Eherenberg Democratia (Isonomia)
Eherenberg Democratia (Isonomia)
Eherenberg Democratia (Isonomia)
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Franz Steiner Verlag is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Historia: Zeitschrift fr Alte
Geschichte.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ABHANDLUNGEN
Origins of Democracy
The Greeks were the first political people in the history of mankind, for
they were the first to create States purely as communities of citizens in which
the administration and the making of policy were the right and the duty of
these citizens1. This is true of all the constitutional forms of Greek States;
but the rule of the majority, or indeed of the whole, of the free popu-
lation, was the final goal of Greek constitutional history - whatever its
J/orstufenwere since the days when the 067rAirat became the noAarat. It was
an ideal rather than a practicable goal; but if it could never be entirely
reached, it certainly could be and was accepted in principle. If it could never
mean that the whole people was actually governing (there would have been
nobody but non-citizens to be governed, as representative government had
not yet been invented), it did mean that every citizen had equal opportunity
of having in turn a share in the government. That is what we call demo-
cracy2. Any investigation into its beginnings will have chiefly to concentrate
on Athens, since only here a consistent and original example of democratic
government was set up, and at the same time we have only here the full
story, or at least something approaching it.
A constitution, unless it is imposed in a single action by some powerful
agent, has no fixed date of origin. It grows, and it will usually be possible to
mention several events which mark the progress of this growth. One or the
other of its stages may be regarded as the real act of foundation; but the
latest possible date would be the moment when the contemporaries them-
selves had found the final and significant name for the new constitution. In
our case, therefore, it can be said that democracy was in existence when
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
516 Victor Ebrenberg
people used that word to indicate the existing constitution. The use of the
word is a certain terminusante quem for the foundation of democracy; the
question is whether it is more than that. Perhaps we may say that with the
coining of the word democracy the idea of democracy had found its full
expression, and that earlier stages of the constitutional development which
had led to that final stage can have been only partial and imperfect reflections
of the idea. Thus I believe that the foundation and the naming of democracy
are at least near contemporaries.
By a strange coincidence, the origins of Athenian democracy, of its name
as well as its idea and meaning, have recently been the subject of indepen-
dent research from three very different points of view: that of the linguist,
that of the constitutional, and that of the social historian. All the three
articles have been published in one Festscbrift or another, and are thus more
or less hidden away3. This may be some excuse for taking up the question
again, but there are other more important reasons. The three articles,
however different in points of view and methods, come to similar results.
Professor Debrunner maintains that there is no evidence for the word
6r,uoxeaTta earlier than the middle of the fiftti century, but he admits the
possibility - unlikely though it seems to him - that it was older. Professor
Larsen concludes that #it was the Periclean age that dubbed Cleisthenes the
founder of Greek democracy<(, and that )>Periclean democracy has a special
right to the name<(. Professor Schaefer sees in the Cleisthenic reform and
the events of the following decades even down to Pericles no constitutional
issues at all, rather the struggles for power of individual aristocratic leaders
and their families. To him the specific and real conception of democracy
originated, in theory as well as in practice, as late as the time of the Pelo-
ponnesian War.
If I dare to challenge the chief common result of the three articles, a
comparatively late date for the origin of democracy, I naturally do so with
some trepidation. I feel, however, justified first because I have learnt a
great deal from the three authors; I have shared myself some of the views
they hold, and I still agree with a considerable part of their arguments
though less with Schaefer's than the two others'. Secondly and chiefly,
however, there is the fact that none of the three learned authors has used a
source which seems to me of outstanding importance. In Aeschylus' Supp-
liants we encounter the earliest picture, as far as we know, of the working
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 517
4. About the constituLtionof Chios (c. 6oo B. C.), see below, P. 538. Diodorus
(i.e. probably Ephorus') version of Tyrtacus' Eunomiawith the line (9) 6s,iov 6&nA '
'
VIM vjv xa XCa'LTOrIneaOat (xa'LTogbeing interchangeablewith XcDrog), which seems to
presuppose the conception of 6rjsoxLoarTa,cannot be genuine, although clearly referring
to the Rhetra. Cf. Hermes LXVlII (1933), 298, o, and Wade-Gery, CQ. XXXVIII
(I944), 3ff., differently Hammond, JHS. LXX (I950), 48f.
5. Part of the following article was read as a paper to the London Classical Society
on December 6th, 1950. I owe corrections and suggestions to points raised in discussion
bv Professors W. A. Laidlaw and T. B. L. Webster, and by Mr. G. Williams who also
let me read a forthcoming paper of his on *The Curse of the Alcmaeonidae* (to be
published in Hermathena).Prof. F. E. Adcock has read the proofs and acted as a very
helpful censor. The following investigation was partly foreshadowed by earlier articles
of mine; cf. the chapter *Die Generation von Marathon# in Os und West (I935), I27ff.;
RE., Suppl. VII, 2g93 f., also Oxford Class. Dictionary, z66.
6. Thus, e. g., Weil, W'ilamowitz,Gilbert Murray,Pohlenz, Kitto, Snell. All attempts
to pin the play down to a more accurate date havc failed. It was in the 70th Olympiad
(499-96) that Aeschylus for the first time competed with a tragedv (Suidas s. Pratinas),
and in 484 he won his first theatrical victory (Marm. Par.), but in either case we do
not know with which play. I believe that no convincing connection of the Suppliants
with contemporary events can be found, whether in Argos or anvwhere else. Against
a dependence of the lines 556ff. on Anaxagoras' explanation of the Nile flood, cf. W. Ca-
pelle, Neue JahrlbiicherXXXIII (I914), 340, and A. Korte, Phil. Wochenscbr.1929, 373f.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
518 Victor Ehrenberg
7. I cannot share the view frequently expressed (e. g., by W. Eberhardt,-Die Antike
XX I944, 96ff.) that the Suppliantssimplv reflect the conflict between the world of the
Polis as the world of order and moderation, on the one hand, and the barbarian and
savage world of Egypt, on the other.
8. Cf. B. Snell, Die Entstehungdes Geistes(I 946), 9 5ff.
9. J. Vurtheim, in his edition of the play (i928), 3.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origin:of Democracy 519
is in no way at the core of the play, it is the theme of its most dramatic
scene (344ff.), and it forms the essential background to the central problem,
the rights and duties of asylum'0. Moreover, the forms of democratic
government are needed to make Pelasgus' decision a responsible choice
rather than an arbitrary verdict. The political aspect is treated by the poet as
a matter of primary importance, in fact as a conflict of principles which is
being fought out between the king and the chorus. After he has told them
that the decision is with the people, the chorus replies with a passionate
appeal to the monarchical principle: a Thou art the State, thou the people 1
(370ff). This proclamation, as it were, of the fundamental principle of
absolute monarchy, the challenge of L'I8at c'est moi (or indeed toi), is
elaborated in an interesting manner. The king is called "rev'ravicJ.eFtrog.
The prytanis is a title preferably used for the highest State officials; but
Pelasgus, though he himself may feel as a mere prytanis, is in the chorus'
view much more than an official. He is not responsible to anybody, he is
tunjudged#, which means that he is not subject to any judgment; he is
therefore in a position truly opposite to that of a democratic official who is
always vt38rctvvogI".The king's iovot'Vppa ev'uazra, his will *voting alonec,
stand over and against the ~p5O9 IroAkwgl2. Pelasgus, sitting on the throne
monarchic ()wielding the sceptre aloneo), is called upon to fulfil all that is
needed and to avert pollution. He is supposed # to rule the altar, the hearth
of the country <; the sovereign power (xearvvetv, cf. 699) is naturally exer-
cised over the Polis as a religious community as well 3. Pelasgus is entreated
to use his full monarchical power to save the suppliants and to prevent the
violation of the sanctity of the altar. Later (423 ff.) practically the same con-
ception is expressed in even stronger terms when Pelasgus is addressed:
io. Cf. E. Schlesinger, Die griecb.Asylie (I933), esp. 4zfg. B. Daube, Zu den Rechis-
problemen in Aischylos' Agamemnon (0938?), 749f. Both books deal intercstingly, though
not always convincinglv, with thc legal aspects. This is also true of the book, written
from a wider philosophical angle, by E. Wolf, Griech. Rerch/denken1 (1950), 345 ff. I have
neither cause nor indeed competence to discuss the original (tribal?) foundations of
the legal question; cf. G. Thomson, Aeschylus and Athens (I 941), 298if.
iI. The expression nLoveTavic 6iXLlO is a similar kind of oxymoronas, for instance,
Aristotle's definition of the aisymnetia as a atLeQlT Tvveavvt (Pol. i285a, 31).
12. In Liddell-Scott-jones s. Aov6tpt7'oq, the passage is regarded as rcferring to
Zeus. But in the whole sccne, however frequently the chorus speaks of Zeus, the person
they directly address is always the king and nevcr the god (cf. in particular 359iff,
381i., 395f., 402ff.). It is clearly intentional that the king is addressed by words which
would equally well fit the highest god; cf. above all, 423-437, which I shall mcntion
presently, but here again the distinction between second person (king) and third person
(Zeus) is strictly maintained. The explanation is, of course, that the chorus views
monarchy in its most absolute form.
I3. Vurtheim, 185, is mistaken in his view that xeaTVVett flwjuov is an exaggeration
on the part of the chorus.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
520 Victor Ebrenberg
14. Thc same expression is used by Her. VII 3, 4, when he describes Atossa's
position.
IS. To assume the contrary was my erroneous view in Oxt und West, i31. It is,
however, by no means certain that this absolute monarchy is *oriental and #barbariane,
as is commonly assumcd. The Greeks saw also in the Persian king a despot not very
different from a Greek tyrant - a point of view w%hich only partially changed under
the impact of the Persian Wars.
i6. Therefore I do not quite agree with fH.G. Robertson, CP. L (I936), 107,
who sees behind the opposite forms of absolute monarchy and democratic leadership
the contrast of vpot and 6(xi7. Though a common thenmeof Greek political ethics
(and of Aeschylean too, as the Persacreveals), the issue in the Supplianit,both political
and religious, is different. See also notc 7.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 521
who may tell him (401): >>Inhonouring foreigners thou hast destroyed the
Polis <#.This is to come very close to the situation which brought democratic
statesmen in Athens to trial as, for instance, Miltiades in 489 on a charge of
aaTin TOV&4YuOV(Her. V I 36).
The evidence so far mentioned seems in general to a surprising extent to
conform to certain features of democratic Athens as we know them from
sources fifty or more years younger. But we have still to deal with the purely
constitutional issue. There can be no doubt that the whole affair is decided
by a decree of the people: &4juov&e'oxTat naVTEAx7 vMTVjuasra (6oI). The
same is stressed again and again, the Y*?0og'eAydwcOv (739),the 6quo'Qaxroq bc
no6kwcg5Vda 7os (942), the Tog of all the citizens (965). These are poetical
variations of the terms used in official language. We know that the early
style of Athenian prescripts had only g6OtE T1O&4uI17, and what the people
decided was called a rTpasya despite the fact that decisions of the assembly
had for a long time been arrived at by raising of hands, and not by Vpi7ot.
Even this is clearly reflected in the play. The chorus asks Danaus who
comes from the assembly (604): *Tell us in what way did 64uov xeaTroika Xeko
prevail? <1o.And Danaus replies that the voting was unanimous: *The air
was moved by the whole people proclaiming their decision with favourable
hands o (607)1'. And again (6zi): the people, after listening to Pelasgus'
speech, )cast their vote with their hands without a herald (who would
probably act as a teller when the voting was not unanimous) that it be so 4.
The modus of counting the votes had, at a comparatively early time,
generally replaced the cruder forms of acclamation such as still prevailed in
Sparta as late as the fourth century-0. If it was to be a secret voting it had to
be done by vispot, otherwise by show of hands. Both methods seem to have
been in use at least in the seventh century, and cheirotoniawas the normal
procedure in the Athenian assembly as early as Solon, if not earlier. In
elections of magistrates or councillors and also in the decision of popular
courts the counting of votes - one way or another - was a necessary
feature; though not limited to democratic constitutions, it was unlikely to
be used under a monarchic ruler, except for purely formal decisions and
possibly in court. As far as open ballot is concerned, it may not have been
17. Cf. the Salamis inscription (now SEG. X, i), and my paper JHS. LVII (1937),
149f.
I8. The second half of the line is corrupt, but the decisive words and thc general
meaning are quite certain.
I9. 1av6?tdq yde Xse'ai 6e$iwvVJuotq kpeiQrvaIOi) rdv6e ,coasvdvrcov U6yov. XQoaIvCo,
a favourite word with Aeschylus with the gencral meaning of 'to make valid', is
used in the Suppliantsespecially in the sense of casting a vote (cf. 6z2, 943). Cf. also
E. Fraenkel, Aesch. Agamti.II, I93f.
20. On voting procedure, cf. the article, comprehensive except for the evidence
from the Supplianis, by J. A. 0. Larsen, CP. XLIV (949), 164ff.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
522 Victor Ehrenberg
21. The whole passage contains unsolved difficulties and at least one certain cor-
ruption not yet finally emended: qpvAdaaot T'aTeEysala (? adTtlag and daTaMag cod.
dac6aena Wilam.) TIAC T6 6da',Uov, rd aT6ALV XeaTwvet, neoya0,.aEOViOtv6PTTtq aLoXa.
The meaning of the first line, whatever its exact wording, is clear from the scholiast's
awraxivi7To rtElev as)rolq ai Tutal, though it still remains to be said what at Ttgal are.
I believe they are neither *prerogatives # nor the position of magistrates, but the honours
due to guests, gods. and parents, according to the three OdacrtaJAx% solemnly invoked
in the following concluding lines (701 If.). Whether this is accepted or not, the words
with which we are chieflv concerned are simple and beyond doubt: *the people who
are the master of the city . It is less certain, though it seems the easiest solution, to assume
(with the scholiast as quoted by Vurtheim, but not in Dindorf's edition) that Td 6dayov
is the subject and dexd an apposition: *as a ruling body, neoauaOi; EvXo&vo'4wurts;. This
seems in essence - though not in the translation of Ttsat - also the view of Wilamo-
witz (Aisbhylos.Interpretaionen,.I. 39f.); but hc detects too much of constitutional
detail in the whole song. For Tucker in his edition (I889), the adxia is the Areopagus
(and the subject), and u3 6dpiov *the public watchcd over bv that Council ((; the corrlpted
passage then bccomes drlaw&t Ts,uaFg. This seems off the mark, and so was Palev
when he took dexa as the government vprotecting the people who arc the strength of
the state#. If the dexi is something to be distinguished from the 6d1uov, it is most
likely the position oc the king which was so important throughout the play. But can
we assume that the two elements, people and king, are mentioned side bv side, without
any connecting TC or xai? On the whole, I fcel, no satisfactory explanation has been
put forth for any phrase in which 3 6daytovis not the subject. Cf. also Bowra's translation
(Greek Lyric Poetry, 4 I 9). But though it might suit my general argument, I do not know
why Suppl.698 ff. should cxpress ) the notion of t'aovopia as the central idea of dcmocracy*.
22. This result is not refuted by v. 398, the passage already quoted, when Pclasgus
is urged to receive the suppliants in his country and to protect them; he repeats that
he must first ask the pcoplc: ov'x dvEv 6r7pOV Ta6E neQaty'dv, ov6 nee xearZv. ))I could
not act without the people, although I am the ruler. For the concessive meaning of
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 523
There may be some doubt left whether Aeschylus actually knew the
abstract word &yuo,xeadra,or perhaps only a phrase such as 3juog xpard,
which, however, would indicate a form of State in which the Demos was
exercising supreme power. Thus I believe that the two come essentially
to the same thing. The idea of democracy as well as an expression for this
idea, as confirmed by the passages mentioned, were known to the poet,
either in the shape of the final abstract noun or as a verbal phrase of virtually
the same meaning. I really think the former possibility is far more likely.
Prof. Debrunner (see note 3), without taking the evidence from the
Suppliants into consideration, has shown that the very words 6i7,uogceaTe',
and they alone, provide the exact meaning expressed in the abstract noun
when first used. According to him, 6nruoxeaTtawas the only possible word
to indicate government by the people, a word shaped after the abstract
nouns, already in existence at that time, indicating the rival forms of govern-
ment: ,uovaeLXaand o'AtyaoxLa.Of these, the former is used by Aeschylus
(Sept. 88I), but it was known as early as Alcaeus (I 19-22, 27); it is clearly
the earliest of the three, and the first to introduce a composite word in
which the first part referred to the subject, and not to the object, of govern-
ment23. To express the conception of the people's rule, r1tuaeXta was
impossible, as it was already used for the rule over, not by, the people24;
apart from that, even if it referred to the subject of government, it would,
just like monarchy and oligarchy, express the rule over somebody else,
and that could hardly be the idea of the word needed25. Thus, &juoxeaTta
was coined; it had no Grundwort, no 6?IIoxeaTs, but it was most fertile
ot36eoeecf., e.g., J. D. Dcnniston, The Greek Particles, 487. It is Pelasgus who rules,
though not without the consent of the demos. This is the democratic monarchy of the
myth, once more set against the absolute monarchy which is in the chorus' thoughts.
If it is not simply democracy, ic certainlv does not contradict it.
23. 1 am not quite convinced that Debrunner is right in dating &,qyoxLoatra later
than dA&yaexoa, or at least whether we can be sure about it. If I have rightly understood
his view, it would otherwise have been 6rjuoxoa're&a and not djyoxLcaTIa. But can the
ending not equally be influenced by povaexla? The form dA)yaexta,it is true, is directly
shaped after puovaeXta,and the rule of the faamAeig in Hesiod's time or that of the
noble clans in the seventh and sixth centuries may have been described by that namc;
there was no other yet, as far as we can tell. But was there a name at all at that time?
At any rate, we shall sec in the following section that the original opposites were tmon-
archyv and 4non-monarchv ; these opposites, whatever the name of the second, seem
carlier than the triad.
24. The 6r7,uaexog was a magistrate in early Chios (Tod, no. I, 3. 5. 26). Hcre as
well as in the later Athenian &76tuaexot,the men administering the local demes of Attica,
6inpoqis the object of rule.
25- We are used to the idea that democracy means that the people are ruled by the
people. But when the word 6njuoxeaTia was first coined, it cannot have included this
almost metaphysical meaning.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
524 Victor Ehrenberg
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 525
Democracyin Herodotus
In Greek political theory three chief forms of government are usually
distinguished, though their names vary to some extent. The most common
distinction is based on the numeral factor: monarchy, oligarchy, democracy
(demos standing for the majority). We have just been discussing some
aspects of the three words, and we also realised that one of the outstanding
features of democracy as depicted by Aeschylus was the predominant
contrast to only one other form of government, to the one man's rule.
This dualism within the triad emerges also from the earliest example extant
of a theoretical discussion on the subject of the best form of government,
the famous debate among the Persian nobles in Herodotus III 8o-8z. Al-
though there is a speech in favour of each of the three constitutions, Otanes in
praising democracy attacks only monarchy; Megabyzus attacks democracy,
but his plea for the rule of the detaot dv6ete is very brief and almost
negligible; finally Darius, while mentioning all three forms, treats oligarchy
because of the inevitable outbreak of rivalry and strife between its members
as a transitional phase only which inevitably leads to monarchy. The real
conflict is, in fact, between monarchy (or trannis) and democracy.
As in the Suppliants so in Herodotus the fundamental tendency seems
to be the opposition to monarchy. Whose opposition? I do not wish to
repeat in this context the word democracy, for if there are only two forms
of government, oligarchy must belong to one of them, and that can only
be the non-monarchical form. Moreover, Otanes never mentions the words
demos or democracy. Darius, on the other hand, speaks of the demos. He
actually - even twice - distinguishes three rulers rather than forms of
rule: ijC4oq, dALyaoXi,q,4uov'vaexo;(8z, i. 5). The lack of logic in this
tripartition is obvious. ) The key to the meaning is the use of monarch
and not monarchy (26, but, as I should like to add, in the mutual opposition
of monarch and demos. Oligarchy, awkwardly put in instead of the &tyot,
the small group of ruling men, looks very much like an afterthought.
The original dualism, once again, is recognisable, although it has grown
into the triad which had become the normal conception.
Herodotus is a late source as compared with the Suppliants.But he must
have had predecessors. He assures us that the story of the debate was Per-
sian, and he turns with some fervour against the scepticism of certain
Greeks. That shows that he told essentially the story which he had found
in his source. This source, written, of course, in Greek, had probably
transferred a Greek debate. - or at least arguments based on Greek condi-
tions and expressed in a purely Greek spirit - to a Persian setting27.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
526 Victor Ebrenberg
Herodotus relied, which already had the Persian setting. The exceptional position of
Otanes' family (83, 3) ruay have been a motive for inventing that sctting, while, on the
other hand, the final arguments in favour of monarchy with their reference to Cyrus
are made from the Pcrsian point of vicw. The allusion in Hcr. VI 43, 3, to the debate
in Book III shows how weak Herodotus' argument actually is. Those Greeks, he says,
who did not belicve that Otanes recommended democracy to the Persians (co; xe'ov El7
6n,yoxeadru6Oaa 17tocTaa) must have been greatly surprised when Mardonius introduced
democracies in the Ionian cities. Herodotus does not even see the fundamental distinc-
tion, underlying the issue, whether it was the Persian empire or some Greek cities which
were to be ruled democratically. - It will be seen that in the discussion between M\or-
rison and Gomme (JHS. LXX 1950, 76f.) I really cannot side with either of them;
but I deprecate any direct reference in Hcrodotus' debate, even in its final form,
to Periclcs (cf. AJP1. LXIX, 1948, I6I, 40).
z8. Cf. my article on Isonomia, RE. Suppl. VII, 293-301, and this paper, p. 530 f.
29. 4e did so on his way to the expedition of 492. His intention must have been to win
the loyalty of the lonians, and later events down to 480 show that he had been successful.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originmof Democracy 527
itself, and there is one more passage in which it is used. That is when
Herodotus mentions Cleisthenes as one of Pericles' ancestors and describes
him as the man who introduced in Athens -ra qvmAaxal n)v 6nyoxearTiv
(VI 131, I). Our first impression from all these quotations will be that
Herodotus had no definite conceptions of, nor a clear-cut name for, any
constitution - with the possible exception of monarchy, though it too
is not distinguished from tyranny30. That general impression is further
confirmed by the fact that, according to V 78, the rise of Athens after the
downfall of the tyrannis was due to liberty expressed in atyoehq, while
we learn from V 92 that Sparta, by destroying 'YoceaT'ag in Greece,
was bound to introduce rveavv(6ag.
Thus the same thing is expressed by 5jouoxQaTla, iaovopl,&, and occasio-
nal variations of which ii?yoQe7i is the freedom of speech in the assembly,
singled out as a specific and ~)excellente feature of democracy, while ao-
xQea-rta looks like an attempt to combine the two more usual words and
thus to indicate the rule of equality. Obviously, Herodotus is well versed
in using abstract nouns to describe a constitution, but none of them seems
yet fully settled. We ask what are the particular contents which make the
various expressions, at least for Herodotus, practically interchangeable.
The outstanding issue is undoubtedly the contrast to monarchy. In
every single case mentioned this is the point in question, and apart from
the debate of the Persian nobles, there is never any further indication what
the specific characteristics of any form of ?yIoxQear1aor laovo1tih actually
were. It was therefore tempting to conclude that there was nothing else
in it, that even when Herodotus speaks of democracy he connects with
the word not more than the general meaning of a free and unmonarchical
constitution31.
This is rather a vague definition, and if we are not satisfied by it, we
had better try to dig a little deeper. Herodotus claims that the democracy
prevalent at his own time, the Periclean democracy, is essentially the same
as that of Cleisthenes. That is, I believe, also the deeper meaning of VI 131,
that short chapter in which the story of the wooing of Agariste, the daughter
of Cleisthenes of Sicyon, from which Megacles the Alcmaeonid emerged
triumphant, leads to the enumeration of his descendents, of another
3o. This can cven lead to using the word ,i6vaexog contrary to its very meaning.
Cypselus was given an oracle (Her. V 920) which set him as the one who was to bring
justice to Corinth against the Bacchiads who, although forming a family oligarchy,
are called ),monarchical men4:. . .. E'v 69 7ecrELTaL av6QdYa ,owatndxotat,&txaLtKale 69
KMQLvOov.
31. Schaefer, 503: *nicht die Demokratic im Sinne der spateren Staatsform, son-
dern. .. ganz allgemein eine Verfassung, bci der die freiheitliche Entscheidung des
Volkes gesichert ist.e
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
528 Victor Ebrenberg
32. Against the view of a derogatory meaning of the famous passage, cf. G. W. Dy-
son, CQ. XXIII (1925), i86ff.
33. Was Athens the spiritual home of Herodotus? This is a disputed question.
To think of him as a one-sided and exclusive partisan of Athens is, I believe, a mistake.
Herodotus is at least as fair to Sparta, while his special contempt is rescrved for the
lonians of Asia Minor. He is, in fact, neither a pure Panhellenist nor simply a Polis
citizen; that in the end he became a citizen of Thurii is rather significant. Yet, it was
in his relations to men like Pericles and Sophocles that his mind received its final shape.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 529
34. It seems certain that ;qrorTardT7j ToiO 6,'Uov did originally mean the leader of the
wholc people, not a democratic capo di par/c. There is no clear evidence at what time
the expression first came into use, though apparently this happened after the time of
the Supplianis. Pelasgus is the perfect example of a nQ7roaTd'T7 TOVt 6v,itov, but if the title
had been in use at the time of the play, he could not have said: neoorraTran 6'ey darlor
TE caVTiE (963), meaning that thcy acted as guardians for the suppliants who were their
metics (See above p. 52o). It would have been almost a pun such as that in Aristoph.
Frogs, 569f. (cf. my People of ArirtophaneS2, I9 i, I 5I, 8). Even without this confirmation
I should have thought that the title of a rLQoardrTaT TOV36 sov was unlikely to have been
introduced as long as the leading politicians had to be satisfied with holding once the
annual office of first archon. The position of the ))leader of the people. developed from
the fact that a man could be re-clected as a member of the board of strategoi, and came
probably into use somc time aftcr 487/6. Perhaps Cimon was the first to bear that un-
official title.
35. This point is madc, perhaps with some exaggeration, the crucial issue in Lar-
sen's paper (see note 3). He also points out the two passagcs from Aeschylus which
I shall mention presently.
34
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
530 Victor Ebrenberg
although he virtually is one; we have seen that the word rrQoaTdr%;is not
yet used in that sense. This confirms that Aeschylus reflects a somewhat
earlierstage of democracythan Herodotus'source; but it does not disprove
that the two constitutions are essentially the same. There is, in fact, not
the slightest difficultyin regardingboth the tragedian'sand the historian's
picturesas reflectionsof the same model: the democracyof Athens between
Cleisthenes and Pericles.
Isonomiaand Dermokratia
We have seen that Herodotus used the two expressions 3i,uoxearia and
icrovoldt'indiscriminately.The praise implied in the words 6vo,ua7dvTwv)v
xdA;UaTov is paid to the name ratherthan the matter. From the very phrase
it seemspossible to conclude that Herodotus knew other dvo6uara for demo-
cracy. They have been discussedin the precedingsection, andthereseems no
need to say more about Herodotus' phraseology. He preferredlaovoyv,
probably because, in avoiding all allusions to power and rule, it set up
some kind of ideal, emphasizing the equal share of all the citizens in the
State36.Aescliylus, on the other hand, laid more stress on the sovereign
power of the people, and apparentlythought of this form of government
as a 6ruoxearta. We must now try to find out whether our remaining
evidence can teachus more about the meaningof, and the relationsbetween,
the two expressions.
Isonomia makes its earliest appearance(as an adjective)in the famous
drinking-song on Harmodius and Aristogeiton (Io-I 3 Diehl). The two
tyrannicides are praised * because they have killed the tyrant and made
Athens i'aov6`ov#. Herodotus (VI I23) realises that they were given the
honour actuallydue to the Alcmaeonids: it was the murderof Hipparchus
that made Hippias' rule truly oppressive and tyrannical,and it was four
years later that Hippias was expelled and Athens liberated. That, on the
other hand, was largely due to the intervention of the Spartanking Cleo-
menes, and it is understandablethat the Athenians should have claimed
their liberationto be the work of Athenians.But who were Ethe E Athenians
who put forward this claim in that lovely little drinking-song? Obviously
it originated among the same people who bewailed their dead in a similar
song remembering the battle of Leipsydrion (24 Diehl). Herodotus
(V 6z) and Aristotle (Ath. poL. I 9, 3) assureus that it was the Alcmaeonids
with their followers who had fortifiedLeipsydrion,and finding no popular
support, were defeated and suffered heavy losses. The song itself calls
Leipsydrion nLoocoaIraqeov, betraying one's hetairoi,and the dead ayaOov'q
36. The evidence shows that to Herodotus laovoprj meant this, and did not mean
equality before the law. Cf. RE., SuppI. VII, 2gs, iOff.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 531
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
532 Vicor Ebrenberg
40. The latest important treatment of the decree is by M. Ostwald, AJP. LXXII
(1951), 24ff.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 533
one way or another, were aiming at an equality which they had to some
extent had under the tyrants, and which would make them safe - safer
than Solon's Evivojta - against aristocraticoppression.
It was, however, something very different to accept the claims made
for Harmodius and Aristogeiton, who after all had been members of
the nobility, and to see in their action the foundation of democracy.
That can only have been done by somebody who had fallen out with the
rest of the nobility and wanted a symbol for his own democraticpolicy.
It must have been the doing of Cleisthenes. The opposite claim that the
Alcmaeonids, and not the tyrannicides,were the true liberatorsof Athens,
could be raised by a later pro-Alcmaeonidtraditionwhen the partplayedby
the Alcmaeonids throughout the years had become a matter of serious
political dispute. In the years immediately after the event, it was just as
impossible to pretend that the Alcmaeonids alone had liberated the State
as to remind the people of those who had actuallyhelped the Alcmaeonids
in their task, but had now become their and the people's enemies. Thus
it was the Alcmaeonid Cleisthenes who made the liberation from the
tyrants the prelude to democracy40a.
A modern archaeologist has maintained that the famous group by
Antenor - the same Antenor who was probablyresponsiblefor the sculp-
ture at the temple in Delphi which the Alcmaeonidshad erected - was the
expressionof a spirit closely relatedto that of Cleisthenes'work4l. However
that maybe, therecould be hardly a stronger falsificationof historicaltruth
than to take the tyrannicidesas a symbol of democracy42.If this was due to
Cleisthenes himself, as we have tried to show, it seems hardly satisfactory
to explain such a policy as self-effacing and to call its #modestyz typical
of ancient Attic traditions43. Cleisthenes was too clever a politician, besides
being a great and creative statesman, for such an explanation to do him
justice. In many ways he probably did not much more than follow the
40 a. Cf. Bowra, Greek Lyric Poetry,4I S, who speaks of the *brillant propagandaof
the Alcmaeonids .
41. K. Schefold, MuscumHhelteiicwm III (I946), 59ff., esp. 7x. This is a very interesting,
if provocative, article. The author recognises (p. 85); *Niemals wurden wir allein aus
dem Wandel der Kunst um 5io auf einen Regierungswechsel schlieB3enkonnen., but
he draws many rash conclusions of exactly the type which he condemns. Some of his
many original suggestions deserve to be studied carefuilly,for example his reconstruction
of three Theseus poems; even here, however, the use he makes, outside the field of art, of
the conccptions of Ionic, Doric, and Altattisch goes far beyond what we can know.
42. We do not deny that there was a historical connection between the murder
of Hipparchus and the establishment of Cleisthenes' new order. But that does not justify
the attempts to see in the private act of vengeance of two noblemen an event which
has an inner relation to the creation of a democratic State.
43. Schefold, 1. c., 64. 68f.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
534 Victor Ehrenberg
trend of public opinion which, at the same time, he tried to direct. But
we can perhaps go a step fuirther.
The outstanding feature of Cleisthenes' new order is the manner in which
he based a rational and at the same time revolutionary system on the natural
foundations of the local communities, the demes, while the ancient social
bodies such as the phratries were left as integral, if powerless, elements of
the new structure of society. It would be quite mistaken to regard this
as a sign of compromise. If ever a statesman was single-minded it was
Cleisthenes; but he was not a doctrinaire. He knew how to give some
share to the forces of the past which otherwise might obstruct his work.
Above all, he knew how to merge the traditions of cult and the living
bodies of religious communities in the life of his new political and social
organisation. It was this kind of political wisdom that enabled Cleisthenes
to lead the way to democracy, using as he did the ideas and the slogans
which had dominated the actual liberation: the legend of the liberation
of A hens by the tyrannicides, and the * most beautiful word of all 'which
offered itself by its emphasis on the idea of equality. Isonomia was a slogan
whiich made it manifest that Cleisthenes did not think of himself as merely
*the defender of the Solonian constitution #44; it was at the same time a
term more acceptable to many than a word such as 6rtioxoa-ra which was
so outspoken in its proclaiming the people as the master of the new State.
There is no evidence to show that the word 6vyuoxeaTta was known as
early as that. When Cleisthenes transferred the conception of Laovogda to
his own democratic order, he deprived at the same time his former- allies
and present opponents, the majority of the nobility, of their anti-tyrannis
slogan. They no less than he himself must have felt the need to have a
positive conception of their respective forms of government, and it may
even have become more urgent to describe the opponent's rather than one's
own form of rule. We cannot decide whether the )>oligarchs # or the * demo-
crats # were the first to announce the name of their particular constitutional
aims, or on the other hand, whether both names were first coined by their
opponcnts. The important and interesting fact is that for all practical
purposes we may assume that the expressions o'AtyaeLXaand 6yuox,Loaiia
made their filst appearances almost simultaneously, although for some time
to come it was democracy which represented the real opposition to mo-
narchy tl.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 535
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
536 Victor Ehrenberg
of political and constitutional issues, did not realise the difference. But we
must not attribute this merely to his personal shortcomings. Isonomia, in
fact, became the democratic ideal, and the aristocrats, no longer fighting
against monarchy, naturally saw their own ideal in Spartan or Solonian
eEvvoyla rather than in Cleisthenian or Periclean tiaovopla.
Does Thucydides confirm these results? That is to say, did the later
fifth century still see the two conceptions in the same light as its early
decades? This in itself is unlikely. We need only think of the Funeral
Speech, and we shall understand that democracy had found its ideal in
its own conception, in the people's rule. The democrats, just like the
oligarchs, no longer saw their enemy in the tyrant; they now fought against
one another. ))Our constitution, because it is governed in the interest not
of a few, but of the majority, is called democracyo (Thuc. II 37, i). The
principles of equal balance and of general share in the government were of
less importance than the idea of equality before the law. Pericles continues:
* But while there is, by law, equality (ro laov) for all in their private disputes,
by reputation, as far as each man is in any way distinguished, he receives
preference in public life, not to a greater extent because of his class or party
than on account of his merit <(5. In these words, the ruling class in democracy
is depicted as an aristocracy of personal merits. It is an ideal, and was there-
fore never attained; but that does not justify anyone in doubting its intrinsic
truth and the right of such a community to be regarded as a true democracy.
In dealing with the reality of political life Thucydides is free from all
purely conventional expressions and distinctions, but the use he makes of
such words as lUovoida, Tveavvtg, or bvvaarrla, throws some light also
on their general meaning and their earlier history. In III 6z, 3, the Thebans
describe the political conditions of their city during the Persian War. It was
not an ICro'voluog oAyaQXianor a democracy; the State was in the hands
of a bvvacrTela oAtycovavbecov. Naturally the Thebans tried to blame only
those few ju61i'aavTa; (Her. IX 86, i) who had been responsible for the
pro-Persian policy. At the same time, they had to be careful not to hurt
the feelings of the Lacedaemonians who were their audience. Nobody was
ever likely to forget that Sparta's policy was governed by her own experience:
cai vvoyu GO iMaia?eiavTQavvevroqlv (Thuc. I i 8, i). The Thebans there-
fore twisted the well-known terms of political theory so as to adapt them
to their own purposes. The dynasteiais * the nearest to a tyrant #, the complete
contrast to law and moderation; correspondingly, there was to be, on the
opposite side, not only democracy but also a form of oligarchy which
suited the anti-tyrannis scheme. While in other passages in Thucydides
(VI 38, 3. 89, 4) 6vvacmeta again appears as a near relative of tyranny,
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 537
5i. The latter word is Gomme's, CR. LXIII (I949), 125. I differ in the following
argument from my own former view (RE. 296, i i ff.).
52. The latest expression of that school of thought is the article by Schaefer men-
tioned before (see note 3).
53 Cf. my earlier papers, JHS. LVII (I937), I47ff., Aspects of the Ancient World,
Miunchen
i 6 f., and H. Bengtson, Sihgungsber. 193 9, Heft i.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
638 Victor Ehrenberg
There is no real need, I believe, to ask first, as so often has been asked,
whether this title is not rather due to Solon. It is well known that Aristotle,
Ath.pol. 41, z, writes that from Solon's legislationadeXqiy,oxear1aq 7y'esro,
and similarideas were prevalent among other Greek writers of the fourth
century',4. Ta 61yoTiLXcTaTa, however,of Solon'snoAlTE1a,to whichAristotle
points (9, i), do not refer to a democratic constitution, or to a constitution
at alli. They were to indicate certain foundations on which democracy
was to be built. Solon was the first to claim in purely human terms the
eternalrights of justice and freedomfor every memberof the community56.
Nobody will doubt that he gave the ordinaryAthenian citizen a standing
without which there would never have been a democracy.Even the con-
stitution which he shaped contained elements of an essentially democratic
charactersuch as an assembly in which every citizen could get up and
speak, and a people's court to which every citizen could appeal.Moreover,
he was the first to question and even to ignore the old Eupatrid order,
and to base the State on principles which, though not democratic,at least
abandonedthe privileges of birthright57.In giving power to the wealthy
he opened the door for the rise of the non-nobles, but in his own time
this didnot yet leadto much,andon the whole the richwerestill the Eupatrids.
In the end therefore,Solon's constitution broke down before it had settled
down, as an attempt,bound to fail, at steeringa middle coursewhile leaving
the government in the hands of the rich and the noble.
had early Chios a better claim to having a democratic constitution?
What we know rests on one severely mutilatedinscription (Tod, no. I).
We hear of 64uov '4Teat and a flovAt)X 6cpoaol7which was composed of
fiity members from each pvA4;the two conceptions seem to correspond
to the "94pac/ZaTa TOVl ftuov and the PovA' (of the Four Hundred) in
Athens. The *popular Council4 in Chios had jurisdiction, probably not
only as a court of appeal, and there were * democratic<(magistrates,the
5~uaexoL,side by side with the aristocraticflaao4i4. Thus, jurisdictionand
execuuve were at least partiallyin the handsof the Demos. The constitution
oi Chios at the time of the inscription (roughly about 6oo B. C.) was more
democraticthan Solon's, but whether it could be called a real democracy
canot be decided, nor whetherit was a kind of predecessorto Cleisthenes'
State, or even a model which he to some extent copied. I must say that
none of these possibilities seems to me at all likely.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 539
7 a. My apology for using the terms feudal and feudalism can be found in note 77.
58. The former passage refers to the period aftcr 462, the latter to the revolution
of 411. If Plutarch's story is true to facts, the oligarchs of the middle of the century
did not yet need to the same extent as did their successors in 41I to disguise their
true aims by claiming the naeTQiog =Aoirea as democratic. On the other hand, they
may have been thinking of the form into which Cleisthenes' order had turned under
the supremacy of the Areopagus after tlhePersian War.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
540 Victor Ehrenberg
against the nobles. Cleisthenes had served as first archon under the rule
of Hippias just like other nobles, for example Miltiades59. Later, possibly
as late as 5I460, Cleisthenes joined the other emigres. When the tyrant
had gone, Cleisthenes had no intention of helping to restore the old supre-
macy of the noble clans; he decided to rely on the people, in particular
on the urban population. It was then that Isagoras for the second time
called in the king of Sparta.Views have been expressed either that Cleisthenes
acted as he did because he was a convinced champion of the people, or,
on the other hand, that he used democracy merely as an instrument to
serve his own lust for power and the glory of his family. I do not think
either view is likely to be adequate. We shall never exactly know what was
in Cleisthenes' mind, but I feel that we should not too easily decide on
one of those two extreme views.
It is hardly too bold to assert that nobody could do what Cleisthenes
did without having fairly strong convictions as to how State and society
should be reformed, nor without previously having made his programme
public, at least in its outlines. On two earlier occasions, in 514 when Hipp-
archus was killed, and somewhat later at Leipsydrion where the Alcmae-
onids were involved, events had shown that a purely aristocratic revolt
would not be supported by the masses of the people, whether urban or
rural. Cleisthenes must have learnt his lesson. He by now realised - and
in this he only revived traditions of Alcmaeonid policy - that he had to
part company with the other noble families and proclaim a political goal
which would catch the people's imagination. As Solon impressed his ideas
upon the people by reciting his elegies, so Cleisthenes must have found
ways and means to let his political programme be widely known. As with
most great statesmen, his own interest became inseparable from the public
interest which at that moment most certainly centred on a form of govern-
ment which would prevent the restoration of either tyranny or aristocratic
feudalism. In the turbulent events of Cleomenes' second intervention, when
the Alcmaeonids and many with them had been banished once more under
the old pollution charge, the council and the people turned against the
attempt to introduce a narrow oligarchy, forced Cleomenes and Isocrates
59. This we know from the fragment of an archons' list: Meritt, Hesperia VIII
(I 9 39), 59 ff. T. J. Cadoux, JHS. LXVIII (I948), iogf. In all likeness it is the younger
liltiades who (cf. Dion. Hal. VII 3, i) also provides the date to put the fragment
in the right position. The list certainly came as a great surprise, and we must admit
that the facts it seems to record largely remain a puzzle. See also next note.
6o. Her. V 62, 2, may be more correct than is recognised when he says of the
Alcmaeonids: pEVyOVT8e HeLatrLoaTibag (not: HeataTLaTov). But see Schefold, 1. c.,
6i ff., on the difficulty of combining the date of 514 with the rebuilding of the temple
in Delphi. There is no evidence allowing to reduce to a more definite date the period
between 525/4 (Cleisthenes' archonship) and 5I4.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 541
6i. Her. V 70. 72. Arist. AtJ. pol. 20, 3. Thuc. I I26, iz.
62. Her. V 71 calls Cylon's followers a lTae'qtn TCrV4A9xCTCOwV.In spite of the
abstract noun, this only cGnfirmsour view.
63. Herodotus speaks of Cleisthenes' imitation of his namesake and grandfather,
the tyrant of Sicyon (V 69, I), though only because he had shown an equal contempt
of the lonians (one of Herodotus' hobby-horses) by abolishing the old Ionian phylae.
This idea had a surprising success with some modern historians. Berve and Schaefer
draw comparisons between the two men simply because in each case the constitutional
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
542 Victor Ehrenberg
changes served the struggle for personal power! Schefold, 73, thinks that the relations
of both men with DeJphi causcd deeper affinities between them, which, though doubtful,
makes better sense.
64. Cf. note 59, also F. Cornelius, Die Tyranmis in Atben (I929), 93.
64a. See next note.
6s. I do not propose to discuss the intricate chronology of the events. I certainly
no longer maintain the position of that early article of mine (Klio XIX I924, io6ff.).
From my text it will be clear that I now assume as early as 5og/8 propaganda for, but
not the actual introduction of, Cleisthenes' programme. The issues are fully and sensibly
discussed by Cadoux, note 249 (against Schachermeyr, Klio XXV 1932, 334ff., and
others).
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 543
as much divided among the new tribes, though the combinedvoting of the
urban and the paraliantrittyes may have brought occasional majoritiesfor
the Alcmaeonids. It is generally acknowledged06that his aim was to create
a uniform type of aoAhtr/s; that is the very opposite to any attempt at
providing for the rule of his own family. He was the first to aim at the
ideal of government by a free people, the first to reach the goal for which
the Greeks had been heading ever since the Polis came into being. He built
his new communityupon the equality of the citizens, upon laovo1ta. There
is no clearer proof of the fact that this was indeed 67j,ioxQaTra than the
surprisingswiftness and smoothness with which the new State settled down
without any revolts or repercussions.Cleisthenesrenewed the State coinage
with Athena and owl which now became the symbol of democraticinstead
of PeisistratidAthens. The danger oi tyrannis disappeared,the danger of
a reversal of Cleisthenes'work never rnaterialised.CleisthenicAthens was
for a time led by the Alcmaeonids, but it remained essentially the same
when others took their place. It was and remained a democracy.
This, of course, does not mean that there were no changes. Just because
the new State was from the first a working and living entity, it went
through various developments which, taken as a whole, only carried
Cleisthenes' order some steps further. It was not until 480 that the new
ascendency of the Areopagus led to a retarding movement. Perhaps the
most significant phenomenpn In the domestic history of the twenty years
after Cleisthenes is the use, made or not made, of ostracism. This novel
and unheard-of device with its idea of a temporary and honourable exile
through a responsible decision of the people combined in a unique way
resoluteness of purpose with mildness of means. By expelling one man and
never more than one at a time it was clearlyaimedat a possibletyrant;it was,
if we rightly understandits original meaning, equally a weapon to support
the unity of the people and to discourage sectional factions. No ordinary
politician would ever have hit on such an unusual measurein which are
combined the boldness, the rationalclarity, and the deliberate moderation
of Cleisthenes' statesmanship67.
Schaefer(p. 491f.) believes that he has found a new reason for assuming
that ostracism did not exist before 490; for otherwise Miltiades' enemies
would not have dragged him before a court when he came home from
the Chersonesein 493 (Her. VI 104). They would have used the weapon
of ostracism which, according to this theory, was designed only shortly
before it was used in 488; it may, in fact, have been invented because of
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
544 Victor Ebrenberg
the failure of the trial of Miltiades,in order to avoid the repetition of such
an event. This is an ingenious argument, and Schaefer largely relies on
the fact that Miltiades was charged with Oyrannis.We know very little of
the internal history of Athens after 500, ar.dthe little evidence we have is
much disputed"8. I am reluctant to express any definite view, but I have
no doubt that ostracism had indeed been created as a weapon against the
restorationof yrannis - naturallyoyrannisin Athens. Miltiadeswas accused
Tveavvi6ogv7; lv XEeao 'ar. Although this referred to the Athenian
citizens over whom he had ruled just as over Thracians"9, there is not the
slightest indication that Miltiades, however great and independent, did
aim, or could be chargedwith aiming, at something like 6,uov xara'Avacn,
at becoming the tyrantof Athens. Certainly,the people who saw in Miltiades
the god-sent leader against the threatening Persian attack, did not think
so, and that may have been one reason why his enemies did not dare to
ask for an ostracism. Moreover, who could foresee what might happen
when that untried weapon was employed? Might Miltiades' enemies not
endanger their own position? Earlier in the year Phrynichus had been
condemned for causing trouble by his play >The Captureof Miletus; but
the next archon was Themistocles who had perhaps been responsible for
the political propagandaof that tragedy, and who had an active naval and
democraticpolicy as his programme.It seems that the people did not want
the appeasement of Persia7O. They certainly preferred Miltiades to his
accusers and elected him strategosimmediately after his acquittal. I doubt
whether it was within the limits of a reasonablepolicy to come before the
people, proposing a measurewith which they were not familiar,at a moment
when it could hardlybe justified. It needed, in fact, anothergreatpolitician,
Themistocles,to makenew anddifferentuse of the weaponwhichCleisthenes
had forged but never used7l. None of the minor politicians who accused
Miltiades would have dared to do so.
68. Cf. Gommc, AJP. LXV (I944), 321ff., an interesting but by no means final
contribution. The debate continues.
69. Cf. my Aspects of the Ancient World, 2zT.
70. Cf. H. T. Wade-Gery, BSA. XXXVII, 269. For Themistocles and The Capture
of Miletus, cf. Walker, C.A.H. IV, 172.
71. The view has been widely accepted that the ostracisms between 488 and 483
were the work of Themistocles. This would partially fill the ten years' gap in his career
(492--83) of which we know little. He was strategos in 490 (Plut. Arist. 5, 4), but that
is all we know for certain. The silence of our sources has caused Gomme (1.c., 323f.)
to discard Thcmistocles' archonship in 493 altogether. This seems to me to he unneces-
sarily sceptical. Themistocles' share in the ostracisms of the eighties was a kind of
behind-the-scene politics which may easily have escaped the historians, though I admit
that it would have provided excellent material for the kind of gossipy anecdotes which
have found their way into Plutarch's Lifes. It remains to be said that no other valid
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Origins of Democracy 545
explanation for the series of ostracisms has been found, and that it is only from rccent
discoveries of ostraca that we learn of politicians, unknown from literarysources, who
were potential victims of an ostracism, e. g. Callixenus, son of Aristonymus, probably
an Alcmaeonid (Stamires and Vanderpool, Hesperia XIX 1950, 376ff.).
72. On tht question of date (504/3 Ot 5ox/o?) see Cadoux, 1. c. 1ixf. - Schaefer,
487, speaks also of the Ephebes' oath as going back to Cleisthenes. This is not impossible,
but there is really no evidence for it. The archaic style of the oath (see Tod, II, no. 204)
provides no certain date, and the Oea,o' of tM3vudvot seem to point to an even earlier
age (cf. mv Rechtridecim fruhen Griechentum, I07).
73. Xen. mem.I i, i8. Lysias XXXI if. [Dem.] LIX 4.
74. Gomme, 1. c., note 13, observes that most of the eponymous archons betwecn
3o6 and 488 are unknown men. This could support the idea that as early as then the
archonship had lost its importance. But if we go through the list of archons during the
sixth century as far as we have their names, we find at least as many names unknown
to us as well-known. The point seems to be that, while normallv any man of wealth
(and therefore usually also of noble birth), without necessarily being an important
politician, may have become archon, it was, on the other hand, the position of the
first archon in which alone an ambitious and important man could exercise power.
We should perhaps not overestimate the numbers of such men available.
35
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
546 Victor Ebrenberg
75. Paus. I 29, 6; the grave of the tyrannicides is mentioned in 5 IS. Cf. Schefold,
69f. I do not know of any evidence for Jacoby's confident assumption that Cleisthenes
was ever 'overthrown' (Athis, x6of., with note 53). Admittedly, Herodotus' record
of the first embassy to Sardes (V 73) is a pro-Alcmaeonid version deliberately reticent
on certain points; but nothing seems to justify the view that he suppressed the overthrow
of Cleisthenes which Jacoby admits wou!d be *an almost unique proceeding with him .
76. It is no longer necessary, I believe, to refute Beloch's strange argument by
which he made Theniistocles a leader of the yv6o5e,sot(Griech.Gescb.II 2, 134).
77. Not the first, but an early and important protest against this kind of moderni-
sation was E. Salin's article *Der Sozialismus in Hellas. in the Gotheie-Festschrift
(1923).
I had better admit that in the present paper I have nevertheless ulsedthe term feudalism,
as it seems the only adequate expression to indicate the rule of noble families based
on a dependent agrarian clientele.
78. Only after I had finished this article I realised that I had sought to do with
democracv what I had done at an carlier occasion with the Polis (JHS. LVII, I937,
147fl.), to slhow from contemporary sources that behind a conception which was often
loosely or wrongly used by later writers both ancient and modern, there was at an
early stage the real thing fully alive and working.
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Originsof Democracy 547
POSTSCRIPT
This article had been set for some time when I received by the author's
courtesy A. E. Raubitschek's paper ?The Origin of Ostracism(<(AJA. LV
195 1, zz i ff.). In a clever and provocative argument R. tries to prove that
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
548 Victor Ehrenberg:Originsof Democracy
This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Tue, 22 Dec 2015 16:49:07 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions