the text became more distant.
A course was first the s ummary ofAristotle's or a scholastic's doctrine, accom
panied by a synopsis of his commentary; then became a copying out of the av
erage opinions concerning the content of the philosophical subjects handled
by the tradition. Nor until the nineteenth century did the programs set ques
tions to be learned, no longer authors to be studied.
From the old point ofview, that notebooks might have been personal work in
any way other than their organization would never have crossed the minds of
teachers and their superiors. They were concerned about the errors, awkward
nesses, and novelties the notebooks contained, arising from what was in the
air at that time, more than about any attempt to be original. The teacher was
the faithful transmitter of a tradition and not a laborer in a philosophy in the
making. Often the regents handed down notebooks that had already served
their predecessors or that they had composed in their first years of service, ne
glecting the recent contributions of science.9
Teaching methods are still suffering from the centuries when they were shaped
by ignorance. For the universities are far from having followed the progress of
the academies. While the new philosophy is beginning to be introduced in the
universities, it is having a lot of trouble gerting established, and even then it is
allowed to enter only on the condition that it put on the rags of scholasticism.
Institutions that were made for the advancement of the sciences can only be
applauded. But they would no doubt not have been formed if the universities
had been capable of fulfilling this goal. The vices of university studies there
fore seem to have been known; however, remedies were not brought about. It
is not enough to mak good institutions: the bad ones must be destroyed or
reformed according to the program of the good ones, even according to a bet
ter one, if possible. 10
little made to correct themselves. Can one presume that the professors will give
up what they believe they know in order to learn what they ate ignorant of?
Will they admit that their lessons teach nothing, or teach only things of no use?
No. But like schoolchildren, they will continue to go to school to carry out a
task. It is enough for them that it gives them something to live on, just as it is
enough for their students that this eats up their childhood and youth. The es
teem enjoyed by the academies is a thorn in their side. What is more, the mem
bers of the academies, who ate free and independent, ate not obliged to follow
blindly the maxims and prejudices of their body. If the old are attached to old
opinions, the young are ambitious to think better; and it is always they who
make the revolutions most beneficial for the progress of the sciences in the
academies. The universiti have lost much of their esteem; emulation is being
lost every day. A good professor is disgusted when he sees himself get mixed up
with pedants disdained by the public and when, seeing what he would have to
do to distinguish himself, he finds that it would be imprudent to attempt to do
so. He would not dare to change entirely the whole scheme of studies, and if
he wants to hazard only a few light changes, he is obliged to take the greatest
precautions. If the universities have these flaws, what will be the case in schools
run by religious orders, that is, by bodies that have a way of thinking to which
all the members are obliged to submit? (235-36; my emphasis)
I have not cited this long text to play with its currentness, nor merely to
note all the lines of cleavage that always, and always in a specific fashion,
divide a field of incessant struggle concerning the philosophical institution.
But to anticipate a little, Condillac opposes one institution to another, an
other institutional place (the academies), and he does so in the name of a
philosophy that will massively inspire the pedagogico-philosophical pro
jects of both the Revolution and the post-Revolution. (We will see the
properly revolutionary episode reduced to almost nothing.) It will therefore
be a matter of a central, visible, or dissimulated stake, the entire politico
pedagogical history from the nineteenth century to the present. We will
begin to analyze it shortly. Seemingly revolutionary or progressivist in re
gard to a certain teaching body, Condillac's discourse already represents an
other teaching body beingformed, an (ideological) ideology poised to be
come dominant, as the saying goes, itself destined to ambiguous reversals,
to a whole complex and differentiated history, playing at once the role of
the breaks and the motor for philosophical critique. In its most formal
characteristics, this schema is also current.
To retain but one sign of this ambiguity today, let us not forget that this
critique, while supporting the progress of modern academies, belongs to
86 Where a Teaching Body Begim
To the fundamental exercise that is the course was added, first of all , repeti
tion. Solitary study was avoided. The teacher, the repeater, or a good student,
the decurion [or prefect], took up the course with the listener, corrected his
mistakes, explained the difficult passages to him. It was a time of personal ex
change between them and was particularly fruitful when his virtue was safe
guarded and he did not turn to learning by rote or to a disciplinary interroga
tion. It is one of the exercises that is most lacking in current teaching.
There will be no fixed political State if there is no teaching body with fixed
principles . . . . A teaching body would exist if all the headmasters, censors,
and teachers in the Empire had one or several leaders, as the Jesuits had a su
perior and provincials . . . . Were it considered important that civil servants
and lycee teachers not be married, this could be achieved easily and quickly. . . .
All disadvantages could be prevented by making a law of celibacy for all mem
bers of the teaching body, except for teachers in special schools and lycees and
inspectors. In these places marriage presents no disadvantage. But the direc
tors and teachers in the colleges could not get married without giving up their
positions . . . . While not bound by vows, the teaching body would be no less
religious. (Imtrnctiom a Fourcroy)
In addition to what I have just recalled, this place transforms and dislo
cates itsel That the majority of you do not belong to the Ecole Normale
Superieure and even, if I am not mistaken, claim to be relatively little at
tached to it (let's content ourselves with this euphemism) is a first sign of
that, one visible here, then, in a cinema or theater hall barely transformed
into a seminar room. Here in the Ecole Normale Superieure, which trans
forms itself by resisting its own transformation, here in the place where I,
Where a Teaching Body Begins
this teaching body that I call mine, a very specific topos in the body sup
posed to teach philosophy in France today, I teach.
I say that I am only going to make proposals, which will always be sub
mitted to discussion, that I am going to pose questions, for example, the
question that, apparendy via my own initiative, I have put on the pro
gram today, that is: "What is a teaching body?"
Of course, anyone can interrupt me, pose their "own" questions, dis
place or cancel mine. I even ask that they do so, with a barely feigned sin
cerity. But everything seems organized, does it not, so that I keep the ini
tiative that I have taken or that I had given to me, that I could only take
by submitting to a certain number of complex and systematic normative
demands of a teaching body authorized, by the goven1ment, to confer
the tide, right, and means of this initiative. In reality the contract to
which I am referring is still more complicated, but it also demands that I
be brief.
When I say I pose questions, I pretend to say nothing that would be a
thesis. I pretend to pose or posit something that at bottom would not pose
or posit itsel 12 Since the question is not, it is believed, a thesis, it would
not pose, impose, or suppose anything. This alleged neutrality; th non
thetic appearance of a question that is posed without even seeming to pose
itself, is what constructs the teaching body.
Of course, even in the barest, most formal, most questioning form itself
(What is? Who? What? : we will identifY in them, next time, the recourse
of recourses for institutional erection and counter-erection) there is no
question that is not constrained by a program, informed by a system of
forces, and invested with a battery of determining, selecting, sifting forms.
The question is always posed (determined) by someone who, at a given
moment, in a language, a place, etc., represents a program and a strategy
(which is by definition inaccessible to individual and conscious, repre
sentable control).
Every time the teaching of philosophy is "threatened" in this country,
its traditional "defenders" warn, in order to convince or dissuade, while
reassuring: careful, it is the possibility of a pure questioning, a free, neu
tral, objective, etc., questioning, that you are going to put into question.
Where a Teaching Body Begim
My body is glorious. It gathers all the light. First of all, that of the spot
light above me. Then it.is radiant and attracts all eyes. But it is also glori
ous in that it is no longer simply a body. It is sublimated in the represen
tation of at least one other body, the teaching body of which it should be
at once a part and the whole, a member letting the gathering together of
the body be seen; a body that in turn produces itself by erasing itself as the
barely visible, entirely transparent, representation of both the philosophi
cal and the sociopolitical corpus, the contract between these bodies never
being brought to the foreground.
Benefit is derived, always, from this glorious erasure, from the glory of
this erasure. It remains to be known by what, by whom, in view of what.
Accounting for it is always more difficult than one believes, given the er
ratic character of a certain remainder. The same goes for all the supple
mentary benefits derived from the very articulation of these calculations,
for example, here, today, by he who says: "1-but who?-represent a teach
ing body."
His body becomes teaching when, the place of convergence and fasci
nation, it becomes more than a center.
More than a center: a center, a body in the center of a space, is exposed
on all sides. On the one hand, it bares its back, lets itself be seen by what it
does not see. On the other hand, the excentricity of the teaching body, in
traditional topology, permits at once the synoptic surveillance that with its
glance covers the field of the body taught-every patt of which is indistin
guishable and always surrounded-and the withdrawal, the reserve, of the
body that does not surrender, offering itself from only one side to the glance
that it nonetheless mobilizes with its entire surface. That is well known.
Let's not insist. The body becomes teaching and exercises what we will call,
even if it means complicating things later, its mastery and magistrality only
Where a Teaching Body Begim 9I
by playing upon a stratified erasUie: in front of (or behind) the global teach
ing body, in front of (or behind) the corpus taught (here in the sense of
philosophical corpus) , in front of (or behind) the sociopolitical body.
Avant-Projet:
For the Founding of a Research Group
on the Teaching of Philosophy
Preliminary work has made dear that it is now possible and necessary to
organize a set of research investigations into what relates philosophy to its
teaching. This research, which should have both a critical and a practical
bearing, would attempt initially to respond to certain questions. We de
fine these questions here, under the rubric of a rough anticipation, with
reference to common notions, which are to be discussed. Greph would be,
first of all and at least, a place that would make possible the coherent, last
ing, and relevant organization of such a discussion.
How does it inscribe itselfthere, that is, how does it operate and repre
sent-(to) itself-its inscription, and how is it imcribed in its very repre-
94 Where a Teaching Body Begins
sentation? What are the "general logic" and specific modes of this inscrip
tion? Of its normalizing normativity and of its normalized normativity?
For example, at the same time as they prescribe a pedagogy indissociable
from a philosophy, the academy, the lycee, the Sorbonne, preceptorates of
every kind, universities, or royal, imperial, or republican schools of mod
ern times also prescribe, in specific and differentiated ways, a moral and
political system that forms at once both the object and the actualized
structure of pedagogy. What about this pedagogical effect? How is one to
de-limit it, theoretically and practically?
Once again, these indicative questions remain too general. They are
above all formulated, by design, according to current representations and
therefore must be specified, differentiated, criticized, and transformed. They
could in fact lead one to believe that essentially, indeed uniquely, it is a mat
ter of constructing a sort of "critical theory of philosophical doctrinality or
disciplinarity," of reproducing the traditional debate that philosophy has
regularly opened about its "crisis." This "reproduction'' will itself be one of
the objects of our work. In fact, Greph should above all participate in the
transformative analytics of a "present" situation, questioning and analyzing
itself in this analytics and displacing itself from the position ofwhat, in this
"situation," makes it possible and necessary. The previous questions should
therefore be constantly reworked via these practical motivations. Also, with
out ever excluding the importance of these problems outside of France, we
would first of all insist strongly on the conditions of the teaching of philos
ophy "here-and-now," in today's France. And in its concrete urgency, in the
more or less dissimulated violence of its contradictions, the "here-and-now"
would no longer simply be a philosophical object. This is not a restriction
of the program, but the condition of Greph's work on its own field of prac
tice and in relation to the following questions:
r. What are the past and present historical conditions of this teaching
system?
What about its power? What forces give it this power? What forces limit
it? What about its legislation, its juridical and traditional code? Its external
and internal norms? Its social and political field? Its relation to other (his
torical, literary, aesthetic, religious, or scientific, for example) kinds of teach
ing? To other institutionalized discursive practices (psychoanalysis in gen
eral and so-called training analysis in particular-for example, etc.)? From
Where a Teaching Body Begim 95
2. What are the stakes of the struggles within and around philosophical
education, today, in France?
(a) these stands would be declared and debated from the position of
real informative and critical work;
Where a Teaching Body Begins
among all the participants and all those who ask for them. Then, at least
partially and according to modalities to be provided for, by way of publi
cation (whether collective or individual, signed or not).
For this reason, it is desirable that, whatever the object (formally elab
orated research, global or fragmentary documentation, bibliographic or
factual information, questions, critiques, diverse proposals), communica
tions within Greph take, whenever possible, a written (preferably typed)
and easily reproducible form. As of now (until the election, at the begin
ning of the university year, of a secretaryship) they can be addressed to the
provisional administrative office of Greph, c/o J. Derrida, 45, rue d'Ulm,
7 5005 Paris.
(This Avant-Projet was approved unanimously at the preparatory meet
ing of r6 April 1974.)
(During its first General Assembly; Greph defined its modes of opera
tion (statutes). Here are some excerpts:
From this date on, Greph will form work and action groups, in Paris and
in the provinces. It will define positions and engage in coordinated con
flicts. All the available informacion on this subject is gathered in an inter
nal bulletin addressed to whomever requests it from the administrative of
fice. Until the month of October 1975, the date on which new statutes16
will be proposed in view of a larger and more effective decentralization (the
creation of autonomous and united groups wherever possible; the defini
tion of a new phase of work and of a new phase of conflict, and so forth),
requests for information or memberships, as well as all correspondence,
should be addressed to the provisional address of the administrative office:
45, rue d'Ulrn, 75005 Paris.)
The Crisis in the Teaching of Philosophy
99
IOO The Crisis in Teaching
would always have been lived by questioning itself about its own resources,
its own possibility, in the critical instance of judging or deciding [krinein]
on its own meaning, like its survival, and of evaluating itself, of posing it
self the question of its rights and legitimacy. From that moment, the move
ment of self-critique, if it can be put this way, would belong to what is
most proper in the philosophical as such. Philosophy would repeat itself
and would reproduce its own tradition as the teaching of its own crisis and
as the paideia of self-critique in general. This paideia always goes hand in
hand, and there is nothing fortuitous about this, with what I will call,
without taking it lightly, an imperialist self-confidence of philosophy. Phi
losophy is an ontology and its paideia an encyclopedia. It has the right to
define and situate all the regions of beings or objectivity. It has no particu
lar object proper because it legislates on objectivity in general. It dominates,
in a precisely critical fashion, all the so-called regional sciences, assigning
them their limits and legitimacy. Dominating the field of the so-called re
gional disciplines and sciences, cultivating it and marking its property lines,
the philosophical onto-encyclopedia is at home everywhere, and its self
critical movement is merely the reproduction of its own authority.
This schema is well known. Excuse me for recalling it here. To be in
troduced to philosophy, to teach philosophy, is often to authenticate this
schema. Without disqualifying it as such, without even having the means
or the time to discuss it here, I will designate it as an alibi. Why an alibi?
Because we have ceased to live simply in the place where such a crisis was
destined to reproduce itself. We have not simply left it-and that is why
the schema of this repetition did not, all of a sudden, cease to require us
but we have exceeded it in a way; rather, we are exceeded insofar as we
would have identified ourselveS in this place. For what we today, making
use of an old language, call the "crisis of philosophy'' already takes part in
a completely different historical necessity: where what comes into "crisis"
is this very perpetuation of the philosophical as .self-critical freedom and
(they are the same thing) as onto-encyclopedic project bound to the uni
versitas, as self-repetition through the language of krinein, through the pos
sibility of decision, according to a logic of the decidable, in other words, of
opposition, whether dialectical or not, whether an idealist or materialist di
alectics. The era of deconstruction-and in making use of this word for the
sake of economy I name neither a method (even if critical, for deconstruc
tion is not simply a critique), a technique, nor even a discourse, whether
philosophical, metaphilosophical, or scientific-would be the era in which,
102 The Crisis in Teaching
is no choice, and the choice that does not exist is not between one language
and another, one group of languages and another (with everything a lan
guage entails) . Every monolingualism and monologism restores mastery or
magistrality. It is by treating each language differently, by grafting languages
onto one another, by playing on the multiplicity of languages and on the
multiplicity of codes within every linguistic corpus that we can struggle at
once against colonization in general, against the colonizing principle in gen
eral (and you know that it exerts itself well beyond the zones said to be sub
jected to colonization), against the domination of language or domination
by language. The underlying hypothesis of this statement is that the unity
of language is always a vested and manipulated simulacrum. There are al
ways languages in language and the structural rigor of the system of lan
guage is at once a positivist dogma of linguistics and a phenomenon that
can be found nowhere. I have attempted to show this elsewhere. All of this
is not without political consequences; better, it is a political theme, through
and through.
It also traverses the space that relates philosophy to the sciences. On this
subject, too, I will have to limit myself to the rough statement of a propo
sition. This proposition concerns a kind of double bind, a contradictory
double postulate, two incompatible and simultaneous demands. Let us
begin with the fact that, if every philosophical language retains in itself an
irreducible connection to a so-called natural (or mother) language, with
scientific language tending, on the contrary, toward a growing formaliza
tion, then this polarity organizes and dynamizes a kind of strange front.
The growing autonomization of the sciences and of the techno-scientific,
the indissociably techno-scientific powers tends, through formalization
and, above all, axiomatic self-jurisdiction, to avoid the reappropriation of
epistemological instances by all sciences, etc., the authority of the philo
sophical as the science of sciences, general ontology or absolute logic,
onto-encyclopedia. In this way, the sciences at - the same time enable a
more effective resistance to the monologic political power that is exerted
through philosophy and that its national or continental forces can exert.
This power is not only exerted through the entire "ideology" (I use this
word out of convenience, conscious that it still belongs to what is to be
deconstructed here) of a kind of philosophical centralism, of a court of
final appeal, and of onto-encyclopedic hegemony; it is also exerted, indis
sociably, from what connects this hegemonic project to a language or fam
ily of European natural languages. To this extent, every formalizing move-
I06 The Crisis in Teaching
ment (and they always already exist in philosophical language itself, just as
there is always still linguistic "naturalness" in scientific languages) devel
ops means to resist onto-encyclopedic hegemony, that is also to say, let us
not forget, to resist the state structure and even the concept of the State,
which we could show is indissociable, in its history and architecture, from
this philosophical hegemony.
But inversely-and this is why I spoke of a double bind and a strange
front-the development of the sciences can entail risks against which philo
sophical critique, in its classic form or in a form more appropriate for de
tecting the dogmatic philosophemes implicated by so-called scientific dis
course, can still be indispnsably effective. The development of the sciences
in itself does not, of course, produce these risks, but what is this self, this
in-itself? As for the physico-mathematical sciences, techno-economic in
vestment allows itself less and less to be dissociated from the scientific pro
cess "itsel" What we call the politics ofscience is in this respect no longer a
secondary discipline, and there is no development of the sciences that does
not immediately put it in play, whether we are conscious of this or not. It
is there that a critical vigilance finds a way to exert itself, and it implements
instruments of analysis, forms of questioning, problematic schemas that
derive from philosophical critique and that assume an expert knowledge of
the history of philosophy, as history and combinatory of conceptual possi
bilities. A State that does not intend to let its scientific policy be held
hostage by forces that it is fighting against and that can make gains on the
terrain of dogmatism or prescientific obscurantism must train philosophers
and extend the field of philosophical analysis in its education programs.
This philosophical critique sometimes turns its vigilance against the State
itself, whether in the form of state rationality as such or specific and par
ticular forces that have for a time appropriated the power of the State.
Hence the trickiness of the problem, of the theoretical problem, and of the
strategic problem. It is always difficult to know where the State is.
What I just said about the physico-mathematical sciences holds a for
tiori for the so-called human sciences, taken one by one or as a group. They
offer a privileged ground for ideological investments of the most ingenu
ous kind, ones that at the same time are the most massively manipulable
by (politico-economic or other) forces or interests. The precritical, the pre
philosophical, indeed, the prescientific or preepistemological lies in wait
for the human sciences as for an easy and precious prey. What here takes
the form of knottiness, and what gives the knot the structure, once again, of
The Crisis in Teaching
a double bind is that the precritical that holds back or delays the so-called
human sciences is often of a philosophical nature: often residues of old
philosophemes that are not recognized as such come, more or less coher
ently, to predetermine the discourse of said sciences. And, of course, the
place of the State-which can also be the place of the specific forces it rep
resents at a given moment-is all the more difficult to pinpoint when it is
necessary to develop at once the sciences and their critical instruments,
philosophy and the instruments of a philosophical deconstruction.
To respond to the urgency of such a demand, we must no doubt deny
ourselves a second alibi. It relates, precisely, to the question of the State.
And it also takes, at first sight, the form of ahistorical generality. Philoso
phy has always been, in essence, linked to its teaching, or at least to a
paideia that at a given moment in history was able to become " teaching,"
in the strict sense that links educative practice to a certain concept or insti
tution of the sign. In any case, philosophy has never been conceived or ex
perienced without this dialectico-pedagogical relation that we today call
"teaching." It follows, for the reasons I evoked a moment ago, that the per
manent, founding, instituting crisis of philosophy will always have been si
multaneously a crisis of the pedagogical. But if we want to situate what
takes placefor us,today, we must no doubt rerurn from the fluctuating gen
erality of this schema to astricter historico-geographical, political, and, in
general, epochal determinacion. Let's put it this way: in Europe, the struc
tures of the teaching of philosophy are now being nationalized directly or
indirectly. I cannot undertake here the analysis of this process, which dates
back to the first half of the nineteenth century. I am simply remarking that
it is not by chance that it is contemporary with great colonial enterprises of
a new type and that, as far as the French example is concerned, the colonial
imposition of pedagogical models set up, at least to some extent (the ped
agogy of the Missions that stemmed from prerevolutionary and prestate
models is another maner) , the state structures being established in France.
Consequently, the specificity of the crises in the teaching of philosophy
will always be closely related to this phenomenon of nationalization, either
in European States, whatever their narure, or in African States, whether the
strucrures of their nationalization (notably, as concerns school and univer
sity mechanisms) remain analogous to European models, deviate from
them, or are opposed to them. How the process of nationalization comes
to regulate the relations between philosophy and its teaching, between the
teaching of philosophy and the teaching of the sciences, of the so-called
I08 The Crisis in Teaching
human sciences and the others, between its "politics-of-science" and its
"politics-of-philosophy," and so forth, is a consequence of the question
whose necessity, it seems to me, cannot be reduced by asking ourselves
about the crisis in the teaching of philosophy. To this degree of great gen
erality, this question seems to me just as valid for "Europe" as for ''Africa,"
proper names I put between quotation marks for the moment for the rea
sons I mentioned a moment ago. No more so than the unity of (European
or Mrican) philosophy do I believe we can trust today the unity of the
"properly European" or "properly African" in general. The crisis of the cri
sis lies there. And if the critique of "ethnophilosophy'' seems to me just as
legitimate for Europe as. for Africa (and truthfully speaking, it reflects a
project of reappropriation, as well as a value of the proper shared by every
philosophy as such), I believe that the radicalization of this critique is nec
essary. It therefore cannot leave intact any criterion of essential unification
or identification, especially not the geographical.
If, therefore, said crisis in the teaching of philosophy always has a pro
found relation with the paths of nationalization, its forms will vary from
one state entity to another, even if this entity is a recent, unstable, or pro
visional formation.
Clearly, then, I will not speak to you about the crisis in the teaching of
philosophy in Africa itself, first of all because I would have nothing to tell
you about it. Considering the generalities I have just mentioned, I doubt
that the "crisis" in Mrica has a unity, even unity as a crisis, unless it is
linked to the crisis of African unity, which is something else again. More
over, I have neither the means nor the pretense to teach you anything at all
about the diversity of Mrican situations. And finally, the scene of a Euro
pean or even a Euro-Mrican coming to diagnose a crisis of Mrican teach
ing before African philosophers, researchers, and teachers seems unbear
ably laughable.
I will therefore speak to you about something of a completely different
sort. If I bring you only a limited testimony of my experience of said cri
sis in France, it will certainly not be to proceed to export a "model" of cri
sis or of response to a "critical" situation. I will nonetheless select, in this
briefpresentation, a few characteristics of the French situation whose anal
ysis and discussion, it seems to me, because of a certain network of analo
gies that I will form by hypothesis, will broaden out to a certain extent be
yond France.
Let's consider, first, the spectacular sign of a crisis by nature older and
The Crisis in Teaching
easier, on new ground, at any rate. But we did not delude ourselves: we
would have to continue to fight to avoid the same interpretation, imposed
by the constraints of the market, both domestic and global, to avoid falling
in line with the education systems of other industrial countries (notably
European ones, in the framework of the so-called unity of Europe), to
avoid, then, the same interpretation and the same politics imposing them
selves under the authority of the "left." These moderate fears were, as we
have known for a few months now, still optimistic. 3
2. Another motivation (this one not admitted) of the Haby Reform: the
destruction of the "philosophy class" should stop masses of high school
students from exercising philosophical and political critique. Historical
critique as well: since the nineteenth century, every time the philosophy
class has been threatened in France, the teaching of history has equally
been a target, for analogous political reasons. The philosophy class was the
only place in which one had the chance to take up theoretical moder
nity-elements of Marxism and psychoanalysis, for example. Never be
fore, never after, for those who did not specialize in these directions-and
who therefore risked being all the fewer in doing so, since they were not
introduced to them before their university studies. Moreover, after '68 all
the signs of a repressive surveillance against the Terminale, certain of its
students, and certain of its teachers were multiplied.
3 When philosophical education was stifled from the lycee on, an ideol
ogy and, in the end, implicit but very particular philosophical contents that
had insinuated themselves, necessarily, through other teachings were al
lowed to take hold without critique. These other teachings are above all
(not uniquely, but above all) "literary" teachings (language and literature,
French and foreign), but also, and this is the point I want to emphasize, the
teaching of what are called the "human sciences"-notably the economic
and social sciences-which people were simultaneously trying to develop
in the lycees. In principle, there is nothing to reproach in such teachings,
on the condition that they be given in a critical fashion, that they not
be, directly or indirectly, ideological and/or techno-economic imperatives.
Everything in the effective and concrete conditions of these teachings, how
ever, leaves one to fear that these so-called human, economic, and social
"sciences" are the object of uncritical discourses, ones crammed with very
particular ideological contents. And thus also a certain implicit philosophy,
The Crisis in Teaching III
for the front here does not form between philosophy and nonphilosophy,
but between specific philosophical practices and contents. The Haby Re
form does not represent an antiphilosophy, but rather certain forces linked
to a certain philosophical configuration, which, in a historico-policical sit
uation, have an interest in favoring this or that institutional structure.
Although it was not formed in response to the project of the Haby Re
form, although its ''Avant-Projet" (a few passages of which I will be able to
read in the course of the discussion) predates that reform, Greph has spread
considerably throughout France and has made better known its positions,
its program of research and action, in the context of the urgency created by
the government plan. Rather than lay out the entire argument that Greph
has attempted to advance for several years, it seems to me preferable to de
fine the singular posicion it took faced with the Haby Reform, precisely at
a time when the "crisis" appeared the most urgent and spectacular. For my
part, this posicion seems relatively revealing regarding our whole problem
atic. Greph opposed simultaneously the forces represented by the govern
ment's posicion-and thus the politics whose aim was the disappearance of
the teaching of philosophy-and the forces that seemed to want to defend,
in a conservative fashion, the status quo and the Terminale class as it was.
In fact, these two apparently antagonistic positions would lead, given the
real state of teaching in these Terminales and the general politics of educa
tion, to the same consequence: the progressive asphyxia of all teaching of
philosophy. The particularity of Greph consisted in demanding not only
that philosophy continue to be taught, and not as an option, in the Terrni
nale, but that it be given the right accorded to every other discipline, that
is, a progressive and "long" teaching from the "youngest" classes on. That
naturally supposed a general reelaboracion of its contents, methods, inter
disciplinary relations, and so forth. This reelaboracion concerns the groups
that have been formed within Greph and that bring together lycee and uni
versity instructors and students. Naturally, Greph is not only a group for
theoretical research. It is also a movement that intends to intervene in the
institution, according to specific political modes that are not those of either
political parties or unions (our independence in this regard is precious and
absolute, even if some of us belong to political and union organizations) ,
nor those of a professional and corporate organization. I could, if you wish,
give you more specifics on the texts and arguments concerning what we
first called the "progressivity'' of this teaching of philosophy. The target of
what was at that time, and remains, our slogan is the politico-sexual dead-
II2 The Crisis in Teaching
bolt that reserved the access to the teaching of philosophy for seventeen- or
eighteen-year-old men, most often belonging to a certain social class and
coming to philosophy once the other teachings (notably those of the "hu
manities" and of the so-called "human'' sciences) had played their role of
ideological impregnation. Therefore, rather than taking up again our entire
argument on this subject (and, one can quickly see, it concerns the whole
philosophical tradition and its teaching, since what is at stake in age is a
kind of general sign) , rather than telling you about the struggles and exper
imentations underway around this slogan, it seems preferable to me here to
insist upon the reasons why we very quickly abandoned the word "progres
sivity'' and have replaced .it with "extension." It appears to me preferable to
insist upon that because it concerns precisely the role of the State in this cri
sis, no matter which forces claim to serve this State or upon which it claims
it relies, even if they are "progressivist" or "left-wing" forces. What is at is
sue here?
Very quickly, and within Greph itself, a certain equivocation came to
light, one linked to the word, if not the thing, called the "progressivity'' of
the teaching of philosophy. We wondered if spreading the teaching of phi
losophy over a number ofyears would not risk leading to its dispersion and
empiricist disarticulation; or reiterating traditional teaching by weakening
it, by making it more accessible to ideological misappropriations or to its
dissolution in nonphilosophical disciplines; or spreading the philosophical
imperium, indeed, in this or that political situation, the hegemony of this
or that philosophy surreptitiously become the official philosophy, the phi
losophy of the State, given as a dogma throughout students' schooling. In
this case, the slogan of progressivity would reproduce and even worsen a
situation that we wanted, on the contrary, to transform ftom top to bot
tom. To this objection, which we took seriously and which in fact had im
mediately been considered within Greph, our response was principally the
following. No doubt, the value of progressivity derives ftom the most tra
ditional pedagogy. We should neither greet it as something new nor, above
all, "fetishize" it. But in a specific phase of the struggle, it was strategically
opportune to demand for the teaching of philosophy the respect of tradi
tional norms that made it legitimate for other disciplines to benefit from a
long and "progressive" teaching. Once a legitimate and "natural" extension
was acquired, other debates could be developed more easily about the con
tents and forms of the teachings, their articulations, and the communica
tions between them and with the outside of the academy. Greph's propos-
The Crisis in Teaching Il3
Since this time, Greph has multiplied its activities and work groups, ex
tended the scope of its first slogans, in particular with regard to what we
now call the necessary "delocalization" of the teaching body: mobility, de
hierarchization, the circulation of teachers in accordance with new "train
ing" methods. We will be able, if you wish, to return to this during the
discussion. What I would simply like to situate, or at least name, if not
analyze, before concluding, are the kinds of difficulty Greph encounters in
its theoretical work and militant activity. Perhaps this typology is not, in
its generality, limited to the French scene. The law of this typology is the
necessity and sometimes the impossibility of fighting on two fronts, while
demultiplying the scope and rhythms of this struggle.
r. On the one hand, we believe we must maintain the unity of the disci
pline of philosophy against all the seductive tropisms of the human sciences
(psychoanalysis, sociology, political economics, ethnology, linguistics, lit-
II 4 The Crisis in Teaching
erary semiotics, and so forth), and through this unity maintain the critical
force of philosophy and philosophical epistemologies. Instructors in grow
ing numbers would have a tendency to give way to these tropisms and thus
to limit the training of students, their training in critical vigilance faced
with all the ideological contents, dogmatisms, or precritical philosophemes
that constantly lie in wait for the discourse of the social sciences.
But on the other hand, we do not want to accept what is reactive, indeed
sometimes obscurantist, in this slogan ("the unity and specificity of the dis
cipline"). It is often put forward by the most legitimate, or, at any rate, the
most official, representatives of the institution. We are therefore fighting to
maintain concern for the specificity of philosophy; up to a certain point, in
the face of a pseudo-scientific, and in fact feebly philosophical dispersion,
but also, at the same time, to extend the field of scientificity in teaching,
even if it might appear to threaten what certain philosophers represent as
the untouchable unity of their discipline. This contradiction or law of the
double bind, whose fate I name dryly here, can, as you know, have very
concrete effects in our practice. To treat it thoroughly; one would obviously
have to deploy a long and powerfUl discourse on the scientific and the
philosophical, on a "crisis" that no doubt exceeds what Husserl wanted to
evoke under the title of The
Crisis ofEuropean Sciences or The Crisis ofEu
ropean Humanity and Philosophy.5
2. In its relations to the State, to everything the State attempts to pro
gram in the teaching of philosophy and its relations to scientific teachings
and practices, to all the modes of training and reproduction by which the
State finalizes the education system, Greph attempts to be as independent,
the master of its critiques, its problematic, its grounds for action, as it is
in relation to the dominant code of the political, to political parties, union
organizations, and corporative associations. Far from being a factor of de
politicization, this (relative) freedom and distance without detachment
should allow us to repoliticize things, to transform the dominant political
code, and to open to politicization zones of questioning that eluded it for
reasons that are always interested and interesting. We do not seek, in the
first place, to take up this freedom in relation to a State in general, to the
State in itself, but, as precisely as possible, in relation to the specific forces
that, dominating the powers of the State at a given moment, dictate-for
example-its politics of science and philosophy.
Moreover, inversely, our relation to the State is neither simple nor ho
mogeneous. A certain state rationality seems to us to have been granted to
The Crisis in Teaching Il5
the unity of the philosophical. We do not want to abandon that purely and
simply, but to represent the most powerful means of srruggling against the
class forces or interests (for example) that would profit from empiricism or
political anarchism. To be sure. Nonetheless, in its most complete form,
state-philosophical rationality (whether we think it in a right- or left-wing
Hegelian, Marxist or non-Marxist, etc., fashion) must also remain within
reach of (theoretical) questioning or (practical) putting into question.
J. We try not to conceal all the contradictions rraversing the reflection
and practice of Greph and we believe they are significant. In their most for
malized generality, they perhaps all amount to the necessity of renouncing
neither a deconstrnction (of the philosophical, of what links the philosoph
ical to the State, teaching, the sciences, etc.), nor a philosophicalcritique in
the most rigorous and effective form in its tradition, today, here, now. Re
nouncing neither deconstruction nor critique, Greph is split, differenti
ated, divided according to place, individuals, urgencies, situations. In a way,
it has no status [statut] , no place, and no fixed form. It has indeed had pro
visional statutes [statttts] , but the history of these statutes shows nicely that
it never could and never wanted to give itself one status [statut] . It is for the
moment, as far as the contradiction I just named is concerned, a rather
vague place in which, over the last four years, a minimal consensus for a
relatively common practice and, above all, for as vigilant and liberal a de
bate as possible has been renewed.
As vigilant and liberal a debate as possible was also the promise of this
conference. And that is what encouraged me to bring you-like a greet
ing-this testimony and to speak to you about this place or from this
place called Greph . About which I forgot to specify that, as French as it
appears, and as confined as it is for the moment within France's borders,
ever since its ''Avant-Projet" it has indicated that it did not intend to "ex
clude the scope of these problems outside of France."6 In fact, more than
one work group has rried to consider non-French or non-European prob
lematics and situations, sometimes by working with fellow members of
Greph who are not French. They are quite numerous in Europe, North
and South America, and especially in Africa, where analogous problems
are experienced, which is in no way fortuitous for francophone Africa.
I could try to extend and argue this very limited testimony, if you wish,
during our discussions. But I wanted above all to insist on this fact: what
I have related or analyzed contained no message. What I have related was
not a report on the state of philosophy, the teaching of philosophy and of
n6 The Crisis in Teaching
IIJ
n8 The Age ofHegel
Do you believe that, at the age of eighteen or nineteen, when one has entirely
completed one's humanities and rhetoric [premises that Greph has now de
nounced] , when one is studying physics and mathematics, one is incapable of
understanding the simple and solid proofs proceeding from the great natural
truths! The more necessary these truths are for the moral life of man, the more
God wanted them to be available to human reason. He has engraved them in
the mind and in the soul with luminous characters, which a skilled teacher
[maitre] must endeavor to reveal rather than obscuring them beneath the hi
eroglyphs of ambitious science. (Ibid.)
Along stages that are always idiomatic, we are guided back to the most
durable tradition of the philosophical concept of teaching: revelation, un
veiling, the discovered truth of the "already-there" [deja Ia] according to the
mode of "not-yet" [pas encore] , a Socrato-Platonic anamnesis sometimes
taken up by a neo-Heideggerian philosophy of psychoanalysis. Through-
122 The Age ofHegel
out these specific determinations may be found, time and again, the same
scheme, the same concept of truth, of the truth of truth linked to the same
pedagogical structure. But the interpretation of these specificities must not
succumb to this determination, as though one had no higher aim than to
uncover the same beneath all variations. One should never settle for this
but also never forget to take the power of the same into account. In the age
of Cousin (which is still ours as well), the question at issue is always, as it
was for Plato, one of a double metaphoric of inscription: a bad writing [une
mauvaise icriture] , secondary, artificial, cryptic or hieroglyphic, voiceless,
intervenes to cover up good writing [Ia bonne ecriture] ; it overdetermines,
occults, complicates, perverts, makes a travesty of the natural inscription of
truth in the soul. By effacing himself, the teacher [maf'tre] must also pro
mote the unlearning of bad writing. But if this motif retains a certain "Pla
tonic" allure, the specificity of its "age" is signaled by a profound "Carte
sian'' reference. My use of its (traditional) philosophical name is a matter of
provisional simplification; ultimately, the specifics do not have a philo
sophical claim on us. Cousin himselfsends us back to Descartes; what is at
stake is an appropriative interpretation of Cartesianism, an attempt both to
confirm that the teaching of philosophy in France must derive from the
Cartesian tradition (since true and French coincide, natural truth is also na
tional; Descartes is France), and also to demonstrate that, contrary to the
allegations of certain adversaries of secular schools and State education,
Descartes is not dangerous: Cartesian doubt, as we all know, remains pro
visional and methodical; it is not a skeptical doubt. The Commission of
Peers concerned with the business of the law under debate had indeed sub
scribed to this statement, penned by the Due de Broglie: ""What is the phi
losophy that is and should be taught in France, not only because its origin
is French, but also because it is really the true and sound philosophy? Most
certainly that of Descartes" (no).
Let us put aside for now the issue of philosophical nationality, its impli
cations, and its effect upon the history of the relative nationalization of
French education since the time of Cousin. We will return to it elsewhere,
so far as it concerns the case of France; here (and later) we will be concerned
with its bearing on the case of the Prussian State. Let's also put aside the
question of the asserted equation of a philosophy that is "really true" and
one that is "sound." For the moment, I wish simply to emphasize the de
termination of truth as certitude. This constitutes a common ground for
Hegel and Cousin in its philosophical phenomenon. And Cousin needs it,
The Age ofHegel 123
and Bossuet to be melted into one, we can judge irs reality by the massive
effects it produces. And those produced by Cousin's impeccable rhetoric.
Here is the "age" that stems from Descartes:
the risk of merely reproducing it, with or without the "liberal" modifica
tions we have observed in Hegel and Cousin.
over the seam of the breeches) for the Minister: this is me berween the
ages of eleven and thirteen. And he does it in the ripeness of age, at a mo
ment when the philosopher (fifty-rwo years old) and his philosophy begin
to speak of their death, at nightfall. The next month (June 1822), address
ing the same ministerial sponsor, with a slight hint of services rendered
bur consistently with systematic philosophical rigor, Hegel speaks of a
"supplementary income," of his children, his death, his widow, and of the
insurance he has taken out for the future. To Altenstein:
express to you the wishes to which these circumstances have given rise. I did
not fail to acknowledge my gratitude when, as a consequence of the duties as
signed me at the Royal Examination Commission [to which our letter of 22
April alludes as a legitimizing experience] , I received a supplement to my in
come. But this supplement is already almost entirely exhausted, owing to the
fact that, as I approach old age, I am obliged to think of the future of my wife
and children-all the more so, since I have devoted all my personal resources
to my intellectual development, which I now place at the service of the royal
government. My insurance premium for the General Fund for Widows, in or
der that my heirs may receive 330 thalers per year, in addition to my manda
tory contributions to the University Widows' Fund; amounts to an annual ex
penditure of 170 thalers. I make this sacrifice year after year with two concerns
imposing themselves on me: first, that if I do not die a professor of the Royal
University, my contributions to the University Widows' Fund will be entirely
lost; and second, that because of my insurance at the General Fund for Wid
ows, my future widow and my children may not be able to count on the gen
erous help of His Royal Majesty.8
This unity is not easy to conceive, but we can neither omit any of the per
tinent terms, forces, desires, or interests, nor relegate any of them to sec
ondary status. We will return to this.
In satisfying Hegel's demands the month following the letter about the
Gymnasium, Altenstein knew whom he was supporting. On 25 June he
sent Hegel a letter informing him of what he had procured (travel reim
bursements, 300 thalers for the previous year, 3 00 thalers for the current
year, etc.) . In order to secure these "extraordinary allotments," he had had
to speak to Chancellor Harden berg in praise of Hegel's philosophy and
politics, in praise not only of his political philosophy, but of his political
influence-of his political influence in a difficult situation, in an atmos
phere of considerable student unrest. Altenstein knows exactly what he has
to say, even if what he actually thinks is more complex:
Certainly I need not expand upon Hegel's merits as a man; a university pro
fessor, or a scholar. His scholarly merits are widely recognized. He is undoubt
edly the most profound and most solid philosopher in Germany. But his value
as a man and as a university professor is even more important [my emphasis] .
His influence upon the young is infinitely salutary. With courage, seriousness,
and competence, he has opposed the pernicious in@rration of a philosophy
without depth, and he has dashed the presumptions of the young. His opin
ions render him worthy of the highest esteem and this fact-combined with
his salutary influence-is recognized even by those who have nothing but dis
dain for anything that has to do with philosophy. (June 6, 1822)9
Hegel knows all this. Practically every thread in this skein where "pri
vate interests" and the interests of historical reason, special interests and
the interests of the State, the interests of a particular state and the univer
sal historical rationality of the State, are so effectively intertwined. He had
just recently expounded this in the Philosophy ofRight. And he knows, at
that moment, how his Philosophy ofRight "had th()roughly scandalized the
demagogues."10 When he thanks Altenstein, the terms of his gratitude
serve to define the locus of the exchange and of the contract, the insurance
of the one and the assurance of the other:
by extrinsic cares, now that Your Excellency's benevolent promises have relieved
me of my worries, and now that manifold and unequivocal evidence has se
cured for me the reassuring conviction that possible misgivings regarding phi
losophy on the part of the high authorities of the State-misgivings readily oc
casioned by false tendencies within philosophy itself-have not only remained
foreign to my public activity as a professor, but also that I myself have labored,
not without commendation and success, to aid those young people studying
here to think properly, and thus to render myself worthy of the confidence of
Your Excellency and of the Royal Government. (Berlin, July 3, 1822; 276)
Having taken out all this insurance on the Heirs (ofHegel), on the State
(of Prussia) , on the University (of Berlin)-he does not forget Bavaria,
where he plays the lottery. In July, after having congratulated Nietharnrner
on the budget for public instruction adopted by the Bavarian State Legis
lature ("the other branches don't concern me"), after informing his corre
spondent of the disciplinary measures against "demagogic" instructors un
der consideration in Berlin (a week before dispatching the Letter about the
Gymnasium) , Hegel continues: "The brilliant state of the Bavarian budget
reminds me that I am still in possession of Bavarian lottery tickets, of
whose fate I have heard nothing. . . . I take the liberty of attaching a scrap
of paper on which I have jotted down their numbers, and would ask your
son-since he works in the Department of Finance-to make inquiries in
this matter." He then alludes to the difficulty of receiving approval in mat
ters of philosophy, theology, and Christianity: "It is in applying concepts
and reason to matters concerning the State that one encounters the most
difficulty [in gaining this approbation], but I myself have already made it
very clear that I have no desire to ally myself further with our gang of lib
ertarian apostles. But there is no sense in trying to please those who are on
the other side, either" (282).
And indeed, i because of his political behavior as well as his political
philosophy, Hegel would seem to uphold the State against a "gang" of
"demagogues," this support is conditional, complex, and an entire strate
gic reserve can make Hegel pass for an enemy in the eyes of those "who
are on the other side." We have plenty of signs of this strategic reserve, of
the recourse it might find in the system of the philosophy of right, of the
concrete effects it had back then in the political arena. For obvious rea
sons, we will have to limit ourselves, in a moment, to those legible in the
"Letter about the Gymnasium." 1 1
Ecce homo, that's me between the ages o f eleven and thirteen. The man .
The Age ofHegel IJ I
who says this is not simply a mature man, already contemplating death,
thinking about the University Widows' Fund, and of a post-Hegelian era
(will he ever have thought of anything else?) . It is Hegel the philosopher,
who is not an adult like any other, one mature man among others. It is a
philosopher who presents himself as the first adult philosopher, the first to
think the beginning and end of philosophy, truly to think them through
conceptually. It is the philosopher of a philosophy that thinks itself [qui se
pense] as having left childhood behind, that claims to think, along with its
own history, all the ages of philosophy, the whole time and teleology of its
maturation. And that, therefore, has nothing but childhoods in its past, in
particular, childhoods under representation, if representation is, already
withoutyet being, "the thought that conceives." Hegel's childhood is thus
more serious, more amusing, more singular, singularity itself: not impos
sible, nor inconceivable, but practically unimaginable. He did everything
to render it unimaginable, until the day when-until that nightfall when,
anxious about the future of the teaching of philosophy in the State, anx
ious as well about the future of his widow and his sons, he evokes, for ar
gument's sake, his childhood; he remembers, he says he remembers, that
which he already remembered between the ages of eleven and thirteen.
For already it was but a matter of memory or understanding, not of spec
ulative thought.
The scene seems all the more comical for its absolute lack of braggado
cio. Were there even the faintest suspicion of this, it would have to be neu
tralized, legitimized, and thereby effaced with whatever good reasons we
would then invoke. And indeed, the comical element is a result precisely of
the good reasons with which Hegel can authorize himself to say such things
in all modesty. First of all, it is true, he must have been very, very gifted. We
have only to read his works-so well known and extremely profound, as
Altenstein reminds the Chancellor. And then, we have the additional testi
mony about that brilliant schoolboy, who read so much and recopied long
passages of the things he read. And again, if he offers himself as an exam
ple [pour exemple] but not as exemplary [en exemple] ; if he plays with the
example the way, elsewhere, he teaches the Beispiel, 12 it is in order to ren
der apparent the essence of a possibility: every normally healthy child
should be Hegel. At the moment when the old Hegel remembers the child
Hegel, but also thinks him and conceives him in his truth, this child Hegel
plays, as do all children, no doubt, but plays here the role of a figure or of
a moment in the pedagogy of the mind. Moreover, the anecdote serves to
1 32 The Age ofHegel
support a thesis; it is intended to carry conviction and pave the way for po
litical decisions. It justifies itself, thereby effacing its anecdotal singularity,
by invoking an older common experience [die allgemeine altere Erfohrung] .
Common experience certifies that this instruction does not exceed the in
tellectual powers [Fassungskraft] of Gymnasium students. Finally, this ca
pacity, to which the litt!e, eleven-year-old Hegel bears wimess, is not yet a
philosophical capacity as such (that is, a speculative capacity) but, ather,
memory, the recollection of certain lifeless contents, contents of the Un
derstanding [entendement], contents that are forms (definitions, rules, and
figures of syllogisms). And this not-yet propagates its effects throughout the
letter, throughout the entire pedagogical machinery that Hegel proposes to
the Minister. This not-yet of the already, as we shall see, forbids precisely
that which it would seem to promote, namely, the teaching of philosophy
in the Gymnasium.
When Hegel says that he still remembers the idea clara and syllogistics,
we note a mixture of coyness (refinement and play, the put-on puerility of
the great mathematician who feigns being astonished that he still remem
bers his multiplication tables), a certain affected tenderness for the rem
nants of the child in himself, most of all, a portion of irony in his chal
lenge to pedagogic modernity, "a challenge directed at current prejudices
against autonomous thought, productive activity." And what is more cur
rent (even today, for the age of Hegel will have lasted that long) than the
monotonous pedagogic modernity that takes issue with mechanical mem
orization, mnemotechnics, in the name of productive spontaneity, of ini
tiative, of independent, living self-discovery, etc.? But Hegel's irony is
double: He knows that he has, elsewhere, objected to mnemotechnic for
malism and learing "by heart." We cannot, therefore, suspect him of be
ing simply and generally a partisan of such techniques. It is a question,
precisely, of age, of the order and teleology of acquisition, ofprogress. And
this progress, from age to age, is not only that of the schoolboy in the
Prussian Gymnasium. We discover its stages and its sequence in the his
tory of philosophy. The age of formalism and quantitative technique
the age of Leibniz, for example-is that of "incapable childhood" (unver
mogende Kindheit), as the Greater Logic puts it. But the modernist theme
of productive spontaneity remains just as abstract, and hence childish (for
the child is more abstract than the adult, like a concept still undetermined),
just as empty or incapable as are formalism and mechanical memory in
sofar as they have not been worked through, sublated. The entire "system''
The Age ofHegel 133
vice versa. Certainly, there was an initial agreement about the conditions
of such a debate, about the new objects (excluded until now) that must be
brought to light; about the old objects that must be seen in a new light;
about a certain number of forces that must be combated. And this con
sensus still exists. But so does the initial openness [ouverture] of the debate.
It is in order to take part in such a debate-keeping in mind certain com
mon assumptions-that I would like to develop certain hypotheses and
advance certain propositions, using, as my point of departure, an applied
reading that might, for the moment, interest no one but mysel What is
to be done with this letter of Hegel's? Where is it to be situated? Where
does it take place? Evaluation is inevitable: is it a "major" text or a "minor"
one? Is it a "philosophical" text? What status, as they say, do we grant it?
What title? One of the tasks of Greph could be a (not only formal, but ef
fective and concrete) critique of all the existing hierarchies, of all the crite
riology, implicit or explicit, that secures certain evaluations and classifica
tions ("major" or "minor" texts) . Further: a general reelaboration of the
entire problematic ofhierarchies. Without this reelaboration, no profound
transformation will be possible. The force that dominates the process of
classification and hierarchization allows us to read whatever it is interested
in having us read (which it then labels major texts, or texts of "great im
port"), and it renders inaccessible whatever it is interested in underesti
mating, which in general it cannot read (describing such texts as minor or
marginal). This holds true for the discourse of the educator and for all his
evaluatory procedures ( grading; juries for examinations, competitions, the
ses; so-called supervisory committees; etc.); it is the evaluative standard de
termining all discourse: from that of the critic and the upholder of tradi
tion to that determining editorial policy, the commercialization of texts,
etc. Once again, it is not simply a matter of texts in print or on black
boards, but rather of a general textuality without which there is no under
standing and no action. Reread the ''Avant-Projet" of Greph: every sen
tence demands that the censured or devalued be displayed, that the vast
holdings of a more-or-less forbidden library be exhumed from the cellars.
And that there be a lack of respect for prevailing evaluations: not simply in
order to indulge certain perverse bibliophilic pleasures (on the other hand,
why not?); nor even in order better to understand what links philosophy
to its institution, to its institutional "underside" and "recesses" [dessous et
envers] ; but rather to transform the very conditions of our effective inter
vention in them. "Underside" and "recesses," because it is not a matter of
The Age ofHegel 135
discovering today, belatedly, what has been known all along: that there
is such a thing as a philosophical institution. Indeed, "Philosophy" ["Ia"
philosophie] has always had a dominant concept to take this into account,
and imtitution is at bottom the name it has reserved for this task. "Under
side" or "recesses," because we are not satisfied with what the institution
reveals about itself: neither with what we can perceive empirically, nor
with what we can conceive according to the law of the philosophical con
cept. "Underside" or "recesses" would no longer have a signification dom
inated by the philosophical opposition that continues to order discourse in
terms of a concealed substance or essence of the institution, hidden be
neath its accidents, circumstances, phenomena, or superstructures. "Un
derside" and "recesses" would designate, rather, that which, while still be
ing situated within this venerable (conceptual and metaphoric) topos,
might begin to extricate itself from this opposition and to constitute it in
a new manner.
The critical reelaboration of this hierarchy and of this problematics of
hierarchy must not be restricted to new "theorems" in the same language
[langage] . It requires that we also write in a language [langue] and that we
operate (practically) according to schemes that can no longer be deter
mined by the old divisions.
This is why the overturning [renversement] of the authorized hierarchy
is no longer enough. This is why it is no longer enough to canonize "mi
nor" texts or to exclude, and thereby devalue, "major" texts. The same
philosophical program can lead to evaluative or classificatory statements
that seem contradictory: this text is a "minor" text (for example: circum
stantial, "journalistic," empirico-anecdotal, feebly philosophical) ; or the
same text is a "major" text (addressing a "great" philosophical theme, en
gaging the great problematic tradition, manifesting all the signs of a pro
found theoretical responsibility) . But are these statements contradictory?
If the same premises lead to evaluations that are apparently contradictory,
what does this tell us about the system of reading and hierarchization at
work? If this system of reading has an essential rapport with "Hegelian
philosophy," with everything this philosophy seems to collect, complete,
configure into its "age," then the "letter" in which we are interested can no
longer be a mere example, a case in point evoked to illustrate this question.
Hegel's Letter on the Gymnasium has, quite obviously, been treated as
a minor text. And not only in France. The letter does not belong to the
"textbook" corpus of Hegel. It was not vouchsafed a place in the corre-
The Age ofHegel
elusions. For the present, let us be content with locating the space of the
strategic negotiations: between the Idea of the State as defined in the third
part of The Philosophy ofRight (reality as an act of substantial will, as a goal
in itself, absolute, immobile, knowing what it wants in its universality)
and personal subjectivity or particularity, whose most extreme forms the
modern State has the power to perfect.
Within this space, Hegel seems to anticipate the ministerial request.
Then, as now (the analogy would take us far, even though it must be fol
lowed with care), the Ministry wants to keep "the teaching of philosophy in
the Gymnasium from losing itself in a babble of hollow formulas [sich in
ein hohles Formelwesen verliere] or from transgressing the limits of school
teaching." Then, as now, these two fears are related, if not confounded.
"What is the hollowness of formulas? -what is babble? -who is to define it?
From what point of view? According to what philosophy and what politics?
Does not every new or subversive discourse always constitute itself through
rhetorical effects that are necessarily identified as "gaps" in the prevailing
discourse, with the inevitable phenomena of discursive degradation, mech
anisms, mimetisms, etc.? The relation of the Formelwesen to the alleged
plenitude of the completed discourse will be definable only in terms of a
strictly determined philosophy. Here Hegel is no more able than anyone
else discoursing on babble to avoid proposing a philosophy-in this case
the dialectic of speculative idealism-as a general criteriology that distin
guishes between empty and full language in education. And which also de
termines the limit between schoolteaching and that which lies outside.
Nowhere in the letter is the question of this criteriology and these limits
posed. Nor, furthermore, are either politics or what lies outside the school
so much as mentioned. But it is in the answer to this unposed question
that, as always, an educational system constructs or reforms itsel
Hegel-Hegel's philosophy-responds to the request, which we can
here distinguish from the question: in order to avoid babble, he advises
loading the mind with content, with a good content as is necessarily de
termined by the Hegelian system, and beginning there, beginning, indeed,
with a content that has been recorded: with memory, with memory as its
concept is dialectically determined within the system ("for in order to pos
sess knowledge of any kind-even the highest sort-one must have mem
orized it [im Gediichtnisse haben] ; regardless of whether this is to be a be
ginning or an end in itsel" -whether this is to be a beginning or an end in
itself, to be sure. But Hegel goes on to justifY his pedagogical proposition:
The Age ofHegel 1 41
it ispreferable that this happen at the beginning, for "if one begins there, one
has that much more freedom and inducement to think for oneself'; ibid.) .
For Hegel, memory was both a beginning and an end; he remembers (be
ing eleven) and remembers that he began by remembering that which he
first learned by heart. But at the same time, this homology of the system
(the dialectical concept of Gediichtnis) and of the autobiographical experi
ence that gave Hegel the inducement and the freedom to think, this ho
mology is to be enriched again by its pedagogical version: by beginning
with teaching the content of knowledge, before even thinking it, we are as
sured of a highly determined prephilosophical inculcation that paves the
way for good philosophy [Ia bonne philosophie] . We know the schema, and
Greph was quick to criticize certain of its current consequences.
To remain within the "limits of schoolteaching," this prephilosophical
content will consist of the humanities (the Ancients, the great artistic and
historical conceptions of individuals and peoples, their ethics and their re
ligiosity), classical literature, the dogmatic content of religion-so many
disciplines that will be studied in light of the content that is essential to the
preparation for speculative philosophy. Time and again, content is privi
leged in this propaedeutic, and the material part stressed over the formal
part. The treatment reserved for religion and its dogmatic content is re
markable enough. Indeed, it defines fairly accurately the lines of negotia
tion. There is, of course, as we know, a war between Hegel and religious
authority. The two parties indulged in violent verbal exchanges. Hegel was
accused and suspected of the worst. But at the same time, his interest is in
wresting religious instruction from the religious powers; the philosophy of
religion defines the conditions and the perspectives of this reappropriation.
At stake is the raising of religion to the level of speculative thought, mak
ing apparent those aspects of religion that are sublatedin philosophy, as in
their truth. The pedagogical version of this movement is not a mere corol
lary of the philosophy of religion, without which the Letter would be in
comprehensible. It is, rather, central to it. In I8IO, he had written to Niet
hammer: "Protestantism has less to do with a particular confession than
with a superior, more rational spirit of reflection and of cultuie; its spiri
tual foundations are not a sort of training adaptable to this or that utili
tarian p urpose." This objection to pedagogical training or utilitarianism,
as expressed in the letter of 1822, whose trace one can follow in Nietzsche
and Heidegger, is therefore indissociable from this Protestant philosophy
pedagogy. In 1816, Hegel writes again: "Protestantism is not entrusted to
1 42 The Age ofHegel
Like knowledge and science, religion has as its principle its own form, which
is different from that of the State, they [religion, science, and knowledge] en
ter into the State partly as means of educating [Mitteln der Bildung] and of
forming attitudes, partly insofar as they are essentially ends-in-themselves, by
virtue of their outward existence. In both respects, the principles of the State
relate to them i terms of application. A comprehensive, concrete treatise on
the State would also have to deal with such spheres-as well as with art and
with mere natural relations-and to consider their relations to and position
within the State.18
The last section of the same chapter situates the question of teaching at
the center of the rapports between Church and State. The example of
Protestantism plays a very important role here, although it is alluded to
only parenthetically: it is the case in which there is no "particular content"
that can remain exterior to the State, since "in Protestantism" there is no
"clergy which would be the sole depository of Church doctrine, for [in
Protestantism] there is no laity."
The Age ofHegel 1 43
against which we are struggling. One could say that it excludes all access to
the practice of philosophy before the University. Hegel proposes introduc
ing in the Gymnasium a bener preparation for the "proper essence of phi
losophy [das eigentliche TI!esen der Philosophie] ," that is, for its pure contents
in the "speculative form." But access to this content remains impossible or
forbidden in the Gymnasium: "But I need not add that the exposition of
philosophy is still to be excluded from instruction in the Gymnasium and
reserved for the University, since the high rescript of the Royal Ministry has
itself already presupposed this exclusion [diese Ausschliejfung schon selbst vo
rausgesetzt] ." This presupposition functions as do all presuppositions (Vo
raussetzungen) in Hegelian discourse; furthermore, it situates the point of
contact between a state fpolitical action (philosophy reserved for the Uni
versity) and the logic of Hegelian discourse, here exempted from the need
to explain itsel The whole paragraph following the allusion to this ex
emption makes its consequences explicit. Up to the point of the strict ex
clusion of the history of philosophy from the circle of secondary education.
Here is the beginning of the next paragraph: "With respect to the more de
fined circle of the fields of knowledge to which Gymnasium instruction is
to be restricted, I would like expressly to exclude the history ofphilosophy."
Now, such an exclusion is justified by the concept of the presupposition of
the Idea (projection or result of beginning at the end) as it organizes the en
tire Hegelian systematic, the entire onto-encyclopedia. And thereby the en
tire Universitas, which cannot be dissociated from it. The "ministerial" pre
supposition matches the Hegelian proposition, both in its principle and in
its end: "But without presupposing the speculative Idea, this history [of
philosophy] will often be no more than a simple narrative [Erziihlung] of
superfluous opinions." In our analysis of this justification of the exclusion
of the history of philosophy from the curriculum of the Gymnasium, we
should not forget that today, in our own lycees, resorting to the history of
philosophy as such still meets with official disapproval, especially if it takes
the form of an expose or a narrative. The "good reasons" invoked to justifY
this ani tude make sense only within the Hegelian concept of presupposi
tion. It is not a maner here simply of disputing these reasons, but rather,
first of all, of recognizing precisely their presupposition, the presupposed
logic of presupposition. Finally, another exclusion, metaphysics: ''A final
consideration has to do with the higher reasons for excluding metaphysics as
such from the Gymnasium" (Hegel's emphasis) . This exclusion postpones
(until the University proper) access to thought-in its speculative form-
The Age ofHegel 147
sal, and can we be satisfied with that? This passage from "minor" to "ma
jor" is tautological and reproduces the Hegelian gesture, the heterotautol
ogy of the speculative proposition. For Hegel, there is, with respect to the
philosophical, no simple exteriority. What other philosophers (the ones I
just called pre-Hegelian) would consider-on account of their formalism,
empiricism, dialectical impotence-to be "everyday," "journalistic" em
piricity, accidental contingency, or external particularity is no less alien to
the system and to the development [devenir] of Reason than, according to
Hegel, the morning "gazette" is heterogeneous, insignificant, or illegible
from the point of view of the Greater Logic. There is a Hegelian hierarchi
zation, but it is circular, and the minor is always carried, subfated beyond
the opposition, beyond the limit of inside and outside in(to) the major.
And inversely. The potency of this age without age derives from this great
empirico-philosophical cycle. Hegel does not conceive of the school as the
consequence or the image of the system, or even as its pars totalis: the sys
tem itself is an immense school, the thoroughgoing auto-encyclopedia of
absolute spirit in absolute knowledge. And it is a school we never leave,
hence a mandatory instruction, mandated by itself, since the necessity can
no longer come from without. The letter-let us not forget this homology
-follows closely on the establishment of obligatory schooling. Altenstein
was one of its most active advocates. As under Charlemagne, schooling is
broadened, and the attempt is made to reduce the Church to the service of
the State.
The Universitas is that onto- and auto-encyclopedic circle of the State.
Whatever the particular forces in "civil society'' may be that dispose over
the power of the State, every university as such (be it on the "right" or the
"left") depends upon this model. Since this model (which, by definition,
claims universality) is always in negotiated compromise with the forces of
a particular State (Prussian, Napoleonic-I and II-republican-bourgeois,
Nazi, fascist, social democratic, popular democratic, or socialist) , the de
construction of its concepts, instruments, and practices cannot proceed by
immediately and attempting to do away with it without risking
attacking it
the immediate return of other forces that would welcome its disappearance.
Immediately to cede and make way for the other of the Universitas might
represent a welcome invitation to those very determinate and very deter
mined forces, ready and waiting, close by, to take over the State and the
University. Whence the necessity for a deconstruction not to abandon the
terrain of the University at the very moment when it begins to come to
The Age ofHegel 149
grips with its most powerful foundations. Whence the necessity not to
abandon the field to empiricism and thereby to whatever forces are at
hand. Whence the political necessity of our alliances, a necessity that must
be constantly re-evaluated. For Greph, as we know, this problem is neither
remote nor abstract. If the current French State is afraid of philosophy, it is
because extending its teaching contributes to the progress of two types of
threatening forces: those wanting to change the State (those, let's say, be
longing to an age of left-wing Hegelianism) and to wrest it from the con
trol of those forces currently in power, and those that, on the other hand
or simultaneously, allied or not with the former, tend toward the destruc
tion of the State.20 These two forces cannot be classified according to the
prevailing divisions. They seem to me, for example, to cohabitate today
within that theoretical and practical field commonly known as "Marxism."
Charlemagne died a second time, but things go on, and a Hegel can al
ways be found to occupy his throne.
In 1822 (the year of our letter), the beneficiary of Hegel's insurance pol
icy at the University Widows' Fund received another missive:
You see, my dear wife, that I have arrived at the goal of my voyage, which is to
say, at its most distant point . . . . We arrived at 10 P.M. at Aachen. The first
thing I saw was the cathedral and I sat down on Charlemagne's throne . . . .
Three hundred years after his death, Charlemagne was found seated upon this
throne-by the Emperor Frederic, I believe . . . and his remains were interred.
I sat on this throne-on which, as the sacristan assured me, thirty-two emper
ors have been crowned-just like any other person, and the entire satisfaction
is simply to have been seated there.21
G. W. F. Hegel
IfO
The Age ofHegel
pletely uneducated and not yet mature. Although one could cite a provi
sion from the starutes of our University (Chap. VIII, 6, art. r, p. 43) that
appears to contradict both practice and the aforementioned siruation, its
effect is superseded and annulled [au.Jiehoben] by a more precise provision
to be found in the October 12, r8n, edict relative to the examination of
Gymnasium students applying to the University, to which acrual practice
accordingly conforms. As a member of the Scientific Examination Com
mission, to which the Royal Ministry deigned to name me, I have had oc
casion to see that the ignorance of those obtaining a diploma to enter the
University extends to all levels and that the preparation required by the
more or less considerable number of such subjects would at times have to
begin with the orthography of their native tongue. Since at the same time
I am also a professor in this University, I cannot but be extremely alarmed
for myself and my colleagues in the face of such utterly deficient knowl
edge and culture in college students, whom we are asked to teach and for
whom we must bear responsibility if the aims and expenditures of the
Government are not fulfill ed: the aim that those leaving the University
take with them not merely vocational training, but an educated and cul
tivated mind. No further elaboration is required to demonstrate that the
honor and esteem of the University also do not benefit from the admis
sion of such utterly immarure young people.
In this context I would like respectfully to offer the Royal Ministry my
own experience stemming from my membership in the Scientific Exami
nation Commission. Namely-insofar as the examinations are designed
to inform those persons, by ascertaining the extent of their knowledge,
who are still thoroughly unprepared for the University, and to advise them
to postpone entering the University until they h ave completed their defi
cient preparation-this aim appears rarely to be attained, since those ex
aminees whose ignorance is thereby revealed learn nothing new; rather,
being entirely aware that they know no Latin, no Greek, nothing of math
ematics or of history, they have already made their decision to enter the
University and hence seek nothing from the Commission but the acquisi
tion of the certificate that allows them to register. They are all the less
likely to take such a certificate as advice against entering the University,
since, independently of its content, it gives them the possibility of being
admitted to the University.
In order now to proceed to the object at hand designated by the Royal
Ministry, that is, preparation in the Gymnasium for speculative thinking and
The Age ofHegel
that it would be an even more futile effort for student youth to give them
selves over to it.
On the contrary, among the fields of knowledge to be included in the
preparational instruction here in question, I would mention the following:
I. So-called empiricalpsychology. Representations of external sensations,
imagination, memory, and other psychic faculties are indeed already in
themselves something so current that an exposition restricting itself to
them would easily be trivial and pedantic. On the one hand, however,
such could be all the more easily dispensed within the University if it were
already to be found in the Gymnasium; on the other hand, it could be
limited to an introduction to logic, whereby in any event this would have
to be preceded by the mention of intellectual activities different in char
acter from thinking as such. Beginning with the external senses, images
and representations, then proceeding to their conjunction or so-called as
sociation, and from there to the nature of languages, and especially to the
distinctions between representations, thoughts, and concepts, much of
considerable interest could be adduced, which, moreover, would be of
great use, insofar as the latter subject matter-once the part that thinking
has in intuition [Amchauungen] had been rendered apparent-would con
stitute a more direct introduction to the study of logic.
2. The rudiments of logic, however, would have to be considered the
main object. Excluding its speculative significance and treatment, instruc
tion could be extended to cover the doctrine of concepts, of judgments, of
syllogisms and their modes, and then to the doctrine of definition, division,
proof, and the scientific method, in full accordance with already-established
procedure. Usually, the doctrine of the concept already takes up determi
nations that more proximately belong to the field of what otherwise is
called ontology; a part of this doctrine is also customarily introduced in the
form of laws of thought. At this point it would be advantageous to intro
duce an acquaintance with the Kantian categories as the so-called elemen
tary concepts of understanding, leaving aside, however, the remainder of
Kantian metaphysics; yet a mention of the antinomies could still open up
at least a negative and formal perspective on reason and the ideas.
What speaks in favor of linking this instruction to Gymnasium educa
tion is the fact that no object is less apt to be judged adequately by the
young in respect to its importance or utility. If such instruction has grad
ually been abandoned, it is in all probability primarily because this insight
has largely been lost. Besides, such an object is not attractive enough in
The Age ofHegel I 55
general to entice the young into studying logic during their stay at the
University, where they are in a position to choose the fields of knowl
edge-outside of their vocational studies-in which they want to become
involved. Moreover, it is not unknown for teachers in the positive sciences
to advise students against studying philosophy, which they also probably
take to include the study of logic. If this instruction is introduced into the
Gymnasium, however, pupils will at least once have the experience of re
ceiving, and thus having, well-formed [formliche] thoughts in their heads.
It should be considered a highly significant, subjective effect if the atten
tion of the young can be directed toward a domain of thought for itself,
and toward the fact that formed thoughts are themselves an object worthy
of consideration-indeed, an object to which public authority itself at
taches importance, as indicated by this organization of the curriculum.
The fact that such instruction does not exceed the intellectual capaci
ties of Gymnasium students is attested to by the general experience of the
past, and if I may be permitted to evoke my own experience, not only
have I daily had before my eyes the ability and receptivity of pupils for
such subject matter, since I have been a professor of philosophical propae
deutics for many years, and a Gymnasium rector; in addition, I remember
having learned, in my twelfth year-destined as I was to enter the theo
logical seminary of my country-Wolf's definitions of the so-called idea
clara, and that, in my fourteenth year, I had assimilated all the figures and
rules of the syllogisms. And I still know them. Were it not to defy openly
contemporary prejudices in favor of "thinking for oneself" and "produc
tive activity," etc., I would not be averse to bringing something of this sort
into the proposal for the Gymnasium instruction of this track: for in or
der to possess knowledge of any sort, including the highest kind, one
must have it in memory, whether one begins or ends with this: if one be
gins with it, one has all the more freedom and occasion to think that
knowledge itsel Moreover, in such a way one coUld most surely counter
act the danger that the Royal Ministry rightly seeks to avoid, "That philo
sophical instruction in the Gymnasium should lose itself in empty for
mulas or exceed the limits of school instruction."23
3 The preceding point joins forces with higher reasons to exclude meta
physics proper from the Gymnasium. Yet there is one aspect of the previous
Wolffian philosophy that could be brought under consideration: what in
the Theologia natura/is is advanced under the name of the proofi ofthe ex
istence of God. By itself, Gymnasium instruction will be unable to avoid
The Age ofHegel
connecting the doctrine of God with the thought of the finitude and the
contingency of worldly things, with the purposive relations within them,
etc.; however, such a connection will be eternally evident to unbiased hu
man intelligence, no matter what the objects of critical philosophy may
be. However, these so-called proofs contain nothing but a formal analysis
of the content that has already introduced itself spontaneously into Gym
nasium instruction. Of course, they require further correction by means
of speculative philosophy so that they in fact correspond to the content
accumulated by unbiased human intelligence along its way. A preliminary
acquaintance with the form of that way would be of more immediate in
terest to all subsequent speculative reflection.
4 In a similar manner, certain just and determinate concepts of the na
ture of volition and of freedom, of law and of duty, can be brought into
the Gymnasium instruction concerning ethics. This will be all the more
feasible in the higher classes, where instruction will be linked to religious
instruction, which runs through all classes and which therefore extends
over a period of possibly eight to ten years. In our times it could also seem
more urgent to work against the shallowness of insight-the results of
which, already manifest in the Gymnasiums, have at times attained public
notoriety-through correct concepts concerning the nature of the obliga
tions of citizens and of human beings.
This, then, would be my humble opinion concerning the extension of
the contents of the philosophical preparatory studies in the Gymnasium,
an opinion that I most respectfully place before the Royal Ministry. As to
what is still at issue concerning the length of time, and likewise the pro
gression to be followed in exposing such knowledge, nothing more need
be called to mind than what has been mentioned regarding religion and
ethics.24 With respect to initiation into the psychological and logical fields
of knowledge, it could be specified that, if two hours per week were taken
up in one year-long course, the psychological component would be dealt
with primarily as an introduction, and hence should be offered before the
logical portion. If, keeping the same number of hours, considered as ade
quate, three or four semiannual courses were devoted to it, more detailed
notions about the nature of the spirit, its activities and states, could be
taught; in this case it might be more advantageous to begin with instruc
tion in logic, on a level that is simple, abstract, and therefore easy to grasp.
This instruction would thereby fall in an earlier period, when the young
are more docile and submissive to authority, and are not so infected by the
The Age ofHegel I 57
demand that, to merit their anention, the subject maner must conform to
their representations [Wmtellungen] and to their emotional interests.
The possible difficulty entailed in increasing Gymnasium instruction
by two additional hours might best be avoided by reducing the so-called
instruction in German and in German literature by one or two hours, or,
even more appropriately, by canceling the lectures dealing with the legal
encyclopedia, where these occur in the Gymnasium, and replacing them
with lectures on logic; all the more so, in order that the general formation
of the spirit in the Gymnasium-an institution that can be considered to
be exclusively devoted to this kind of formation-not continue its appar
ent decline in favor of a training oriented toward vocational service and al
imentary studies.
Finally, concerning the textbooks that can be recommended to teachers
for such preparatory instruction, I would not know which of those with
which I am acquainted to indicate as preferable.25 The material can, per
haps, be found more or less in any textbook, but in the older ones it is
more complete and defined, and less contaminated with heterogeneous in
gredients; an ultimate instruction from the Royal Ministry could put forth
the directives designating which materials should be selected.
Reaffirming my beholden respect and obedience to the high Royal
Ministry
Hegel
Pro at the Royal University
Philosophy Repressed
Considering what we do not yet know and what we can already anticipate,
the treatment reserved for philosophy deserves particular attention. It is
not that the privilege of our attention is required by the sovereign ex
cellence of a discipline that it would once again be a matter of "defend
ing." But the fact is that the teaching of philosophy would be affected
Philosophy and Its Classes I 59
more profoundly than any other discipline by the current plan, in condi
tions that shed light on and determine the entire orientation of the new
"education system." The evidence is this. Since the new Terminales are
organized according to a totally "optional" system, there would no longer
be any required teaching of philosophy in the only class in which, up to
this point, it has been offered. Philosophy would be given three hours a
week in the "premiere": 1 about as much, on average, as in the sections of
the Terminales that receive the least today. Even before examining the
grounds for or aims of such an operation, let's move on to what is irrefut
able: the number of hours reserved for philosophy, for all students, is mas
sively reduced. Philosophy was already the only discipline confined to a
single class at the end of the final year of secondary studies; it would still
be contained in a single class, but with fewer hours. Thus an offensive that
had proceeded, in recent years, more prudently and deceitfully is openly
accelerated: the accentuated dissociation of the scientific and the philo
sophical, the actively selective orientation of the "best" students toward
sections giving less room to philosophy, the reduction of teaching hours,
coefficients, teaching positions, and so forth. This time, the plan appears
dearly to be adopted. No systematic introduction to philosophy could
possibly be attempted in three hours a week. How can one doubt that?
Since students will have had no other access to philosophy as such during
their entire studies, the candidates for the "philosophy'' option will be more
and more rare. Combined with the technico-economic pressures of a cer
tain market, with a politics of education ruled, more openly than ever, by
the law of this market, establishing the so-called "basic" baccalaureat, at
the end of the premiere, will reduce the number of students in the new
"Terminale," and later in the university. Already very appreciable, the grow
ing shortage of teaching positions in philosophy will be accelerated and
will produce the conditions for its progressive acceleration, discouraging
possible candidates for the "philosophy" option and therefore limiting pro
fessional prospects. And what we know about "teacher training" confirms
this threat. The recruitment of philosophy teachers might even be sus
pended, it is said, for several years. A machine has therefore been put in
place or, rather, has been perfected and finally put on display, a machine
that would quickly lead in practice to the evacuation of all philosophy in
"general and technical lycees," that would lead to its progressive extinction
in the universities. The separateness of the two "ministries" is here a de
ceptive fiction.
r 6o Philosophy and Its Classes
feet not only the forms of its organization but its contents. It would pro
duce new relations between these: inside philosophy and between philos
ophy and the other disciplines. In order for philosophy to be teachable, in
order for it to be taught differently, long before the premiere and beyond
the Terminale, we will have to avoid (a very difficult task) both atomiza
tion (for example, to the benefit of the "social sciences") and traditional
onto-encyclopedic hegemony. To accomplish that, we will have to reartic
ulate new contents with those of other scientific and nonscientific fields.
Instructors will thus receive a different (philosophical, scientific, pedago
gic) training.
Let's anticipate very ql,lickly the interested objection of those who would
like to shrug their shoulders. It is not a matter of transporting to the "six
ieme" a teaching that is already impracticable in the Terminale, but, first of
all, of accepting here, as in all the other disciplines, the principle of a cal
culated progressivity in the introduction to, training in, and acquisition of
kinds of knowledge. We know that in certain conditions, precisely those
that must be freed up, the "philosophical capacity'' of a "child" can be very
powerfUl. The progression would concern questions and texts from the tra
dition as well as those of modernity. Their alleged difficulty is due essen
tially to the politico-pedagogical machine that is put into question here. It
would be especially necessary to organize critical connections between this
teaching of philosophy and the other teachings themselves being trans
formed. To reorganize them, rather: who can doubt in fact that a very spe
cific philosophy is already being taught through French literature, the lan
guages, history, and even the sciences? And have we ever worried about the
real difficulty of these other teachings? About religious instruction? About
moral education? The explicit and critical locating of clandestine "philoso
phemes," as they are at work in teaching and outside of it, requires train
ing. This training can develop in a specific manner in each discipline and
in competition with it, at the same time that new philosophical reflections
and interventions would be involved in the transformed contents. A single
example: since it has to resort to new techniques and new conceptual re
sources (let's juxtapose the signs, to be brief: modern poetics, semiology,
linguistics, psychoanalysis, historical materialism, and all the new theoret
ical mechanisms that take these into account), the teaching of languages
and literatures will have to call for new and specific philosophical debates.
We can say as much about the mathematical and physical sciences, about
all the "human sciences," about their implicit or explicit epistemology.
Philosophy and Its Classes
That does not mean that a philosophical arbitration over all other disci
plines must be reinstituted, but that, after new divisions and a redefinition
of the so-called "interdisciplinary" limits and practices, appropriate tech
niques would be taught to analyze the inevitably politically committed
philosophical stakes, whether we recognize this or not, even and especially
if something like Philosophy were ever to be put into question.
That cannot be done without a general mutation, from the school to
the university, that is to say, first of all, in society. Instead of clinging to
the "defense-of-philosophy'' or resigning ourselves to a certain "death-of
philosophy" and being bound, in both cases, with the same pathos, to the
same interests, must we not work to impose, audaciously and offensively,
new programs, new contents, new practices?
This mimicry of freedom is all the more shocking and cynical as everything
has been put in place to favor social selection, to increase massively the pro
portion of students leaving before the Terminale, to make teaching posi
tions in philosophy scarce. Since the plan's publication, this machinery has
been described in all of its economico-political implications or aims.
And thus its philosophical implications or aims. I would like to insist
upon this point, instead of reiterating legitimate but now well-known de
nunciations. The Giscard-Haby plan has philosophical aims. I will not say
that it literally "contains a radical destruction of Philosophy." Within a field
of struggle that extends beyond it and determines it from all sides-and
that also includes its own philosophical instance-the plan tends to impose
an apparatus capable of inculcating a philosophy or maintaining a cer
tain philosophical type, a philosophical force or group of forces, in the
dominant position. Even in its sketchy argumentation and crude rhetoric
(Cousin did a much better job in the same vein) , the text Pour une modern
isation du systeme educatif (For a Modernization ofthe Education System), of
which six hundred thousand copies were printed, I believe, is also a philo
sophical text that must also be interpreted as such. Striving to contain-in
sofar as this is possible today-the teaching of philosophy as such, this pro
ject aims to reduce the scope of a field of critique and struggle at a time
when other philosophical forces were likely to progress, were in reality in
the process of progressing, there. The government plan would allow a cer
tain force or coalition of forces to occupy the ground and to resist this
progress, which is also political, in other ways: through other kinds of teach
ing, indeed, systems other than the school system in the narrow sense. One
more reason for not keeping the debate enclosed within one discipline or
even within teaching, and for recalling that what is at stake is not simply
the radical destruction or the unending survival of something like Philoso
phy. There is nothing radical about the accentuation of an offensive that
has been underway for a long time. In particular, its inability or its unwill
ingness to see that this offensive is not a case of nonphilosophy against Phi
losophy has rendered the traditional defense-of-philosophy unable to rec
ognize its own contradiction or to organize anything more than its own
retreat. We cannot retrace here the origins of the teaching of philosophy,
not even its foundations in France. We need only remember the most re
cent episodes and keep in mind the powerlessness of such a defense ever
since '68 (the reduction of the hours and coefficients in the Terminale, the
reduction of the number of teaching positions, the accentuated dissociation
r66 Divided Bodies
of the scientific and the philosophical, the repression exercised against cer
tain teachers or students in the Terminale, and so forth).
But while there is nothing radically new about it, the reform envisaged
proposes a formula of compromise that follows a novel pattern, as far as I
know: the elimination of the required study of philosophy and of a neces
sary set number of hours dedicated to the subject in certain sections of the
Terminale, a philosophy requirement for all with a greatly reduced sched
ule (three hours) in the Premiere. Fouchet indeed thought of this exploi
tation of the Premiere, Fontanet of the "optional" ruse.3 But the situation
was not ripe or not urgent enough, and they had to back down. It is there
fore not a question of a "new idea'' by Haby-that goes without saying
but the effect of a contradiction, the cobbling together of a compromise
formation that was expected, after a very brief analysis, to be acceptable in
the end. The field of the exercise of critique had to be reduced, for the rea
sons I have evoked; the ground of philosophical battles (in the Terminale
and in higher education) closed. ''A training in a limitedfield, one that tra
ditionally keeps at a distance all controversial domains of knowledge and
modes of thought" (Haby's emphasis) had to be guaranteed, and the num
ber of "professional" philosophers, about whom the market could not care
less, limited. Professional specialization had to be hastened, and the check
points of this specialization made more definitive and pushed forward in
time. But at the same time, since the balance of forces did not allow the
frank suppression, pure and simple, of the teaching of philosophy as such,
the vestige conceded had to retain its traditional form: locked up in a sin
gle class, at the end of secondary studies, a cloister for the old "queen-of
disciplines" or for the ceremony of the "crowning-of-studies," a liberal
neutral-objective-secular (see above) reflection on an accepted knowledge.
Virginal innocence, questioning and (understandably) taken aback, is not
supposed to see the curtain raised on the scene until the moment when
family, school, and classes have already consolidated their own preparation.
It was thought that this compromise would reassure everyone, even a cer
tain right (and, why not, a certain left) that sees in the philosophy class (in
its classical model) a safeguard against the spread outside the institution of
philosophies that it considers wild and that it would rather domesticate,
reappropriate, frame: this is how Duruy justified reestablishing the philos
ophy class under the Second Empire. This contradiction (maintaining the
status quo without maintaining it) took a specific form that led to tamper
ing (irresistibly, imprudently) with what one still called, for old times' sake,
Divided Bodies
plan and to the previous reforms already had a considerable history. We can
now begin to identifY it. We saw that a whole "defense" of philosophy, es
sentially reproducing Cousin's argumentation (in Definse de l'Universite et
de La Philosophie, 1844), established itself on traditional bases: the preserva
tion of the status quo, an immutable attachment to the-philosophy-cla.Ss, an
apolitical and objectively corporatist, idealistic, conservative critique of a
plan considered "threatening," indeed "criminal," regarding, say, a singular
corpus, a discipline that is as vulnerable as it is preeminent. What is more,
this defense of a pure power of questioning, as crucial as it is impoverished,
crucial because it occupies the shotgun seat, finds its objective reinforce
ment in the partisans of ilie death-of-philosophy. The pathos is fundamen
tally the same. This defense in itself has never been very effective, and in any
case has never defended what it said or believed it was defending.
In the other camp (I leave aside, for the moment, in the analysis of this
principal confrontation, differences that another situation might bring to
the fore), those who, taking an unequivocal position against the system
atic whole of the plan as a political project, demand not only that philos
ophy as such continue to be taught where it is already taught (in all the
Terminales as a required subject), but also and already in previous classes:
at least, to begin with, from the Seconde on. Philosophy must no longer
be contained in the fortress-prison of one class (the Terminale or the Pre
miere) . This offensive position has brought together, for the first time, a
large number of teachers, students, and pupils from all disciplines. It was
elaborated and clearly stated by Greph, 4 in particular, in a call largely ap
proved among the most activist students and teachers. It demands that
philosophy be "aligned with the other disciplines, that is, that it be subject
to a progressive teaching spread over several years." The thing is to put an
end to the false "privilege" ("the glory of French education") in whose
name a critical teaching was fenced off in an imperial reserve. By demand
ing this alignment, we challenge this sort of hegemonic belatedness (a no
tion that I cannot analyze here), no doubt, but we also give the teaching
of philosophy as such the means and the space granted to other disci
plines, at least means and space for a critical debate elsewhere, for an ar
ticulation of branches of knowledge, and so forth. At least. The issue was
not to approve or negotiate the introduction-reduction of philosophy in
the Premiere under the form provided for by the government. On the
contrary. Neither in fact or objectively nor is this our intention: rejecting
the plan in its entirety, Greph proposes:
Divided Bodies
in the short term, to join forces with all those who intend to oppose the immi
nent regression and to form an alliance with them on a minimal demand: we
believe that the teaching of philosophy in the "Premiere" could, under other
conditions (a transformation of its contents and of pedagogical practice, among
others), constitute a first positive component; but we demand that philosophy
be m?-intained as a requirement in the Terminale within a common core cur
riculum. These minimal demands are meaningful, of course, only within a
struggle for a uue overhaul of the teaching of philosophy-and of education in
general-an overhaul that alone is capable of imposing the idea that there is no
natural age for the practice of philosophy and that philosophy should already
be taught as early as the Seconde and in technical schools.
ple interests and phantasms have cooperated to construct this dogma and
to make it pass for common sense. Even if the value of intellectual matu
rity were not, at this level of generalization, more than suspect, even if
there were no way of proving, and in the most convincing way, under cer
tain conditions, the more than sufficient "maturity'' of pupils-not to men
tion their demand for philosophy-why is no one astonished by the fact
that disciplines equally "difficult" are taught from the sixieme on, and by
the fact that, in one way or another, so much philosophy seeps through
these other disciplines?
3 It is also said: since philosophy "forms-a-whole," a "structured-system
of-concepts," and so forth, its teaching must be global and be given in one
year. Without getting involved in the very difficult problem of such a
"systematic-totality," let's accept this hypothesis: But why, then, one year
(nine months)? Why this number of hours? (And how many? The num
ber varies from section to section, is being reduced incessantly, and tends
more and more to be interrupted.) Why not a month, a week, an hour,
the time of a single long sentence or of the wink of an eye? With a logic
just as respectfully subordinated to the aforementioned philosophical sys
tematicity, the severest ministerial compression can be supported. But the
same logic has another relay: if spread over several years, teaching would
be entrusted to "different instructors [maftres]," and this would in some
way damage the consistency of philosophical teaching. We are thus re
ferred to what is in fact a very classical concept of philosophical mastery
or magistrality. Let's call it, subject to analysis, Socratico-transferential.
Not only does it involve all sorts of risks (dogmatism, charismatism, and
so forth), it is not even in line with the critico-liberal ethics of the "tradi
tional defense." Logically, it should lead to the uninterrupted presence of
the same instructor in higher education (why not present the same request
there?), indeed one's entire life, a mentor, guide to wisdom, confessor or
director of conscience, the analyst for an interminable training. What,
then, is one afraid of when the unity of the philosophy-class or of the
teacher-of-philosophy comes into question?
4 Reservations were also voiced about the value of progressivity: Does
it not risk provoking an empiricist fragmentation or incompleteness? Or
reproducing the traditional teaching, merely making it less consistent,
more vulnerable to ideological corruption, exposed to dissolution into non
philosophical disciplines? Or extending the imperium of philosophy, in
deed, in this or that historico-political situation, of a philosophy, repro-
Divided Bodies I?I
clueing thus the very thing that must be transformed? This objection is
more interesting, and it is the only one that makes a certain labor possi
ble. It must therefore be specified that the value of progressivity belongs,
of course, to a very classical tradition of pedagogy. We must not welcome
it with tranquil assurance. Still less fetishize the word or slogan "progres
sivity." It is simply a question, in the very specific phase of a struggle and
a strategy, of winning acceptance for the extemion of the teaching of phi
losophy over several years, of making it coextensive with other subjects
taught, for which progressivity is accepted as completely "natural." By re
ferring to an established norm, we hope to take philosophy out of its nar
row pedagogical bounds and to justifY a demand (for class hours equiva
lent to those in the scientific or literary disciplines) . Once this legitimate
extension is acquired-at the price of a difficult struggle-other debates
will be sure to arise to define the contents and forms of the kinds of teach
ing, their structure, and the communications between them and the out
side of the academy. Greph's proposals concerning progressivity appeal
indissociably-to such transformations. Of course i under the pretext of
progressivity, an apprenticeship or even a training (whose ends remain
suspect) were reestablished, if the schools were to issue a "training" ori
ented like a progress toward the harmonious fulfillment of some telos,
whatever it be, we would, we will, certainly have to fight against such a re
appropriation, whose risk (or security) will always reappear. Other fronts
will emerge. But once philosophy is no longer the lot of one class, the
broadening of the field will make the work, the critical exchanges, the de
bates, and the confrontations more effective. This much at least is already
certain: to refuse the extension of the teaching of philosophy under the
pretext that the motif of "progressivity" does not resolve all the problems
and can be reappropriated by what is called the opposing camp is to give
credence to a mystifYing argument, whether or not it is advanced in good
faith. MystifYing and without future, it has been shown.
We must, on the contrary, work from now on to create the conditions
for an extension and transformation of so-called philosophical teaching.
We must open debates, fashion experiments, join with the greatest num
ber of instructors and students, not only in the "discipline" of philosophy,
and not only in school. The process is underway. We have more than one
symptom of it. And the ground for struggles to come is already laid out in
it. Whatever the immediate fate of the government plan, this regime can
not give itself a "system of education" that does not point out its own con-
Divided Bodies
tradictions in their most critical and manifest state. Critical and manifest
precisely because systematic and philosophical and because education there
becomes a more and more fateful stake. The regime will therefore have to
pretend to change systems every day or to have several alternative systems
always under construction: with a compulsive, convulsive bustle, as though
in the hurry of a final phase.
Question III: Beyond the simple and imufficient defeme ofphilosophy such as
it is, how do you think philosophy should be thought?
(I have askedfor the floor right away in order to say a ftw words-and I
think this is necessary-about the preparation, indeed, the premises ofthese Es
tates General. I do this, ofcourse, in my own name, as one of the members,
among many others, ofa planning committee whose working sessions were ab
solutely open and whose participants were even more numerous and diverse
than is suggested by the list asfirstpublished. As to whatpreceded andprepared
for today's meeting, we owe you some information or explanations. Those that I
willpropose toyou, from my own point ofview, are my responsibility alone and,
moreover, are my responsibility only insofar as I tookpart in the initial work.)
I73
174 Philosophy ofthe Estates General
the logic of such a situation. Knowing these paradoxes is our job. Thus, for
example, some of us had to be able and believed we were able to constitute
ourselves provisionally as spokespersons and act as responsible mediators, so
to speak, of the appeal that the Estates General would have in a certain
sense launched in its own direction and to which certain of us would have
been the first to answer. It was indeed necessary, in effect, that certain
among us be able to meet, claiming to perceive, understand, and translate
in theirfashion a first appeal. From that point on, they thought they ought
to take what is called the initiative or the responsibility for the organization
of the Estates General. In part-which was at times a heavy part-this or
ganization remained technical and neutral. But this could only be a part,
and it would be frivolous and dishonest to deny that. An interpretation
and certain expectations were already at work, and it is on this subject that
I would like to venture a few statements. They are brief and schematic, and
thus all the more open to discussion.
The planning committee merely tried-this was one of its rules and I
believe I can attest to it-to translate in a faithfUl way the signs of a broad
virtual consensus.
To be sure, the members of the committee had their part in this con
sensus; they themselves gave proof of this, whatever may elsewhere have
been their philosophy of the Estates General, their philosophy of the con
sensus or the signs, indeed their philosophy of philosophy.
To do justice to the conditions of this virtual accord, they tried to re
spect the differences, even the fundamental disagreements [diffirends] that
could in another context divide all those who would be gathering here.
The shared and implicit certainty was, it seems to me, the following: in
the present situation, this consensus could only be affirmed as such, could
only be put forward as such in practical, effective, and efficacious under
takings to the extent that it made itself by rights independent of the con
stituted agencies I have just named, whether they be pedagogical, profes
sional, corporative, syndicalist, or political, et caetera (and under that "et
caetera," you could list whatever individual or group might be tempted to
use these Estates General as a base, studio, or staging ground). That these
agencies might also, in another context, be able to claim competency, legit
imacy, even-there is still time-efficacy in this or that specific domain,
no one will disagree. It is possible and normal that many among us feel
represented by these organizations and that we say so even here. It is desir
able-for obvious reasons to which I will return in a moment-that the
Philosophy ofthe Estates General 175
proposals the Estates General will be led to make tomorrow should receive
the approval and then the support of such organizations. It is more than
desirable, of course. But it does not seem to me desirable that, de facto or
by decision, our proposals be subordinated, even implicitly, to the agree
ment of these organizations. For them as for us, freedom and indepen
dence should be, it seems to me, total. This is even the condition of the
possible alliances of solidarity which I would consider, for myself and within
certain limits, indispensable.
Why? Because the consensus, to give it that name, seems to exceed con
siderably the borders of these legitimate organizations; it does not find it
self to be strictly or fully represented there, particularly as concerns that
which demands an emergency transformation of an unacceptable situation.
This consensus, if it is to exist, seems to take shape beyond a certain num
ber of philosophical or politico-ideological divisions.
Is this to say that it remains philosophically neutral or apolitical? Not
at all.
It corresponds no doubt to a new position taking, to a new philosoph
ical and political taking sides, even if such a taking sides no longer recog
nizes itself in the reproduction of codes and still less in common stereo
types. This reproduction would be, on the contrary, the most visible and
the most sinister mark of the limits within which some would like to en
close philosophical debate-the debate for philosophy or as to philosophy
(in it, around it, inside and outside its institutions)-limits within which
some would like to leave us to fight among ourselves and which we want
to tear down.
One may want such a consensus, if it exists or if it is still to come, to be
very broad, but it will not be unanimity or a general will. It would rather
be a matter today of a broad front and another front. At stake perhaps is
what has been called in the tradition we know so well "the need of philos
ophy'' or "the interest in philosophy."
Interest in philosophy, interest of philosophy: this does not designate
the particular taste for a type of exercise, an expertise, or a discipline, the
specialist's vocation, or a cult that is respectful to the point of frightened
fetishism for everything that has the name philosophy, for the philosoph
ical tradition, or even for a philosophy. The interest in philosophy, ifthere
is any, is an affirmation that ofitself, in itself, knows no limit. If there is
any interest in philosophy, it is not conditioned. That is, perhaps, what we
must attempt to think here.
1 76 Philosophy ofthe Estates General
legitimate, and registered body, whatever it may be. If the Estates General
of 178 9 broke with those that preceded them, it was because they inaugu
rated something by proclaiming themselves a national and then a consti
tutional assembly, putting radically in play the order or the orders that had
previously constituted them. If there was an event, it was on the order of
this eminently philosophical project of self-foundation, which has its ini
tiative only in itsel without any reference to prior guarantees, hierarchies,
or legitimacies.
I do not know whether, for philosophy, this gesture has a meaning or a
chance today (and at least for the moment, here, I am not going to venture
to discuss the bases of this problem) . I believe, however, in fact I know
that, mutatis mutandis, such an idea, the principle of an analogous ambi
tion, is audible in the Appeal for the Estates General of Philosophy.
For example, the word "affi rmation'' lets it be heard at least three dif
ferent times.
Now if, over the next two days and beyond these two days, we are not to
lose sight of any of the concrete givens, the conjunctura! premises, the em
pirical and tactical necessities of our action, the constraints of all sons with
which we must reckon even in detail, then we will only be able to do so
and it will only be worth doing if measured by what I will call traditionally
the Idea, the great principle that comes to be affirmed in the Appeal.
While we hear and understand this affirmation, it is not certain that we
all hear it in the same manner. Because it is not dear. In a certain manner,
it had to be that way. A certain enigmatic reserve had to remain, one that
must not be confused with an equivocation to be manipulated. This re
serve comes, perhaps, from what remains essentially undecided today in
the destination of philosophy.
The signs of this indecision are concentrated in the prologue of the Ap
peal. There is, for example, no indecision in the brief demonstration called
''A Tableau Noir" or in the minimal demands formulated in "To Begin
With." What is schematically but dearly brought together in these two
documents seems to me to derive from objective and statistical demonstra
tion. It is indisputable that philosophical teaching and research are declin
ing and will continue to decline in an accelerated manner until they reach
atrophy and irreversible asphyxia if the devices put in place by the present
government, by those that preceded it, and by the forces, fractions, or al
liances of forces that support them are allowed to take over the stage. It is
indisputable that this process-which signals a serious danger not only for
Philosophy ofthe Estates General 1 79
philosophy but for the whole of the educational system and of society
will only be interrupted on the conditions we define, at least for the short
and medium term: for example, an increase in the number of instructors
and therefore of students and researchers; a redefinition of the "needs" and
a minimal staffing per class; the minimal schedule of four hours for all ly
cee students in all categories; the retention of philosophy and of philoso
phy professors in the ecoles normales d'instituteurs: the extension of the
second cycle and outside philos
teaching of philosophy to every year of the
ophy departments in the university- extension with all of its consequences,
which are not limited either to philosophy or even to education. This last
demand- extension -is legitimate, vital, decisive, and the impressive num
ber of those who subscribed to this Appeal, as well as of those who are par
ticipating or are represented at these Estates General, allows one to measure
the distance traveled since the moment certain people pretended to judge
this extension utopic or dangerous. There is nothing in the two documents
accompanying the Appeal that cannot be demonstrated. If we want to be
consistent, we will attach to them-resolutely, despite whatever happens
our uncompromising demands and clear-cut determinations.
Naturally, this demonstrative character, this recourse to the most stub
born objectivity, could not characterize the Appeal itself, in particular its
prologue. This was, it seems to me, neither possible nor desirable. There,
an affirmation is put forward, and an affirmation is not demonstrative in
the same way. It commits, it decides, it pronounces-in this case, forphi
losophy. Yes to philosophy.
But it can today no longer do that in one stroke, a simple and indivisi
ble stroke. We are no longer young enough, neither is philosophy, for such
a militant affirmation on our part to be simple, lighthearted, unruffled,
fresh, and untried. If there is reason to reaffirm, it comes at a very singu
lar moment, overburdened with history-the history of philosophy, of this
society, of its institutions, and of its pedagogical structures.
We do not forget all the water that has flowed under the bridge called
philosophy. It has been a long time since we were ready to be taken for a
ride, on whatever boat, and we're not about to treat yesterday's rainwater
as something fallen from heaven, especially when it's the old trick of ap
pealing to the purest and most archaic source. A vigilant, rigorous mem
ory, one critical of this history of philosophy, does not necessarily imply
that the affirmation I am talking about must be weighed down or broken
with age. It can, at least if it has the strength, be just the opposite.
!80 Philosophy ofthe Estates General
The result is that the Appeal opens with an affirmation and an indeci
sion. It thus does not have the same demonstrative character as the two
succeeding documents. Whence certain questions, which I would like to
try to answer.
The prologue of the Appeal has a somewhat optimistic resonance, even
(why deny it?) a triumphant one. It alleges a certain number of signs that
could attest to the life, youth, and diversity of the demand for philosophy
in this country and throughout the world. Some of us were bothered by
this (among those who approved overall our gesture and even among those
who, like myself, took a, let us say, active part in the drafting of this text).
What bothered them? A certain formulation that might lead one to believe
all these signs were cause only for rejoicing, notably the signs coming from
the publishing industry (by which I mean in general), the written and spo
ken press (in general), the television industry (in general).
Now, i t goes without saying (we know this only too well) that things are
far from being that simple. Today no one, either among philosophers who
are somewhat aware or among those who have a little experience of the
world and have developed some discernment in these areas (publishing,
press, television), would dare testifY to philosophical vitality or rigor by
invoking a large part, we can say the major part, of what has been exhib
ited recently on the stage that is most in the public eye, of what noisily
proclaims itself to be philosophy in all sorts of studios, where, as of a rel
atively recent and very determined date, the loudest speakers have seen the
loudspeakers entrusted to them without wondering (in the best of cases)
why suddenly they were being given all this space and all this air time in
order to speak thus and say precisely that.
If one thinks of what dominates the scene or the market, of what so of
ten (I do not say always, for one would, of course, have to refine, differen
tiate, multiply the types of analysis, which is what I hope we will begin to
do here) can be produced there and can invade everything with its naive,
precritical paucity of thought, ignorant to the point of barbarity, smug and
gloating to the point of buffoonery, or even, for us, for me in any case, un
forgivably boring-if one thinks of all this, then one may indeed be both
ered by the appearance of using it as an argument to prove that philosophy
is booming. Such was simply not the intention of the drafters of the Appeal.
Here, in a few words, is the principle of the analysis that convinced me,
for my part, to subscribe to this Appeal and to take part in drafting it in
this form. To be sure, this form is not perfect; by necessity, it is too brief,
Philosophy ofthe Estates General 181
elliptical, simplifying. I will not defend i t for itself o r the letter o f it, but
only its implicit logic. What is more, the Appeal was not meant to com
mit the Estates General to anything in advance or to be approved by them
a priori; it is right here that it will be submitted to discussion.
In the first place, it was, as you may well imagine, for us not a matter of
applauding the content and the quality of all these equivocal signs, notably
those that snore or rattle away on the front page of the newspaper or on
television. No one is asking for that, and nothing in the Appeal seems to
me to invite that. This said, these are signs or symptoms that we would be
wrong to neglect, whose scope must be interrogated from all angles, which
is to say, from angles and according to criteria and modes of questioning
for which we are not all equally prepared. The intra-philosophical (others
would say the properly philosophical) criteria, which, when our sense of hu
mor is on the blink, might often dictate the most ruthless-in fact the
most somber and desperate-evaluations when we read or hear this or that
performance, these criteria concerning the philosophical quality of such
messages no doubt do not provide the essential measure of what is hap
pening-and even what is happening with respect to philosophy. In the
wake of all sorts of transformations or upheavals in the sociology of edu
cation and outside education, in the ideological and philosophico-policical
landscape of this country and of the world, in the technology of informa
cion, the recourse to something that still resembles philosophy manifests it
self largely in social spaces, in forms and according to norms that largely
overflow the space of professional competence, which, moreover, has never
been above suspicion in this regard and which also possesses, let us not for
get, the old form of powers of evaluation, promotion, selection, and even
its little pocket "media"; it thus possesses powers, very concentrated pro
fessional and editorial levers, whose critical analysis we ought not to per
form sparingly or with indulgence. Who can seriously regret that this space
of professional competence .has been overwhelmed; and along with it the
social space that traditionally supplied the majority of philosophers by pro
fession in France?
Such a regret would be not only sad, reactive, negative, it would also be
totally in vain. This process is and must be irreversible. But it does not ex
cuse us from asking ourselves what are the profound and multiple condi
tions of this enlargement and of the strange effects it is in the process of
producing. It would be a serious mistake on our part to ignore the fact
that when we are often shocked or made indignant by certain of these ef-
!82 Philosophy ofthe Estates General
ity-the latter word refers to a judicial code that I do not like and it is not
at all a matter here of incriminating anyone whatsoever. What is more, no
one is purely and simply external to this process, even if no one occupies
the same place there-far from it, and fortunately so. A profound com
plementarity, therefore, between an unqualifiable repression of philosoph
ical teaching and research, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the
frantic overexploitation, outside the academy, of philosophical signs and
discourses whose weakness, facileness, convenience are the most glaring
but also, for the big decision makers, for the great deciding forces of our
society, the most acceptable, the most useful, and the most reassuring. One
could show that cohabitation can be very harmonious today between, for
example, what remain of petty, reactive philosophical powers within edu
cational institutions, of uptight, ossified academicism still clutching the
control levers on the one side, and, on the other side, outside the institu
tion, the big philosophical theme parkand the amnesiac, gossipy stereo
types that run wild under more or less anonymous, discreet, but effective
supervlSlon.
These two types of power neither contradict each other nor get in each
other's way in the least, for a reason. Each conditions the other.
For my own part, these last years I have been very aware that the publi
cations billing themselves as philosophy and benefiting, not by chance,
from the most diligent and effective, the most assiduous, promotional sup
port, that the publications most likely to be accepted, let us say, are also the
most devoid of, the most exempt from, any question, even more so, any
critical problematic concerning the official politics of education, the educa
tional and university systems, the publishing and telecommunication sys
tems, the rhetorical normativity controlled by these systems, which is to say,
above all, that the majority of said publications reproduce outside the acad
emy the most well-behaved scholarly models. There is here a solid com
plementarity (although it may sometimes be difficult to read) between the
most immobilized, uptight academicism and all that which, outside the
school and the university, in the mode of representation and spectacle, plugs
almost immediately into the channels or networks with the highest accept
ability. It is this complementarity, this configuration-wherever it ap
pears-that one must, it seems to me, combat. One must combat it simul
taneously, joyously, without accusation, without putting on trial, without
nostalgia, with an uncompromising gaiety. Without regret for the more
padded forms that were sometimes (only sometimes) more distinguished,
Philosophy ofthe Estates General
less rowdy, and that will have in part prepared yesterday what we are inher
iting today. In part at least-let us discern.
One last word, if you do not mind. I just said "uncompromising."
Well, an affirmation, if there is any, must affirm something uncompro
mising, that is, not negotiable, intransigent. Affi rmation, if there is any, is
unconditionaL
During these two days and thereafter, through that which, we must
hope, will assure almost everywhere in France a sort of permanent active
duty of these Estates General until there can be another large meeting, it
will no doubt be necessary to undertake actions, transactions, complex,
careful, persevering, minute negotiations with all the interested parties
official, governmental, and even presidential agencies, labor unions and
corporative associations, whose support will be essential to us. We will have
to define carefully, in all areas, the objectives and the stakes of these nego
tiations and consultations, as well as their margins.
But we ought also to formulate uncompromisable, nonnegotiable de
mands. No affirmation without that. Such would be the philosophy of the
Estates General. And along this line of the nonnegotiable, which we also
ought to trace very concretely (proposals will be made in this direction),
the Estates General should, in my opinion, reach decisions in an abso
lutely unconditioned, autonomous fashion, and invent, so as to accede to
this, collective or individual modes of action, intervention, resistance that
are its own; one must hope-for nothing will be possible without this sol
idarity-that these will play an avant-garde role and will set an example to
be followed, not only but especially for corporative, labor union, and po
litical organizations.
It has already happened.1
(I yield the floor to Roland Brunet. A moment ago I said that the Es
tates General should belong to no one, be beholden to no one, and I reit
erate that. But, perhaps I will contradict myself by saying nevertheless that
without Brunet I doubt that these Estates General could have taken place,
whether we are talking about the "idea'' or the planning of this event. Sev
eral of us here could testify to this.)
Appendix
Appeal
The demand for philosophy has never asserted itself in a more lively,
youthful, and diverse way. It is everywhere on the move and everywhere it
gets things moving, in this country, but also, as recent orientation discus
sions at UNESCO remind us, throughout the world. Whether or not we
are philosophers by profession, we can testifY to this and recognize in it a
vital necessity. This surge is literally overwhelming: it manifests itself, in
effect, through new forms, beyond institutional partitions and academic
criteria, in social circles and age groups that have been kept away from it
until now. The demonstration is breaking out everywhere-in schools
and in the university, in the most diverse kinds of teaching (technical, lit
erary, scientific, j uridical, medical, and so forth), bur also, in a daily fash
ion, in the life of publishing, in the press, on radio and television, in all
artistic practices, in the debate over the fundamental directions of society,
and so forth. Not only the philosophical tradition, bur the most novel and
adventurous research is everywhere being asked to intervene, to renew the
languages of analysis and criticism, or to open new roads for reflection.
And those who are undertaking to do so are more and more numerous,
even when they do not practice philosophy as a profession.
Between this extraordinary boom and the official politics of education,
the contrast is frightening. The government continues to pur in place plans
that would implacably condemn philosophical teaching and research. We
already have withdrawal and atrophy. If we sat back and did nothing, to
morrow things would be more or less dead. Bur we will not sit back. The
I86
Philosophy ofthe Estates General
A Tableau Noir
A demonstration is in order and it is easy to do: if left to itself, present
policy will see to it that philosophy has the most dismal of futures. We
must gather together here a few givens that those in power try to force
into oblivion or to disperse in the shadows. We recall that the law to re
form the educational system (called the "Haby Reform''),3 passed in June
1975, set out only a general framework and some pedagogical principles.
As for the content of secondary instruction, discipline by discipline and in
the hourly distribution, this has been in large part-and at the insistent
demand of the government-left to regulatory bodies. It is thus by im
plementing decrees that the fate of philosophy will be decided in second
ary education. Of course, the consequences of this will make themselves
felt, inevitably, in university teaching and research. The question of phi
losophy cannot, to be sure, and ought not to be treated independently of
188 Philosophy ofthe Estates General
the general economy of a reform. But, to the extent that, for the moment
(and, we hope, provisionally), this reform is imposed on us by law, we find
ourselves forced to struggle als-o-and we will do so without ceasing-in
the limited and preordained field of implementing decrees. How does this
field look?
To Begin With
In the immediate, concerning either teaching or research, the catastrophic
process of this dismantling will be interrupted only under the following
conditions. They represent a vital minimum:
I. An increase in positions competed for, in accordance with an immedi
ate redefinition of needs, based on the maximum number of twenty-five
students per class. This demand has been around for twenty-five years, and
its pedagogical soundness is universally recognized, including by the min
isterial services.
2. A required minimum schedule of four hours of philosophy for all stu
dents, whether they are in classical or modern, technical or professional
lycees.
3 The retention of the positions of the professors of philosophy pres
ently teaching in the ecoles normales.
In the medium-term, in order to respond to demand and to needs, the
teaching of philosophy will have to be extended to the whole second cycle
in the lycees, inclusive from the Seconde to the Terminale (with the possi
bility of modif}ring the schedule in the Terminale) and to all lycee students,
including those in professional lycees.9 As several recent experiments have
demonstrated, this extension is possible and necessary. It corresponds not
only to aptitudes, but to a wide and deep demand among students who are
not yet in the Terminale. This has been verified, just as one may also ob
serve such a demand for philosophy instruction at the university coming
from students or researchers specialized in other areas. This demand may
also be felt outside the educational system. Such an extension should be ac
companied by a redefinition of content and methods. It has nothing to do
with the caricature represented by the introduction of philosophy in the
Premiere in the abandoned version of the Haby plan.
But beyond this fight for survival, as it has been imposed on us by the
Philosophy ofthe Estates General
R. Brunet M. Hocquet-Tessard
(Lycee Voltaire, Paris) (Doc. Ecole Normale,
D. Cahen Bonneuil)
(Eco. Pol., Paris) V. Jankelevitch
F. Chatelet (Universite de Paris-I)
(Universite de Paris-VIII) H. Joly
J. Colombe! (Universite Grenoble)
(Lycee Herriot, Lyon) G. Kaleka
Ch. Coutel (Lycee Pothier et IREM,
(Lycee de Lievin) Orleans)
G. Deleuze G. Labica
(Universite de Paris-VIII) (Universite de Paris-X)
J. Derrida Ph. Lacoue-Labarthe
(Ecole Normale Superieure) (Universite Strasbourg)
J .-T. Desanti M. L. Mallet
(Universite de Paris-I) (Lyce Recarnier, Lyon)
E. de Fontenay J.-L. Nancy
(Universite de Paris-I) (Universite Strasbourg)
F. Godet P. Ricoeur
(Lycee Technique Vauban, (Universite de Paris-X)
Courbevoie) H. Vedrine
B. Graciet (Universite de Paris-I)
(Lycee de l'Isle-Adam)
Philosophy ofthe Estates General
The Estates General are to take place beginning June 16 at the Sor
bonne. More detailed information will be available later. We will gladly
welcome all proposals. Signatures and in general correspondence should be
addressed to: Roland BRUNET, 11, rue Massenet, 94120 Fontenay-sous-bois
(tel.: 875-34-21) . Financial support: to the same person, CCP: Lyon 5645
58-Y. SpecifY (For the Estates General of Philosophy) . You can also help us
by photocopying this text and distributing it.
Privilege
A number of notes in the French original were provided by Elizabeth Weber.
They are noted below by the designation EW.-Trans.
r. Right to Philosophy was first of all the title of a seminar I gave beginning in
I93
194 Notes to Pages 3-4
ciology of knowledge or culture, from rhe history of rhe sciences or pedagogical insti
tutions, from rhe politology of research. But beyond an epistemology of rhese 1m owl
edges, we will begin to situate rheir professionalization and rheir transformation into
disciplines, rhe genealogy of rheir operative concepts (for example, "objectification,"
"legitimation," "symbolic power," and so forrh), rhe history of rheir axiomatics, and
rhe effects of rheir place in rhe institution.
In this too general space, under rhe title Right to Philosophy, are sketched out two
concurrent trajectories:
r. The study of juridical discourse, which, wirhout occupying rhe foreground,
founds philosophical institutions. What are its relations wirh social, historical, or po
litical fields? Wirh rhe structures of rhe "modern state"?
2. The study of rhe conditions of access to philosophy, language, teaching, research,
publishing, philosophical 'legitimacy." Who has a right to philosophy? Who holds its
power or privilege? What, in fact, limits rhe alleged universalism of philosophy? How
does one decide rhat a rhought or statement can be accepted as "philosophical"? Even
if this network of questions is not distinguished from philosophy itself (if such a rhing
exists and claims to be unified), one can still study in specific contexts rhe modalities
of rhe determination of rhe "philosophical," rhe divisions it implies, rhe modes of ac
cess reserved for rhe exercise of philosophy: systems of teaching and research in which
philosophy is offered as a principal or secondary discipline, extra-scholastic or extra
university circles, verbal "supports," wherher in books or not. The question of a "sup
port" (speech, book, journal, newspaper, radio, television, cinema) is not purely tech
nical or formal. It also affects content, rhe constitution and modes of rhe formation or
reception of rhe rhemes and statements, of rhe corpus of philosophy. Are rhese rhe
same once rhey are no longer given, dominated, and accumulated, in rhe form of an
archive of books, in specialized institutions, by subjects or communities of aurhorized
and supposedly competent "guardians"? We will begin wirh numerous signs of a mu
tation rhat has been underway since rhe nineteenrh century at least and in a more ac
celerated fashion over rhe last two decades.
The main rheme for rhis preliminary approach: rhe example of the College Inter
national de Philosophie. Is rhis a new "philosophical institution"? The multiple possi
ble interpretations of its origin, its conditions of possibility, its destination.
2. Rectitude, rectilinearity, the "straight path": we know what role these val
ues (which are, moreover, also implied in those of the norm or rule) have played
in the axiomatics of numerous methodologies, in particular that of Descartes.
[On this subject, see J. Derrida, "La Langue et le discours de la methode," in Re
cherches sur fa philosophie et fe langage, no. 3, La Philosophie dans sa langue (Gre
noble: Universite de Grenoble 2, 1983).-EW.]
3 Having often dealt with this law of the title, notably in the space of literary
works, I will refer to "Devant la loi" (1982) in La Facufte dejuger (Paris: Minuit,
1985), as well as to "Survivre" (1977), "Titre a preciser," and "La Loi du genre"
(1979), in Parages (Paris: Galilee, 1986). ["The Law of Genre" and "Before the
Law" appear in Acts ofLiterature, ed. Derek Attridge (New York: Routledge,
1992).-Trans.]
Notes to Pages s-2I 19 5
elected President) appointed Minister for the Budget in 1981. In 1983 he became
Minister oflndustry and Research. Jack Lang rose within the Socialist Parry in the
late 1970s and was appointed Minister of Culture by Mitterand in 1981. Roger
Gerard Schwarrz.enberg was Secretary of State for the Minister of Education from
1981 to 1986.-Trans.
14. From this (in fact very philosophical) point of view, one would presume
the pUiity or the untouchable indivisibility of such a limit, the limit that ensUies
the division between the philosophical itself, philosophy properly speaking and,
stricto semu, its "business," on the one hand, and, on the other hand, everything
outside it, however close. This is what was behind Georges Canguilhem's polem
ical but essential (in fact rigorously essentialist) argument in the clear and vigor
ous response he made to questions from the Nouvelle Critique when the Haby
Reform plan menaced: "To this point, many arguments invoked by most of those
who have come to the rescue of philosophy without neglecting to put themselves
in the spotlight have missed the mark either because of their desire for publicity
or because of their routine return to worn out themes. . . . In short, defending
the teaching of philosophy, that is, inventing its renewal, is not a matter of one
sector. Mr. Haby's entire reform is in question. Philosophy does not need any de
fenders, insofar as its own justification is its very business. But the defense of the
teaching of philosophy would require a critical philosophy of teaching" (Nouvelle
Critique 84 [May 1975]: 25; see also 239). Let this be said in passing: in 1975,
whether its author intended it or not, this final phrase defined at least one part
of the project of Greph, which had never been undertaken in France to thatpoint
by any official (individual or collective) representative ofFrench philosophical imti
tutions. Therefore, how could one not subscribe to it? And how could one not
subscribe (this was also one of the principal themes of Greph) to the sentence
opposing the "sectorization" of this debate?
That being said, the distinction between philosophy's "business" in its self-jus
tification and "the critical philosophy of teaching" seems to me to be of the most
problematic kind. Not only because it contradicts the critique of "sectorization,"
but because what is "proper" to philosophy is the name of the problem that this
affirmation assumes it resolves. This is what is at stake (I no longer dare say it is
the stake "itself" or the "very'' stakes), one of the inevitable stakes, of deconstruc
tionist thinking. Although "deconstruction"-which has never been a doctrine or
a teachable knowledge as such-has never been called to constitute the charter of
any institution, in particular of a group as open and diverse as Greph, this group
could not, in any case, take such a paralyzing distinction between philosophy's
"business" and a "critical philosophy of teaching" as its rule. In its research and
open struggles (that is to say, necessarily-and fortun ately-public, which does
not mean "publicizing," struggles) and in the very Uigency of these struggles (it is
not for nothing that they sought the withdrawal of the Haby Reform plan, to
Notes to Pages 25-42 197
take but this example), Greph undertook first of all to connect the two, philoso
phy's "business" and the "critical philosophy of teaching." Greph intends to dem
onstrate the necessity of this connection. As for the value of "critique," in the ex
pression "critical philosophy of teaching," I will rerum to it later.
15. "Popularities: From Law to the Philosophy of Law," forthcoming in Eyes
ofthe University: Right to Philosophy 2.-Trans.
r6. See, notably, "Signature Event Context," in Margim ofPhilosophy, trans.
Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), pp. 30r3o, and Limited
Inc (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1988), pp. r-24.
17. As for the passage evoked above, I refer here to the Garnier-Flammarion
edition of Diogenes Laertius, Vie, doctrines et sentences des philosophes illustres,
trans. R Genaille, 1: 242 ff. and n6 ff. [English translations are retranslated from
the author's citations.-Trans.]
r8. I refer again to OfSpirit: Heidegger and the Question.
19. In the seventh of the Addresses to the German Nation, Fichte develops an
argument of this type. See "La Main de Heidegger (Geschlect II)," in Psyche,
pp. 416-r8.
20. This question of idiom was at the center of a seminar I gave over several
years on Nationality and Philosophical Nationalism, which was the necessary de
velopment of the 1983-84 seminar (Right to Philosophy) whose outline or schema
I follow here. I hope to be able to prepare this seminar for publication later.
21. These quotes are from the French Universal Declaration ofthe Rights of
Man (1791).-Trans.
22. See R Balibar and D. Laporte, Le Franrais national: Politique etpratique de
Ia langue nationale sot/S !a Revolution (Paris: Hachette, 1974); M. de Certeau, D. Ju
lia, and J. Revel, Une politique de Ia langue: La Revolution franraise et les patois
(Paris: Gallimard, 1975); R Balibar, L1nstitution dufranrais: Essais sur le colinguisme
des Carolingiens a Ia Republique (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1985).
23. I have attempted elsewhere to expose this topology of the "chiasmic in
vagination of borders," notably in Parages.
24 "Coercion" here translates contrainte ("constraint") in order to follow the
English translation of Kant more closely.-Trans.
25. See "The Pupils of the University: The Principle of Reason and the Idea of
the University," forthcoming in Eyes ofthe University: Right to Philosophy 2.-Trans.
26. The Terminale is the final year of the French lycee before srudents take the
state exam, the baccalaureat.-Trans.
27. See "Mochlos" and "Theology of Translation," forthcoming in Eyes ofthe
University: Right to Philosophy 2.-Trans.
28. [See Jacques Derrida, "The Politics of Friendship," in journal ofPhiloso
phy 85, no. ro (November 1988): 632-44.-EW] See also The Politics ofFriend
ship, trans. George Collins (New York: Verso, 1997).-Trans.
Notes to Pages 42 -45
29. In the heading to this section, en direct means not only "direct" but "live,"
as in a live radio or television transmission, for example.-Trans.
30. See Austin, "The Meaning of a Word," in Philosophical Papers (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1961), p. 55 See also Memoiresfor Paul de Man.
31. S'expliquer avec, not only "to explain oneself" but "to sort out" and even
"to have it out with."-Trans.
32. Within the limits of these introductory remarks, I cannot take up in itself
the very necessary debate that M. Villey opens-and immediately doses-in
particular in his Preface to the French edition of Kant's Metaphysics ofMorals,
trans. A. Philonenko (Paris: Vrin, 1979). The conclusions of this long Preface
would no doubt call for a long and meticulous discussion-and perhaps a gen
eral recasting of this immense problematic. They discredit without fUrther ado
the Kantian doctrine of right, as well as all the philosophical discourses that take
it seriously. "For us [jurists and philosophers of law] Kant's Rechtslehre, which
misses the point on the subject, the aims, the methods, and the instruments of
our work, is not a theory ofthe law. It marks the summit of a period of the for
getting of the philosophy of law. Kant believed he could speak to us about the
law (he was of course the victim of the German habits of the School of Natural
Right), while he did something else. If Kant believed he could constitute science
from principles, a priori foundations, as the mathematics ofright, he began with
a sort of non-Euclidean mathematics that is essentiallyforeign to ourjuridical expe
rience. Such is, at least, the reaction of one jurist historian of the law-who does
not really expect to be followed. There is no chance that philosophers will con
sent to take our critique of Kant seriously, if all they know of the law they have
learned by reading Kant, or Fichte, or Hegel, or other successors of Kant, in
cluding Kelsen. . . . No doubt, the success of the Rechtslehre can be explained in
its era. It could, at the beginning of the nineteenth century, have been of service
to a particular politics, the cause of state control, individualism, bourgeois liber
alism. But it has never been the purpose of either judges or the law to put them
selves in the service of a party," pp. 24-25.
33 This remark is developed in "Popularities: The Right to the Philosophy of
Law," forthcoming in Eyes ofthe University: Right to Philosophy 2.
34 Christian Garve, Vennischte Aufiiitze (Breslau: William Gottfried Korn,
1796), PP 352 f.
35 Kant, The Metaphysics ofMorals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cam
bridge University Press, 1996), pp. r4 I take this allusion to Logodaedalm as a
pretext to refer, as I should in every sentence, to two great books by Jean-Luc
Nancy that clear the way for so many discussions: Le Discours de !a syncope: I.
Logodaedalm (Paris: Flarnmarion, 1976) and L'Imperatifcategorique (Paris: Flam
marion, 1983). In the latter work, the fundamental article entided "Lapsus ju
dicii" must receive here a privilege to which I will return again later. On the pas-
Notes to Pages 45-55 199
sages from Kant that I eire or evoke at this moment, see in particular the chap
ter 'TAmbiguite du populaire et la science sans miel," in Le Discours de !a syn
cope, pp. 56 ff.
36. See "Popularities," forthcoming in Eyes ofthe University: Right to Philoso
phy 2.
37 Kant, The Metaphysics ofMorals, p. 25. The uanslation has been modified
slightly to approach Derrida's French translation more closely.-Trans.
38. Comcience, at once consciousness and conscience.-Trans.
39 These motifs have been developed elsewhere: that of stricture very exten
sively in Glas (Paris: Galilee, 1974); Glas, trans. John P. Leavey, Jr., and Richard
Rand (Lincoln : University of Nebraska Press, 1986), notably concerning Hegel's
Philosophy ofRight; that of the relations between being and the law, in the course
of a debate with Heidegger, in Memoiresfor Paul de Man.
40. Forthcoming in Eyes ofthe University: Right to Philosophy 2.
41. See note r6, above.
42. On the absolute autonomy of the faculty of philosophy according to Kant,
see "Mochlos." It isn't the jurist or the legal advisor as such who has the authority
to pronounce the law of law, the truth about the law, what is just and unjust. He
can do so no more than the logician can respond to the question "What is the
truth?" Having recalled this fact, Kant adds:
What is laid down as right (quidsit iuris), that is, what the laws in a certain place and
at a certain time say or have said, the jurist can certainly say. But whether what these
laws prescribed is also right, and what the universal criterion is by which one could
recognize right as well as wrong (iustum et iniustum), this would remain hidden from
him unless he leaves those empirical principles behind for a while and seeks the sources
of such j udgments in reason alone, so as to establish the basis for any possible giving of
positive laws (although positive laws can serve as excellent guides to this). Like the
wooden head in Phaedrus' fable, a merely empirical doctrine of right is a head that
may be beautiful but unforrunately it has no brain. (23)
43 "It would be a definition that added to the practical concept the exercise of
it, as this is taught by experience, a hybrid definition [Bastarderklii..rung] (defini
tio hybrida) that puts the concept in a false light" (19). In the Appendix to the In
troduction to the Doctrine of Right, "equivocal right" (ius aequivocum) is de
duced suiccly and calmly into its two kinds: equity (right without coercion) and
the right of necessity (coercion without right). What is the "foundation" of this
"ambiguity''?: "The fact that there are cases in which a right is in question but for
which no judge can be appointed to render a decision" (27). There is no use in
specifYing that what is played out in the following three pages is simply dizzying.
As was the allusion to the "exceptions" in the realm of virtue.
44 I refer once again to "Lapsus judicii" (in L1mperatifcategorique, notably
pp. 50-51). There, Nancy remarkably describes the lining or the doubling that
200 Notes to Pages ss-63
course on history. Text established by Georges le Roy. Corpus general des philo
sophes franc;:ais, Auteurs modernes, vol. 33 (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1948), p. 235.-EW.
II. Canivez, "Jules Lagneau," pp. 90-91.
12. Poser, at once "to pose" (a question, for example) and "to posit."-Trans.
13. The name for the arts class preparing the competitive examination for en
trance to the Ecole Normale Superieure.-Trans.
14. The Centre National de Recherche Sciencifique and the Fondacion Thiers
both provide positions for researchers who do not necessarily teach within the
framework of these institutions.-Trans.
15. When a collectivity subscribes to Greph's bulletin, we will ask this collec
tivity for the list of those of its members who desire affiliation with Greph.
16. The new statutes have since been passed.
I . The author here italicizes "Ia philosophie," indicating the unity and unique-
r. For this and all subsequent quotes from G. W. F. Hegel's letter "To the
Royal Ministry of Spiritual, Academic, and Medical Affairs," April 16, 1822, see
the Appendix to the present essay.-Trans.
2. Reference to the texts of the Philosophy ofRight of Berlin as well as to the
political scene of the epoch is a precondition for the minimal intelligibility of
this letter. We should therefore specifY immediately that it is becoming increas
ingly clear we must speak of the "Philosophies of Right" of Berlin. This multi
plicity is not simply a matter of revisions, versions, editions, or additions. It is
part and parcel of the complexity of the political situation in Berlin, of the over
determinations, stratagems, and occasional secrets of Hegel's political practice or
writing. Today we can no longer siniplify this multiplicity-as has often been
done to the point of caricature-no longer reduce it to the "Prussian State phi
losopher." As a preface to this letter, and in view of the reelaboration of all these
questions (the "Philosophies of Right," Marx's and Engel's relations to this entire
politico-theoretical aggregate, Hegel's effective political writings, etc.), I will in
dicate at least two absolutely indispensable discussions: Jacques d'Hondt's Hegel
et son temps (Berlin, 1818-31; rpt. Paris: Editions Sociales, 1968) and Jean-Pierre
Lefebvre's preface to his translation of La Societe civile bourgeoise (Paris: Maspero,
1975). See also Eric Weil, Hegel et l'Etat (Paris: Vrin, 1970) .
20 4 Notes to Pages n8-3o
It will also be necessary to read two other texts concerning teaching in the Gym
nasium and at the university. They are as yet little known and will be translated
soon. The first is the Report to Nietharnrner, Inspector General of the Kingdom
of Bavaria, on the teaching of the philosophical propaedeutic in the Gymnasium
(1812). This report constitutes a systematic and important ensemble regarding
what can be assimilated at one age or another, regarding the necessity to begin by
learning philosophical content rather than "learning to philosophize," concerning
the speculative; that is, "the philosophical in the form of the concept," which can
appear only "discretely" in the Gymnasium. The second is On the Teaching a/Phi
losophy at the University (text addressed to Pro Von Raumer, Governmental
Counsel of the Kingdom of Prussia, 1816). [These two texts later appeared in
translation in Philosophies de l'Universite: L'Idealisme allemand et fa question de
l'Universite (Paris: Payor, 1979), pp. 331 ff.-EW.]
3 The ENA (Ecole Normale d'Administration) is the training academy for
the French administrative elite.-Trans.
4 [Victor Cousin, La Defense de l'universite et de fa philosophie (Paris: Joubert,
1844), p. 123.-EW.] In addressing the correspondence between Hegel and Cousin
about all these questions (a correspondence reread, afi:er a manner, in Glas [Paris:
Galilee, 1974; English trans. John P. Leavey, Jr., and Richard Rand (Lincoln: Uni
versity of Nebraska Press, 1986)-Trans.]), I have analyzed, in the course ofwork
on the teaching body, the defense of philosophy, ideology, and the Ideologues,
Cousin's famous discourse, its content, and its political inscription. Parts of this
work will be published later. The same applies to certain writings from 1975 to
1976 about Nietzsche and teaching, Ecce homo, the political heritage of Nietzsche,
and-since I allude to it later-the question of the ear. [See Otobiographies: L'En
seignement de Nietzsche de fa politique du nom propre (Paris: Galilee, 1984); "Oro
biographies: The Teaching of Nietzsche and the Politics of the Proper Name,"
trans. Avital Ronell, in Jacques Derrida, The Ear ofthe Other (Lincoln: University
ofNebraska Press, 1988), r38.-Trans.] .
5 Destutt de Tracy, Observatiom sur le systeme actuel d'Imtmction publique
(Paris: Panckoucke) , 9: 2-3.
6. Cousin, La Difeme de l'universite et de fa philosophie, p. 136.
7 In French, ilse raconte, literally, "he narrates himsel"-Trans.
8. Hegel, Correspondance, val. 2, r8rJ-I822, trans. J. Carrere (Paris: Gallimard,
1963), PP 27o-7r.
9 Hegel, Briefi, val. 2, r8r;-r822, ed. J. Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Felix Meiner,
1953), appendices, p. 495
ro. Hegel to Duboc, July 30, 1822, in Hegel, Correspondance, 2: 285.
II. Once again, in order fUlly to fathom the complexity of this strategy, all the
constraints its ruse had to take into account, I refer to Jacques d'Hondt, Hegel et
son temps, particularly to the section "Les Demagogues" and to the chapter "Hegel
clandestin temps."
Notes to Pages Ip-s6 205
where the matter will already appear for itself and only its formal aspect need be
added; but this knowledge would have to be given only in a wholly historical man
ner, rather than projecting a modern contempt upon forms that (since Anselm
deleted) come from Catholic theology and even from ancient times, and which
have always been venerated."
25. Addendumfrom the rough draft: "Not as if I held none of the present text
books to be suitable, but because every book fair presents us with new compen
dia and I am not in the habit of following up this literature; in my experience
those that I have seen are nothing more than more or less elaborate repetitions of
the older manuals, augmented with useless innovations. Without attempting to
anticipate, in my view the entire aim and mode of this instruction would require
teachers to refer to previous textbooks, on the whole to those belonging to the
Wolffian School, with perhaps the single modification of replacing the Aristo
telian category-table by the Kantian.
I. The final years of lycee instruction before the baccalaureat are called "Sec
Divided Bodies
This essay first appeared in La Nouvelle Critique, 84-65 (May-June 1975). Re
printed in Greph, Qui a peur de Ia philosophie? (Paris: Flammarion, 1977)-EW.
I. Named for Valery Giscard d'Estaing, then President of France, and Rene
were subsequently dropped or never implemented. Two years later, the Socialist
Party and Franc;:ois Mitterrand were elected on a platform that specifically in
cluded several of the proposals of Greph and the Estates General concerning the
extension, rather than the curtailment, of the teaching ofphilosophy in second
ary schools.-Trans.
2. Blackboard, but also a black picture.-Trans.
3 Named after Rene Haby, then Minister of National Education.-Trans.
4 The second cycle refers to the final three years of pre-baccalaureat instruc-
tion, called respectively Seconde, Premiere, and Terrriinale.-Trans.
5 The administration of central education. There is an inspecteur d'academie
for each departement in France.-Trans.
6. National competitive exams that certifY for a teaching position in a lycee or
university. CAPES: Certificat d'aptitude professionelle d'enseignement second
aire.-Trans.
7 Each of the academies or regions of the French national education system
is administered by a Rector. It should be noted that agreges and those receiving
the CAPES are civil servants and, in principle, are guaranteed a teaching position
for the duration of their careers.-Trans.
208 Notes to Pages I90-92
8. The agregation and the CAPES exams are almost equally difficult and com
petitive; nevertheless, the first is considered more prestigious and carries with it
more privileges.-Trans.
9 In professional lycees, students complete what is known as the shon second
cycle. They do not do a Terminale year and they earn a professional degree (the
"brevet d'etudes professionelles") rather than the baccalaureat.-Trans.
IO. Cahiers de do!eances: the traditional name of the lists of grievances drafted