VELTMAN, Andrea. Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
VELTMAN, Andrea. Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
VELTMAN, Andrea. Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Studies in Feminist Philosophy is designed to showcase cutting-edge monographs and collections that
display the full range of feminist approaches to philosophy, that push feminist thought in important new
directions, and that display the outstanding quality of feminist philosophical thought.
1
3
Oxford University Press is a department of the Universityof Oxford.
It furthers the Universitys objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide.
OxfordNewYork
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala LumpurMadridMelbourneMexico CityNairobi
New DelhiShanghaiTaipeiToronto
With officesin
ArgentinaAustriaBrazilChileCzech RepublicFranceGreece
GuatemalaHungaryItalyJapanPolandPortugalSingapore
South KoreaSwitzerlandThailandTurkeyUkraineVietnam
135798642
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-freepaper
{ Contents}
Index 351
{ Notes on Contributors}
Introduction
Andrea Veltman and MarkPiper
1
As characterized by John Christman, Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy, in The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, August2009.
2
Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society, Journal of Social Philosophy 29:1 (Spring
1998):81-102; Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate,2006).
2 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
3
For more on the importance of autonomy in normative philosophy, see Mark Piper,
Autonomy:Normative, in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, December2010.
4
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2003),18.
5
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,19.
Introduction 3
6
Marilyn Frye, The Politics of Reality:Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, CA:Crossing Press,
193),33.
7
Sandra Bartky, On Psychological Oppression and Iris Marion Young, Five Faces of Oppression
reprinted in Feminist Theory:APhilosophical Anthology, edited by Ann Cudd and Robin Andreasen
(Malden, MA:Blackwell,2005).
8
Ann Cudd, Analyzing Oppression (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2006), 26, cf.2327.
9
Bartky, On Psychological Oppression,105.
10
Bartky, On Psychological Oppression, 106,112.
11
Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice:ADefense of Pluralism and Equality (NewYork:Basil Blackwell,
1983), 176. Walzer here cites Stewart E. Perrys San Francisco Scavengers:Dirty Work and the Pride of
Ownership (Berkeley:University of California Press, 1978),7.
12
As Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth write, practices that confer denigration or humiliation
threaten self-esteem by making it much harder (and, in limit cases, even impossible) to think of one-
self as worthwhile. The resulting feelings of shame and worthlessness threaten ones sense that there is
4 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
point to ones undertakings. And without that sense of ones aspirations being worth pursuing, ones
agency is hampered. Anderson and Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice, in
Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism:New Essays, edited by John Christman and Joel Anderson
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005),131.
13
Jane Dryden, Autonomy:Overview, in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, November2010.
14
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, Introduction: Autonomy Refigured, in Relational
Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie and
Stoljar (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), 21; Natalie Stoljar, Feminist Perspectives on
Autonomy, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2013.
15
See, e.g., John Christman, Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy.
Introduction 5
16
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Social Disruption and Women, in The Feminist Philosophy
Reader, edited by Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo (NewYork:McGraw-Hill, 2008). See also Friedmans
chapter Relational Autonomy and Independence in this volume.
17
Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational
Autonomy.
18
Uma Narayan, Minds of Their Own: Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices and Other
Women, in A Mind of Ones Own:Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (Boulder, CO:Westview
Press,2002).
19
John Christman, Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism, and the Social Construction of
Selves, Philosophical Studies 117 (2004):143164; Andrea Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,
Hypatia 24 (2009): 2649; Serene J. Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment
(NewYork:Oxford University Press,2011).
20
Diana Tietjens Meyers, Gender in the Mirror: Cultural Imagery and Womens Agency
(NewYork:Oxford University Press 2002),11.
6 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
authentic lives, and to overlook the agency women exercise even in contexts
of oppressive circumstances. Yet value-neutral accounts serve poorly as tools
of social critique and suffer on account of packing autonomy into purely pro-
cedural processes of reflection that effectively neglect the possibility that a
well-integrated, smoothly-functioning self could be in need of rigorous scru-
tiny and drastic overhaul.21 In light of potential pitfalls of both approaches,
Meyers argues that a compelling feminist account of autonomy must ac-
knowledge that oppression impedes autonomy without stripping women of
that autonomy which they have managed to wrest from a patriarchal, racist,
heterosexist, ageist, class-stratified world.22 In her contribution to this volume,
she further distinguishes ways values enter autonomy theories, demarcating
new conceptual axes along which to position accounts of autonomy.
In this collection of new papers, leading scholars carry forward exami-
nations of central theoretical and practical issues at the intersection of au-
tonomy studies and feminist philosophy. Contributors examine fundamental
components and commitments of autonomy, examining for instance the
role of reflective deliberation, reasons, values, cares, emotions, self-worth,
self-care, adaptive preferences, social and political commitments, and norms
of independence in accounts of autonomy. Some papers pursue the question
of whether autonomy is compatible with subordination, including forms of
gender subordination and class-based subordination. Others examine how
ideals of autonomy are affected by capitalism, political commitments to inclu-
sivity, and feminist emphases on the relationality of human agency. In looking
at autonomy amid oppression, the volume represents a plurality of perspec-
tives about autonomy. Some contributors examine the agency of women and
oppressed persons through the lens of value-neutral accounts of autonomy,
whereas others utilize dialogical accounts, capabilities accounts, or thicker
value-saturated accounts. Still others make meta-arguments about the merits
of different kinds of approaches relative to feminist ambitions. Anumber of
papers focus on assessing autonomy in social contexts in which agents form
adaptive preferences or internalize gendered norms, and some focus on how
autonomy bears in social and personal contexts of raising girls, working, preg-
nancy and abortion, and end-of-life decisions.
We have organized the papers in the volume into five sections, beginning
with an initial cluster that explores key dimensions of the concept of autonomy,
especially in regards to its relational character and associated notions of inde-
pendence and freedom. In Chapter 2, Catriona Mackenzie focuses on the con-
cept of autonomy itself. According to Mackenzie, one of the key reasons that
autonomy remains a contested value is because philosophers have tended to
view autonomy as a unitary concept. She argues that autonomy ought instead
to be understood as a multidimensional concept consisting of three logically
distinct but causally related dimensions:self-determination, self-governance,
and self-authorization. In addition, Mackenzie provides a relational analysis
of each of these dimensions of autonomy and argues that what is required to
satisfy the conditions of autonomy in particular contexts will often fluctuate.
The result of her work is to provide philosophers with a more nuanced under-
standing of autonomy, one that will allow debate on autonomy to proceed with
greater clarity, precision, and sensitivity to context.
Chapter 3, by Marilyn Friedman, explores ways the concept of autonomy can
combine relational and individualistic elements. Focusing on the discussion of
liberal individualism in Jennifer Nedelskys book Laws Relations:ARelational
Theory of Self, Autonomy, and Law, Friedman contends that relational and in-
dividualistic aspects of autonomy need not be irreconcilable:acknowledging
the constitutive relationality of human selves is consistent with maintaining
boundaries among individuals, such as occurs when the state serves to pro-
tect individuals from threats posed by one another. She argues further that
the popular notion of the self-made manvalorized by some but criticized by
othersis not relevant to discussions of autonomy so much as to debates about
capitalism. Freidman concludes her paper with a defense of independence as
an ideal for subordinate persons:not only does an ideal of independence pro-
vide a useful goal for liberatory movements, partly because it protects against
some forms of vulnerability, but it also serves a classic feminist goal of freeing
women to shape their own lives rather than accepting confining definitions
imposed by others.
Chapter 4, by Nancy Hirschmann, further explores the theme of indepen-
dence. Hirschmann registers skepticism about relational autonomy, argu-
ing provocatively that the concept originates from a pathology in feminine
psychoanalytical development: in sexist and heteronormative practices of
childrearing, girls and women emerge with relational self-identities oriented
toward care and empathy that undermine the need to cultivate an indepen-
dent self. She suggests that if we retain the concept of relational autonomy,
then we also need a feminist concept of freedom in which a person remains
an individual responsible for her own choices. Whatever desires and abilities
we cultivate through relationships with others, she argues, we need to act by
and for ourselves.
The volume continues with a second cluster of papers focusing on the nor-
mative and social commitments of relational approaches to autonomy. In
Chapter 5, Paul Benson contends that many of the ongoing disagreements
about the normative commitments of relational autonomy can be overcome
by considering the practical question of how a conception of autonomy can
best advance the ethical, social, and political aims of feminism. He argues that
a conception of autonomy that focuses on autonomous agents authority to
8 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
speak or answer to others for their choices and actions affords a preferred way
to understand autonomys relational character. Such a conception is especially
congenial to advancing the practical goals of feminism, according to Benson,
because it captures the importance of womens attitudes toward their own ex-
perience and because it accurately takes account of the social conditions that
inform that experience. Chapter 6, by Diana Meyers, also discusses the issue of
the normative commitments of autonomy. Taking as her starting point the on-
going disputes between those who defend substantive accounts of autonomy
and those who defend content-neutral accounts, Meyers argues that values
may be implicated in autonomy theories in two distinct ways. On one hand, an
autonomy theory may prescribe or proscribe certain types of behavior or allow
that any sort of behavior might be autonomously chosen; she calls this the
Directivity Axis. On the other hand, an autonomy theory may utilize or invoke
background values to elucidate the process of autonomous choice; she terms
this the Constitutivity Axis. According to Meyers, this Double Axis Thesis has
the benefit of making room for autonomy theories that are both value neu-
tral and value utilizing. Echoing the practical concerns addressed in Bensons
paper, Meyers ends her paper by arguing that value-neutral positions on the
Directivity Axis serve feminist purposes well.
In Chapter 7, by contrast, Marina Oshana sees feminist purposes served well
with a thicker conception of autonomy in which autonomy requires author-
ity over certain choices, a lack of domination and exploitation in social rela-
tionships, and enough economic security to maintain control over important
aspects of our lives. Without meaningful economic security, she points out,
a person cannot maintain control over fundamental choices, such as choices
concerning family or life partners. Broadly, Oshana also argues biconditionally
that a commitment to autonomy entails a commitment to feminism and that
a commitment to feminism entails a commitment to autonomy. For Oshana,
respecting autonomy entails opposing forms of social domination and thus
respecting autonomy entails the core demands of feminism, which mutually
entails respecting the abilities of persons to make their own decisions and en-
gage in action by means of their own authority.
A third cluster of papers in the volume attends particularly to care, emotion,
and reason in accounts of autonomy and challenges certain influential notions
about autonomy. In Chapter 8, Christine Tappolet rebuts a notion found in
both historical and contemporary philosophical sources that emotional agents
(and by extension women) cannot be autonomous. She draws on an account
of emotions she develops elsewhere to show not only that emotions are inte-
gral in autonomous agency but also that emotions and reason-responsiveness
are not at odds. In addition to dismantling a ludicrous argument that women
cannot be autonomous, Tappolets paper thus constitutes a powerful challenge
to autonomy accounts that are predominantly rationalistic in character. This
paper dovetails with our ninth chapter by Andrea Westlund, who argues that
Introduction 9
23
Judith Jarvis Thomson, A Defense of Abortion, Philosophy and Public Affairs 1:1 (Autumn
1971):4766.
Introduction 11
A unitary concept is a concept for which there is a single set of necessary and
sufficient conditions for the correct application of the concept. Natural kind
terms such as water, gold, and elephant are unitary concepts. Ethical concepts,
such as goodness, trust, and autonomy, are also often treated as unitary con-
cepts. In the case of individual autonomy, the kernel of what is taken to be the
unitary concept of autonomy is the notion of self-governance, the idea that to
be autonomous is to be capable of making decisions and acting on the basis of
1
I also explore these connections in Mackenzie, The Importance of Relational Autonomy
and Capabilities for an Ethics of Vulnerability, in Vulnerability: New Essays in Ethics and Feminist
Philosophy, edited by Catriona Mackenzie, Wendy A. Rogers and Susan Dodds (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2014). For a related discussion, see Marina Oshanas contribution to this volume.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 17
motives, values, or reasons that are ones own in some relevant sense. Different
conceptions of autonomy aim, in part, to analyze the necessary and sufficient
conditions for a motive, value, reason, or action to be onesown.
In the literature two broad kinds of condition for self-governance have been
identified: competency conditions, which spell out the cognitive, volitional,
normative, or other competences deemed necessary to act effectively on ones
motives, values, or reasons; and authenticity conditions, which spell out what it
means for these elements of ones motivational structure to be genuinely ones
own. Much debate about autonomy in philosophical moral psychology, in-
cluding debate among theorists of relational autonomy, has focused on advanc-
ing differing interpretations of these conditions, with debate proceeding by way
of examples and counterexamples designed to test the necessity or sufficiency
claims of rival interpretations. Not surprisingly, no agreement on a single, defin-
itive interpretation of the competence or authenticity conditions for autonomy
has emerged from the debate. Ithink there are two connected reasons for this.
First, the concept of autonomy is employed for different purposes in different
social and normative contexts. This is one reason why we need a multidimen-
sional analysis of the concept. Second, the unitary notion of self-governance,
which identifies conditions for autonomy that relate to agents practical identities
and the skills and competences required for autonomy, is inadequate to capture
the multidimensional nature of the concept of autonomy.
My suggestion is that the concept of autonomy involves three dis-
tinct but causally interdependent dimensions or axes: self-determination,
self-governance, and self-authorization. Self-determination involves having
the freedom and opportunities to make and enact choices of practical im-
port to ones life, that is, choices about what to value, who to be, and what to
do. The self-determination axis identifies external, structural conditions for
individual autonomy, specifically freedom conditions and opportunity condi-
tions. Freedom conditions identify the kind of social and political constraints
that interfere with the exercise of self-determination and the kind of political
and personal liberties that enable it. Opportunity conditions specify the kinds
of opportunities that need to be available to agents in their social environ-
ments for them to have choices about what to value, who to be, and what to
do. Gerald Dworkin, Joseph Raz, and Marina Oshana have all emphasized the
importance of freedom and opportunity conditions for autonomy.2
Self-governance involves having the skills and capacities necessary to make
choices and enact decisions that express, or cohere with, ones reflectively
constituted diachronic practical identity. Following Korsgaard,3 Iunderstand
2
Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (NewYork:Cambridge University Press,
1988); Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1986); Marina Oshana, Personal
Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate,2006).
3
Christine Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,1996).
18 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
4
Tom Beauchamp and James Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed. (NewYork:Oxford
University Press,2012).
5
For reasons-responsiveness views, see Susan Wolf, Freedom within Reason (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 1990); for normative competence views, see Paul Benson, Autonomy and Oppressive
Socialization, Social Theory and Practice 17 (1991): 385408; Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the
Feminist Intuition, in Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social
Self, edited by C. Mackenzie and N. Stoljar (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), 94111; for
skills-based views, see Diana Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University
Press,1989).
6
For the notion of identification, see the essays in Harry Frankfurt, The importance of what we care
about (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1988); for care-based analyses, see, e.g., Frankfurt, On
Caring, in Frankfurt, Necessity, Volition and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999),
155180; Agnieszka Jaworksa Caring and Internality, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74:3
(2007):529568; Jaworksa, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism, in Naturalized
Bioethics:Towards Responsible Knowing and Practice, edited by H. Lindemann, M. Verkerk, and M.
Walker (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2009), 80105.
7
John Christman, The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2009).
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 19
8
Paul Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy, in Personal
Autonomy:New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Stacey Taylor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 124142; Paul Benson,
Taking Ownership:Authority and Voice in Autonomous Agency, in Autonomy and the Challenges to
Liberalism, edited by J. Christman and J. Anderson (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005),
101126; Andrea Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009):2649.
9
Carolyn McLeod, Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy (Cambridge, MA:MIT Press,2002).
10
Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice, in
Christman and Anderson, Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, 127149; Joel Anderson,
Vulnerability and Autonomy Intertwined, in Vulnerability: New Essays in Ethics and Feminist
Philosophy, edited by Catriona Mackenzie, Wendy A. Rogers, and Susan Dodds (NewYork:Oxford
University Press,2014).
11
For discussions of the distinctions between local, programmatic, and global autonomy, see espe-
cially Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice; Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society.
20 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
12
See the discussion of autonomy in Beauchamp and Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics.
See also UK Department for Constitutional Affairs, Mental Capacity Act 2005 Code of Practice
(Norwich:Stationery Office,2007).
13
For further discussions of this claim and of the significance of relational autonomy for bio-
ethics, see Susan Sherwin, A Relational Approach to Autonomy in Health Care, in The Politics of
Womens Health:Exploring Agency and Autonomy, edited by S.Sherwin and the Feminist Health Care
Ethics Research Network (Philadelphia:Temple University Press, 1998), 1947; Catriona Mackenzie,
Autonomy, in Routledge Companion to Bioethics, edited by John Arras, Elizabeth Fenton, and Rebecca
Kukla (NewYork:Routledge, forthcoming).
14
For more extended discussion of these claims, see Mackenzie and Stoljar, Introduction:Autonomy
Refigured, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy.
15
Astronger version of normative individualism is proposed by Elizabeth Anderson, Towards
a Non-Ideal, Relational Methodology for Political Philosophy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009): 132. She holds
that the claims of individuals have normative priority over the claims of social groups or collectives.
Relational autonomy need not be committed to this stronger form of normative individualism, al-
though some relational theorists might endorse the strongerview.
16
See. e.g., Martha Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press,2011).
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 21
17
This is not to deny that some sources of vulnerability (e.g., abusive interpersonal relationships,
or political repression) may undermine autonomy. For more detailed analysis of vulnerability, see
Catriona Mackenzie, Wendy A. Rogers, and Susan Dodds, eds., Vulnerability:New Essays in Ethics and
Feminist Philosophy (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2014). For reflections on the complex relation-
ship between autonomy and vulnerability, see especially the essays in that volume by Joel Anderson,
Catriona Mackenzie, and Jackie Leach Scully. For extended discussion of the way that some social
relationships, including relations of care, can undermine autonomy, see especially Marilyn Friedman,
Autonomy and Social Relationships:Rethinking the Feminist Critique, in Feminists Rethink the Self,
edited by Diana Tietjens Meyers (Boulder, CO:Westview Press, 1997), 4061; Friedman, Autonomy,
Social Disruption, and Women, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, 3551; Friedman,
Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press,2003).
18
See especially Martha Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice:Disability, Nationality, Species Membership
(Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press,2006).
22 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
This third premise is implicit rather than explicit in many accounts of relational autonomy.
19
Theorists who have explicitly discussed the social justice implications of relational autonomy are
Anderson and Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice; Catriona Mackenzie,
Autonomy: Individualistic or Social and Relational? in Risk, Welfare and Work, edited by G.
Marston, J. Moss, and J. Quiggin (Melbourne:Melbourne University Press, 2010), 107127; Mackenzie,
Conceptions of Autonomy and Conceptions of the Body in Bioethics, in Feminist Bioethics:At the
Center, on the Margins, edited by Jackie Leach Scully, Laurel Baldwin-Ragaven, and Petya Fitzpatrick
(Baltimore:Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010); Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy and Society,
Journal of Social Philosophy 29:1 (1998):81102; Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society.
20
The way I have formulated this point is influenced by Elizabeth Andersons analysis of rela-
tional inequality in Anderson, What Is the Point of Equality? Ethics 109:2 (1999):287337; Anderson,
Towards a Non-Ideal, Relational Methodology for Political Philosophy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009):130145;
Anderson, Justifying the Capabilities Approach to Justice, in Measuring Justice:Primary Goods and
Capabilities, edited by Harry Brighouse and Ingrid Robeyns (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,
2010), 81100.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 23
the judiciary, and the legislature. Relational theories aim to develop analyses
of autonomy that are responsive to the effects of such inequalities on agents
abilities to lead self-determining, self-governing, and self-authorizinglives.
Second, Isee relational autonomy as a form of non-ideal theorizing about
autonomy, which is aligned with non-ideal approaches to justice.21 It does not
assume that persons are ideally, or even hypothetically, fully rational agents or
that their motivational structures are transparent to themselves. Nor does it
take as its starting point a model of an ideally just society and assess the extent
to which current social relations fall short of this model. Rather, its starting
point is the individual as situated in, shaped, and constrained by her sociorela-
tional context in all its complexity; that is, its starting point is non-ideal agents
in a non-ideal world, characterized by social oppression, injustice, and ine-
quality. Given this starting point, the aim of relational autonomy theory is to
theorize the kind of autonomy that is possible for non-ideal human agents; to
diagnose how social domination, oppression, stigmatization, and injustice can
thwart individual autonomy; and to hypothesize possible solutions, in the form
of proposing how specific social relations, practices, and institutions might be
reformed in such a way as to protect and foster individuals autonomy.
In the following three sections of the paper Ielaborate the three axes of au-
tonomy in more detail and develop a specifically relational conception of each
axis and its distinct conditions.
3. Self-determination:ARelational Conception
21
In his critique of ideal theory, Charles Mills describes relational autonomy as a form of non-ideal
theorizing about autonomy. Mills, Ideal Theory as Ideology, Hypatia 20:3 (2005):165184. For a re-
lated discussion of non-ideal theory, see Ingrid Robeyns, Ideal Theory in Theory and Practice, Social
Theory and Practice 34:3 (2008):341361. For a different kind of critique of ideal theory, see Amartya
Sen, The Idea of Justice (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2009).
24 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
over ones life.22 Oshana argues that certain structural sociorelational condi-
tions must be in place for an agent to be genuinely self-governing in this sense.
Agents who stand in relations of subordination, subservience, deference, or
economic or psychological dependence, for example, cannot be self-governing
because they do not enjoy practical control over their lives. This is the case
even if the agents in question endorse (or are not alienated from) their subor-
dinate, subservient, or dependent position and even if they seem to satisfy the
competence and authenticity requirements for self-governance. Oshana uses
an array of examplesvoluntary slaves, prisoners, women subject to extreme
forms of gender oppression, members of restrictive religious ordersto sup-
port the guiding intuition behind her accountnamely, that a person cannot
lead a self-governing life if her options are severely restricted and she is effec-
tively under the control of others.
I am very sympathetic to Oshanas guiding intuition, but Ialso think that she
is forced into an overly strong position because she attempts to articulate this
intuition in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions for self-governance.
Her view is overly strong because it is easy to devise counterexamples or to find
real-life examples of persons who are subject to severe constraint but who are
nevertheless clearly self-governing. Moreover, as John Christman and others
have argued, the view seems to impugn the autonomy of persons who, despite
being subject to crushing forms of oppression, nevertheless struggle to make
plans, set goals, and have clear identity-defining commitments that are gen-
uinely their own.23 For this reason, Ithink a better way to articulate Oshanas
guiding intuition is by distinguishing self-governance and self-determination
as two distinct, but causally interdependent, axes or dimensions of autonomy.
I develop this argument in what follows. Before doing so, however, Iwant
briefly to discuss Christmans way of accounting for the structural constraints
on and enabling conditions for autonomy. Irefer here to his autonomy-based
conception of justice as democratic legitimacy, as developed in The Politics of
Persons.24 Christmans account of the competence and authenticity conditions
for self-governance is premised on a thick, sociohistorical conception of the
person, and he is highly sensitive to the way that social group memberships and
historic and ongoing injustice shape and constrain individual practical identi-
ties. But, contra Oshana, he does not think that structural conditions should
be included in the conditions for self-governance.25 Instead, he includes these
See, e.g., his critique of Oshanas position in Christman, Politics of Persons, 167173.
23
24
Christman, Politics of Persons.
25
Christmans reason for excluding structural conditions from the conditions for self-governance
is that he thinks including them involves unacceptable perfectionism. Christman criticizes Oshanas
view on these grounds, claiming that her account requires that autonomous agents must have cer-
tain value commitments and/or must be treated in certain normatively acceptable ways, even if
the agents in question do not endorse those value commitments. Christman, Politics of Persons, 171.
For a detailed response to Christmans perfectionism argument, see Oshana, Personal Autonomy in
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 25
Society; Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism, Journal of Social
Philosophy 39 (2008):51233.
26
Christman, Politics of Persons,224.
27
The distinction between freedom conditions and opportunity conditions overlaps to some ex-
tent with Isaiah Berlins distinction between negative and positive liberty in Berlin, Two Concepts of
Liberty, in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1969). As Iexplain in the following
text, theorists who understand the freedom conditions for autonomy in terms of negative liberty con-
strue the freedom required for autonomy primarily as freedom from the undue interference of other
persons or the state. Theorists who understand the freedom conditions for autonomy in terms of sub-
stantive freedom or opportunity think that although some degree of negative liberty is a necessary con-
dition for autonomy it is insufficient. What matters for autonomy is the extent of a persons substantive
opportunities to be and to do. Autonomy-enabling opportunities require a lot more than freedom from
interference; they require substantial support by other persons and by state agencies.
28
Joseph Carens and Phillip Cole are examples of theorists who argue that liberal political prin-
ciples entail that freedom of international movement should be included among the basic liberties.
26 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
With respect to the personal liberties, again Ithink there is likely to be sub-
stantial agreement among liberal, democratic, and feminist theorists about the
basic personal liberties that are preconditions for self-determination. These lib-
erties include freedom of movement (if not international movement), freedom
of sexual expression, and freedom from all forms of coercion, manipulation,
exploitation, and violence, including sexual exploitation and assault. However,
again, there will be substantive disputes about what counts as coercion or ex-
ploitation. In bioethics, the question of how exploitation should be understood
is at the core of debates about the commodification of reproductive tissue, body
parts, and blood products. Bioethicists of a more libertarian persuasion, for
example, insist that commodificationthat is, markets in tissue, body parts,
and blood productsneed not be exploitative and that if properly regulated
such markets enable individual self-determination. Their critics argue that in
the constrained and often oppressive social contexts in which such markets
operate, commodification is inherently exploitative.29 Similarly, while liberal,
democratic, and feminist theorists support the principle of reproductive free-
dom, there are substantive disputes about how far this liberty should extend.
Bioethicists of a more libertarian persuasion think it extends to a right to deter-
mine the sex or to enhance the characteristics of ones offspring. Their critics re-
spond that the libertarian position equates autonomy with negative liberty and
mere preference satisfaction, fails to account for the social influences on and
social impacts of individual choice, and trivializes the responsibilities and obli-
gations attendant upon the exercise of reproductive autonomy, in particular
parental responsibilities for the well-being and future autonomy of children.30
Carens, Aliens and Citizens:The Case for Open Borders, Review of Politics 49:2 (1987):251273; Cole,
Open Borders:An Ethical Defense, in Debating the Ethics of Immigration:Is There a Right to Exclude?,
edited by Christopher Heath Wellman and Phillip Cole (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Liberal theorists who reject this claim and who seek to defend the rights of nation states to exclude
immigrants include Michael Blake, Immigration, in Companion to Applied Ethics, edited by R. Frey
and Christopher Heath Wellman (Malden, MA:Blackwell, 2005), 224237; David Miller, Immigrants,
Nations and Citizenship, Journal of Political Philosophy 16:4 (2008):371390. This is of course a com-
plex debate that Icannot enter into here, and Irefer to it purely for illustrative purposes.
29
Theorists who appeal to the right to self-determination to defend markets in body parts, tis-
sues, and eggs, include, e.g., J. Radcliffe-Richards, Selling Organs, Gametes and Surrogacy Services,
in The Blackwell Guide to Medical Ethics, edited by R. Rhodes, L. Francis, and A. Silvers (Malden,
MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2007), 254268; David Resnik, Regulating the Market for Human Eggs,
Bioethics 15:1 (2001):125; James Stacey Taylor, Autonomy, Constraining Options, and Organ Sales,
Journal of Applied Philosophy 19:3 (2002):273285. For critiques, see, e.g., Margaret Jane Radin, Contested
Commodities:The Trouble with the Trade in Sex, Children, Body Parts and Other Things (Cambridge,
MA:Harvard University Press, 1996); N. Scheper-Hughes, Illegal Organ Trade:Global Justice and the
Traffic in Human Organs, in Living Donor Organ Transplants, edited by Rainer Gruessner and Enrico
Benedetti (NewYork:McGraw-Hill, 2007), 106121; Tamara Zutlevics, Markets and the Needy:Organ
Sales or Aid? Journal of Applied Philosophy 18:3 (2001):297302.
30
The most well-known advocates of the libertarian position on genetic enhancement are Nicholas
Agar, Designing Babies: Morally Permissible Ways to Modify the Human Genome, Bioethics 9:1
(1995): 115; John Harris, Clones, Genes and Immortality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998);
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 27
With respect to both these issues, I disagree with the libertarian position.
Although I cannot engage in a detailed discussion of these specific normative
issues here, hopefully the basis for my stance will become clearer in what fol-
lows. What these debates point to is that although the freedom and opportunity
conditions for self-determination overlap and often converge they can also be in
tension. Theorists who understand freedom in terms of negative liberty are likely
to give more weight to freedom conditions than to opportunity conditions and
hence to interpret the freedom conditions quite expansively. Theorists who em-
phasize the importance of substantive equality of opportunity think that what is
important is not the promotion of freedom per se, since not all kinds of freedom
are either important or desirable, but those freedoms that enable equality of op-
portunity.31 According to this view, which freedom conditions count as important
will be determined by the opportunity conditions for self-determination. On my
interpretation, theories of relational autonomy prioritize opportunity conditions
and hence fall into this latter category of theory.
Opportunity conditions specify the personal, social, and political oppor-
tunities that are preconditions for individual self-determination. Among
theorists of autonomy, Raz is the most prominent exponent of the view that
self-determination, as Ihave defined it, requires access to an adequate array
of significant opportunities, or what he refers to as options.32 Although access
to options requires certain freedoms, in the form of basic rights and liberties,
Raz rejects the libertarian conception of freedom as minimally constrained
freedom of choice, arguing that this conception conflates self-determination
with license.33 Raz develops a nuanced analysis of options as those complex
and multidimensional activities, practices, and relationships that make our
lives meaningful, such as pursuing a career in a particular profession, being
a parent, being a member of a religious community, or participating in sport,
cultural activities, or politics. Options, in other words, are ways of life, dense
webs of complex actions and interactions, which depend on social prac-
tices, with their implicit rules, conventions, and shared meanings. Specific
options are available only to those who have developed the relevant skills, as
embodied in social practices and transmitted by habituation.34 Aculture,
Julian Savulescu, Procreative Beneficence:Why We Should Select the Best Children, Bioethics 15:56
(2001):413426.
I develop critiques of the libertarian position with respect to debates in bioethics in Mackenzie,
Autonomy:Individualistic or Social and Relational?; Conceptions of Autonomy and Conceptions of
the Body in Bioethics; Autonomy, in Arris etal., Routledge Companion to Bioethics.
31
This is clearly Nussbaums position as well, and it is on these grounds that she criticizes Sens in-
terpretation of capabilities theory as concerned with promoting freedom. See, e.g., Nussbaum, Creating
Capabilities,6976.
32
Raz, Morality of Freedom.
33
Raz, Multiculturalism:ALiberal Perspective in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain:Essays in the
Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1994) 17191.
34
Raz, Multiculturalism,177.
28 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Raz, Multiculturalism,177.
35
37
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,8486.
38
Elizabeth Anderson, What Is the Point of Equality?; Anderson, Justifying the Capabilities
Approach to Justice; Martha Nussbaum, Women and Human Development:The Capabilities Approach
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2000); Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice; Nussbaum, Creating
Capabilities; Ingrid Robeyns, Sens Capability Approach and Gender Inequality: Selecting Relevant
Capabilities, Feminist Economics 9:23 (2003):7184; Robeyns, Gender and the Metric of Justice, in
Brighouse and Robeyns, Measuring Justice, 215235.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 29
39
See Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1992) for a
detailed analysis of the notions of capability and functioning.
40
See the chapter on social choice in Sen, Idea of Justice.
41
For a recent version of this list, see Martha Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities.
42
Anderson, Justifying the Capabilities Approach to Justice,83.
43
Robeyns, Sens Capability Approach.
30 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
44
For the original formulation of the problem of adaptive preferences, see Jon Elster, Sour
Grapes:Studies in the Subversion of Rationality (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1983). For
its relevance in motivating capabilities theory, see Sen, Inequality Reexamined; Nussbaum, Women
and Human Development; Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options, Economics and
Philosophy 17 (2001):6788. For a recent discussion of its relevance for gender oppression, see Serene
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2011).
For discussion of its relevance to relational autonomy theory, see Natalie Stoljars contribution to this
volume.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 31
4. Self-governance:ARelational Conception
Self-governance, as Ihave defined it, involves having the skills and capacities
necessary to make choices and enact decisions that express or cohere with
ones reflectively constituted diachronic practical identity. The self-governance
dimension of autonomy picks out autonomy conditions (competence and
authenticity) that are in some sense internal to the person, whereas the
self-determination axis identifies external, structural conditions. However,
from a relational perspective, the distinction between internal and external
conditions is complicated. If persons are socially constituted, then external
conditions, including our social relations with others, shape the process of
practical identity formationthe self of self-governanceand the develop-
ment of the skills and competences required for governing the self. On the
one hand, this is not necessarily problematic from a relational perspective
it points to the facts of developmental and ongoing dependency and to the
extensive interpersonal, social, and institutional scaffolding necessary for
self-governance. On the other hand, in contexts of social oppression, as is
shown by the phenomenon of adaptive preference formation, severely limited
opportunity conditions can deform the process of practical identity formation
and impair the development and exercise of autonomy competence.
Authenticity conditions specify what it means to be self-governing with re-
spect to ones motivational structurethat is, what it means for a choice, value,
commitment, or reason to be ones own. Relational autonomy theorists are
critical of conceptions of self-governance, such as hierarchical or endorsement
conceptions, which analyze authenticity in terms of structural features of an
agents will at the time of choice or action. The argument, in brief, is that such
synchronic accounts and criteria for authenticity that appeal to relations of
internal coherence within the agents will (e.g., identification, endorsement)
fail to account for the historical processes of practical identity formation.45
In particular, they fail to account for the internalized effects of psychological
oppression, that is, the way oppression shapes agents practical identities and
motivational structures, for example their preferences, values, and cares.46
Furthermore, criteria for coherence, such as identification, wholehearted-
ness, or endorsement, seem to rule out any kind of ambivalence or internal
45
Examples of synchronic hierarchical theories include Dworkin, Theory and Practice of Autonomy;
Frankfurt, Importance of What We Care About. Endorsement theories include Gary Watson, Free
Agency, Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975):205220; Korsgaard, Sources of Normativity.
46
For the first critique along these lines, see Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy and the Split-Level
Self, Southern Journal of Philosophy 24:1 (1986):1935. For a more detailed overview, see Mackenzie
and Stoljar, Introduction:Autonomy Refigured. Christman is the best-known proponent of the his-
torical approach, first articulated in Christman, Autonomy and Personal History, Canadian Journal
of Philosophy 21 (1991): 124 and developed in its most sophisticated form in Christman, Politics of
Persons.
32 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
For critiques along these lines, see Benson, Taking Ownership; Oshana, Autonomy and
47
50
For discussion of the importance of these skills for autonomy, see especially Meyers, Self, Society
and Personal Choice; Mackenzie, Imagining Oneself Otherwise, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational
Autonomy, 124150; Mackenzie, Critical Reflection, Self-Knowledge, and the Emotions, Philosophical
Explorations 5:2 (2002):186206.
51
Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,1989).
52
Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities,3334.
34 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Nussbaum provides the most extensive discussion of these reasons in Nussbaum, Political
53
Liberalism and Respect: A Response to Linda Barclay, SATS: Nordic Journal of Philosophy 4:2
(2003):2544.
54
Nussbaum also seems to think that those who support the value of autonomy, such as Raz, think
that a life in which a person does not exercise this capacity is less valuable and less worthy of respect.
Idont think that Raz holds a derogatory view of persons whose lives are not autonomous. His view is
rather that individual autonomy is crucial for living a decent human life in contemporary democratic
societies and that therefore the state has an obligation to support its development and exercise by
ensuring that individuals have an adequate range of significant opportunities.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 35
Nussbaums second reason, which Ithink underpins the first, concerns the
relationship between autonomy and epistemic and normative authority. Itake
up this issue in the following section.
5. Self-authorization:ARelational Conception
55
See, e.g., Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy; Benson,
Taking Ownership; Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism;
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy.
56
Nussbaum, Political Liberalism and Respect,41.
36 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
57
See Taylors distinction between strong and weak evaluation in What Is Human Agency?
in Taylor, Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1985), 1544; Taylor, Sources of the Self. For Darwalls account of the second-person stand-
point, see Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint:Morality, Respect and Accountability (Cambridge,
MA:Harvard University Press,2006).
58
Benson, Taking Ownership; Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 37
59
For different variants, see, e.g., Trudy Govier, Self-Trust, Autonomy, and Self-Esteem, Hypatia
8 (2003):99120; Paul Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994):650
668; Carolyn McLeod, Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy; Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy,
Normative Authority and Perfectionism.
60
Anderson and Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice.
61
Anderson and Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice,132.
62
See Anderson, Vulnerability and Autonomy Intertwined for a detailed analysis of the inter-
relation between the psychological and normative dynamics of social recognition with respect to the
self-evaluative attitudes.
38 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
The impact of work on personal autonomy has been curiously neglected in the literature. This
63
neglect is a serious omission, given the importance of work for our lives. For valuable analyses of work
and autonomy, see Beate Roessler, Meaningful Work:Arguments from Autonomy, Journal of Political
Philosophy 20:1 (2012):7193; Andrea Veltmans contribution to this volume.
64
The question of how to distinguish appropriate from misplaced self-evaluative attitudes raises
complex psychological and normative issues that do need to be addressed by theorists who emphasize
the importance of these attitudes for autonomy. However, it is beyond the scope of my discussion in
this chapter to address this question.
65
For criticisms along these lines, see, e.g., John Christman, Relational Autonomy, Liberal
Individualism, and the Social Constitution of Selves, Philosophical Studies 117 (2004):143164; Jules
Holroyd, Relational Autonomy and Paternalistic Interventions, Res Publica 15:4 (2009):321336.
66
For a more detailed argument for this claim, see Mackenzie, Importance of Relational
Autonomy and Capabilities for an Ethics of Vulnerability.
Three Dimensions of Autonomy 39
Conclusion
67
This categorical notion of respect is what Stephen Darwall refers to as recognition respect, as dis-
tinct from appraisal respect, which involves positive evaluation of a persons character or accomplish-
ments and attributes and which is context dependent, earned, and a matter of degree. Darwall, Two
Kinds of Respect, Ethics 88 (1977):3649. It should be noted that having appropriate self-evaluative
attitudes seems to be dependent on both recognition and appraisal respect.
40 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the editors, Mark Piper and Andrea Veltman, for ex-
tremely helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter. Thanks also to
Natalie Stoljar for extensive and ongoing discussions about autonomy. Earlier
versions of the chapter were presented at the conference on Thick (Concepts of)
Autonomy, Institute for Advanced Study in Bioethics, University of Muenster,
and to a seminar at the University of Amsterdam. Thanks to audiences on both
occasions for helpful comments.
{3}
1
Catriona MacKenzie and Natalie Stoljar, eds., Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on
Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2000),4.
2
Jennifer Nedelsky, Laws Relations: A Relational Theory of Self, Autonomy, and Law
(NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2011). Some parts of this essay draw on my review of Nedelskys
book in the University of Toronto Law Journal, Volume 63, Number 2 (April2013).
Relational Autonomy and Independence 43
1. Liberal Individualism
3
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, e.g.,7.
4
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 3, 86. Ihave argued by contrast that mainstream theorists of autonomy,
whether specifically liberal or not, do not generally reject, and often mention, relational or social
connections in their accounts of personal autonomy. See Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy and Social
Relationships:Rethinking the Feminist Critique, in my Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2003),8197.
5
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 7,9,86.
6
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 382, note 14. Nedelsky also lists Ronald Dworkin, Owen Fiss, Frank
Michelman, and Cass Sunstein.
44 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
9
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,55.
10
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,45.
11
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 142. Nedelsky claims that in a 1964 essay Charles Reich associates this
sort of autonomy with property. Reich, The New Property, Yale Law Journal 73(5):733787.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 45
Nedelsky, may well be norms that a person recognizes as stemming from the
significance or aims of the life she is living.12
What is noteworthy is that Nedelsky gives all of these individualistic
sounding claims a relational interpretation. As quoted already, she asserts that
autonomy is a mode of interacting with others. She argues that, for a rela-
tional self, nothing is ever simply ones own. She holds that the capacity to find
ones own law must be nurtured by relationships and that the content of ones
own law is meaningful with reference to shared norms, values, and concepts.
Indeed, her whole project includes giving a relational interpretation to key con-
cepts that liberalism supposedly interprets individualistically, concepts such as
autonomy, equality, dignity, individuality, and individuation. For Nedelsky, all
of these values arise out of community and constitutive relationships.13
Also significant is Nedelskys insistence that her relational interpretation
does not deny the significance of the experience of making or claiming some-
thing as ones own.... As well, recognizing the centrality of relationships does
not entail denying the value of privacy or solitude. Rather, it reveals how these
values are sustained by practices of allowing people to step back from each
other in certain ways.14 In general, Nedelsky insists that her approachis
very attentive to and concerned with the particular individual. Indeed,
Iwould say that Ihave insisted on such attention. Much of the relational
approach is a call to attend to the individual in her particularity, which must
include her particular context.15
Nedelsky writes that her approach
participates in the vision of self-defining interiority as the core of what is
human, the ground and purpose of the liberal commitment to freedom. At
the same time, Iurge a return to relationality as constitutive of self.... One
might say that Iam trying to claim the best of both worlds, to propose a kind
of synthesis. Iembrace the notion of the unique, infinite value of each indi-
vidual, and the value of interiority, and the value of the ability of individuals
to shape their own lives. But Ireject the liberal variants of these values that
fail to see the central role relation plays in each of them.16
Thus, Nedelskys relational interpretation, by her own account, does not
undermine the apparent individualism of many of her own claims about au-
tonomy. Instead she accommodates their apparent individualism. She either
reconceptualizes those claims in relational terms or simply combines them
as they stand with relational ideas. This prompts a question: Why not treat
12
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 46, 166167, 123124, 121,33.
13
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 55, 49, 124,36.
14
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 49,33.
15
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,374.
16
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,36.
46 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
17
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,55.
18
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,52.
19
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,5152.
20
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 36,52.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 47
called for at the outset. First, Nedelsky is mistaken to suggest that the dom-
inant picture of autonomy is opposition to the collective. That is not the
dominant picture among philosophers, at any rate.21 No major philosophical
account of autonomy holds that autonomy requires opposition to any col-
lective norms, roles, or practices. Philosophical accounts generally include
procedural requirements that a person reflect on her choices, values, or com-
mitments. When philosophical accounts specify the sorts of commitments a
person must hold to be autonomous, these commitments usually have to do
with valuing autonomy or regarding oneself in a certain way, such as trusting
oneself.22 Opposition to collective norms or traditions is not typically a philos-
ophers defining feature of autonomy. Also, although philosophical accounts
do not always emphasize the collective origin of an individuals perspective,
this is usually not precluded either.23
It is possible that Nedelsky is aiming her critique at popular conceptions
of autonomy rather than those in academic philosophy. However, philosoph-
ical works are still legitimate sources of counterexamples since there is a sub-
stantial amount of work in philosophy on autonomy and, especially, on liberal
theories in which autonomy figures as a fundamental value. Also, Nedelsky
makes clear that academic philosophy is among her targets; for example, she
points to a still powerful individualism within academic political theory and
philosophy.24
A second reservation about Nedelskys combined individualized and rela-
tional approach is this. There is need for clarification of how the individu-
alism that remains in Nedelskys account coheres with the relationality that she
claims as fundamental. It seems that, on Nedelskys account, individualistic
ideas about autonomy arise when one first thinks about autonomy, ideas such
as finding ones own law. Relationality seems to enter Nedelskys account
when those starting points are explained. One interpretation of Nedelskys
approach is that the relational explanations of autonomy replace and thereby
eliminate the individualism of the initial understandings of autonomy. On this
interpretation of Nedelsky, the deeper explanatory understanding gets at what
is really true about autonomous selves. Individualistic appearances of au-
tonomy would turn out to have been mere appearances without any deeper
reality.
21
This is important because it is not clear that many people outside philosophy actually deal in any
depth with the concept of autonomy.
22
On self-trust, see, e.g., Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition,
and Justice, in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism:New Essays, edited by John Christman and
Joel Anderson (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005), 127149.
23
Nedelsky seems to direct her critique toward at least three different social sectors: academic
theorists (including philosophers), law, and government. My comments deal with academic theorists
unless otherwise indicated.
24
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,9.
48 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
27
Cf. Audre Lorde, The Masters Tools Will Never Dismantle the Masters House, in Audre Lorde,
Sister Outsider:Essays and Speeches (Berkeley, CA:Crossing Press, 1984), 110113.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 49
of that different role, challenges to the idea of self-made persons do not un-
dermine any particular conceptions of autonomy. My conclusion to the next
section will be that the idea of self-made persons should be dropped from
debates over autonomy.
28
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 120,49.
50 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
president of the company. From this position, he eventually bought out the
original owner. At the time of his death in 1967, my uncle was a millionaire
(when that was still a lot of money!) who owned the company in which he had
started out as a low-ranking laborer. He reached his successful position from
humble origins that involved no inherited wealth, immigrant status, English as
a second language, and few if any special privileges.
Nedelsky claims that terms such as independent and self-made man refer to
myths and illusions. In her view, no one is really independent or a self-made
person.29 Nedelsky would be right about self-made man if this expression were
taken literally. Aliteral interpretation would treat a self-made man as one who
created himself out of nothing. This idea is, of course, metaphysically ridicu-
lous. (I can assure you that my family did not think my uncle created him-
self out of nothing. My grandmother would have had a thing or two to say
aboutthat.)
There is another interpretation of self-made person that may not be meta-
physically impossible but would come very close to it. According to this sec-
ond interpretation, a self-made man is one who depended on no other persons
in any way on his path toward workplace success. This notion would also be
wrong because any successful career person had to have depended on other
persons and on social institutions for the care, support, technology, means of
communication, and so on that allowed the successful person to grow from
childhood and do what he or she did to succeed.
To be sure, several contemporary social commentators agree with Nedelsky
in rejecting the image of the self-made person. Brian Miller and Mike Laphams
book The Self-Made Myth:The Truth About How Government Helps Individuals
and Businesses Succeed30 shows the central role played by government in creat-
ing the conditions that enable people to gain economic prosperity. The gov-
ernment provides public education, a regulatory environment that protects
businesses, copyright and intellectual property laws, an infrastructure in-
cluding roads and airports, and support for the Internet. Miller and Lapham
also observe that success is partly due to luck, fortunate timing, and sources of
social capital such as race, gender, appearance, and upbringing.31 Social capital
is obviously relational.
29
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 43, 118, 120. Asimilar position is defended by Iris Young, Autonomy,
Welfare Reform, and Meaningful Work, in The Subject of Care:Feminist Perspectives on Dependency,
edited by Eva Feder Kittay and Ellen K. Feder (Lanham, MD:Rowman & Littlefield, 2002),4060.
30
Brian Miller and Mike Lapham, The Self-Made Myth: The Truth About How Government
Helps Individuals and Businesses Succeed (San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers, 2012); cited
favorably by Sara Robinson, Self-made men debunked, http://www.salon.com/2012/04/30/
self_made_men-debunked_salpart/print/.
31
Miller and Lapham, Self-Made Myth,23.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 51
32
MikeMyatt,Self-MadeManNoSuchThing,http://www.forbes.com/sites/mikemyatt/2011/11/15/self-
made-man-no-such-thing/print/.
33
Myatt, Self-Made Man,1,2.
52 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Frederick Douglass, Self-Made Men, in The Frederick Douglass Papers, Series One, vol. 4, edited
34
by John Blassinghame and John McKivigan (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1992), 545575.
See also http://www.monadnock.net/douglass/self-made-men.html. References here are to the online
version.
35
Douglass, Self-Made Men,4.
36
Douglass, Self-Made Men,4.
37
Douglass, Self-Made Men,5.
38
Douglass, Self-Made Men,5.
39
Douglass, Self-Made Men, 12,14.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 53
My theory of self-made men is, then, simply that they are men of work....
[H]onest labor faithfully, steadily and persistently pursued, is the best, if not
the only, explanation of their success.... Other agencies co-operate, but this
is the principal one and the one without which all others would fail.40
Douglass is clear that self-made men need relationships with others. However,
this need for relationships does not prevent self-made man from having a
qualified, nonliteral meaning, namely, as that of a man (today:person) who
comes from humble origins and achieves great success due principally to her
or his own hardwork.
Another example of my interpretation of self-made persons can be found
in an article on an otherwise objectionable website on The Art of Manliness.
The article is entitled 25 of the Greatest Self-Made Men in American History
and is coauthored by Brett McKay and Kate McKay.41 The authors explain what
they mean by self-mademan:
anyone who attains far greater success than his original circumstances would
have indicated was possible. The self-made man often has to overcome great
obstacles to achieve his goals. Self-made men attain their success through
education, hard work, and sheer willpower. While no man is an island, its
not external help or special relationships that make the crucial difference in
the self-made mans rise.... Nor is luck the deciding factor.... While there
are always many factors to success, all are subordinate to work, which is the
great key to success.42
McKay and McKay do not deny that education, relationships (no man is an
island), and luck play a role; what they claim is that the deciding factor, the
great key to success is how hard the self-made man works. The concept of a
self-made person is, in their view, the concept of someone who achieves ca-
reer success that is unusual in light of his humble origins and is based, among
other things, most importantly on his hard work. Their qualified terminology
again allows that relationships could be included among the conditions that
together explain success in these cases. However, the authors single out hard
work as the most important factor. Understood in this way as a comparative
concept, the idea of a self-made person becomes harder to dismiss as mythic
or illusory.43
40
Douglass, Self-Made Men,17.
41
Brett McKay and Kate McKay, 25 of the Greatest Self-Made Men in American History, http://
artofmanliness.com/2008/12/28/self-made-men/print.
42
McKay and McKay, 25 of the Greatest Self-Made Men,1.
43
Readers might disagree with the twenty-five examples of self-made men that McKay and McKay,
25 of the Greatest Self-Made Men, list. However, the list does span something of a political and eco-
nomic range. It includes Clarence Thomas, Barack Obama, Ronald Reagan, Harry Truman, Harry
Reid, Frederick Douglass, Booker T.Washington, Henry Ford, Ralph Lauren, Sean Combs, and Ben
& Jerry (326).
54 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Recall that Miller and Lapham challenge the concept of the self-made
person on a very specific point. They are not making a general claim that eve-
ryone is dependent on other persons in many ways. They are instead making
the more specific claim that every successful businessperson depends on gov-
ernment.44 Their argument is with those who reject government programs
and regulations in particular. At least two sorts of government programs and
regulations are relevant:those that intervene in business activities and those
that provide welfare services for the poor and needy.45 Let us consider welfare
programs more specifically.
Critics of welfare programs might agree that everyone is dependent on some
others in various ways but argue that we are not all dependent on government
handouts; they might cite self-made persons as examples of those who do not
depend on government programs. Miller and Lapham, as noted already, argue
specifically that successful business people are dependent on government sup-
port in one form or another. This argument makes it even clearer that debates
over self-made persons are irrelevant to the debates over autonomy because
relational theorists of autonomy are not trying to make the case that autonomy
requires dependence on government in particular.
However, Miller and Laphams argument is very relevant to what I be-
lieve the concept of self-made person is really about. As I argued earlier, a
self-made person, as understood by those who defend the concept in a plau-
sible way, is a person who achieves great career success despite humble origins
and principally by hard work. If people can be self-made in this sense, then
being self-made is not humanly impossible, and human impossibility would
be the wrong reason for excluding the idea of self-made persons from accounts
of autonomy.
However, there is a right reason for excluding the image of self-made person
from debates over autonomy. The right reason is that the image of self-made
persons is not an image of autonomyat least not an image that necessarily
meets philosophical definitions of autonomy. For example, it is not about
self-reflection or acting authentically according to ones own values. Defenders
of the concept of self-made person are not assuming that a self-made person
reflects on her own values or commitments in any way, let alone endorses
them. Aself-made person may or may not exemplify autonomy in any philo-
sophical definition of theterm.
A self-made person is one who is (presumed to be) a success in con-
ventional capitalist terms. The debate over self-made persons, I suggest, is
For a discussion of the concept of dependency in relation to welfare programs, cf. Nancy Fraser
45
and Linda Gordon, A Genealogy of Dependency: Tracing a Keyword of the U.S. Welfare State, in
Kittay and Feder, Subject of Care,1439.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 55
implicitly part of debates over the nature and value of capitalism and the re-
lated debate over the justification of welfare programs. Praise for a self-made
person tends to reflect a capitalist, anti-welfare-program mentality. A suc-
cessful businessperson who started her work life in the paid labor force with
few resources (and no friends in high places) and worked her way up the
business ladder is an epitome of what capitalist defenders say is possible in
capitalism.46
Perhaps there could be a sense of self-made person that is relevant to au-
tonomy. If so, we should not simply speculate on what that sense would be
like. We should first find expressions of such an account by those who would
actually defend it. Otherwise, we would risk conjuring up, and then attacking,
a straw person. Thus far, my admittedly nonsystematic researches into public
debates over the idea of self-made persons do not reveal any important mean-
ings that are relevant to the concept of autonomy.
It thus appears that the insistence that self-made persons are a mythic illu-
sion fails to discredit either capitalism or autonomy. It fails to discredit capi-
talism because there are examples of self-made persons, in the nonliteral sense
its defenders have in mind. If a self-made person is someone who starts her
income-producing work life from humble origins, works hard in that capacity,
and becomes successful in conventional capitalist terms, then there do seem to
be some of those persons around. Ibelieve my uncle was an example. McKay
and McKay, as noted earlier, give famous contemporary examples. However,
and more importantly for this essay, even if self-made persons are genuine pos-
sibilities, this tells us nothing about how to understand autonomy. As Ihave
been arguing, the idea of self-made persons, even in the plausible, nonliteral
sense, is not about autonomy.
46
The economically successful person who rose up from humble origins is supposed to be evi-
dence that the inequalities of capitalism are not absolute barriers to success in the workplace. If some
people can be self-made, that is, can achieve economic success principally by hard work even from
humble origins, then, so the story goes, anyone who works hard can do so as well; poverty is no neces-
sary barrier to workplace success. From this perspective, welfare programs serve only those who refuse
to work hard or to work at all at an income-producing job. Refuting this claim is part of the significance
of the argument in Miller and Lapham, Self-Made Myth, that all businesspeople depend on government
in particular.
Thus, the existence of self-made persons does not bring the critique of capitalism to an end. Far
from it. Those who oppose capitalism have various options. They can argue that, even if a few people
can achieve career success from humble origins by working hard, such successes are so few in number
that their existence does not show that the system is inherently fair. They can debate the extent to which
such lives are still possible today. They can ask what costs and trade-offs are imposed on those who
dont succeed, and, especially, on their young children and other dependents? Critics of capitalism do
not yield any ground by conceding the possibility of self-made persons, in the sense that Douglass and
others definethem.
56 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
3.Independence
47
The idea that independence is a form of relationship involving dependency appears in
Nancy Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender
(Berkeley:University of California Press, 1978), e.g., 187188.
48
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 1920,31.
Relational Autonomy and Independence 57
to cover her financial needs. Why be reluctant to say that she is financially
independent?
This notion of financial independence leaves open the possibility that the
person in question is relatively dependent in nonfinancial ways. The finan-
cially independent woman may rely on other persons to grow her food, build
her dwelling, and provide her health care. Also the notion of financial inde-
pendence is quite consistent with the idea that the person in question was
constituted by early relationships with parents and teachers and continues
in adulthood to be constituted by relationships with friends and by gender
norms and employment practices. Thus, my proposed use of independent is
easily consistent with a relational approach to selves and to autonomy. On my
proposal, independence, interpreted as a relatively low form of some type of
dependency, need not be a myth or an illusion.
Why does the idea of independence matter to an account of autonomy? Are
there any special reasons for wanting to reclaim the idea of independence?
Ibelieve there are such reasons. Independence can identify a useful ideal for
disadvantaged or subordinated persons to aim at. It can constitute one legiti-
mate goal among many for emancipatory movements. Onora ONeill, for one,
cites financial independence as a valuable attribute for women worldwide.49
Poor women worldwide are often dependent on the economic terms and con-
ditions set by others. As ONeill writes:
They are vulnerable not only to low wages, low standards of industrial safety,
endemic debt and disadvantageous dependence on those who provide
credit, but also to disadvantageous patterns of entitlement within the family.
Debtors who need further loans for survival cannot make much fuss about
the terms creditors offer for purchasing their crops; the most dependent
womendaughters-in-law and younger daughters in some societiesare
acutely vulnerable both to market forces and to more powerfulkin.50
The term independence can serve to stand for a capacity that Nedelsky her-
self lauds, namely, the human capacity for creation in the shaping of ones life
and self. It can serve to guide a feminist concern that Nedelsky cites, namely,
freeing women to shape their own lives and to define themselves rather than
accepting the definition given by others (men and male-dominated society, in
particular).51
49
See Onora ONeill, Justice, Gender, and International Boundaries, in Onora ONeill, The
Bounds of Justice (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2000), 162167. See also my discussion of
ONeill on these issues in Marilyn Friedman, Independence, Dependence, and the Liberal Subject,
in Reading Onora ONeill, edited by David Archard, Monique Deveaux, Neil Manson, and Daniel
Weinstock (Abingdon:Routledge, forthcoming), 111129.
50
ONeill, Justice, Gender, and International Boundaries,164.
51
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,121.
58 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 4243. On this point, Nedelsky cites Margaret Walker, Moral Contexts
53
as people should not be stigmatized for failing to develop any capability for
which they lacked appropriate relationships or material circumstances.
However, the faulty application of an ideal of independence does not entail
that independence is a faulty ideal.55 The key point for discussions of autonomy
is that if independence is defined as the lesser form of some specific type of
dependence, then independence is humanly possible. In addition, persons can
be independent in some ways while being (more) dependent in otherways.
We can also ask whether any sort of independence is especially impor-
tant for autonomy. The notion of independent-mindedness comes to mind.
Saying that someone is independent-minded seems highly relevant to saying
she is an autonomous person, even if it is not the only relevant considera-
tion.56 Independent-mindedness need not be interpreted as a narrow kind of
rationality or rational agency. Mindedness can encompass reason, emotion,
desire, will, and so on.57 Nedelskys own conception of autonomy fits well with
a notion of independent-mindedness. As discussed earlier, Nedelsky writes
that autonomy involves finding ones own law, which consists of values and
commitments that arise from within the self and are not imposed by others.58
Nedelsky does not use the term independent-mindedness for her account, but
there is no need for her to reject it. As Ihave been suggesting, independence
can be understood consistently with a relational account of autonomy, and it
offers a valuable aspirational ideal for women and other subordinated persons.
One final point about liberalism, independence, and autonomy: Nedelsky
criticizes liberalism for focusing on the way people are threats to each other and
ignoring the positive or constructive ways they affect each other relationally.
Nedelsky suggests that regarding individuals as independent and as threats to
each other is at odds with regarding them as constitutive of each other.59
However, the two perspectives are not incompatible at all. First, an emphasis
on the threats posed by (some) others does not entail a belief that all others are
55
One widely scorned sort of dependency is dependency on government programs by those who
are poor and need those programs to meet their basic needs. Nedelsky is concerned that the esteem for
independence becomes part of a discrediting of the poor for their (welfare) dependency. Nedelskys
strategy for contesting this approach is to discredit the standard of independence so that it is not avail-
able for condemning people who depend on welfare services.
However, criticizing the idea of independence does not succeed in defending welfare programs.
One key question is whether welfare programs are required or justifiable as a matter of justice.
Unfortunately, discrediting independence does not make a positive case for the justice of social wel-
fare programs. Arguing that no one is literally independent and everyone is dependent does not by
itself justify government programs that redistribute wealth to those dependents who arepoor.
56
For a strong defense of the importance of favorable external social conditions, see Marina
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate,2006).
57
The notion of independent mindedness may seem to exclude embodiment. This could be rem-
edied, however, by building embodiment into the accounts of reason, emotion, desire, and will. Most
scientific accounts of mindedness today are accounts of brain function.
58
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 46,123.
59
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,121.
60 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to the editors, Andrea Veltman and Mark Piper, for helpful sug-
gestions on an earlier draft of this chapter.
60
People are no more always constitutive of each other than they are always threats to each other.
Also, lives can vary in the proportions of each sort of relationships.
61
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,6.
62
Nedelsky, Laws Relations,211.
63
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 22, does say, at one point, that liberalism has not paid the right kind of
attention to threats to persons.
{4}
1
See particularly Martha Fineman, The Autonomy Myth:ATheory of Dependency (NewYork:New
Press, 2004). But also see Sarah Lucia Hoagland, Lesbian Ethics: Toward New Values (Palo Alto,
CA:Institute of Lesbian Studies, 1989); Catharine Keller, From a Broken Web:Separation, Sexism, and
Self (Boston:Beacon,1986).
2
Nancy J. Hirschmann, Rethinking Obligation: A Feminist Method for Political Theory (Ithaca,
NY:Cornell University Press,1992).
62 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Harding and Evelyn Fox Keller, not to mention social theorists like Dorothy
Dinnerstein and Jessica Benjamin.3 This feminist deployment of object rela-
tions theory arguably ushered in a revolution within the ongoing revolution of
feminist theory by kick-starting the argument that, rather than rejecting the
traditional work of care and relationship that women have historically been
assigned to, we should value its contributions and importance to the human
condition.
Yet I have become more ambivalent about the concept of relational au-
tonomy in recent years. Part of this ambivalence stems from the work on the
concept of freedom that I have done, in which I have increasingly come to
believe that whatever desires, preferences, and abilities our relationships may
have led us to have, we need to act by and for ourselves. Even when we act
wrongly, perhaps even against our own interests, we must be free to so act.
Ibelieve that this position diverges from the views of many (though not all)
relational autonomy theorists because freedom is still relevant even if an agent
fails a variety of autonomy tests and measures. Consider, for instance, a driver
who causes an accident while drunk:even if we excuse her decision to drive
(on the argument that her judgment was impaired), the choice to drink in the
first place when she knew that she had to drive home afterward clearly fails var-
ious autonomy tests of self-reflective judgment and rational self-interest. But
we consider her action free, which is why we hold her responsible for the harm
she causes. I may want to act recklessly, irrationally, even self-destructively,
but the freedom to choose to act in such ways is nonetheless important to our
conception of a person:we want to be able to make our own choices.
Part of my ambivalence, however, stems from going back to where rela-
tional autonomy started:object relations theory. The psychoanalytic origin of
relational autonomy is something that we tend to forget about, and this forget-
ting suppresses the dark side of relational autonomy, a suppressing that Ihave
been as guilty of as anyone.
That worry is the starting point for this paper. Ibegin by describing object
relations theorys account of relational autonomy and why Ithink it is prob-
lematic for feminism. Ithen turn to the ways feminist accounts of freedom and
agency can help us get beyond this problematic point of origin. My goal is not
to argue against autonomy per se, much less against relational autonomy. Indeed,
3
Nancy Hartsock, Money, Sex and Power: Toward a Feminist Historical Materialism (Evanston,
IL: Northeastern University Press, 1983); Jane Flax, Political Philosophy and the Patriarchal
Unconscious: A Psychoanalytic Perspective on Epistemology and Metaphysics, in Discovering
Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science,
edited by Sandra Harding and Merrill B. Hintikka (Dordrecht:D. Reidel, 1983); Christine DiStefano,
Configurations of Masculinity:AFeminist Perspective on Modern Political Theory (Ithaca, NY:Cornell
University Press, 1991); Sandra Harding, The Science Question in Feminism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1986); Evelyn Fox Keller, Reflections on Gender and Science (New Haven, CT:Yale
University Press, 1985); Dorothy Dinnerstein, The Mermaid and the Minotaur:Sexual Arrangements and
Human Malaise (NewYork:Harper and Row, 1976); Jessica Benjamin, The Bonds of Love:Psychoanalysis,
Feminism, and the Problem of Domination (NewYork:Pantheon,1988).
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 63
feminists such as Drucilla Cornell, Wendy Brown, Linda Zerilla, and Ihave de-
veloped many shared concerns and features between autonomy and conceptions
of freedom, even as different as those theories are from one another.4 Rather,
Iwant to suggest that recognizing the problems of relationality may lead us to
the view that it is appropriate to conceive of autonomy only in tandem with a
theory of freedom. Indeed, perhaps relational autonomy should be better thought
of as relational freedom. As a more open-ended concept, Isuggest that freedom
may allow for more flexibility in how we theorize the choice-making subject, and
Iclose the paper with some speculative notes on that suggestion.
4
Drucilla Cornell, At the Heart of Freedom:Feminism, Sex, and Equality (Princeton, NJ:Princeton
University Press, 1999); Wendy Brown, States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity
(Princeton, NJ:Princeton University Press, 1995); Linda Zerilli, Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom
(Chicago:University of Chicago Press, 2005); Nancy J. Hirschman, The Subject of Liberty:Toward a
Feminist Theory of Freedom (Princeton, NJ:Princeton University Press,2003).
5
Flax, Political Philosophy and the Patriarchal Unconscious,250.
6
Margaret Mahler, On Human Symbiosis and the Vicissitudes of Individuation (New York:
International University Press,1968).
7
Flax, Political Philosophy and the Patriarchal Unconscious,251.
64 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
8
Nancy Chodorow, Feminism and Difference:Gender, Relation, and Difference in Psychoanalytic
Perspective, Socialist Review 46 (JulyAugust 1979):54.
9
Nancy Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender
(Berkeley:University of California Press, 1978),78.
10
Chodorow, Reproduction of Mothering, 150; Mahler, Human Symbiosis; see also Flax, Political
Philosophy, 251; Jane Flax, The Conflict between Nurturance and Autonomy in MotherDaughter
Relationships and within Feminism, Feminist Studies 4:2 (1978):171189.
11
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Prose of the World, edited by Claude Lefort, translated by John
ONeill (Evanston, IL:Northwestern University Press,1968).
12
Again, operating within a heteronormative framework in which there are only two genders.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 65
woman, girl infants see themselves as the same as, or connected to, the entire
outside world, whereas boy infants sees themselves as separate from, or even
opposed to, thatworld.
That is, as a girl identifies with her mother and perceives a basic definitional
connection and continuity between herself and her mother, she also sees the
world itself, as represented by her mother, as continuous and connected with
her. Her otherthe not-me, the boundary of the selfis very much con-
nected to and part of the self. Self and other constitute a continuum, a move-
ment from the core self to external objects that she perceives as connected to
her core self. The self, to a significant degree, is the other.13 In contrast, for the
boy, self and other constitute a dichotomy; since gender is viewed as a mu-
tually exclusive category and it is culturally forbidden for him to identify as
female, he is culturally and psychically forced to expel that part of himself that
is embodied by his mother. But that is an impossible task. Under conditions
of patriarchy, the boy copes with this task by denial (of having been related),
by projection (women are bad; they cause these problems), and by domination
(mastering fears and wishes for regression by controlling, depowering, and/
or devaluing the object [viz. women]).14 The other is radically separated and
different from the self:other is female; self is male. In doing this, masculinity
is defined by the boy in negative terms, that is, as that which is not feminine
and/or connected to women.15
This gender difference leads to two different models of autonomy. For the
boy, autonomy is conceptualized reactively, as a reaction against the mother.
According to Evelyn Fox Keller, reactive autonomy confuses autonomy with
separation and independence from others.16 Reactive autonomy is static, ac-
cording to Keller, because it is locked into a reductive and negative conception
of the self as non-mother. If autonomy is defined as, in her terms, the psy-
chological sense of being able to act under ones own volition instead of under
external control and turns on individuality and the integrity of the self, then
reactive autonomy is self-defeating. In fact, it robs the individual of self-creative
agency, for such autonomy is premised on an artificial separateness that cannot
be sustained without repression and on abstract roles and rules, which are
13
Chodorow, Reproduction of Mothering,93.
14
Flax, Political Philosophy and the Patriarchal Unconscious, 253. Other feminists, like Hartsock
in Money, Sex and Power, further maintain that violence is another tool men use to establish their dis-
tinction from the mother. Indeed, erotic violence and the linkage of sex with domination is, Hartsock
argues, the logical outcome of this situation, a conclusion with which other object relations theorists
at least implicitly agree, such as Dinnerstein, Mermaid and the Minotaur; Benjamin, Bonds of Love;
Harding, Science Question in Feminism.
15
Chodorow, Reproduction of Mothering, 174, 175. By negative Ido not imply a normative judg-
ment; Imean only that it is defined as not female.
16
Keller, Reflections on Gender and Science,97.
66 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Ibid.
17
David Bakan, The Duality of Human Existence: Isolation and Communion in Western Man
18
23
Flax, Political Philosophy and the Patriarchal Unconscious; Hartsock, Money, Sex and Power;
DiStefano, Configurations of Masculinity; Hirschmann, Rethinking Obligation.
24
Harding, Science Question; Keller, Reflections on Gender and Science.
68 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
of individual identity. Mahler and Winnicott similarly show how the girls in-
ability to separate adequately from the mother creates serious problems of de-
veloping self-confidence, self-awareness, and even an understanding of the self
as an individual.25 And Flax notes that girls have the most serious difficulty in
psychically separating themselves from their mothers, a difficulty that carries
through into adulthood and into their own roles as mothers. She cites clin-
ical evidence that female therapy patients commonly express a lack of sense
where they end and their mothers begin, even in a literal, physical way.26 This
finding is supported by Macoby and Jacklins work on the gender-specific ways
mothers discipline boys and girls.27
As Chodorow put it in probably the most famous passage from The
Reproduction of Mothering: Girls emerge from this period with a basis for
empathy built into their primary definition of self in a way that boys do not.
Girls emerge with a stronger basis for experiencing anothers needs or feelings
as ones own (or of thinking that one is so experiencing anothers needs and feel-
ings).28 Ihave added emphasis to that conditional phrase because it is signifi-
cant that Chodorow puts it in parentheses, as if to obscure it for the reader. But
what it describes is the pathology of the lack of separation, the notion that we
think we experience others feelings as our own. We know that Icannot liter-
ally feel what you feel; even Hume acknowledged that sympathetic vibrations
were less pronounced in the string next to the one plucked.29 Parents who have
had a seriously ill or injured child and who have desperately wished or prayed
that they could take on their childs suffering know that we cannot feel the
others feelings; we can only imagine and mourn. We suffer at the suffering of
others, but it is of a qualitatively different nature. Believing that you literally
feel anothers feelings as your own, as Flaxs clinical patients reported, is a sign
of pathology called borderline personality syndrome.30
But many relational autonomy theorists tend to forgetor indeed per-
haps were never awarethat this is where the idea of relational autonomy
25
Bakan, Duality of Human Existence; Mahler, Human Symbiosis; D. W. Winnicott, The Family and
Individual Development (NewYork:Tavistock,1965).
26
Flax, Conflict between Nurturance and Autonomy,174.
27
Eleanor Macoby and Carol Jacklin, The Psychology of Sex Difference (Stanford: Stanford
University Press,1975).
28
Chodorow, Reproduction of Mothering,167.
29
David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries Concerning
Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by L. A. Selby-Bigg, 3rd ed.,
revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1975); Nancy J. Hirschmann, Sympathy, Empathy,
and Obligation: A Feminist Rereading, in Feminist Interpretations of David Hume, edited by Anne
Jacobsen (University Park:Pennsylvania State University Press,1999).
30
Jane Flax, Thinking Fragments: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and Postmodernism in the
Contemporary West (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990). Dinnerstein, Mermaid and the
Minotaur, which Ihave not brought into the discussion because even Ifind it too gloomy in its por-
trayal of the disastrous gender inequality that womens mothering produces, provides an even stronger
account of this pathology.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 69
originates. Even those who have never read this literature, however, should be
aware that the idea of relational autonomy emerged out of this trajectory, from
nonfeminist analysts like Mahler and Winnicott to feminist nonphilosophers
such as Chodorow, Dinnerstein, Gilligan, and Benjamin, to feminist philos-
ophers and political theorists such as Keller, Harding, and Hartsock. From
there, the concept of relational autonomy was taken up by feminist theorists
and philosophers who may not have even read this literature, despite the effec-
tive critiques that leading feminist philosophers, such as Diana Meyers, have
made ofit.31
None of this is to deny that there are valid objections to object relations
theory. It is often difficult to recognize the family forms it depends on, namely,
the heterosexual two-parent family where the woman has primary responsi-
bility for child care. It may at times seem more appropriate to an episode of
Mad Men than to the complicated lives we live today. After all, feminists have
struggled for the past three decades to change this family structure, and many
of us are very proud of the fact that, in our own families, male and female
partners share equally (more or less) in childrearing. We are also rightly proud
of the fact that different family forms, such as gay and lesbian families, have
succeeded in part because of our political advocacy.
But let me offer a reminder: we are not the majority or the mainstream.
Studies show that although the sexual division of labor has shifted somewhat,
women still perform the bulk of labor associated with childrearing, and partic-
ularly early childrearing (the first six months of life).32 Although some women
have male partners who also took parental leave, it is still rare, even among
feminists, for men to be as actively engaged in early infant care as women.33
31
Diana T. Meyers, The Subversion of Womens Agency in Psychoanalytic Feminism:Chodorow,
Flax, Kristeva, in Revaluing French Feminism:Critical Essays on Difference, Agency, and Culture, edited
by Nancy Fraser and Sandra Lee Bartky (Bloomington:Indiana University Press, 1992). Idisagree with
her that Chodorow deploys a traditional feminine tendency to reduce care and nurturance to conflict
minimization and uncritical support (140), because Ithink Meyers downplays the role of capitalism
in Chodorows argument. However, Ithink she is correct that Chodorow ends up valorizing feminine
pathology in spite of herself. See also Meyers, Gender in the Mirror: Cultural Imagery and Womens
Agency (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2002), esp. chap.1.
32
Rhona Mahoney, Kidding Ourselves:Breadwinning, Babies, and Bargaining Power (Boston:Basic
Books, 1996). According to research funded by the National Science Foundation, women are still doing
two to three times more household work:seventeen to twenty-eight hours per week for women versus
seven to ten hours per week for men. Bobbie Mixon, Chore Wars:Men, Women and Housework,
http://www.nsf.gov/discoveries/disc_summ.jsp?cntn_id=111458.
33
See, e.g., the symposium on Nancy J. Hirschmann, Mothers Who Care Too Much, Boston
Review, JulyAugust 2012, particularly the response of Lane Kenworthy, Time for Public Childcare,
and my response to him, The Sexual Division of Labor is the Problem. Particularly relevant to
readers of this volume is an American Association of University Women study showing that among
tenure-track faculty, parental leave is associated with positive outcomes at tenure for men but negative
outcomes for women, the implication being that many men use such leaves to advance their scholar-
ship whereas women use them to care for their infants exclusively. Mary Ann Mason, Title IX and
Babies:The New Frontier? Chronicle of Higher Education, November 29,2012.
70 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
But even so, object relations theory posits that the solution to patriarchy is
precisely what feminists strive for todayshared parenting and redistributing
the sexual division of labor. That is, although object relations theory may de-
scribe a natural process of human developmentin the sense that the devel-
oping infantile brain responds to the external stimuli of its relationships with
other people who shape its encounter with the physical worldthe particular
form those reactions take will differ by the specific cultural practices of child-
rearing. Within the profoundly sexist late-capitalist Western sexual division of
labor, we end up with gender dichotomy. Object relations theory shows that
the sexual division of labor is not just unfair to women:it is damaging to boys
and mens psychic and emotional well-being as well. Accordingly, feminists
who mother in heterosexual relationships where men share equally, as well as
gay and lesbian shared parenting families that radically break the heteronor-
mative pattern, offer significant hope for the feminist future we all seek. This
does not disprove the theory but rather supportsit.
It is also important to remember that psychoanalytic theory is best under-
stood not as a series of reductive empirical claims about infantile psychology
but is rather an interpretive framework. Certainly, part of the logic of psy-
chology and psychoanalysis entails the attempt to understand the meaning
that adheres to real social relations, hence its reliance on case studies and
interviews. But gender psychology also provides a symbolic language that can
help us understand these meanings in a new way by offering a larger theoret-
ical framework:larger because it allows questions that a liberal individualist
framework forbids; symbolic because the unconscious gains its most impor-
tant expression at the cultural level, in the symbols and structures that a cul-
ture adopts. As Chodorow says, psychoanalysis is a deeply embedded cultural
discourse, not simply a scientific one.34 Indeed, given that this literature was a
response to the decidedly sexist tendencies of Freudian psychoanalysis, its pri-
mary contribution from a feminist theoretical perspective is precisely to point
out that what has been taken to be truesuch as the classic Freudian concept
of penis envyin fact represents a particular masculinist reading of masculine
experience. Yet it is out of the sexist, heteronormative model of childrearing
that relational autonomy arises.
The grounding of the idea of relational autonomy in this pathology of fem-
inine development is what worries me. In our arguments critiquing Kantian
individualist morality we are at least tacitly endorsing the feminist object re-
lations view that masculine individuation and separation is less valuable than
womens connectedness. Ibelieve that this is problematic. For all our attention
to the need to stress relationship and connection, we have failed to stress the
34
Nancy Chodorow, Feminism and Psychoanalytic Theory (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press,
1989),179.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 71
need for individuation and separateness, at which girls and women too often
fail. It is because of my unease about these aspects of relational autonomy, par-
ticularly the critique of individualism, that Ithink that freedom needs to be an
important part of the discussion. Its greater stress on individuality, combined
with its more flexible and perhaps less well-defined conception of the subject,
can usefully complement theories of relational autonomy.
35
John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, in On Liberty and Other Essays, edited by John Gray
(NewYork:Oxford University Press,1991).
36
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, edited by C. B. Macpherson (NewYork:Penguin, 1985),189.
37
John Locke, Two Treatises of Civil Government, edited by Peter Laslett (NewYork:New American
Library, 1963), sec.2.4.
38
Mary Astell, Reflections on Marriage, in Astell:Political Writings, edited by Patricia Springborg
(NewYork:Cambridge University Press, 1996), 18. See also Astell, A Serious Proposal to the Ladies,
for the Advancement of Their True and Greatest Interest, edited by Patricia Springborg (Brookfield,
VT:Pickering and Chatto,1997).
39
Mary Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Women, edited by Miriam Brody
(NewYork:Penguin Books, 1992); Harriet Taylor, The Enfranchisement of Women and Marriage
and Divorce, in Essays on Sex Equality, John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor, edited by Alice Rossi
(Chicago:University of Chicago Press,1970).
72 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
40
Isaiah Berlin, Two Concepts of Liberty, in Four Essays on Liberty, Isaiah Berlin
(NewYork:Oxford University Press,1971).
41
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses, translated by G. D. H. Cole
(London:J.M. Dent and Sons, 1973), bk. 1, chap.8.
42
Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by H. J. Patton (NewYork:
Harper and Row,1964).
43
Charles Taylor, Whats Wrong with Negative Liberty? in The Idea of Freedom:Essays in Honor
of Isaiah Berlin, edited by Alan Ryan (NewYork:Oxford University Press,1979).
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 73
44
Idocument this at considerable length in the theories of Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Kant, and
Mill in Hirschmann, Gender, Class and Freedom.
74 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
But it is my view that, just because the inner self, the individual, is socially
constructed does not mean that it is not real.45 And fundamental to the very
concept of the individual is that she is able to exercise choice:she is able to
make choices that affect, shape, and direct her own life. This is the essential
value that the Enlightenment bequeathed to us, a value that has been vitally
important to feminists throughout history.
Rather than proving the superiority of negative liberty over positive, how-
ever, recognizing the value of individual choice leads us to the need to con-
sider the two conceptions together. Both positive and negative liberty share
the notion that choice is central to freedom:both conceptions of liberty have
at their heart the ability of the self to make choices and act on them. The con-
tested terrain between them generally covers differences about what consti-
tutes the process and activity of choosing and what constitutes the product
or an actual choice. For both models, choice is constituted by a complex
relationship between so-called internal factors of will and desirethe prefer-
ences one has, which of the available options one prefers, and how one chooses
among themand factors outside the self that may inhibit, enable, or en-
hance ones ability to pursue ones preferences, including the kind and number
of choices available, the obstacles to making the choice one prefers, and the
variable power that different people have to make choices.
The terms internal and outside, however, point out that implicit in these
debates is the more fundamental question of what or who the self is that makes
these choicesa question particularly relevant to relational autonomy. The
social constructivist thesis posits that what is internal to the self, such as de-
sire, is socially produced through culture, practice, law, custom, history, and
languageall ostensibly external to the individual. Yet those very cultures,
practices, laws, customs, history, and language are themselves produced by
individuals who participate in them every day. Social constructivism chal-
lenges the duality of inner and outer, and Ibelieve that this challenge is illus-
trated in the concept of freedom. Social construction shows that a feminist
conception of freedom is as relational as autonomyis.
Yet this understanding of freedom that feminist social constructivism
yields us allows more space for the individual and for the indefinable, unde-
tectable (to others), and perhaps even incommunicable aspects of human ex-
istence than do many versions of relational autonomy. Feminist freedom does
not require an essential core self, but it does require an identifiable self who is
Standpoint Theory Reader, edited by Sandra Harding (New York: Routledge, 2003); Hirschmann,
Subject of Liberty, chap.3. See also Judith Butler, Bodies that Matter:On the Discursive Limits of Sex
(NewYork:Routledge, 1994) for a critique of linguistic monism and the possibilities of the real
coming out of social constructivism.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 75
the final arbiter of her own choices.46 That is, even if my desires are ultimately
opaque to myself, in that Icannot truly know where they came from or why
Ihave them, it is important for me to be able to identify them as mine and
there is value in my being able to assert and pursue them. In keeping with
negative liberty, a feminist theory of freedom demands that the individual self
must make her own choices. Yet that self, its status and content, is continually
in doubt and requires context and relationship with others to provide and sus-
tain its meaning. The relational aspects of freedom mean that others may see
me, or at least think they do, better than Isee myself, much like positive liberty.
And this in turn means that my freedom may in part depend on their engage-
ment with my understanding of my own desires.
Understanding the relationality of freedom requires a subtle distinction.
Specifically, granting that positive libertys second guessing must be rejected
by a feminist conception of freedom as antithetical to womens agency and
self-determination does not mean that the interrogation of desirewhich is
what often leads to second guessingshould itself be avoided. On the con-
trary, it is vitally important to freedom that critical questioning about desire,
about who we are and what we want, be engaged. The issue is where we draw
the line between asking questions and providing answers. Autonomy theorists,
like positive liberty theorists, may often provide external standards for what
answers are legitimately autonomous.47 Feminist freedom holds that others
can, and indeed should, ask me questions. However, only Ican come up with
the answers; nobody else can answer those questions for me. Indeed, freedom
does not even require that Icome up with any reasoned answers at all; Ican
say I dont really know, Ijust want to do it and still be free, even if doing
so fails the autonomy test. If you dont like or disagree with my answers
as a shelter worker might when a battered woman decides to return to her
abuseryou can only persist in asking more questions, which Imay refuse to
answer.48 Feminist freedom requires relationship, much as autonomy does, but
46
Admittedly, my assertion may point to a disciplinary fracture in the concept of autonomy, per-
taining to the methodologies and modes of inquiry that we engage in as philosophers; as an interna-
tionally known colleague in an English department said in response to a draft of this paper, in my
field, the subject who is opaque to herself is simply a given, we dont even argue about that anymore.
By contrast, philosophersas well as many political theorists, including myselfdo not wish to give
over entirely to the claim of opacity. Many of us still believe that the point of philosophy is to clarify
our understanding of ourselves. But the social construction thesis requires us to acknowledge that the
project of knowing ourselves, not to mention knowing others, is ongoing, in process, always partial,
and never complete.
47
Procedural autonomy theorists suggest that autonomy is measured not by the outcome of a de-
cision but rather by the procedures that the decision maker follows. However, these theorists, too,
must indicate the standards that the decision maker must meet. See Diana T. Meyers, Self, Society,
and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1989); Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and
Practice of Autonomy (NewYork:Cambridge University Press,1988).
48
Idiscuss this theory in relation to domestic violence at greater length in The Subject of Liberty,
chap.4.
76 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
the obligations of critical engagement lie on others, not on the self, for the self
must be free to reject such engagement at alltimes.
Such rejection does not mean that Ihave somehow placed myself outside
of the processes of social construction, of course, like the abstract individual
often associated with negative liberty. As Foucault suggests in one of his last
interviews, freedom is not simply resistance or liberation. Nor is freedom a
quality one possesses or a condition that one could attain by meeting preset
criteria. Rather, freedom is a mode of activity in which people participate by
partaking in practices that create the self. That self is both passive and active;
we are produced through social formations over which we have little control,
yet we act upon these formations in daily and ongoing processes through spe-
cific actions. Such actions involve individualsin some ways intentionally, di-
rectly, consciously, in some ways notin the creation of who they are. Central
to the practices of freedom is the exercise of self upon self by which one
tries...to transform ones self and to attain a certain mode of being.49 But
this care for the self...implies also a relationship to the other...in order to
really care for self, one must listen to the teachings of a master. One needs a
guide, a counselor, a friendsomeone who will tell you the truth.50 Given
that Foucault is most well known for his rejection of the idea of truth,51 not to
mention his attention to the ways relations of power can produce oppression,52
this claim may sound odd, but Ibelieve he means only critical observation.
The counselor is to ask hard questions that challenge the answers we have
come up with for ourselves in defining the self. The point of this questioning is
to engage the process of social construction, to entangle oneself in the messy
paradox of desires that are constituted and produced through social forma-
tions, out of which one often needs someone to help pull one out in order to
understand and express theself.
49
Ral Fornet-Betancourt, Helmut Becker, and Alfredo Gomez-Mller, The Ethic of Care for the
Self as a Practice of Freedom:An Interview with Michel Foucault on January 20, 1984, translated by
J.D. Gauthier, Philosophy and Social Criticism 12:23 (1987):124, 123,114.
50
Fornet-Betancourt etal., Ethic of Care,118.
51
See, e.g., Michel Foucault, Two Lectures, in Power/Knowledge:Selected Interviews and Other
Writings, 19721977, edited by Colin Gordon (NewYork:Pantheon Books,1980).
52
Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, translated by Alan Sheridan
(NewYork:Vintage,1979).
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 77
The first thing my account of freedom adds is the relationship of the passive
subject to the active subject, both of which Foucault insists on. Autonomy pri-
marily involves an active subject; as Raz says, autonomy is a kind of achieve-
ment.53 Relational autonomy theorists suggest that autonomy requires some
kind of conscious work, as Nedelsky argues. Friedman defines autonomy as
acting and living according to ones own choices, values, and identity within
the constraints of what one regards as morally permissible.54 Autonomy par-
ticularly involves reflective judgment, the critical evaluation of desires,
self-discovery, self-definition, and self-direction, living life from the inside.55
Meyers puts it best:Since one must exercise control over ones life to be auton-
omous, autonomy is something that a person accomplishes, not something
that happens to persons.56 All of these ideas cohere with the activeself.
But a key feature of freedom is that it involves a combination of what indi-
viduals do and what happens to them: both the active and the passive. As
Foucault notes, even if the subject constitutes himself in an active fashion,
by the practices of self, these practices are nevertheless not something that the
individual invents by himself. They are patterns that he finds in his culture and
which are proposed, suggested and imposed on him by his culture, his society
and his social group.57 As I read Foucault, because we are situated in such
patterns that preexist us, what is relevant to understanding freedom is not
simply the act of making choices within these patterns but rather the degree to
which a choosing subject has the capacity to participate in the creation of the
options from which she must choose. This is essential for feminism, because
the choices that women make every day are constitutedto varying but al-
ways important degreesby and through patriarchal social relations that de-
fine even the terms of relationships between women. The paradox of relational
autonomy is that autonomy is defined by relationships that are created and
shaped by patriarchywhich has womens nonautonomous status as one of its
foundations. According to social constructivism, women cannot just say no
to patriarchy and form new relationships because the new is constituted by
and through the old.58 Instead, women need to be able to participate in the
53
Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1986),204.
54
Jennifer Nedelsky, Laws Relations: A Relational Theory of Self, Autonomy, and Law
(New York: Oxford University Press, 62); Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Social Disruption, and
Women, in Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, edited
by Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2000),37.
55
Robert Young, Personal Autonomy:Beyond Positive and Negative Liberty (NewYork:St. Martins
Press, 1986), 42; John Christman, Introduction, in The Inner Citadel:Essays on Individual Autonomy,
edited by John Christman (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), 10; Emily R. Gill, Becoming
Free:Autonomy and Diversity in the Liberal Polity (Lawrence:University Press of Kansas, 2001),29.
56
Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice,96.
57
Foucault, Ethic of Care,122.
58
See, e.g., The Milan Womens Bookstore Collective, Sexual Difference:ATheory of Social-Symbolic
Practice, translated by Patricia Cicogna and Teresa de Lauretis (Bloomington:Indiana University Press,
1990). Idiscuss this work at greater length in The Subject of Liberty, chap.7.
78 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
social formations that structure, both actively and passively, the framework
within which relationships are formed and exist, options are made available,
and desire is formed. They need to participate in the processes of social con-
struction that produce their freedom and restraint.
A second contribution that freedom can make to relational autonomy
involves a shift in the dynamics of relationship. That is, in my previous ac-
count Isaid that freedom requires engagement with others and critical ques-
tioning, which might seem to be identical to the requirements of autonomy.
Autonomy theorists, including many relational autonomy theorists, stress the
importance of the subjects ability to articulate reasons for choice: Dworkin
defines autonomy as a capacity...to reflect critically upon...preferences,
desires, wishes, an idea Raz echoes.59 And many of the passages I cited to
demonstrate the role of the active subject in autonomy theory also involved
critical thinking and reflective judgment. Moreover, relational autonomy theo-
rists maintain that such judgment cannot be an isolated activity. Nedelsky, for
instance, maintains that although one can exercise freedom simply by choos-
ing, choosing autonomously requires the exercise of judgment. But judg-
ment emerges out of relations of dependency:We are dependent on others for
the social world that enables us to develop all of our core capacities, including
reason and judgment.60 We must critically engage and interrogate our own
desires within a context of relationship because relationship does not merely
make it possible to exercise those capacities:it is also part of those capacities.
By contrast, note that my formulation requires others to ask questions, not
the self. Questioning by others operates from a position outside my particular
context and therefore potentially challenges the assumptions and givenness
that experience has produced in my self. It is such challenges that open up
possibilities for my thinking and choosing differently. At the same time, how-
ever, because Iam the one who has the experience, Imust be the filter and
arbiter of such questions, challenges, and information, even to the point of
deciding to reject them. Also, Imust be the one to come up with the answers,
no matter how imperfect or imperfectly formulated they might be. Autonomy
theorists might agree with that. However, where a theory of freedom diverges
is that, as Isaid earlier, Ido not have to answer others questions at all:Ican
simply say this is what Iwant, Ido not need to engage in the kind of critical
self-reflection that autonomy usually requires. Nedelsky suggests that what
this means is that people can choose to use their freedom in a weakly auton-
omous manner,61 but Ithink that even that is too strong. The value judgment
that that imposes on my freedom, it seems to me, echoes the paradox of pos-
itive libertys forcing you to be free. The choices that we make are not nec-
essarily self-conscious, objectively rational, or even well thought out, but to
deny or devalue the role and power that individuals have to make choices and
that help constitute the self is equally mistaken. Freedom must lie in the self s
ability to make choices and act on them, regardless of what othersincluding
philosophersthink of those choices.
This leads to the third, and perhaps most important, contribution that
thinking of freedom in tandem with relational autonomy can make:namely,
helping us rethink the role of the self. Because a feminist theory of freedom
requires us to hang on to negative liberty and not just positive liberty, it
reminds us of the value of the liberal individual. Relational autonomy theory
is built on a rejection of the classical model of the isolated self thought to sit at
the heart of traditional autonomy theory from Kant onward. The rejection of
the idea of a true or strong core self may have been gradual among some rela-
tional autonomy theorists (who nevertheless argued for a different, relational
way of understanding that core),62 but the relational self that others promote
seeks to reject altogether the liberal, atomistic self. Nedelsky, for instance,
spends much of her excellent book Laws Relations struggling with the idea
of the self at the heart of relational autonomy. She explicitly targets liberalism
as the model that she wishes to reject.63 Although she claims to acknowledge
human difference, self-creation, and individual choice, she spends much of
the book arguing for a conception of relationality that is so all-encompassing,
and so deep, as to allow very little room for individuality.64 Indeed, she says
that well-known communitarian Alistair MacIntyre understates the nature of
our dependence and interdependence claiming that relationships are part of
autonomy, rather than simply providing the condition for autonomy.65 Indeed,
she draws on object relations theory explicitly, particularly Jessica Benjamin
and to a lesser degree Chodorow and Evelyn Fox Keller, to shore up her cri-
tique of the idea of autonomy as control that is associated with the male
model of reactive autonomy.66 Moreover, in a section titled Understanding
and Overcoming Pathology, she says the most promising model, symbol, or
62
In Self, Society, and Personal Choice, e.g., Diana Meyers said not only that one must be able to
offer reasons but also that what guides those reasons must be firm goals or moral views rather than
feelings, intuitions, and arguments of the moment, for autonomy expresses the true self a view that
she no longer shares according to her essay in the present volume. See also Diana T. Meyers, Personal
Autonomy and Feminine Socialization, Journal of Philosophy 84:11 (1987):619.
63
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, esp. chap.3.
64
In this, although Iagree with much of Marilyn Friedmans critique of Nedelsky in the present
volume, Idisagree that Nedelsky is sympathetic to some aspects of liberalism. Rather, Nedelsky seeks
to claim some concepts that liberalism first gave us, such as equality, to transform them for her own
project.
65
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 28 (emphasis added),41.
66
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 296298,48.
80 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Nedelsky, Laws Relations, 62. Since the days when Flathman advised my doctoral disserta-
68
tion, he has been in strong disagreement with feminist arguments for relationality. See particularly
Richard Flathman, The Philosophy and Politics of Freedom (Chicago:University of Chicago Press, 1984),
where he endorses a strongly individualist conception of negative liberty as the only philosophically
and politically coherent conception; Reflections of a Would-Be Anarchist (Minneapolis:University of
Minnesota Press, 1998), which, to quote the publisher, warns of the individualism-limiting potential of
even liberal efforts to promote social justice; Thomas Hobbes:Skepticism, Individuality, and Chastened
Politics (Lanham, MD:Rowman and Littlefield, 2002), where he holds up Hobbesian individualism as
a model for contemporary political theorists to follow. He thus opposes almost everything Nedelskys
book arguesfor.
69
See, e.g., Quentin Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2008); John Dunn, The Political Thought of John Locke:An Historical Account of the Argument of
the Two Treatises of Government (NewYork:Cambridge University Press, 1983); Gordon Schochet,
The Authoritarian Family and Political Attitudes in Seventeenth Century England:Patriarchicalism in
Political Thought (New Brunswick, NJ:Transaction, 1988); Joanne H. Wright and Nancy J. Hirschmann,
Introduction:The Many Faces of Mr. Hobs, in Feminist Interpretations of Thomas Hobbes, edited by
Nancy J. Hirschmann and Joanne Wright (University Park:Pennsylvania State University Press,2013).
70
In Rethinking Obligation, Ilinked the liberal subject of social contract theory to the male model
of object relations theory. Istill believe my analysis of the masculinism of the natural self in obliga-
tion theory is correct, because contemporary theories deploy an abstract model that the historical theo-
ries did not. However, Ialso believe that Ishould have attended to the greater subtleties of relationship
in those canonical theories, a failure Ibelieve Iaddressed in Gender, Class and Freedom.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 81
autonomy requires. In keeping with the idea that it is important to view the
passive self in conjunction with the active self and that freedom is a function
not just of what the subject does but what happens to the subject, the self nec-
essary to freedom theory is more fluid and porous. Yet it is decidedly present.
Granting that nothing escapes social relations, a feminist theory of freedom
reminds us that some things at the least make relations beside the point. If
everything and everyone is always already socially constructed, if there is no
way not to be socially constructed, there is no way to exist outside social re-
lations, outside social contexts, outside language. We can grant that. But then
relationality becomes so expanded as to make it almost meaningless:even re-
active autonomy is relational because it entails a reaction against the mother.
In other words, if we take the concept of relationality and social construc-
tion to its logical end, we are led to an impasse, and autonomy itself starts to
look incoherent. This is not a problem Iattribute to any of the arguments in the
present volume as much as it is a conceptual problem that exceeds the grasp
of all of us. Autonomy is fundamentally about capabilitiesas several papers
in the present volume suggestspecifically the ability to assess ones choices,
to reflect critically about them, and to make choices that allow one to exert
some control over ones life. Thus, there must be a self. But if we are always
and already socially constructed, then how can autonomy actually exist? What
purpose does the notion of self rule really serve if the self is always already
constructed and produced through complex webs of relationships, which were
in turn constructed by other social relations, all the way down? Indeed, how
can there be a self necessary to the idea of self rule? We always insist that
the self exists, yet that acknowledgment is a challenge for the logic of relation-
ality. Our alternative, to reject social construction, can return us only to the
naturalism of social contract theory that gave birth to the liberal individual.
Treating that liberal individual as a metaphor, however, can help us recog-
nize that this deep embeddedness in relationship that social construction gives
us does not forestall self-definition and acting for the self by acting against
context. Returning to where Ibegan this paper, my anxiety about relational au-
tonomy is that relationship is not only complex, as many relational autonomy
theorists note, but also is as problematic for autonomy as it is helpful. Surely,
can some relationships be harmful, as many relational autonomy feminists ac-
knowledge. However, even the good relationshipslike that between mother
and daughter in object relations theorycan harm us, by hiding the ways in
which oppressive power relations of patriarchy are replicated and reinforced
in our daily interactions.
By calling for a recuperation of the liberal self as a metaphor, Iam in a sense
suggesting that feminist autonomy theorists should reassess the importance
and value of reactive autonomy. What reactive autonomy can contribute is
the recognition that autonomy importantly must develop against others and
against prevailing norms and customs, such as Hirsi Ali discussed in Marina
82 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Oshanas essay for this volume. Iagree with Oshana and Friedman that it may
be time for the liberal self to be recuperated, though, Iwould argue, recuper-
ated within a context of freedom, specifically relational freedom.71
Perhaps ironically, Ifind a model for what Iam suggesting in John Stuart Mill,
with whom Iopened my discussion of freedom. Often seen as the icon of clas-
sical liberalism and of negative libertynot to mention a problematic femi-
nist72Mill actually deployed both negative and positive liberty elements as
well as the idea of social construction in his theory. In the chapter Of Liberty
and Necessity in his System of Logic Mill agrees with determinists that a per-
sons character determines his desires and causes him to act on his prefer-
ences: given...the character and disposition of the individual, the manner
in which he will act might be unerringly inferred.73 In turn, an individuals
character is formed by his circumstances: by the experiences he has, how he
was brought up, the kind of influences and education he was exposed to, and
so forth. In true social constructivist fashion, Mill says that we cannot stand
outside of ourselves to create ourselves ab initio, because we are who we are
through the social conditions, institutions, practices, relationships, language,
and frameworks in which we cometobe.
However, this does not foreclose the power of self-creation or free action.
That a persons character is formed for him, is not inconsistent with its being,
in part, formed by him as one of the intermediate agents. That is, he has, to
a certain extent, a power to alter his character. He does this by changing his
circumstances:We, when our habits are not too inveterate, can, by similarly
willing the requisite means, make ourselves different. If [others] could place
us under the influence of certain circumstances, we, in like manner, can place
ourselves under other circumstances. We are exactly as capable of making
our own character, if we will, as others are of making it for us.74 When the
Ithink it is significant that Oshana draws on Nussbaums capability approach, which is a theory
71
of freedom, to develop her own theory of autonomy. This is a point that would require another paper,
but Ioffer the provocative suggestion that a number of the essays in this volume are writing about
freedom rather than autonomy or at least are developing a theory of autonomy that tacitly depends on
the understanding of freedom that Iam articulatinghere.
72
See Nancy J. Hirschmann, Mill, Political Economy, and Womens Work, American Political
Science Review 102:2 (May 2008):199213, on Mills ambiguity over married womens participation in
paid labor that, for all but women of property, was essential to their independence and equality.
73
John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, Being a Connected View of
the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation (Books IVVI), in The Collected
Works of John Stuart Mill, edited by J. M. Robson, vol. 8 (Toronto:University of Toronto Press, 1974),
836837.
74
Mill, System of Logic,840.
Autonomy? Or Freedom? 83
determinist asks where the desire to change our character comes from, Mill
responds that the desire to alter our character, and thereby our circumstances,
comes from the experience of the painful consequences of the character we
previously had; or by some strong feeling of admiration or aspiration, acciden-
tally aroused.75 In other words, experience is not only backward-looking, to
consider how we got to be the way we are, but also forward-looking, to pos-
sibilities of what we couldbe.
Despite his strong social constructivism, then, his argument also invokes
a strong sense of self that produces its own construction:the self-made man
that Friedman discusses in this volume becomes literally self-made, in that he
(to continue the metaphor) engages in the construction of his self. What Mill
gives us, Ithink, is a sense of how freedom depends on a notion of the self that,
although deeply constructed and socially related, is nevertheless independent,
capable of rejecting specific relationships, and capable of forging the self in
and through new contexts. The passive subject, who is formed by his context,
can act to change that context.
When one is considering the kind of wide-ranging circumstances that
feminists confront, howeverpatriarchy, including the heterosexism, classism,
and racism that it is in part built onthis task becomes proportionately more
difficult. But that is why feminism is so vital to freedom and autonomy:if we
are socially constructed by our contexts, and if those contexts are oppressive
to women, then the only way for women to achieve freedom is by partici-
pating in the processes of social construction to change that context to pro-
duce new meanings and possibilities. Greater participation in the processes
of social construction allow greater freedom not for self-imagining per se but
for group imagining within which individuals can define and construct them-
selves. Without the discursive categories defining the larger context, the indi-
vidual has no vocabulary with which to imagine the self. But changing those
categories, and the struggle to change the context of patriarchy, is beyond the
grasp of any given individual; it is multigenerational and ongoing.
In a sense, of course, this notion of relational freedom can be taken to sug-
gest that autonomy is a fiction after all, as some postmodern theorists assert.
But Ibelieve that the picture of relational freedom Ihave put forth supports
relational autonomy by recognizing that, insofar as we are produced by rela-
tionships, we can participate in those relationships in ways that are shaped by
our feminist beliefsbeliefs that have come from relationships both positively
and supportively and negatively and reactively. That is, relational freedom can
help us see that we need not just relational autonomy; we may also need a
little reactive autonomy as well to achieve the sense of individual selfhood that
many autonomy theorists desire.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to the editors of this volume, the other contributors who participated
in the Montreal conference related to this volume, and participants in the
Gender, Sexuality, and Womens Studies Faculty Works-in-Progress workshop
at the University of Pennsylvania for their comments and suggestions, partic-
ularly Sally Scholz and HeatherLove.
{ PartII }
One of the notable features of Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljars in-
fluential volume Relational Autonomy1 was the contributors clear commit-
ment to investigate personal autonomy from explicitly feminist perspectives.
Mackenzie and Stoljar announced this commitment on the opening pages of
the volume, asserting that the collections aim was to challenge feminist theo-
rists suspicion of the ideal of personal autonomy and to affirm that the notion
of autonomy is vital to feminist attempts to understand oppression, subjec-
tion, and agency.2 Mackenzie and Stoljar employed the term relational au-
tonomy as a refiguring of the concept of personal autonomy in the wake of
feminist concerns about the concepts allegedly masculinist, individualist, and
rationalist baggage.3 In particular, they saw feminists attention to the inter-
subjective and social dimensions of selfhood and identity as offering fruitful
standpoints from which refiguration of individual autonomy could proceed.4
Thus, the dual aims of the broad set of projects to construct relational con-
ceptions of autonomy were, at the start, (1)to craft theories of personal au-
tonomy that could do the work that feminist ethical and social theories need
from accounts of autonomy without succumbing to the pitfalls that seem to
lurk in many contemporary accounts of autonomy and, thereby, (2)to make
important, new contributions to the philosophical literature on autonomy,
a literature that had undergone significant resurgence in the wake of Harry
Frankfurts and Gerald Dworkins groundbreaking scholarship in the 1970s
and 1980s. This latter aim of bringing feminist investigation of autonomy into
active dialogue with so-called mainstream theorizing about autonomy was es-
pecially noteworthy and has been particularly fruitful.
1
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, eds., Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on
Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (NewYork:Oxford University Press,2000).
2
Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy,3.
3
Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, 34. Mackenzie and Stoljar attribute the first such
feminist articulation of relational autonomy to Jennifer Nedelsky, Reconceiving Autonomy:Sources,
Thoughts and Possibilities, Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 1 (1989):736.
4
Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy,4.
88 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
5
Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational
Autonomy, 94111.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 89
be able to present arguments that hold sway decisively among most feminist
theorists of autonomy. The ensuing discussion seeks to diagnose this polem-
ical situation by drawing critical attention to some of the appeals to feminist
normative commitments that various influential theories of autonomy have
made recently. The diagnoses proposed here will suggest that some of the pri-
mary disagreements concerning relational accounts of personal autonomy
can be understood and addressed effectively by considering how a conception
of personal autonomy can best advance feminist ethical, social, and political
commitments. Future progress in work on relational autonomy, Ishall suggest,
will depend in large measure on greater attention to what feminists really need
a conception of personal autonomy to do in relation to the normative social
purposes of confronting and overcoming womens subordination.
Our discussion will begin by analyzing the ways Marina Oshana and Natalie
Stoljar, respectively, invoke feminist normative commitments to construct their
particular accounts of autonomys constitutively relational character. Ithen ex-
amine Marilyn Friedmans and John Christmans respective appeals to certain
feminist principles of social and political inclusion to support their nonrela-
tional theories of autonomy. While Friedman and Christman both appreciate
ways in which social relations influence persons capabilities for autonomous
agency, neither accepts, as do Oshana and Stoljar, that certain kinds of inter-
personal or social relation are conceptually requisite components of personal
autonomy. Consideration of the difficulties that arise with the ways these four
theorists envisage personal autonomy to function within feminist social theory
leads me to contend that a conception of personal autonomy may best serve
feminist commitments by integrating considerations of autonomous agents
voices, which nonrelational theories characteristically highlight, with consid-
erations of the sort of agential authority that distinguishes autonomy, which
relational theories characteristically highlight. Iuse this contention to propose
that conceptions of autonomy that focus on autonomous agents authority to
speak or answer to others for their choices and actions afford a preferred way
to understand autonomys relational character. Such conceptions may take a
value-laden form (as Ihave argued elsewhere), or they may offer purely formal
conditions of autonomy (as Andrea Westlund has argued).6
I conclude by surveying some of the primary lessons that this approach
affords about the role that personal autonomy should serve within accounts
of social and political life informed by feminist commitments. As will become
clear, this paper does not aim to present a detailed account of the necessary
and sufficient conditions of autonomous action.
6
As explained in Section 5, this chapter does not seek to resolve the debate between substantive
and formal, or content-neutral, theories of autonomy.
90 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
See Marina A. L. Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Hampshire, UK: Ashgate, 2006).
7
Oshanas important essays on autonomy include Oshana, Personal Autonomy and Society, Journal of
Social Philosophy 29 (1998):81102; How Much Should We Value Autonomy? Social Philosophy and
Policy 20 (2003):99126; Moral Accountability, Philosophical Topics 32 (2004):255274; Autonomy
and Self-Identity, in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism:New Essays, edited by John Christman
and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 7797; Autonomy and Free
Agency, in Personal Autonomy:New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral
Philosophy, edited by James Stacey Taylor (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005), 183204.
8
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,3.
9
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,4.
10
Oshana, Autonomy and Free Agency,196.
11
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,8687.
12
Oshana, How Much Should We Value Autonomy?104.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 91
These broad claims about the social and psychological conditions required
for personal autonomy are reflected in Oshanas judgments about various case
studies in which autonomy may appear to be under threat. Oshana surveys a
range of cases in which agents are subject to the domination, rule, or authority
of others and, in each case, contends that the agent in such circumstances has
been stripped of autonomy, regardless of how the person came to be in that
state and independently of the persons reflective appraisals of her situation
and its history.13 For example, by Oshanas lights, the willing, contented slave
and the reflectively subservient woman both lack autonomy to a substantial
extent. Notwithstanding the alignment between the agents life and her values
or her reflective endorsement of the way she arrived in her circumstances,
lives of slavery or subservience compromise self-governance by obstructing
the persons powers of self-determination and rendering the person substan-
tively dependent on others who rule major portions of their lives.14
In a similar vein, Oshana elsewhere presents the case of courageous Iranian
womens advocate and Nobel laureate Shirin Ebadi as an illustration of why,
given the subjugation of women in the postrevolution Iranian legal system,
even an accomplished jurist, influential writer, and defiant womens advocate
like Ebadi fundamentally lacks autonomy.15 Although Ebadi is a vocal and
highly visible proponent for the rights of women in Iranian society, Oshana
regards her as being deprived of personal autonomy because the Iranian state
stripped her of many of her basic political rights and unfairly deprived her of
her economic and professional livelihood as an attorney and judge. Persons
in Ebadis circumstances, on Oshanas analysis, lack the social security that
is forthcoming only when others with whom a person dwells and works and
interacts are dispossessed of arbitrary power over the person.16
Oshanas appeal to intuitions about the restriction of autonomy in cases
such as these clarifies why Oshana regards autonomy as a global feature of
persons, as opposed to an episodic, or local, characteristic of an agents atti-
tudes, values, decisions, or actions.17 Because she believes that autonomy must
guarantee persons a reasonable measure of the social, political, and economic
power and authority they need to determine the course of their lives, apprais-
als of autonomy cannot, in her judgment, be confined narrowly to the local
13
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society, 5268. See also her discussion of earlier versions of some
of these cases in Oshana, Personal Autonomy and Society,8693.
14
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,5360.
15
Oshana discussed the situation of Ebadi at a workshop on autonomy and social transformation
held on March 12, 2012, at the University of California, Davis. In a discussion elsewhere of Rosa Parkss
protest, Oshana writes, Any person who lives in an environment she cannot challenge, change, or
contribute to without the say-so of others lives in a place where impediments to self-government are
present. This person lives in the shadow of others, insecure of what her steps toward self-government
might incur from others. See Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,175.
16
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,87.
17
For instance, see Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,23.
92 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
In her review of Oshanas Personal Autonomy in Society, Diana Tietjens Meyers, Review of
18
Personal Autonomy in Society, Hypatia 23 (2008): 202206, makes a similar point, contending that
such disagreement over Oshanas case studies isnt merely semantic. What is at stake is the point and
purview of autonomy theory....The underlying issue here is the relation between political desiderata
and personal autonomy(205).
19
While Oshanas theory of autonomy certainly is not motivated solely by feminist commitments,
Oshanas repeated and sustained attention to the psychological and social domination of women makes
it clear that explaining the wrongs involved in such domination is one central purpose of her concep-
tion of personal autonomy.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 93
Like Oshana, Natalie Stoljar also appeals to an intuition about personal au-
tonomy that is rooted in specific feminist social and political commitments
to develop her conception of autonomy. As noted earlier, Stoljar explicitly
advances the idea that an adequate conception of autonomy must serve sub-
stantive feminist convictions about the bearing that gender socialization has
upon womens agency. She asserts that an acceptable theory of autonomy must
conform to and be able to explain the belief she terms the feminist intuition,
according to which women whose preferences and decisions are motivated
by oppressive and misguided norms that are internalized as a result of femi-
nine socialization cannot be autonomous.20 While most of Stoljars influential
paper, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, is devoted to arguing that only
a strong substantive account of autonomy can properly respect the feminist
intuition, examining her arguments against procedural, content-neutral con-
ceptions and so-called weak substantive conceptions is not my main interest
here.21 Instead Iwant to consider whether Stoljar has given us compelling rea-
sons to hold that any satisfactory conception of personal autonomy must sus-
tain the social and political commitments that the feminist intuition reflects.
Icertainly feel the force of Stoljars position, as Ionce held a view much like
hers.22 Yet Ido not think that Stoljar succeeds in showing that a suitable con-
ception of autonomy must advance certain feminist convictions in the manner
she proposes.
I have two main concerns about Stoljars understanding of the role of an
account of personal autonomy within feminist social theory. First, Stoljars
position fails to afford sufficient room for the legitimate diversity of feminist
convictions about how best to understand internalized feminine socializa-
tion across a wide range of social, political, economic, historical, and cultural
For extended discussion of those arguments, see Paul Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the
21
Normative Substance of Autonomy, in James Stacey Taylor, Personal Autonomy: New Essays on
Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy (Cambridge:Cambridge University
Press, 2005), 124142.
22
See especially Paul Benson, Freedom and Value, Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 465487;
Benson, Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization, Social Theory and Practice 17 (1991):385408.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 95
circumstances. There can be strong reasons for some women to accept the in-
fluence of stereotypical and incorrect norms of femininity23 even as they take
genuine ownership of their decisions and actions. Such womens rejection of
feminist social ideals need not be taken by those of us with feminist sensibilities
as showing that their actions are not meaningfully their own. As Diana Meyers
observes, conceptions of autonomy, such as Stoljars, that embrace strong sub-
stantive conditions on what may count as autonomous agency homogenize
authentic selves and autonomous lives. The paradoxical effect of ahistorically,
acontextually foreordaining what individuals can and cannot autonomously
choose is to deindividualize autonomy.24 Similarly, Marilyn Friedman points
out the need for feminist accounts of personal autonomy to accommodate
another feminist intuition. Friedman observes that, even within oppressive
social conditions that ought to be resisted and overcome, traditionally subor-
dinate feminine lives nevertheless can and do often nonslavishly embody and
express values worth caring about.25
Admitting the appropriate diversity of autonomous responses to the in-
fluence of internalized lessons of subordination is especially important for
feminist conceptions of autonomy because this diversity opens up conceptual
space for autonomous criticism of and resistance to oppressive social practices
and institutions from within. In other words, such space permits feminists
to acknowledge the autonomous agency of those women who come to criti-
cize traditional feminine norms even as they initially accepted the wrongs and
injustices to which those norms subjectedthem.
A second concern about Stoljars understanding of the role that a concep-
tion of autonomy should serve within feminist social theory emerges from
the manner in which Stoljars account seeks to do justice to the lived experi-
ence and perspectives of women who have internalized oppressive norms of
femininity. On Stoljars account, the familiar feminist dictum that we should
take womens experiences seriously cannot mean that womens sense of their
own agential authority must be respected. That is, for Stoljar, womens sense of
their own authority should not necessarily be respected on the basis of their
autonomy. For the feminist intuition entails that women who regard them-
selves as competent and worthy to answer for their actions can nevertheless
suffer diminished autonomy if their attitudes and decisions are the products
of internalized oppressive socialization that they do not see to be misguided.
Hence, the social commitments that shape Stoljars conception of autonomy
would lead her to regard the significance of womens experiences as being re-
flected in the degree to which those experiences evidence their freedom from
23
Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,98.
24
Diana T. Meyers, Feminism and Womens Autonomy:The Challenge of Female Genital Cutting,
Metaphilosophy 31 (2000):469491,480.
25
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2003),25.
96 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
compulsory femininitys harmful influences. But there are more natural and
straightforward ways to take seriously womens experiences of their agency.
We can respect their attitudes toward their status as potential answerers for
their actions, even when they have been influenced by their social training to
adopt unjustified or harmful attitudes about what they should do or who they
shouldbe.26
Not only does this way of understanding the value of womens experiences
of their agency expand the sphere within which women in patriarchal socie
ties may achieve some autonomy, but it also permits us to distinguish in an
appealing way between the self-governance in which autonomous agency con-
sists and the ability to discern the true and the good, which may be termed
orthonomy.27 By contrast, Stoljars normative commitments require her to
align autonomy much more closely with the ideal of right rule.28 Autonomous
agency, for Stoljar, is a concept that aims, in part, at capturing the conditions
under which persons practically can escape the pervasive influence of false or
unjustified social norms. As we have seen, however, this view leads to unpal-
atable implications, irrespective of how valuable it would be to elude the reach
of oppressive socialization.
26
Ireturn to and expand on this point in Section5.
27
Cf. Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy,132.
28
See Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, 111n51.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 97
us, for example, that autonomy cannot emerge except out of social relation-
ships. Although autonomy is individuating in its effects on persons, it never
loses its social rootedness.29 Friedman goes on to say, however, that what
distinguishes an autonomous self from those who are not autonomous but
who are equally the products of social context is the degree of individuated
distinctness and coherence that an autonomous self achieves by acting in ways
that accord with her reaffirmation of certain deeper wants and commitments
that characterize her in particular.30 Christman notes more explicitly the dis-
tinction between theories of autonomy according to which social conditions
are contributory factors and theories in which social relations are concep-
tually necessary requirements of autonomy.31 With Friedman, Christman
accepts that social conditions that enable us to develop and maintain the
powers of authentic choice and which protect the ongoing interpersonal and
social relationships that define ourselves are all part of the background require-
ments for the development of autonomy.32 Yet he rejects views that see social
conditions as not only supportive of autonomy but [also] definitive of it....33
It is Friedmans and Christmans rejection of the latter type of position that
marks their theories as nonrelational for the sake of the present discussion.
Friedman, like Oshana, initiates her examination of personal autonomy by
invoking the notion of being self-determining in ones choices and actions. For
Friedman, to choose or act autonomously the self as a whole, as the particular
self she is, must somehow (partly) determine what she chooses and does.34
Friedman understands the particularity of an agents selfhoodthe agents
differentiated distinctness35to reside in her reflective endorsement of cer-
tain of her deep and pervasive wants and values. Determination of the persons
choices and actions in part by those self-reflectively affirmed attitudes then ren-
ders those choices and actions at least minimally autonomous. Autonomous
choices and actions are those that mirror wants or values that an acting person
has reflectively reaffirmed and that are important to her.36 Autonomy is a
matter of degree, on Friedmans account, because (among other things) reflec-
tive endorsement of ones motives may be more or less probing and extensive.
Practically any self-reflective reaffirmation will do for minimally autono-
mous action, Friedman maintains.37 She also contends that minimal autonomy
29
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,17.
30
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics.
31
John Christman, The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2009),166.
32
Christman, Politics of Persons,184.
33
Christma, Politics of Persons,185.
34
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,4.
35
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,18.
36
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,14.
37
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,7.
98 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
requires that one have significant alternative options38 from among which to
choose and that one have the competency necessary to act on ones reflectively
endorsed wants and values in the face of some obstacles.39
Friedman develops two especially important claims about substantive
conceptions of autonomy, which she takes to be conceptions that require
that autonomous agents choose and act to promote the value of personal au-
tonomy itself in their own lives or, at least, not to undermine or conflict with
the value of autonomy.40 First, Friedman contends that, from the perspective
of the content-neutral conception she develops, this sort of substantive au-
tonomy comprises more autonomy. That is, even if we understand autonomy
to be constituted by conditions of reflective endorsement of ones deep motives
and values, independently of the content of those attitudes, a person counts
as being more autonomous if she chooses and acts in accordance with the
value of autonomy in her life. Hence, Friedman contends that some substan-
tive conceptions of autonomy should be regarded as being continuous with
content-neutral conceptions. She writes, Substantive autonomy involves
more autonomy because with it, autonomy seeking becomes a stable and en-
during concern of the agent....She tends to choose intentionally according
to that ideal and so helps to secure its ongoing importance as a feature of her
character.41
While this is a provocative claim, Ido not find Friedmans reasoning for it
to be sound. It is trivially true that, if one cares about affirming the place of au-
tonomy among ones values and realizing its value through ones conduct, then
autonomy has a larger role within ones motives, values, and actions than it
would have otherwise. But that does not mean that acting on a central, reflec-
tively affirmed concern for autonomy is itself necessarily more autonomous
than acting on a similarly affirmed concern for some other values, including
values that may conflict directly with that of personal autonomy. The degree
of an agents autonomy, according to Friedmans own content-neutral crite-
ria, should be independent of the extent of autonomys importance within the
agents motivational and valuational systems.
More germane to this discussion, however, is a second claim that Friedman
makes about substantive conceptions of autonomy in relation to the inclu-
siveness of the moral and political commitments that substantive, value-laden
accounts of autonomy can sustain. Because such accounts advance more re-
strictive requirements for autonomy, Friedman worries that they could limit
40
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics, 1920. In my judgment, this is an unorthodox way of
defining what makes a theory of autonomy substantive. By comparison, see the account in Mackenzie
and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy,1921.
41
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,20.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 99
42
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,23.
43
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics.
44
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics.
45
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,68.
100 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
I have three kinds of concern about Friedmans claim that the promotion of
a more inclusive sense of respect-worthiness for autonomous choices is a war-
ranted social criterion for the acceptability of a conception of autonomous agency.
To begin with, the fact that there may well be potential obstacles to the social
recognition or appreciation of persons autonomy, such that the autonomy of so-
cially marginalized persons may regularly be rendered nearly invisible to others,
is not necessarily a ground for rejecting a particular conception of what consti-
tutes personal autonomy. In discussing Stoljars account, Ialready have noted that
conceptions of autonomy that would fuel widespread skepticism about when, if
ever, anyone acts autonomously are objectionable for that reason. But Friedman
is making a much bolder claim. She is proposing that conceptions of autonomy
that have the likely practical consequence that some persons autonomy may be
difficult (though not impossible) for others to recognize can be criticized on that
basis. This seems mistaken. For the difficulty of persons actual autonomy gaining
broad social visibility may reflect the regrettable social fact that, owing to differ-
ences in social power and privilege, some persons capabilities for autonomous
agency may be less transparent than others powers of autonomy. Iconcur with
Friedman that this is a very serious social barrier to be identified, resisted, and
surmounted. However, it is not, in itself, a reason to reject a particular account of
what autonomy consists in. The very fact that one conception of autonomy would
make persons autonomy more readily visible to others than would be the case
on another account does not automatically lend weight to the case for the former
conception, even if the expansion of the social visibility of and appreciation for
autonomy would be a good thing in general.
Second, if this argument of Friedmans against strong substantive theories of
autonomy were sound and if such theories could be criticized on the grounds
that they set the bar too high for the special respect-worthiness that properly
accompanies autonomous action, then it also should be possible that, on social
or political grounds, a theory of autonomy could be criticized for setting the
bar for respect-worthiness too low. That is, such a theory could be faulted for
being unreasonably or excessively inclusive. Friedmans account runs precisely
this risk, I believe. Agents who reflectively endorse the deep and pervasive
wants and values that motivate their actions and thus who satisfy Friedmans
minimal conditions for autonomy nevertheless may lack autonomy if, at the
same time, they are afflicted by psychosocial forms of manipulation that assail
their fundamental sense of their competence and worthiness to speak for their
decisions and actions. Ihave argued at length for this claim elsewhere and re-
turn to it in Section5.46
46
See, e.g., Paul Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994): 650
668; Benson, Taking Ownership: Authority and Voice in Autonomous Agency, in Christman and
Anderson, Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, 101126; Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the
Normative Substance of Autonomy.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 101
The political liability for Friedmans position here is that, in virtue of embrac-
ing an overly inclusive understanding of autonomy, her account becomes less
able to detect politically significant ways social practices and institutions ac-
tually do undermine autonomy without disrupting persons ability to act on
their reflectively affirmed or endorsable desires and values. As a consequence,
Friedmans view risks making invisible the wrongs that such practices or insti-
tutions inflict. If, as Friedman contends, it is politically objectionable for a
theory of autonomy to foster the invisibility of certain persons autonomy, then
it should also be politically objectionable for a theory to foster the invisibility
of certain kinds of assault on personal autonomy. Friedmans account seems to
have just such a consequence.
Finally, Iam concerned that Friedmans inclusiveness argument obscures
some critically important distinctions. It is important to be able to distinguish,
first, between the conditions under which a person actually acts autonomously
and the conditions under which a person possesses the capacity to act auton-
omously. The former conditions incorporate the latter, but the contrary is not
the case. Someone can fail to act autonomously without losing the capacity to
have acted autonomously. Typically, the special kinds of respect-worthiness
that attach to autonomy do so in relation to the persons capacity for autono-
mous agency47 so that failing to act autonomously on a particular occasion
does not undermine the special respect or consideration the person deserves
as an autonomous agent. For example, a person may fail to act on her deep-
est, reflectively endorsed wants or values for reasons of temporary akrasia,
inattention, or fleeting ambivalence without thereby losing the entitlement
to live free of domination or without losing claim to others respect as an
autonomousagent.
Similarly, it is important to distinguish between having the capacity to act
autonomously and simply possessing the potential to acquire, strengthen, or
regain that capacity. As in the former distinction, a transitory undermining
of someones capacity for autonomy does not entirely strip away the grounds
to respect the persons autonomous agency if she has the potential to regain
that capacity, perhaps as readily as she lost it. In many cases, persons who
have suffered diminished capacity for autonomous decision making through
illness or disability retain the potential for autonomy. Through modest sup-
port from others, they could regain or strengthen their capacity for autonomy
sufficiently well to render their decisions worthy of respect. The impairment
of the capacity to carry out certain functions required for autonomous action
need not entail the destruction of the potential to act autonomously and the
respect-worthy status that accompaniesit.
47
Friedman seems to acknowledge this, in fact. Cf. Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,23.
102 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
48
Christman, Politics of Persons, 175. Christman does not follow Friedman, however, in thinking
that a substantive conception of autonomy can be accepted at the same time, as a matter of being
autonomous to a greater degree than the minimal, procedural conditions of autonomy would entail.
49
For the purposes of the present discussion of relational autonomy, see especially Christman,
Politics of Persons; John Christman, Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism, and the Social
Constitution of Selves, Philosophical Studies 117 (2004):143164; Christman, Procedural Autonomy
and Liberal Legitimacy, in Taylor, Personal Autonomy, 277298.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 103
50
Christman, Politics of Persons, 173174.
For Christmans specification of the pertinent authenticity and competence conditions, see
51
52
Christman recognizes, of course, that certain values and forms of relationship will be necessary
for the very realization of democratic procedures. He is concerned about substantive or relational ac-
counts of autonomy that would impose normative constraints on autonomy that are far more restrictive
than these basic prerequisites for democratic politics. See, e.g., Christman, Politics of Persons, 175n16.
53
Christman, Politics of Persons,176.
54
Another worry about Christmans argument from egalitarian democratic inclusion is that his
account appears implicitly to adopt substantive and constitutively relational elements of autonomy by
way of the broad and incompletely specified competency conditions that he presumes to be necessary
for autonomy. See the discussion in Christman, Politics of Persons, of the place that interpersonal rela-
tions may have within autonomys competency conditions, 177, 182183, 184185. If this is so, then his
own account may fail to preserve the value-neutral, nonrelational character that heavows.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 105
55
Mark Piper suggests that Oshana and Stoljar might respond to this criticism by invoking the
scalar character of autonomy. This would allow that many persons could exhibit some degree of au-
tonomy in their actions even if few persons act with full autonomy by Oshanas or Stoljars lights. To
my knowledge, neither Oshana nor Stoljar gives any indication of taking such a stance. Nor do their
theories indicate how the minimal conditions for acting with any degree of autonomy at all should be
determined. Neither theory adopts Friedmans strategy in this regard.
106 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
We have found, as well, that both Friedman and Christman explicitly appeal
to ideals of social and political inclusion in ways that extend the scope of personal
autonomy too broadly. One reason for the overly permissive character of their
theories is that they presume that locally autonomous agency must be coupled
tightly to the conditions for basic entitlement to equal respect and democratic
participation; autonomy is a condition of a certain respect-worthy social or polit-
ical status, they believe. Ihave argued that this approach is mistaken because the
conditions for such basic social recognition and political participation are insuffi-
cient to ensure that persons act autonomously, or have the capacity to act autono-
mously, in whatever they choose to do. The conditions for entry into the arena of
democratic deliberation are weaker than those demanded by personal autonomy.
This diagnosis of some of the most influential lines of recent argument about
whether or not feminist normative commitments favor relational conceptions
of autonomy over nonrelational conceptions can be deepened by considering
the differences in importance these competing approaches give to the role of
autonomous agents voices in their choice making and conduct compared with
the importance they assign to persons agential authority over their values,
choices, and actions. The more inclusive of these theoretical approaches to au-
tonomy typically assign greater emphasis to the respects in which autonomous
agents can give expression, or voice, to what they care aboutor at least to
what they would find acceptable, or nonalienating, upon reflection. The more
restrictive of these approaches typically assign greater emphasis to the ways
persons are authorized to embrace values, make choices, and perform actions
autonomously, normally with an eye toward identifying some objective con-
straints on such authority. It is important for present purposes to recognize
that this distinction is a matter of emphasis and degree. All reasonable accounts
strive, at least implicitly, to acknowledge and understand the roles of both
voice and authority in autonomous agency. Iwill propose that consideration
of the ways competing theories of autonomy emphasize these different, though
closely intertwined, dimensions of agency reveals how we might constructively
improve our understanding of the role that a conception of personal autonomy
should serve in relation to feminist social and political commitments.
Notice, to begin with, that nonrelational theories such as Friedmans and
Christmans that invoke political arguments as grounds for expanding their
inclusiveness do so, in large measure, to protect the voices of individual auton-
omous agents, or the expressive capacities of their motivation and conduct.
For such theories of autonomy, persons who act on authentically formed and
sustainedor hypothetically acceptable (or nonalienating) and sustainable
values, wants, and choices are in an appropriate position to give expression, or
voice, to what they care about.56 And what such agents care about may clash
56
For stylistic simplicity I will ignore, for the most part, the particular differences between
Friedmans and Christmans respective conditions for personal autonomy. While those differences are
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 107
deeply with prevailing social norms or with the substantive constraints impli-
cated in certain interpersonal relationships or social practices in which they
participate, however liberatory or oppressive those norms, relationships, or
practices may be. For such nonrelational conceptions of autonomy, the im-
perative of protecting agents capabilities for voice means being willing to em-
brace the widest possible range of legitimate social or political disagreement
and difference. Any substantive restrictions on the evaluative commitments,
relationships, or decisions of autonomous agents could, from this perspective,
threaten persons capability to give voice through their actions to their most
important wants or deepest valuesor, at least, to what they would accept
upon reflection. Theories of autonomy should be as inclusive as they reason-
ably can be, according to this approach, because this is the best way to ensure
that they respect appropriately persons authentic voices as realized in their
decisions and conduct. That is, what is at risk in overly restrictive, insufficiently
inclusive conceptions of autonomy is the silencing, or exclusion, of authentic
voices, whether this occurs in the context of interpersonal relationships, social
practices, or the arena of politicallife.
By contrast, relational conceptions of autonomy of the sort surveyed thus
far typically embrace more restrictive conditions on autonomy as a way of
ensuring that autonomous agents are appropriately authorized to govern their
effective motives, values, choices, and actions (and the processes by which they
arose). On the approaches taken by theorists such as Oshana and Stoljar, au-
thentically formed and sustained motives, values, and actions may arise within
social conditions that diminish, circumvent, or undermine agential authority
and, in so doing, obstruct the persons autonomy. External social relations and
normative practices can be relevant to determination of a persons autonomy,
these theorists maintain, because such factors can interfere directly with the
persons ability to exercise authority over her choices and actions, however
authentically those choices and actions may express what she cares about or
wants or would reflectively accept. Thus, whereas nonrelational conceptions of
autonomy tend to highlight the dimension of self in agential self-governance
and therefore emphasize the agents capacities for voice, relational concep-
tions tend to highlight the dimension of governance in autonomous agents
self-governance and therefore emphasize the conditions of the agents author-
ity. Most importantly for the present discussion, these divergent emphases are
reflected through the ways theorists of autonomy appeal to social and political
commitments in the course of defending their preferred theories.
considerable, they do not affect the fundamental proposal Iam advancing, even though Friedmans
account lends itself somewhat more readily to the interpretation offered here than does Christmans
account.
108 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
57
Cf. Benson, Taking Ownership, esp. section II, 106110, for more extended discussion of the
normative, social, and discursive aspects of autonomy. That paper approaches the relationship be-
tween authority and voice in theories of autonomy rather differently, however, interpreting these con-
cepts against the background of the idea that autonomous agents take ownership of their actions in a
distinctiveway.
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 109
potential criticisms and the voicing of reasons in response.58 Or, to use Andrea
Westlunds related terminology, this authority may turn on the disposition to
hold oneself answerable to external critical perspectives59 or ones disposi-
tions for dialogical answerability.60
The autonomous agents voice, on this approach, does not consist simply
in her capability to express through her actions what she most cares about or
values or would reflectively accept. Instead, the agents voice is composed of
the persons regarding herself as being in an appropriate position to speak for
her decisions and actions in response to potential criticisms, irrespective of
whether her actions actually issue from her deepest or reflectively acceptable
motives or values. And the agents authority is not a matter of her deciding
and acting in social circumstances that are largely free of unjust subordination
or of acting on the basis of judgments that have not been influenced inappro-
priately by misguided or harmful social norms. The agents authority arises,
rather, from her taking up the position of a potential answerer for her actions,
from holding herself potentially answerable to others for what she does. Such
authority need not depend on the agents being able to see through misguided
gender norms or having the unimpeded social opportunity and power to ad-
vance her fundamentalaims.
Forging internal connections between agential voice and agential
authority in this manner intuitively may seem too weak, as it appeals to
self-regarding attitudes that could be wholly unfounded or may result from
autonomy-undermining processes. Agents regard for their own competence
and worthiness to answer for their acts can arise under conditions that plainly
disrupt their autonomy. Thus, some objective constraints on these attitudes
are necessary, including, first, autonomous agents attitudes toward their own
capabilities and worthiness to function as answerers must be formed in a suit-
ably rational way, on the basis of their evidence for such attitudes.61 Second,
autonomous agents must be capable of gaining otherwise socially available in-
formation that would be practically germane to the formation of these attitudes
and to the making of their decisions. Such capability is impaired, for instance,
in societies dominated by Orwellian propaganda. Third, autonomous agents
attitudes must not be modified by processes that circumvent their capacities
for rational consideration, as in cases of forcible mind control. Finally, the
norms in relation to which agents regard themselves as capable of presenting
their reasons must be publicly shareable, in principle.62
58
Benson, Taking Ownership, 108109. Also see Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth.
59
Andrea C. Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24 (2009):2649,28.
60
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,35.
61
John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, Moral Responsibility and Control (Cambridge:Cambridge
University Press, 1998), 213214, 235236, propose a similar condition in their account of taking respon-
sibility for acting from a particular kind of action mechanism.
62
These four conditions also are presented in Benson, Taking Ownership, 117118.
110 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Conceiving in this manner the distinctive forms of voice and authority that
characterize personal autonomy should enable the conception of autonomy
that results to avoid the respective excesses in inclusiveness and restrictive-
ness that we identified in the theories surveyed in this chapter. Understanding
voice in this way does not restrict substantively the particular values, motives,
choices, or actions that autonomous agents can adopt, possess, make, or per-
form. Agents who take up the position of potential answerers for their actions
are not thereby constrained in what they care about, hold to be worthwhile,
or aim to do. Simply in virtue of being in a position to speak for their actions,
they are not subject in any evident way to direct, substantive constraints on
their attitudes or values. Hence, this approach should be capable of realizing to
a significant (though not unlimited) extent the inclusiveness that procedural,
nonrelational theories typicallyseek.
At the same time, this approach to conceiving of autonomous agents
authority does not carry unduly restrictive or skeptical implications for the
scope of autonomy. While agents will not attain the authority to speak or
answer for their actions simply because they meet procedural conditions of
authenticity and competence, or the like, the requirements for having such
authority do not incorporate the notably idealized social or evaluative condi-
tions that relational theorists like Oshana or Stoljar envisage. Most healthy,
socially functional adults are able to sustain the requisite dispositions for di-
alogical answerability notwithstanding routine social injustices to which they
may be subject or the limitations in their apprehension of how best to live
their lives or structure human social relations. Hence, this way of relating the
dimensions of voice and authority in our understanding of personal autonomy
seems neither to be overly restrictive nor excessively inclusive.
Thinking of the distinctive dimensions of authority and voice that comprise
autonomy as being internally related in this way, and recognizing that this ap-
proach avoids some of the most prominent deficiencies that have surfaced in
other influential conceptions of relational and nonrelational autonomy, pro-
vides good reasons for holding that personal autonomy is constitutively re-
lational. We cannot make sense of agents holding themselves to be potential
answerers for their choices and actions unless we understand persons to be po-
tential participants in relationships and social interactions in which others can
criticize their conduct. We cannot conceive of agents who have the requisite
authority and voice to act autonomously apart from a web of relationships and
normative domains within which persons are permitted to hold others to ex-
pectations and are disposed to present reasons, where appropriate, in response
to others expectations. As we have seen, however, this form of constitutive
relationality does not mean that autonomous agents are subject, inherently
and directly, to specific, substantive normative constraints on what they want,
value, or aim to do. Ishall not explore further here how best to understand
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 111
63
For further discussion of whether or not to interpret this approach as weakly, or indirectly,
substantive, as I have argued previously, or whether to interpret the approach as yielding only
formal, content-neutral conditions on autonomy, see Paul Benson, Narrative Self-Understanding
and Relational Autonomy, Symposia on Gender, Race, and Philosophy 7 (2011), http://web.mit.edu/
sgrp/2011/no1/Benson0511.pdf; Andrea C. Westlund, Reply to Benson, Christman, Rocha, and Stoljar,
Symposia on Gender, Race, and Philosophy, http://web.mit.edu/sgrp/2011/no1/Westlund0511.pdf. Also
relevant to this issue is Diana Tietjens Meyers important contribution to this volume, The Feminist
Debate over Values in Autonomy Theory, in which Meyers argues that the usual ways in which debates
between value-laden and value-neutral conceptions of autonomy have been framed conflate two inde-
pendent axes along which theories of autonomy may incorporate normative substance.
112 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
hand, and ideal social and political practices and institutions, on the other, that
are only distantly attainable. In contrast with Oshanas theory, my approach
makes room for the autonomy of courageous crusaders, like Shirin Ebadi,
who plainly assert their authority to speak and answer for their own reasoning
and conduct, notwithstanding the grave injustices inflicted upon them. At the
same time, my approach allows that, for many other women in postrevolu-
tion Iran, crushing restrictions on womens political, professional, and eco-
nomic rights may have the additional effects of undermining their disposition
to hold themselves answerable for what they do, of engendering passivity, and
of diminishing their sense of authority to take ownership for their choices.
This contrasts with procedural theories that would ask only that autonomous
agents act in ways they would reflectively accept, even when their own sense
of agential authority has been retarded or destroyed. Any politically useful
approach to autonomy must be able to distinguish between the autonomous
agency of the defiant resister of oppression (even when her resistance fails to
achieve many of its goals) and the damage done to other womens autonomy by
that very oppression. It is an appropriate social and political priority that our
understanding of womens agency carefully track these differences among in-
dividual womens social and psychological locations within the same systems
of domination.
Third, the approach proposed here is capable of distinguishing clearly be-
tween persons actual autonomy and their capabilities for autonomous ac-
tion, on one hand, and their status as full moral and political agents, on the
other. For example, women whose autonomy is compromised by profound
self-doubt or the pervasive sense that they are socially invisible, and hence
are not in a position to speak for their own decisions and actions, are not
thereby to be exempted from moral accountability or barred from political
participation. It is one thing to be capable of claiming the authority and voice
that distinguish autonomous agents; it is quite another to possess the stand-
ing of a person with equal moral worth and full rights to political participa-
tion, whether or not that standing actually is honored. The latter conditions
are necessary for the former, but the converse is not the case. Thus, the view of
relational autonomy that emerges in this paper avoids one of the primary dif-
ficulties with Friedmans and Christmans nonrelational theories.
6.Conclusion
This chapter opened with the observation that the increasing influence that
feminist commitments have had in constructing new theories of personal au-
tonomy has been accompanied by the emergence of increasingly rigid bound-
aries among feminist accounts of autonomy. Our exploration of the role that
a conception of autonomy should have in relation to feminist normative
Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy 113
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Mark Piper and Andrea Veltman for their many insightful
comments on an earlier version of this chapter.
{6}
The starting point of this paper is a pair of clashing feminist intuitions about
the relationship between values and autonomy. For Natalie Stoljar, desires
influenced by oppressive norms of femininity cannot be autonomous.1 For
Marilyn Friedman, however oppressive their conditions might be and how-
ever much change is morally required, traditionally subordinate feminine
lives nevertheless can and do often nonslavishly embody and express values
worth caring about.2 Prioritizing resistance to oppression as an objective for
an adequate feminist theory of autonomy, Stoljar calls for a strongly substan-
tivethat is, value-saturatedaccount. Such an account must deem actions
conforming to false conceptions of womanhood nonautonomous regardless of
whether the agent has reflected on and endorsed them. In contrast, Friedman
prioritizes recognizing and respecting the values and agency of women in
patriarchal societies, and her value-neutral view of autonomy allows for the
possibility that womens compliance with oppressive feminine norms may be
autonomous. Like Stoljar, Ithink that a feminist account of autonomy must
render social critique and oppositional agency intelligible and achievable.
However, like Friedman, Idoubt that a womans nonautonomy can be inferred
from her compliance with subordinating femininenorms.
Paul Benson and Andrea Westlund have recently taken on the challenge of
reconciling the competing intuitions Stoljar and Friedman defend. Eschewing
his earlier value-saturated theory of autonomy, Bensons bid to end the Stoljar
Friedman stalemate proposes what he calls a weak substantive account of
autonomy. Iargue, however, that Bensons proposal does not offer a compro-
mise between value-saturated and value-neutral accounts.3 Instead it adum-
brates a previously unnoticed way theories of autonomy incorporate values.
1
Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, in Relational Autonomy, edited by
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2000),95.
2
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2003),25.
3
In email correspondence, Benson tells me that he didnt intend to identify a midpoint between
value-neutral and value-saturated theories of autonomy. However, I believe that use of the term
substantive to cover all autonomy theories that incorporate values regardless of how the values are
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 115
incorporated leads readers to assume that Bensons weakly substantive account is on a continuum be-
tween value-neutral (nonsubstantive) theories and strongly substantive theories. As well, Ibelieve that
this use of the term substantive masks the distinction between the two axes that Ipresenthere.
116 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
1. Two ValueAxes
In this section, Idistinguish two axes that represent different ways autonomy
theories incorporate and exclude values. Along one axis, autonomy theories
vary with respect to their degrees of value prescriptivity. Along the other axis,
autonomy theories vary with respect to what Ill call their constitutive value
sets. In my view, Bensons conception of a weakly substantive autonomy theory
appears to collapse the Constitutivity Axis into the Directivity Axis with con-
fusing results.
The Directivity Axis is scalar, and like a scale for measuring weights its
values start at zero and range upward. On the Directivity Axis, theories of
autonomy range from value-neutral theories to value-saturated theories with
more or less value-laden theories in between. Value-neutral theories place no
limits on the values or disvalues that people may autonomously elect to live
by. Instead, they assess autonomy on the basis of the motivational structure
of the agentic subject and/or on the basis of the procedure behind an individ-
uals choices and actions.4 Value-saturated theories demand that autonomous
individuals repudiate particular disvalues or fulfill particular values. Susan
Babbitts value-saturated position maintains that autonomous individuals
must conduct themselves in a manner that satisfies their objective interest in
fully flourishing.5 Falling short of standards of self-respect, dignity, and libera-
tion defeats autonomy, and satisfying these standards forbids compliance with
oppressive norms and capitulation to oppressive circumstances.6 Thus, women
cannot autonomously defer to their husbands, and members of marginalized
social groups who have the talent to be medical researchers cannot autono-
mously opt to become pharmacists instead.7
It is clear that Natalie Stoljar rejects value neutrality because it fails to sup-
port her feminist intuition. However, it is less clear just how prescriptive she
thinks an adequate feminist theory of autonomy needs to be, for she offers
two versionsone considerably less potent than the otherof her feminist
4
Harry Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About (Princeton, NJ:Princeton University
Press, 1988); Harry Frankfurt, Reply to Lear, in The Contours of Agency, edited by Sarah Buss and
Lee Overton (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002); Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics; John
Christman, The Politics of Persons (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009); Andrea
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, Philosophical Review 112:4 (2003): 483523;
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009): 2649; Diana Tietjens Meyers,
Self, Society, and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1989); Meyers, Gender in the
Mirror: Cultural Imagery and Womens Agency (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002); Meyers,
Being Yourself:Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life (Lanham, MD:Rowman and Littlefield,2004).
5
Susan Babbitt, Feminism and Objective Interests: The Role of Transformation Experiences
in Rational Deliberation, in Feminist Epistemologies, edited by Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter
(NewYork:Routledge, 1993), 246248.
6
Babbitt, Feminism and Objective Interests,261.
7
Babbitt, Feminism and Objective Interests, 249, 251252.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 117
8
Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,95.
9
Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, 98. Emphasisadded.
10
My thinking about value-laden theories has been influenced by Jason Stiglianos work in my
Spring 2012 Philosophy of Action seminar. It is important to note that in feminist philosophy of ac-
tion substantive theories of autonomy, which Iparse as value-laden and value-saturated theory, were
introduced specifically to address the problem of internalized oppression. In this paper, Iconfine my
discussion to feminist autonomy theories. Although Stoljar centers her thinking on the way oppressive
gender norms undermine womens autonomy, Iformulate my account of value-laden autonomy theo-
ries to include compliance with the norms imposed by any type of oppression, for feminist philosophy
is centrally concerned with intersections of multiple systems of oppression and privilege.
11
I take this analogy from the 1975 body-snatcher film The Stepford Wives, directed by Bryan
Forbes.
118 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
12
I wont attempt to determine whether the standards I have sketched are faithful to Stoljars
overall text or whether these standards are more philosophically satisfying than the strong normative
competence theory of autonomy that she ultimately endorses at Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist
Intuition, 107108.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 119
with proponents of value neutrality, for it does not affirm that the extent or
the gravity of womens compliance with oppressive gender norms is decisive
with respect to their autonomy, and it asserts that women can autonomously
comply with such norms.13 If so, Bensons view is not a value-laden position of
the sort Ihave sketched. Nevertheless, he labels his position a weak substan-
tive one, which gives the impression that his view is located on the continuum
between value-saturated positions that directly impose normative constraints
on autonomous choice and latitudinarian value-neutral positions.14 However,
I believe that his explanation of how it is possible for a woman to autono-
mously comply with an oppressive social norm alerts us to a second axis of
analysis for autonomy theories.
At stake in the debate between proponents of value-saturated accounts and
proponents of value-neutral accounts is whether it is possible to autonomously
conform to oppressive norms. I have suggested that the middle area of the
Directivity Axis is occupied by positions that place limits on an autonomous
agents absorption into an oppressive regime but that allow that oppressive
norms may have some influence in an autonomous agents life. According to
value-laden theories, autonomy is inversely related to the sway oppressive
norms exert over a persons conduct.
In contrast, Benson holds that the autonomy of gender conformists derives
from their favorable attitudes toward their own competence and worth to-
gether with their retention of a sense of their own authority as reasoning, po-
tentially answerable agents.15 Those who have these positive reflexive attitudes
and take agential ownership are autonomous; those who lack these attitudes
and deflect agential ownership are not.16 If so, autonomy is not devoid of nor-
mative content, in Bensons view, yet normative considerations do not enter
into his theory in the same way that they enter into value-saturated and val-
ue-laden theories. The latter restrict the types of action that an autonomous
agent can choose and/or the constellations of motivations that can give rise to
autonomous actions. Benson introduces values by another route. For Benson,
the psychological values of self-confidence and self-worth are constitutive of
autonomous choice and action. Self-confidence is needed to assure you of
your ability to explain your actions by citing your reasons, and self-worth is
needed to assure you of your entitlement to answer for yourself.17 Together,
13
Paul Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy, in Personal
Autonomy, edited by James Stacey Taylor (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005),
128130,136.
14
Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 136,125.
15
Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 136137.
16
Benson, Feminist Intuitions,128.
17
Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 128. Paul Benson, Taking Ownership: Authority and Voice in
Autonomous Agency, in Autonomy and the Challenges of Liberalism, edited by John Christman and
Joel Anderson (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2005), 109,116.
120 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
18
Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, 107, quoting Benson.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 121
19
Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 135. Here Irepudiate a concession to Bensons argument Imade
in Diana Tietjens Meyers, Review of Personal Autonomy in Society by Marina Oshana, Hypatia 23:2
(2008):206.
122 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
20
Benson, Taking Ownership, 114115.
21
Benson, Taking Ownership,115.
22
Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice, 195197.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 123
a mystery to them, and the constitutive value set presupposed by their autono-
mous choices may remain in the background without deleterious effects on
their autonomy.23 They have no more need to theorize their autonomy and
commit to exercising the skills that sustain it than they have to comprehend
and commit to the physiological processes that enable them to walk around
without bumping into things or fallingdown.
Cheshire Calhouns distinction between commitments and deep psy-
chological attractions is helpful here.24 Although some philosophers re-
gard motivations that are deep-seated and impervious to change as passive
commitments, Calhoun maintains that all genuine commitments are active
in the sense that they are made, not merely discovered as facts about ones
psychology.25 Calhoun allows that decisions can be made with more or less
awareness, but she insists that commitments are authored both because they
arise from decisions for which the agent has reasons and because they require
us to make an effort to revive them should they flag and to resist temptations
to abrogate them.26 My claim is that an autonomy theory with a constitutive
value set can ascribe autonomy to people who have unwittingly absorbed the
relevant cognitive, affective, and volitional dispositions regardless of whether
those individuals have decided to deploy those dispositions when they make
choices and regardless of whether they have decided to uphold the theorys
constitutive value set. Because value-utilizing theories do not require indi-
viduals to incorporate the desiderata included in their respective constitutive
value sets into their conceptions of the good life, letalone pursue them as in-
strumental or intrinsic ends, these theories do not require that autonomous
individuals be committed to these values.
Now, it goes without saying that people who arent acquainted with the vo-
cabulary of philosophy of action dont value autonomy under that description.
Nevertheless, people commonly do value a solid sense of who they are and
what really matters to them, and they value leading a life that is truly their
own. Thus, it seems plausible to suppose that many people who have gradually
assimilated autonomy capabilities during childhood and who now regularly
avail themselves of those capabilities do come to value what philosophers call
autonomous choice and action. Moreover, some might form commitments to
23
Westlund echoes this point:To be self-governing, we dont need to have a clear understanding of
what makes us self-governing....We just need to function that way in fact. See Westlund, Selflessness
and Responsibility for Self,3.
24
Cheshire Calhoun, What Good Is Commitment? Ethics 119 (2009):616617.
25
Calhoun, What Good Is Commitment?617.
26
Calhoun, What Good Is Commitment? 617618. There is of course a familiar logical thesis
that you are committed to the presuppositions of your beliefs and to the implications of your belief set.
However, transposing this conception of commitment into the realm of practical philosophy would do
violence to the subtlety of the distinctions we use to make sense of individuals normative identities
and their conduct. Acommitment is not the same as a tentative plan; caring about X is not the same as
being committed to X, and soforth.
124 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
27
Harry Frankfurt, Importance of What We Care About,22.
28
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility, 496; Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,
3637. Please note that Westlunds view is evolving. Although she still holds that her view of autonomy is
formal, she now holds that a disposition to answer for yourself is partly constitutive of the answerabil-
ity self-relation but not the whole of it. See Andrea Westlund, Reply to Benson, Christman, Rocha, and
Stoljar, Symposia on Gender, Race, and Philosophy 7:1 (2011):23, http://web.mit.edu/sgrp; Westlund,
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 125
does not depend on favorable beliefs about or attitudes toward yourself, nor
does it presuppose that you are symmetrically situated in relation to those who
may pose challenges to your commitments or in relation to those with whom
you interact most frequently or intimately.29 It is a formal relation, constituted
by a disposition to respond to normative pressures on ones commitments.30
Having assimilated this disposition, you take queries about your value com-
mitments from other points of view seriously, and you are prepared to examine
your reasons for your commitments.31 However, satisfying this criterion does
not oblige you to engage in hard-knuckle debate with every and any opponent
of your beliefs and practices. Challenges sometimes come from left field, and
challengers are sometimes out of line.32 Moreover, telling stories or describing
exemplars are acceptable ways to justify your beliefs and actions, and thinking
through legitimate challenges privately may suffice.33 Westlunds answerabil-
ity criterion cognizes a variety of discursive styles, and it grants individuals a
measure of discretion in their encounters with would-be challengers.
Westlund concludes that properly understood, autonomy is relational and
value- neutral.34 In characterizing self-answerability as a formal relationship to
potential interlocutors, Westlund sets aside the claim that autonomy requires
egalitarian relationships with others or a self-respecting relationship to your-
self. Specifically, she is rejecting not only Stoljars and Babbitts contention that
deference to a subordinate social status is incompatible with autonomy but
also Bensons contention that the self-doubt and self-effacement promoted
by subordination are incompatible with autonomy.35 Iagree that her theory is
value-neutral. Still, Iwould argue that her account is value-utilizing, for she
grounds her conception of answerability in the epistemic value of rational
Autonomy, Authority, and Answerability, Jurisprudence 2:1 (2011):171n25. Here, Iquote from her ear-
lier work because she articulates the formality of her position in an especially clear and emphatic way
in these papers. In my discussion in Section 4 Ill shift to her modified account of the self-answerability
self-relation. Inote, though, that it is possible that her contribution to this volume may further amend
or jettison parts of the view she has previously published. Iwont attempt to take her chapter into ac-
count because Ihavent had access to it in time to do so. Since my purposes in considering her work are
(1)to help me clarify the distinction between the Directivity Axis and the Constitutivity Axis (Section
2)and (2)to illustrate the usefulness of the Constitutivity Axis (Section 4), Idont think my discussion
will do any injustice to herwork.
29
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, 27,39.
30
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, 37. Also see Westlund, Selflessness and
Responsibility, 520n16.
31
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility,497.
32
Westlund, Autonomy, Authority, and Answerability,171.
33
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,3840.
34
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,28.
35
For related discussion, see the valuable distinction in Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy, 32, between deference and deep deference. As my purpose here is not to assess the
strengths and weaknesses of Westlunds account but rather to use her account to illustrate my distinc-
tion between the directivity axis and the constitutivity axis, Iwont take up the question of whether
Westlunds account successfully fends off substantive theories of autonomy.
126 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
dialogue and the moral value of interpersonal accountability.36 If so, her claim
that answerability is a formal relationship must do double duty. In addition
to addressing Stoljars, Babbitts, and Bensons reservations about the tena-
bility of value-neutral theories, it must provide a convincing response to the
claim that value-utilizing theories dont differ in kind from value-laden or
value-saturated theories.
I believe that Westlund underscores the formality of the answerability
relationship for the same reason that I refer to autonomy competency as a
modus vivendi. Both of us aim to preserve the value neutrality of our views.
Westlunds conception of self-answerability as a formal relation and my con-
ception of autonomy competency as a modus vivendi suggest an analogy to the
experimental method in science. The experimental method rests on a bundle
of epistemic valuesfor example, accurate data and replicatable resultsyet
it does not predict what questions scientists will pose or what results their
experiments will yield. Likewise, our value-utilizing autonomy theories and
the constitutive value sets implicit in them do not predict what autonomous
people will choose to do or become other than being autonomous.37 Just as the
answerability relationship does not preordain what propositional content your
answers will contain, so too autonomy competency does not predetermine the
selection of projects and aspirations that youll decide to organize your life
around. Unlike personal life plans or individualized value systems, answer-
ability and autonomy competency are frameworks suitable for anyone to use
in conducting alife.
That some sets of constitutive values are amenable to being diverted into
the service of a nonautonomous way of life further supports the feasibility of
conceiving value-utilizing autonomy theories that are value-neutral. Consider
some of the values implicated in the agentic skills Ispecify. Such attributes as
perspicacity, resourcefulness, creativity, rationality, self-esteem, stability, resil-
ience, tenacity, and corrigibility might be directed away from leading a life of
your own and dedicated exclusively to raising perfect children or writing great
novels. An individual might take up the project of parenting or fiction non-
autonomously, and she might assiduously devote her talent and energy to ex-
cellent parenting or writing as judged by standards set by others. Living up to
36
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, 494495; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy, 3435. Paul Benson, Commentary on Mackenzie and Poltera (2010) and Westlund (2009),
Symposia on Gender, Race, and Philosophy 7:1 (2011):3 makes a similar point about Westlunds position.
And in her response to Bensons commentary, Westlund, Reply to Benson, Christman, Rocha, and
Stoljar, 3, concedes that her view invokes what Iam calling a constitutive valueset.
37
This point is on a par with David Vellemans claim about the role of your understanding in
autonomous agency. According to Velleman, your understanding is your inalienable point of view in
the following sense:You cannot suppress or abandon this capacity without sacrificing your status as
an autonomous agent. See J. David Velleman, The Possibility of Practical Reason (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2000), 137138.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 127
38
Benson, Feminist Intuitions,132.
128 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
I close this section as Ibegan it with a reflection on Paul Bensons work on sub-
stantive autonomy theory. Near the end of the essay in which he introduces his
conception of weakly substantive theories, Benson incisively remarks:
More interesting is our finding that the distinction between substantive and
content-neutral theories, which seemed so sharp and straightforward in ear-
lier phases of contemporary writing on autonomy, should be reconceived as
a range of theories that impute varying kinds of normative substance, through
disparate pathways, to autonomous agency.39
Although this passage might be read as affirming a single spectrum of substan-
tive theories, Ithink that Benson might be receptive to the Double Axis Thesis.40
After all, he clearly recognizes that different theories incorporate different kinds
of norms in different ways, and the purpose of the Double Axis Thesis is to pro-
vide a framework for articulating and analyzing this heterogeneity. In the next
section, Ill say why as a feminist Iadvocate the Double Axis Thesis.
39
Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 137. Emphasisadded.
40
In email correspondence, Benson has told me that he endorses the Double Axis Thesis as Ive
laid itout.
41
Mark Piper explicitly argues for the Single Axis Thesis, though not under that rubric. See Mark
Piper, Autonomous Agency and Normative Implication, Journal of Value Inquiry 46:3 (2012):317330.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 129
42
However, I note that a constitutive value set that entails a value-saturated position on the
Directivity Axis shrinks the gap between the two axes. See my comments on strong normative compe-
tence theory in Section2.
43
Babbit, Feminism and Objective Interests, 253256.
44
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics, 2024,67.
130 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
I cannot address the question of the authority for autonomous choice and
action in all its complexity here. However, Ido want to say a little about why
it would be inadvisable for feminists to embrace the Single Axis Thesis. This
framework exacts the following trade-off:It downplays the possibility that an
individuals distinctive attributes provide the authority for autonomy in order
to highlight the fact that all credible autonomy theories incorporate values
in some way. Of course, the Single Axis Thesis does not deny that there are
stronger and weaker versions of substantive autonomy theories. Some sub-
stantive theories issue restrictive commandsfor example, an autonomous
woman must not risk pregnancy to prove that shes fertile and marriageable.45
Such strongly substantive theories are far more overbearing than weaker ones
that allow women to defer to mens sexual demands and engage in risky re-
productive behavior provided that they have distinctive personal motives for
doing so.46 Weakly substantive theories are quite permissive, and they secure
greater latitude for agents to express their particular needs, desires, and values.
This being so, it might seem that the Double Axis Thesis sacrifices theo-
retical parsimony for the sake of a mere label and a misleading label at that.
Calling an autonomy theory value-neutral, it might be objected, perpetuates
the misconception that it is possible to theorize autonomy without invoking
any values apart from autonomy itself. This objection would be sound if Iwere
maintaining an alternative Single Axis Thesisone that acknowledged only the
spectrum ranging from value-saturated theories to value-neutral theories with
value-laden theories in between. However, the Double Axis Thesis is designed
to perspicuously represent both the possibility that self-expression takes prec-
edence over reason-responsiveness in autonomous action and the insight that
all accounts of the process of autonomous choice implicitly or explicitly invoke
values. Whereas the array of constitutive value sets on the Constitutivity Axis
encodes the latter insight, the value-neutral pole of the Directivity Axis sanc-
tions autonomous expression of individuality.
For feminists, the Double Axis Thesis and its correlative conception of the
Directivity Axis are attractive on several counts. One reason to foreground in-
dividuality and freedom through value-neutral autonomy theory is to preserve
the dynamism of the feminist liberatory agenda. Feminists have repeatedly
underscored the personal and societal damage caused by silencing womens
voices.47 Value-neutral autonomy theory guards against suppressing the diver-
sity of womens perspectives and concerns because it does not preemptively
45
Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,99.
46
For related discussion, see Benson, Feminist Intuitions, 128130.
47
Maria Lugones and Elizabeth V. Spelman, Have We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory,
Cultural Imperialism, and the Demand for the Womans Voice, Womens Studies International Forum
6 (1983):573581; Maria Lugones, Playfulness, World-Traveling, and Loving Perception, Hypatia 2:2
(1987):319. Meyers, Gender in the Mirror,1722.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 131
deny the autonomy of any womans beliefs about how she should live. Because
its zero point is value neutrality, the Directivity Axis allows for an open-ended
view of the scope of autonomous choice. Another advantage of conceiving the
Directivity Axis as Ipropose is that it creates theoretical space for an innova-
tive conception of value-laden theoriestheories that take into account the
potency or harmfulness of the influence of oppressive norms in individuals
lives. Feminist exploration of this category of theory may prove fruitful, for the
value-laden sector of the Directivity Axis invites theorists to develop more re-
fined analyses of how oppression enters into diverse individuals deliberations
and conduct. Finally, the Double Axis Thesisand specifically the Directivity
Axis it positsclarifies what is at stake in feminist debates regarding adaptive
preferences. Iturn to that issuenow.
In my view, the main appeal of value-laden and value-saturated theories of
autonomy stems from feminist concerns about adaptive preferencesprefer-
ences that are harmful to the agent, that are formed in response to an oppres-
sive context, and that help to perpetuate oppression. Feminists often affirm
that an account of autonomy should have something useful to say about adap-
tive preferences. But just what an account of autonomy should contribute to
discussions of adaptive preferences is controversial.
Value-neutral accounts address the problem of adaptive preferences
obliquely. For example, Ibelieve that by and large and in the long run women
who have full repertoires of well-developed, well-coordinated agentic skills,
who exercise these skills frequently enough to keep them from atrophying,
and who mobilize them when they make significant decisions or when they
sense trouble in their lives are less likely to submit to oppressive practices
and more likely to join with others to overcome oppression.48 Along similar
lines, Westlund adduces relational capacities for self-correction to explain how
adaptive preferences can be exposed and shunned. In her view, the process
of grappling with external critical perspectivesthat is, challenges to your
beliefs and values that are posed by someone who doesnt share your world-
viewcan prompt you to reconsider misguided self-subordinating prefer-
ences and to modify resulting patterns of behavior.49 Neither of us believes that
any capacity for autonomy provides failsafe protection against the persistence
of adaptive preferences, but both of us recognize the potential of exercising
agentic capacities for eroding adaptive preferences.
In contrast, value-saturated and value-laden accounts confront the problem
of adaptive preferences head-on. To the extent that women enact adaptive
48
Diana Tietjens Meyers, Feminism and Womens Autonomy:The Challenge of Female Genital
Cutting, Metaphilosophy 31 (2000):469491.
49
Andrea Westlund, Autonomy in Relation, in Out from the Shadows: Analytical Feminist
Contributions to Traditional Philosophy, edited by Sharon Crasnow and Anita Superson (NewYork;
Oxford University Press, 2012), 61,7576.
132 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
preferences they lack autonomy, and when they shed adaptive preferences they
gain autonomy. It is surely tempting to kill two birds with one stone in this
way. Yet there is reason to hesitate before adopting this solution.
Babbitts value-saturated theory espouses conversion experiences that
rid you of adaptive preferences as a step toward autonomous agency.50
Paradoxically, she holds that you can gain autonomy by nonautonomously
relinquishing adaptive preferences.51 Now, few would deny that you can au-
tonomously decide to temporarily suspend autonomous control in order to
achieve an autonomously adopted goalsay, undergoing hypnosis to quit
smoking. It is clear, though, and Babbitt agrees that involuntarily undergoing
a nonautonomous transformation can destroy autonomy.52 You might end up a
mindless acolyte of a crazed cult leader. But because Babbitts position presup-
poses that those who induce you to undergo a conversion experience are right
about its capacity to augment your autonomy, her position is either incomplete
or faulty. Incomplete if it does not furnish criteria for entrusting yourself to
convertors or criteria that pick out autonomy-enhancing conversion schemes.
Faulty if it leaves autonomy enhancement toluck.
Serene Khaders arguments against analyzing adaptive preferences as au-
tonomy deficits spark related concerns about value-saturated and value-laden
theories of autonomy.53 As Khader observes, building adaptive preferences into
a theory of autonomy unwisely presumes that you already know which types
of behavior are expressions of adaptive preferences.54 Khaders more circum-
spect approach posits a minimal perfectionist account of flourishingthat
is, a conception of flourishing that is limited to ensuring basic human needs
and that musters broad assent from members of diverse cultural groups.55
Where women fall short of enjoying this minimal level of flourishing, there
are grounds for suspecting that adaptive preferences have taken root, but this
suspicion can be vindicated (or quashed) only through a process of delibera-
tive inquiry with the women who lead this form of life.56 Because peoples rea-
sons for acting as they do are not transparent, two individuals may be acting
in a seemingly identical way, yet one may be acting on an adaptive preference
while the other isnt. If so, adaptive preferences cannot be singled out on the
basis of the gendered social meanings feminist theorists ascribe to different
types of behavior. It seems, then, that Khaders deliberative approach to identi-
fying adaptive preferences would counsel locating feminist autonomy theories
50
Babbit, Feminism and Objective Interests,251.
51
Babbit, Feminism and Objective Interests, 254256.
52
Babbit, Feminism and Objective Interests,251.
53
Serene J. Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment (Oxford:Oxford University
Press, 2011), chap.2.
54
Khader, Adaptive Preferences, 75, 9697,103.
55
Khader, Adaptive Preferences, 21,138.
56
Khader, Adaptive Preferences, 3536, 42, 6073, 138140.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 133
57
Velleman, Possibility of Practical Reason; Christman, Politics of Persons; Marina Oshana, Personal
Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate,2006).
58
Westlund, Autonomy, Authority, and Answerability, 171; Westlund, Selflessness and
Responsibility for Self, 500, 503; Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,28.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 135
59
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility,498.
60
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy,3233.
61
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility,503.
62
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility, 508; Westlund, Reply to Benson,4.
136 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
63
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility, 506, 507, 510; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy, 3741; Westlund, Reply to Benson,4.
64
Westlund, Reply to Benson,5.
65
Westlund cant resolve this problem by affirming that generating internal dialogues and being
accountable to yourself for your actions presuppose that youve internalized the answerability mode
of relating to others, for this move would reduce answerability to a causally relational, as opposed to a
constitutively relational, theory of autonomy. Nor does her claim in Westlund, Relational Autonomy,
35, that the internal psychological condition of the autonomous agent...point[s]beyond itself, to the
position the agent occupies as one reflective, responsible self among many resolve this problem. If this
internal psychological condition is never activated by external challenges to your important values and
desires, an autonomous person will be indistinguishable from a nonautonomous person. For related
discussion, see Westlund, Autonomy, Authority, and Answerability, 175; also see Westlund, Reply to
Benson,5.
66
This pair of values brings out the kinship between Westlunds thought and the suggestion in
Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 1986), 127, that the best
we can do is to try to live in a way that wouldnt have to be revised in light of anything more that could
be known about us. In email correspondence, Westlund speculates that it may be possible to theorize
reflexive insightfulness and accountability to yourself relationally. So she may seek to salvage the con-
stitutive relationality of her view by offering such an account in futurework.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 137
67
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility, 495500; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy, 2830, 3738; Westlund, Autonomy in Relation, 7076. Although Westlund asserts that
we have good reason to treat pressures toward self-answerability...as the very form that the pres-
sures toward the self-governance of practical reasoning take, Inote that urging someone to think for
herself is no less salient a form that pressures toward self-governance take, and this advice comports
with the modified constitutive value set Ive proposed. Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility,501.
68
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility, 500505; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy, 2830, 3233; Westlund, Autonomy in Relation,7476.
138 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
answerablea bit muddled about her needs and hesitant about her reasons
with respect to her dealings with a domineering husband. If Westlunds theory
is to capture the complexity of womens autonomous agency, it must be able to
discriminate fine-grained gradations of degree as well as the qualities of rela-
tionships that are more and less conducive to answering for yourself. Perhaps
the woman who finds herself tongue-tied when answering to her domineering
husband is able to be sharply self-critical and articulate in answering criticisms
in a quiet moment alone. The constitutive value set Ive ascribed to Westlunds
nuanced answerability theory accommodates this possibility.
However, because being tightly gripped is an absolute state of nonautonomy,
a commensurately exacting constitutive value set is needed to underwrite it.
Whereas a modulated theory that accommodates internal reflection as a basis
for autonomy would confer autonomy on deeply deferential and blindly fanat-
ical individuals, a theory of autonomy premised on the constitutive value set
of rational dialogue and interpersonal accountability would not. If Westlunds
(and my) intuition that these individuals arent autonomous is correct, the less
stringent constitutive value set Ive attributed to Westlunds fully developed
position effectively abandons them to their nonautonomy.
This split between the version of Westlunds view that is needed to account
for autonomy and the version that is needed to account for nonautonomy
deprives her of a key argument for her answerability requirement. Once the
two constitutive value sets are in view, it is evident that her fully developed
theory of autonomy is too permissive to explain nonautonomy. Although it
is an open question whether a single theory might be able to explicate auton-
omous choice and action as well as nonautonomy resulting from adaptive
preferences, so far as Ican see Westlund does not provide a theory that accom-
plishes both aims.69
At this point, however, Iwould like to set aside these difficulties and con-
sider a notable strength of Westlunds position. Here, too, it is helpful to ex-
amine its underlying constitutive value set. In the course of presenting and
defending her view, Westlund describes a number of plausible scenarios in
which someones autonomy comes under scrutiny, and these discussions dem-
onstrate the tremendous practical appeal of her position. Social workers and
medical practitioners are often called on to judge whether a client or patient
has the cognitive wherewithal to competently direct her own affairs. Atheory
committed to the constitutive value set of dialogical rationality and interper-
sonal accountability suggests a sensible strategy for arriving at assessments of
autonomy in these social service and medical settings.
69
As Imentioned in Section 3, Serene Khader warns against theorizing adaptive preferences as
autonomy deficits.
Feminist Debate over Values in AutonomyTheory 139
70
As Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, 40, rightly observes, Part of the burden for
facilitating justificatory dialogue thus falls on the shoulders of the would-be critic, who must position
herself appropriately with respect to the agent in question.
71
Frankfurt, Importance of What We Care About, 5868; Christman, Politics of Persons,145.
72
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics, 720; Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice; Meyers,
Gender in the Mirror; Meyers, Being Yourself.
140 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Andrea Veltman, Mark Piper, Andrea Westlund, Paul Benson, and
the participants in the Relational Autonomy: Ten Years On conference for
their invaluable comments on an earlier version of thispaper.
{7}
1. The Problem
1
Ayaan Hirsi Ali, Infidel (NewYork:Free Press,2007).
2
Alissa J. Rubin, For Punishment of Elders Misdeeds, Afghan Girl Pays the Price, New York
Times, February 16, 2012, http://www.nytimes.com/2012/02/17/world/asia/in-baad-afghan-girls-
are-penalized-for-elders-crimes.html?_r=1&ref=todayspaper.
142 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
3
See Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2006), 6467.
Psychological autonomy (in the realm of the inner citadel) is incapable of empowering a person
in many areas of life that are crucial to successful agency where conditions of this sort are present or
probable. Moreover, neither a legal right of authority over ones affairs nor a moral right of authority
shall suffice for autonomy.
4
What I will say on this point echoes some remarks made by Martha C. Nussbaum, Women
and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (The Seeley Lectures), (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2000); Nussbaum, The Future of Feminist Liberalism, reprinted in Cheshire
Calhoun, ed., Setting the Moral Compass:Essays by Women Philosophers (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2004), pp. 7288; and Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach
(Cambridge:Belknap Press,2011).
5
In formulating this definition, Irelied on Sally Haslanger and Nancy Tuana, Topics in Feminism,
2004, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-topics/ (original publication February 7,2003).
6
Marilyn Friedman, Feminism in Ethics:Conceptions of Autonomy, in The Cambridge Companion
to Feminism in Philosophy, edited by Miranda Fricker and Jennifer Hornsby (Cambridge:Cambridge
University Press, 2000),205.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 143
course, but in the past twenty years they have been affirmed to a surprising de-
gree, especially among younger adults. Keeping these definitions of autonomy
and of feminism in mind, let us turn to the cases Imentioned:the low-wage
laborer; Ayaan Hirsi Ali; and a young Afghanigirl.
7
Barbara Ehrenreich, Nickel and Dimed:On (Not) Getting By in America (NewYork:Metropolitan
Books,2001).
8
Sarah Jane Glynn and Audrey Powers, See The Top 10 Facts About the Wage Gap:Women Are
Still Earning Less than Men across the Board, Center for American Progress, April 16, 2012, http://www.
americanprogress.org/issues/labor/news/2012/04/16/11391/the-top-10-facts-about-the-wage-gap/, re-
port that more than one-quarter of the wage gap is due to the different jobs that men and women
hold. Notably, women are more likely to work in low-wage, pink-collar jobs such as teaching,
child care, nursing, cleaning, and waitressing. The top ten jobs held by women include secretaries
and administrative assistants (number one); elementary and middle school teachers (number four);
cashiers and retail salespeople (number six); maids and housekeepers (number ten), and waitresses.
These jobs typically pay less than male-dominated jobs and are fueling the gender wage gap. In addi-
tion, Glynn, The Wage Gap for Women:The Consequences of Workplace Pay Inequity for Women
in America, August 16, 2012, http://www.americanprogress.org/issues/labor/news/2012/08/16/12029/
fact-sheet-the-wage-gap-for-women/, cites the familiar statistic that women who work full time year
round continue to earn only about 77percent of what men earn. The gap between the median wage
for a man and that of a woman in 2010 was a whopping $10,784 per year. That is enough money for
the average woman to fund a year of higher education and a full year of health care costs, while still
having more than $2,400 to contribute toward her retirement. The U.S. Department of Labor, Bureau
of Labor Statistics, Characteristics of Minimum Wage Workers:2011, March 2, 2012, http://www.bls.
gov/cps/minwage2011.htm, reports that in 2011, 73.9million American workers age 16 and over were
paid at hourly rates, representing 59.1percent of all wage and salary workers. Among those paid by the
hour, 1.7million earned exactly the prevailing Federal minimum wage of $7.25 per hour. About 2.2mil-
lion had wages below the minimum....About 6percent of women paid hourly rates had wages at or
below the prevailing Federal minimum, compared with about 4percent of men. The Department of
Labor, Labor Force Statistics from the Current Population Survey, February 16, 2011, notes, Women
who worked full time in wage and salary jobs had median weekly earnings of $657 in 2009. This rep-
resented 80percent of mens median weekly earnings ($819). To learn more, see Women in the Labor
Force:ADatabook (2010 Edition), BLS Report 1026, December 2010, http://www.bls.gov/cps/demo-
graphics.htm#women.
144 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
might gain control over them through their needs.9 Persons who rely on day
labor or low-income unskilled labor for their livelihood generally live in eco-
nomically precarious conditions. Often their physical and psychological states
are fragile as well. The same can be said of someone who is one paycheck away
from homelessness. Most occupy a state of vulnerability that, fortunately, is
not a feature of the actual situation of persons such as myself. Most persons
in my positionwell-educated, successful academics who enjoy the security
of a tenured job and its benefitsare autonomous. We who enjoy this kind of
security have genuine control over affairs of importance to us in large part be-
cause we are not living hand tomouth.
Of course, we must accept that some degree of insecurity and dependency is
present even in the lives of well-situated adults. Obviously, not all of instances
of insecurity and dependency compromise self-government in a serious way.
How are we to distinguish genuine threats to autonomy from more benign
and commonplace lapses of practical control and authority? Isuggest we em-
ploy a three-step assessment.10 To determine whether a persons situation in
life undermines the practical control demanded of autonomy, we must ask,
first, what is the insecurity a person encounters? Are significant areas of a per-
sons life at risk? Significant areas will encompass those in which a person has
a fundamental interest. For instance, such areas include the interest one has
in choosing ones partner, in making choices about whether to start a family,
and in ones pursuit of a career. In addition, most humans have a deep-seated
investment in the quality of their future lives, and what they can plan, hope
for, and expect depends in no small part on their current state of autonomy.
Notably, too, self-governance in these areas signals ones success as a human
agent. Being a successful agent means being capable of more than simple in-
tentional action. It means being able to own ones action. Next, we must ask
what is required to challenge the insecurity. How demanding is the type and
level of exertion a person must expend to confront the conditions of insecu-
rity and dependence that may undermine her autonomy? Finally, what effect
does this have on the person? What does it cost a person when struggle and
indefatigability are the price one must pay to have ownership over significant
domains of oneslife?
If an individual is financially insecure and this insecurity means she cannot
challenge potential encroachments on the part of those who have power
over her, then her autonomy will be diminished and of less practical value.
9
Diana Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1989) 12.
As Meyers observes, If one can take care of oneself, one is beholden to no oneneither to the state
nor to any other individual(12).
10
The three-step assessment is developed in greater detail in my paper, Marina Oshana,
Is Social-Relational Autonomy a Plausible Ideal? in Personal Autonomy and Social
Oppression:Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana (London:Routledge, forthcoming).
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 145
11
Tommie Shelby, We Who Are Dark:The Philosophical Foundations of Black Solidarity (Cambridge,
MA: Belknap Press, 2005), 193. For a development of this claim, see Oshana, Is Social-Relational
Autonomy a Plausible Ideal?
12
Friedman, Feminism in Ethics:Conceptions of Autonomy,219.
146 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Islamic cultures (as well as in very conservative strains of Christianity and some
ultra-orthodox sects of Judaism).
Ayaan HirsiAli
Even while the details of her autobiographical narrative have been challenged,
facts about Ayaan Hirsi Alis life attest to a remarkable set of experiences. Hirsi
Ali spent her youth in a seminomadic Somali Muslim family, mainly in Kenya.
Her mother was a devout adherent of Wahhabi Islam, a particularly conservative,
politicized, and patriarchal variety practiced largely in Saudi Arabia. In her own
words, Hirsi Ali lived by the Book, for the Book.13 But after witnessing the frus-
tration and experiencing firsthand the misplaced anger of her mother, Hirsi Ali
came to believe that she had to escape Somali culture. Failing to do so, she feared
she would suffer her mothers fate. In Hirsi Alis estimation, her mother had sub-
limated her independent spirit to prevailing patriarchal and religious expecta-
tions, with the result that she became a devoted, well-trained work-animal.14
Had she remained, Ali remarks, I could never become an adult. Iwould always
be a minor, my decisions made for me. But Iwanted to become an individual,
with a life of my own.15
Thus, it came about that in 1992 at the age of twenty-two Hirsi Ali fled to the
Netherlands, claiming political asylum under the pretense that she was escaping
a forced marriage. (This claim was later admitted to be false.) In the aftermath of
September 11, 2001, she denounced Islam and converted to atheism. By 2002, she
was elected to the Dutch parliament on a wave of anti-immigrant sentiment.
Hirsi Ali has made it her mission to criticize Islamic customs. In particular
she has taken to task emigrant Muslim communities in Europe and the United
States for what she regards as their failure to embrace the secular political cus-
toms of their adopted nations. In 2004, Hirsi Ali wrote the screenplay and pro-
vided the voice-over for filmmaker Theo van Goghs made-for-television piece
Submission. The subject of the film was the treatment of women in Islamic cul-
ture. This was recounted by way of the tale of a Muslim woman coerced into a
violent marriage, raped by an uncle, and then viciously punished for adultery.16
13
Hirsi Ali, To Submit to the Book Is to Exist in Their Hell, Sydney Morning Herald, June 4, 2007,
http://www.smh.com.au/news/opinion/to-submit-to-the-book-is-to-exist-in-their-hell/2007/06/03/
1180809336515.html.
14
Johann Hari, My Life under a Fatwa, Independent, November 27, 2007, http://www.indepen-
dent.co.uk/news/people/profiles/ayaan-hirsi-ali-my-life-under-a-fatwa-760666.html.
15
Hari, My Life under a Fatwa.
16
Juxtaposed with passages from the Quran were scenes of actresses portraying Muslim women
suffering abuse. The film also features an actress dressed in a semi-transparent burqa who has texts
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 147
The film, which aired on Dutch television in August 2004, infuriated members
of the DutchMuslim community who viewed it as insensitive, profoundly
sacrilegious, and untruthful. On November 2, 2004, van Gogh was assassi-
nated by Mohammed Bouyeri, an Islamic radical and member of the Hofstad
Group.17 Impaled upon the knife stabbed into van Goghs body was a five-page
letter condemning Hirsi Ali to death as an apostate. After a fatwaa decree of
deathwas delivered against her in 2004, Hirsi Ali lived under armed guard.
In 2006, she moved to the United States, following uproar over the lies she had
told to obtain asylum, which grew to include a false name and birthdate. She
now holds a fellowship at the conservative American Enterprise Institute in
Washington,D.C.
Depending on your point of view, Hirsi Ali is a radical individual freedom
fighter, someone who has put her life on the line to defend women against
radical Islam,18Islam of a sort that presses for the institution of Islamic
law in government and civic lifeor she is a chameleon of a woman with a
talent for reinvention19 whose motives are to be regarded with some skepti-
cism. Notably, her refusal to distinguish mainstream Islam of a sort practiced
by roughly three million people in the United States from its politicized and
radicalized variants is empirically misguided and deeply troubling, not least
of all to feminist Muslim women.20 For instance, she charges that all of Islam
is full of misogyny.21 But whatever you think about Hirsi Aliand let me be
upfront about the fact that Iam not a fan of hersshe presents an absorbing
from the Quran written on her skin. The texts are among those often interpreted as justifying the sub-
jugation of women. Toby Sterling, Dutch Filmmaker Theo Van Gogh Murdered, Chicago Tribune,
November 2, 2004, http://metromix.chicagotribune.com; Gunman Kills Dutch Film Director, BBC
News, November 2, 2004, http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/europe/3974179.stm.
17
This was an Islamic militant group of men of Dutch and Moroccan descent who met in The Hague
and who had been tried in Dutch appellate court on charges of fomenting terrorism. BBC News, Dutch
Jail Terror Group Muslims, March 10, 2006, http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/europe/4793546.stm. For an
update in the case, see Court Orders Retrial of Dutch Terror Group, Radio Netherlands Worldwide,
February 2, 2010, http://www.rnw.nl/english/article/court-orders-retrial-dutch-terror-group; Wendy
Zeldin, Netherlands:Retrial of Hofstad Group, Library of Congress, February 22, 2010, http://www.
loc.gov/lawweb/servlet/lloc_news?disp3_l205401830_text.
18
Patt Morrison, Feminisms Freedom Fighter, Los Angeles Times, October 17, 2009, http://arti-
cles.latimes.com/2009/oct/17/opinion/oe-morrison17.
19
Economist, A Critic of Islam, February 8, 2007, http://www.economist.com/node/8663231.
20
Iranian American author Firoozeh Dumas is one such critic. http://firoozehdumas.com/ The
estimated number of Muslims really is rough. Statistical citations range from two to five billion. See
http://www.religioustolerance.org/isl_numb.htm, http://www.adherents.com/largecom/com_islam_
usa.html, and http://www.islam101.com/history/population2_usa.html.
21
In Bob Drogin, Book Review: Nomad by Ayaan Hirsi Ali, Los Angeles Times, June 7, 2010,
http://articles.latimes.com/2010/jun/07/entertainment/la-et-book-20100607, writes: Fired with the
zeal of a convert, Hirsi Ali insists Islam and the West are locked in a clash of civilizations...The dys-
functional Muslim family constitutes a real threat to the very fabric of Western life, and the Muslim
mind is in the grip of jihad.
148 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
picture of one womans determination to assert her autonomy against the most
resistant of forces.
Moreover, Hirsi Alis call for heightened scrutiny of political Islam does not
reflect simple paranoia or alarmism. In 1991, Sharia law, which is based on the
Quran, became authorized for use in arbitration over civil matters such as
property rights, divorce, and child custody in Ontario, Canada, ostensibly as a
way to lessen the load borne by the civil courts. Margaret Wente of the Globe
and Mail wrote of the decision:
The arbitrators can be imams, Muslim elders or lawyers. In theory, their
decisions arent supposed to conflict with Canadian civil law. But because
there is no third-party oversight, and no duty to report decisions, no out-
sider will ever know if they do. These decisions can be appealed to the reg-
ular courts. But for Muslim women, the pressures to abide by the precepts
of sharia are overwhelming. To reject sharia is, quite simply, to be a bad
Muslim.... Opponents of the new tribunals argue that the governments
imprimatur will give sharia law even greater legitimacy....What is called
sharia varies widely (in Nigeria, for example, it has been invoked to jus-
tify death by stoning). The one common denominator is that it is strongly
patriarchal.22
The decision to authorize sharia law has been hotly contested. Some of
the most vocal opponents are Muslim women who emigrated to Canada
and whose children are Canadian by birth. Two of these women are Alia
Hogben, who headed the pro-faith Canadian Council of Muslim Women,
and Homa Arjomand.23 Arjomand recounts the following story in support of
her concern:
I have a client from Pakistan who works for a bank, Ms. Arjomand tells
[Wendt]. Shes educated. She used to give all her money to her husband.
She had to beg him for money to buy a cup of coffee. Then she decided
to keep $50 a month for herself, but he said no. They took the matter to
an uncle, who decreed that because the wife had not been obedient, her
husband could stop sleeping with her. (This is a traditional penalty for dis-
obedient wives.) He could also acquire a temporary wife to take care of his
sexual needs, which he proceeded to do. Now the woman wants a separa-
tion. Shes fighting for custody of the children, which, according to sharia,
belong to the father.24
22
Margaret Wente, Life under Sharia, in Canada? Globe and Mail, May 29, 2004, http://www.
theglobeandmail.com/news/national/life-under-sharia-in-canada/article743980/.
23
http://www.nosharia.com/.
24
Wendt, Life under Sharia?
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 149
ShakilasStory
We move now to the third case, which was reported in February 2012 in the
NewYork Times. In 2010, Shakila, an Afghani Pashtun girl from rural Kunar
Province was abducted and enslaved for a year under a traditional Afghan
method of justice known as baad.25 Shakila was eight years old at the time.
Baad uses girls as compensation for moral and cultural transgressions per-
petrated by their relatives and tribal elders. In Shakilas case, the violation
occurred when one of her uncles ran off with the wife of a regional leader.
During the course of the year, Shakila was beaten, deprived of food, and con-
fined for most of the day. She managed, miraculously, to escape, but her ordeal
is hardly over. Fearing retribution, her family has fled their home, and they
now eke out a precarious living some distance from their village.
The objective of baad is to appease the anger of an injured family and
to partially reimburse them for whatever loss they suffered. In addition, by
forcing a girl into slavery, feuding families are integrated, thus minimizing the
prospect of sustained hostility. While baad is technically illegal, it is widely
accepted in rural Pashtun regions as a form of justice emanating from a Jirga,
the judicial court of tribal elders. Shakilas fathers response to her abduction
makes plain that he had no quarrel with the practice of baad. Rather, his ob-
jection was that Shakila had been promised in infancy in marriage to someone
else; she was thus someone elses property, not his to dispose of. His view is
commonplace even among members of the legislature. Fraidoon Mohmand, a
member of Parliament from Nangarhar Province, assesses the practice from a
pragmatic, utilitarian standpoint. He states that giving baad has good and bad
aspects. The bad aspect is that you punish an innocent human for someone
elses wrongdoings, and the good aspect is that you rescue two families, two
clans, from more bloodshed, death and misery. Like most men in this cul-
ture, Mohmand believes the good outweighs the bad; the girl given away may
suffer for a year or two, but when she brings one or two babies into the world,
everything will be forgotten and she will live as a normal member of the fam-
ily. His rosy assessment was challenged by the Afghan women interviewed
for the piece. One woman, Nasima Shafiqzada, who oversees womens matters
for Kunar Province states that the woman [or girl] given to a family in baad
will always be the miserable one. The girl not only represents the enemy but
also at a tender age is completely unprepared both for the brutality she will
encounter because of it and for the sexual relations often demanded ofher.
25
Alissa J. Rubin, For Punishment of Elders Misdeeds, Afghan Girl Pays the Price, New York
Times, February 16, 2012, http://www.nytimes.com/2012/02/17/world/asia/in-baad-afghan-girls-
are-penalized-for-elders-crimes.html?_r=1&ref=todayspaper. Baad is not an Islamic practice. The
Times reports that it predates Islam and can be traced to an era when nomadic tribes traveled
Afghanistans mountains and deserts.
150 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
The cases of Hirsi Ali and of Shakila discuss examples from Muslim culture.
The reader might well criticize them as being cheaply purchased by exploiting
Western liberal bias and of being bluntly inattentive to widely (and rightly)
discredited cultural imperialism. And indeed, one need exert only mild effort
to find cognate examples within certain cultural enclaves in Western societies
where non-Muslim culture does not predominate. Although low-wage labor
of the sort discussed in Section 2 is not a social practice rooted in patriarchy
or religion, it is widespread in the West and destabilizes autonomy dispropor-
tionately for women. It would seem obvious that feminists would take up the
campaign of low-wage laborers on the grounds that their economic vulner-
ability makes equal opportunities for self-governance (for women and men)
a struggle. It would seem obvious that feminists would take up the banner
of females in patriarchal societies on the grounds that they endure customs
that violate autonomy. Just as Hirsi Alis life in Kenya meant subjugation and
a loss of autonomy, Shakilas tale illustrates a socially entrenched practice that
unquestionably fails to respect the dignity and the autonomy of females. It
seems equally apparent, to my mind at any rate, that champions of autonomy
would decry the blatantly sexist (and thus arbitrary) basis on which female
low-wage workers are financially exploited. Similarly, Iwould expect propo-
nents of autonomy to denounce the manner in which girls in Shakilas situa-
tion are deprived of their rights of self-governance. Neither, however, is true.
Not all feminists have embraced the value of autonomy as readily as one might
suppose, nor have some proponents of autonomy unequivocally taken up the
banner of feminism. Let us explore why this is the case. Having done so, we
will be in a better position to see why both would be better off as allies.
4.Autonomy
26
Andrea Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009):32.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 151
27
Uma Narayan, Minds of Their Own: Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices, and Other
Women, in A Mind of Ones Own:Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, 2nd ed., edited by Louise
M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt (Boulder, CO:Westview Press, 2002), 418432.
28
Ithank Wilson Mendona for pressing thispoint.
152 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
that autonomy is related (in some way) to feminism will be utterly without
controversy. By contrast, the account of autonomy Iadvance is quite broad.
My position is that a person is autonomous when she has (1)the ability to su-
perintend those of her decisions, activities, and personal associations that are
central to human agency, (2)the warrant to do so, and (3)the power to act on
that ability. Together, these imply the presence of social roles and relations of a
particularly autonomy-friendly variety. Many might not interpret autonomy as
Ihave done; they may accuse my conception of being an interpretation of au-
tonomy that includes ideas of agency, self-sufficiency, individuality, empower-
ment, and human dignity. They might protest that autonomy as Ihave defined
it imports narrowly Western values or values that peremptorily designate the
good for any person, regardless of what the person professes her conception
of the good to be. In a nutshell, some would argue that we must attend to the
distinction between thin autonomy of a sort that may well be comfortable with
feminism and a thick or substantive species of autonomy of a sort that some
feminists dispute. Even if Iam correct that feminists must value the broader
conception of autonomy, feminists need not agree that this is what autonomy
is. It is certainly true, for example, that Westlund supports feminism, even if
she does not do so on the basis of a thin construction of autonomyalone.
But Ithink there is more agreement than there is disagreement regarding
the proper interpretation of autonomy for feminist concerns. Most feminists
do not advocate just a commitment to a legal or moral right to self-governance
but also a commitment to self-governance as an actual state of life. The ap-
pearance of disagreement might be traced to the belief that the conception
of autonomy I advance is normatively substantive in the sense proposed by
Natalie Stoljar and by Paul Benson. But in fact Iam not claiming, as Stoljar and
Benson have claimed, that the autonomous agent cannot internalize oppres-
sive norms or that she cannot value subordinate roles, although as a matter
of empirical fact doing so may be correlated with or give rise to diminished
autonomy.29 What I am claimingand here I suspect most feminists at any
rate agreeis that the practical control autonomy demands draws both from
sources internal to the agent and from external authority of a variety that man-
dates the absence of domination. And Iam claiming, further, that autonomy is
a matter of living in this way regardless of a persons preferences and subjective
interests. If there is convergence of opinion on this point, then there is less
daylight between the thicker, more socially demanding notion of autonomy
Iadvance and whatever account of autonomy is congenial to feminists.
For this reason, Ithink there is something perplexing about the view of au-
tonomy taken by Westlund and the view of feminism taken by Narayan. It is
29
My account is minimally substantive in that the autonomous agent cannot internalize oppressive
norms to such an extent that doing so critically undermines the possibility of effective practical control.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 153
true that not everyone will include an autonomous life among the objectives
he or she esteems. It is also obvious (and Iwould say regrettable) that not eve-
ryone will embrace the concerns of feminism. But although neither Westlunds
construal of autonomy nor Narayans views about western feminism call for
legal rights to nondomination, and while both would grant that someone
could freely choose to be dominated, Isuspect neither Westlund nor Narayan
would claim autonomy was a feature of life for persons such as Shakila (or for
Hirsi Ali before she fled to the Netherlands). And Ithink they could deny that
Shakila and Hirsi Ali lacked autonomy because respect for feminism, along
with the practical resources feminism requires of society, was missing from
their lives.30 If we take seriously the goals of feminismnamely, advocating
for the equal rights of women and ending the oppression and exploitation of
women and girlsthen we cannot rest content with a thin variety of autonomy
premised on a persons free acceptance of and willingness to defend her cir-
cumstances. It really would not make any practical difference to Hirsi Ali if she
had accepted her life in Kenya or if Shakila had been a bit older and had agreed
to be used in baad. Baad violates autonomy owing to the patently chauvinist
foundation on which girls are divested of the power of self-governance, creat-
ing a situation in which some persons are in no way capable of freely choosing
their way of life. What this signals to my mind is that scholars such as Narayan
and Westlund may in fact construe autonomy rather thickly as a de facto or
actual state of life. Any situation where people live in common and where
some have power over others will only be congruent with feminist concerns if
thick autonomy is respected. It is one thing to acknowledge a variety of social
arrangements that comport with individual ideals and quite another to assert
that each of these arrangements will provide a life of autonomy. The three-step
assessment for autonomy serves as a filter for the satisfaction of feminist cri-
teria as gauged by the details provided by the assessment:(1)what areas of life
are insecure, (2)what is called for to diffuse the insecurity, and (3)what effect
does this have on the lives of the parties?
30
The same could be said of some low-wage pink-collar workers whose employment conditions
are precarious.
154 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
women requires that we take seriously the centrality they accord interpersonal
relations in their lives. Aclassic feminist insight into the nature of womens
moral experience is that women are more likely than are men to value relational
interdependency; the moral perspective of women reflects this. Women (it is
argued) have a relational conception of moral ideals and appear less inclined
than do men to dismiss the emotions as a legitimate and essential component
of moral judgment. This does not mean that women care less about their own
powers of self-governance than do men or that the concept of autonomy must
demand less of the social and relational conditions women encounter for their
autonomy to be valued. What it means is that taking seriously any womans
autonomy involves honoring her interdependent, social personality.
What does this require? The capabilities approach to human and moral
development articulated by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen offers an an-
swer to this question. The approach is congenial to the account of autonomy
Iadvance and offers a reason to treat thick autonomy as an essential element
of womens development.31 Let me say a bit more about why Ithink this is so.
The cornerstones of classical liberalism and, more specifically, of the idea of
liberal justice are the concepts of individual choice and liberty. Any liberal
ideology will begin with these two cornerstones and from these describe the
public and institutional arrangements best tailored to guarantee their pres-
ence in human life. Nussbaum argues, however, that we need to recast lib-
eral theory in a way that preserves these cornerstones while also capturing
what it means to be a flesh and blood human functioning in the real world.
To this end, liberalism would do well to begin with a conception of persons
as immersed in relationships of caring and dependency. These relationships
reflect the diverse intellectual, emotional, and bodily abilities persons possess.
What we must do, counsels Nussbaum, is start with a conception of the person
that corresponds to this human experiencethe person as both capable and
needyas opposed to a conception of persons as the impartial moral delib-
erators or self-interested contractors that populate the philosophical imagina-
tions of Kant, or Rawls, or contractarian theory.32 Having done so, we will see
that assessing who qualifies as well-off according to liberal justice calls for a
measurement that includes, among primary goods, the ability of persons to
take part in an extensive range of human endeavors. With a suitable list of the
central capabilities as primary goods, we can begin designing institutions by
asking what it would take to get citizens up to an acceptable level on all these
capabilities.33
31
Ithank Maria Silvia Possas for suggesting the connection between my conception of autonomy
and the liberal capabilities view of Nussbaum andSen.
32
Nussbaum, Future of Feminist Liberalism,79.
33
Nussbaum, Future of Feminist Liberalism,79.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 155
Nussbaum is not prepared to say just what that level would involve, but she
does offer hints. With Sen, she defines capabilities as substantial freedoms
of the sort that include combinations of opportunities to function in various
ways. Importantly, capabilities are not just abilities residing inside a person
but also the [totality of] freedoms or opportunities created by a combination
of personal abilities and the political, social, and economic environment.34 For
instance, she would include among the basic goods the need for carewhich
is something that all of us, given our animality, will require at somepoint.
The NussbaumSen approach suggests that autonomy as Ihave character-
ized it is a capability, located among the list of primary goods founded in the
dignity of human need itself,35 such that any measurement of liberal justice
calls for a measurement that includes autonomy. The principal questions posed
by Nussbaum and Sen for the more comprehensive assessment of justice they
advocate are, What are people capable of doing? and How are people able
to live? Both Nussbaum and Sen note that what people seek is meaningful
lives for themselves; what Iwould add is that being self-governing is an ele-
ment of a meaningful life and, more generally, that people are most capable of
accomplishing this if they are self-governing in a robust way.36 To put the point
somewhat differently, autonomy is, borrowing from terminology employed by
Jonathan Wolff and Avner de-Shalit, a particularly fertile capability, that is,
a capability that is essential to removing corrosive disadvantages of the sort
that undermine other dimensions of a persons experience that spell out how
the person is able to livedimensions such as health, well-being, social re-
spect.37 Autonomy lends security to these other capabilities, promising that
one can bank on their presence in the future. And this type of security is an
objective matter...for each capability we must ask how far it has been pro-
tected from the whims of the market or from power politics.38
If my appropriation of elements of the capabilities approach in defense of
robust autonomy survives inspection, then the strain of liberalism behind
which some feminists and autonomy theorists seek the protective shelter of
neutrality is not nearly as neutral as might be hoped with respect to the social
34
Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities,20.
35
Paraphrased from Nussbaum, Future of Feminist Liberalism,79.
36
Some people might quarrel with the idea that a life bereft of autonomy is a meaningless life.
Let me be clear that Iam not claiming that meaning can only be found in lives that are rich with au-
tonomy. In other work, Ihave taken pains to show that autonomy is not the sole good and that there
are other measures of a meaningful life, such as flourishing or satisfaction. Oshana, Personal Autonomy
in Society. Nonetheless, Ithink ample evidence can be marshaled in support of the claim that where
people do lead meaningless lives, the reason for the meaninglessness can be a lack of opportunities
for growth, development and relationship, which can be due to oppressive social relations (Andrea
Veltman in editorial commentary). Arobustly autonomous person avoids these circumstances.
37
Jonathan Wolff and Avner de-Shalit, Disadvantage (New York: Oxford University Press, June
2007). Their work is discussed in Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities,44.
38
Nussbaum, Creating Capabilities,43.
156 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
goods and capabilities all persons are assumed to need. Autonomy is in some
measure constitutive of a meaningful life for persons. And, in truth, other phi-
losophers whose scholarship often addresses explicitly feminist concerns but
who publically have challenged (indeed, disavowed) portions of the account
Idefend nonetheless speak of the conditions needed to realize a feminist soci-
ety in terms that echo the capabilities approach. Marilyn Friedman, for in-
stance, argues that in order to challenge the formidable structures of male
domination that remain in this world, it is crucial for feminism to insist that
mature women are as capable as men of being full moral agents in their own
rights and should no more be dominated or controlled over the course of their
lives than men are.39 Being as capable as men entails having a commensurate
array of opportunities and a network of support at the ready, as championed
by the capabilities approach.
We might press this point from a different direction. Aright of autonomy
is found in the moral idea that persons have an inherent dignity in virtue
of which they are entitled to a certain standing that constrains both how
persons are to be treated and what they are permitted to do and expected
to do vis vis one another. Ithink it is clear that if many of the rights that
we indisputably have are to be respected, then autonomy must be respected
as well. And for autonomy to be respected, the social institutions that per-
meate our affairsand this includes institutions of law, whether they are
found in the United States or in Afghanistanmust afford us de facto and
de jure power to counter attempts to intrude capriciously in our lives. This
requirement is especially pressing in cases such as Shakilas, where attempts
to deprive a person of her rights are rampant. No person who is in a society,
and particularly those who are most vulnerable, can determine how she
shall live unless she is part of enduring social relations and shared traditions
that afford her authority over the most fundamental areas of her life, in law
and in practice, and without undue cost. If we are committed to something
more than the legal promise of autonomy and if we are committed to more
than a moral right of self-governanceif, that is, we are committed to an
idea of autonomy as a practical condition in which a person is empow-
ered to choose what to do by means of her own authoritythen it seems
straightforward that a commitment to autonomy entails a commitment to
feminism as a moral and a political ideal. This is certainly a conclusion to
which we are led if we follow Nussbaum and Sen in drawing on a richer
variety of social goods deemed essential to the promises of liberal justice.
39
Friedman, Feminism in Ethics, 216. Emphasisadded.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 157
6. Some Objections
Let us turn to some objections that my account might face. To begin, what
would be the consequences for my account if a commitment to autonomy
entailed a commitment to a social structure that is de facto supportive of
womens equality and equal rights while lagging in a moral commitment to
the equality of women? A number of modern affluent societies might meet
this description, including, perhaps, the United States. Indeed, this possibility
is reminiscent of the criticism some feminists have registered against classical
liberalism as an adequate political philosophy, one attentive to the status of
women.40 Mark Piper worries that this would be enough to undermine the
notion that a commitment to thick autonomy entails a commitment to the
moral aspects of feminism dealing with a commitment to the equal value of
women.41 Iam not sure Ishare Pipers worry. It may be that such societies are
only committed to autonomy of a thinner variety. In the United States there is
certainly ample lip service to the moral dimensions of feminism; it is in the lack
of a tangible commitment to the institutional and practical dimensions of fem-
inismwhere this would call for a commitment to thick autonomythat the
true nature of this commitment is revealed. Such societies do not really sup-
port feminist goals in a functional wayif they did, the United States would
have passed an equal pay for equal work amendment long ago. The failure to
do so belies not just a commitment to the moral claim that men and women
have equal value but also a commitment to thick autonomy. It may also be the
case that a commitment to thick autonomy is incumbent on a commitment
to de facto support of equality but less so to the moral dimensions of equal-
ity. Perhaps the moral commitment is less urgent than is the commitment to
practical equality. Imyself think that de facto support is unlikely absent an at-
tendant moral commitment and that a commitment to moral equality in itself
is cold comfort for one whose autonomy is elusive or denied altogether infact.
A second worry for the account Idefend was raised by John Christman in
conversation. Christman suggested that it is an implication of my position
that only feminists can be autonomous. It would certainly seem a stretch to
deny that nonfeminists can be autonomous, and if the view Iwas defending
yielded this result the account would be less plausible. Fortunately, this is
not an implication of my account. That a person manages to live according
to ideals and allegiances that are recognizable as her own, without trouble-
some interference, is a real possibility even for people who repudiate any
40
See, e.g., Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989);
Catherine Mackinnon, Reflections on Sex Equality under the Law, Yale Law Journal 100:5 (March
1991): 12811328; Mackinnon, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (Cambridge,
MA:Harvard University Press,1987).
41
In private commentary.
158 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
42
The discussion that follows is from Marina Oshana, The Autonomy Bogeyman, Journal of
Value Inquiry 35:2 (June 2001):209226.
Commitment to Autonomy Is a Commitment to Feminism 159
7.Conclusion
If we accept what I have said about autonomy, then I think we can expect
feminism of at least a modest variety. The point is not that in some cases the
concerns of feminism and of autonomy go hand-in-hand. The point is that
respecting autonomy means respecting feminist concerns and vice versa.
Proponents of autonomy must unequivocally uphold feminism. And being
committed to feminist concerns leads one more closely to a robust relational
account of autonomy than might initially seem the case. Recall my initial def-
inition of feminism as a belief in and advocacy of equal rights for women
based on the idea of the equality of the sexes. People who are autonomous
have a characteristic type of social standing. This is the social standing people
have when they live in the presence of other people and when, by virtue of
social design, none of those other dominates them.43 This characterization is
consistent with the initial definition Ioffered, namely, that a person is autono-
mous when she makes decisions and engages in actions by means of her own
authority. Iwould also suggest that it is a definition of autonomy that ought to
be accepted by feminists, even those who worry about an excessively individ-
ualistic conception of thatstate.
To avoid misunderstanding, let me state clearly that the point I wish to
make is that one cannot be committed to autonomy unless one is also com-
mitted to feminism and, conversely, that one cannot be committed to femi-
nism unless one is also committed to autonomy. This does not mean that any
society in which autonomy happens to be realized by its members will be a
society committed to feminism. Asociety may be inconsistent in upholding
those goals to which it professes commitment or may fail to give sufficient
weight to these goals. What Ihave attempted to do in this paper is show why,
to the extent that autonomy is prized, feminism ought to be prized as well
and vice versa. Thus, despite criticisms of certain interpretations of autonomy
from feminists and despite the idea that under certain conditions autonomy
and oppression may be compatible, I have uncovered no discussion in the
philosophical literature or in feminist commentary that would cast serious
doubt on the idea that a commitment to autonomy is a commitment to fem-
inism and vice versa. Despite the interminable debate over thick and thin
conceptions of autonomy, my position is that most theorists of autonomy are
not as thin as theythink.
43
Philip Pettit, Republicanism:ATheory of Freedom and Government (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 1997),122.
160 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
1
Alison Jaggar, Love and Knowledge:Emotion in Feminist Epistemology, Inquiry 32 (1989):166.
2
Diana Tietjens Meyers, Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization, Journal
of Philosophy 84 (1987):621.
3
Lorraine Code, Second Persons, in What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction
of Knowledge, edited by Lorraine Code (Ithaca, NY:Cornell University Press, 1991),78.
164 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
4
See Jennifer Nedelsky, Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts and Possibilities,
Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 1 (1989): 736; Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy and the Social
Relationships:Rethinking the Feminist Critique, in Feminists Rethink the Self, edited by Diana Tietjens
Meyers (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1997); Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, Relational
Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2000); Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate,2006).
5
Interestingly, this is a question that has been on the agenda of relational autonomy theorists.
See Mackenzie and Stoljar, Introduction, Autonomy Refigured, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational
Autonomy,2122.
6
One difficulty comes from the fact that there could be gender differences concerning (1)the kinds
of emotions that tend to be felt, (2)what tends to trigger emotions of the same kind, (3)the different
aspects of emotions, such as expression and motivation, and (4)the regulation of emotions. Another
difficulty is that generalisation of this kind are in danger of downplaying individual as well as socio-
cultural differences.
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 165
7
See, e.g., Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy and the Split-Level Self, Southern Journal of Philosophy
24 (1986):1935.
8
For the term full-blooded, see J.David Velleman, What Happens When Someone Acts? Mind
101 (1992):462.
9
Gary Watson, Introduction, in Agency and Answerability:Selected Essays (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2004),1.
10
Watson, Introduction,2.
11
See, e.g., Harry Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, Journal of
Philosophy 68 (1971): 520. Note that insofar as Frankfurt suggests that reflection is the source of
higher-order volitions, the contrast is less stark. See, e.g., Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the
Concept of a Person,7.
12
David Shoemaker, Caring, Identification, and Agency, Ethics 114 (2003): 94; see Tappolet,
Autonomy and the Emotions, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy:Special Issue on Emotions and
Rationality in Moral Philosophy 2 (2006):4559.
166 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
13
The best introduction to emotions theory Iam aware of is Julien Deonna and Fabrice Teroni, The
Emotions:APhilosophical Introduction (NewYork:Routledge,2012).
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 167
14
Friedman, Autonomy and the Split-Level Self, 3031. Cf. Alison Jaggar, Love and
Knowledge:Emotion in Feminist Epistemology; Karen Jones, Emotion, Weakness of Will, and the
Normative Conception of Agency, in Philosophy and the Emotions, edited by Anthony Hatzimoyis
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2003).
15
Friedman, Autonomy and the Split-Level Self,3031.
16
See Alexius Meinong, Ueber Emotionale Prsentation, Kaiserliche Akademie der Wissenschaft
in Wien 183, Part 2, On Emotional Presentation, translated with an introduction by Marie-Luise
Schubert Kalsi (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1917), 1181; Ronald de Sousa, The
Rationality of Emotion (Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 1987); de Sousa, Emotional Truth, Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society 76 (2002):247263; Christine Tappolet, Les motions et les concepts axi-
ologiques, in La Couleur des penses, Raisons Pratiques, edited by Patricia Paperman and Ruwen Ogien,
(Ville:dition, 1995), 237257; Tappolet, motions et Valeurs (Paris:Presses Universitaires de France,
2000); Tappolet, Emotions, Perceptions, and Emotional Illusions, in Perceptual Illusions:Philosophical
and Psychological Essays (Palgrave-Macmillan, 2012); Sabine Dring, Explaining Action by Emotion,
Philosophical Quarterly 53 (2003): 214230; Dring, Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and
Rational Motivation, Dialectica 61 (2007):361394; Jesse Prinz, Gut Reactions:APerceptual Theory of
Emotion (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2004); Prinz, Is Emotion a Form of Perception? The
Modularity of Emotions, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (2008):137160; Julien Deonna, Emotion,
Perception and Perspective, Dialectica 60 (2006):2946.
17
The account is often presented in terms of perceptions instead of perceptual experiences, but
because emotions can misfire, the perceptual account claims only that emotions are the perception
of evaluative properties unless defeated. By contrast with perceptions, perceptual experiences are not
factive. If you perceive that the cat is black, then it is black, but you can of course have the perceptual
experience of a gray cat asblack.
168 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
18
For concepts and nonconceptual contents, see, inter alia, Gareth Evans, Varieties of References
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1982); Christopher Peacocke, A Study of Concept (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press,1992).
19
See William James, What Is an Emotion? Mind 9 (1884): 188204; Carl G. Lange, Om
Sindsbevaegelser:Et Psyki-fysiologisk Studie (Kjbenhavn:Jacob Lunds, 1885), translated in The Emotions,
edited by C. G. Lange and William James (Baltimore:Williams and Wilkins,1922).
20
See Robert C. Solomon, The Passions (Indianapolis:Hackett Publishing Company, 1976); Martha
Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press,2001).
21
The same problem arises for so-called Judgmental Theories, according to which the cognitive
states are taken to be thoughts (Patricia S. Greenspan, Emotions and Reasons (NewYork:Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1988)) or construals (Robert C. Roberts, Emotions:An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2003)).
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 169
22
See Meinong, On Emotional Presentation; Tappolet, motions et Valeurs, chap. 6; Prinz, Gut
Reactions. A Perceptual Theory of Emotion, chap. 10; Prinz, Is Emotion a Form of Perception?;
Deonna and Teroni, Emotions, chap.6; Michael S. Brady, Emotions, Perception and Understanding,
in Morality and the Emotions, edited by Carla Bagnoli ( New York: Oxford University Press, 2001),
chap.2.
23
See, inter alia, Tappolet, Emotions, Perceptions, and Emotional Illusions, in Perceptual
Illusions: Philosophical and Psychological Essays, edited by Clotilde Calabi (Houndsmill,
UK:Palgrave-Macmillan,2012).
24
See de Sousa, Rationality of Emotion; Bennett Helm, Emotional Reason:Deliberation, Motivation,
and the Nature of Value (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2001); Mikko Salmela Salmela, Can
Emotions e be Modelled on Perceptions? Dialectica 65 (2011):129; Deonna and Teroni, Emotions;
Jrme Dokic and Stphane Lemaire, Are Emotions Perceptions of Values, Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 43 (2013):227247; Brady, Emotions, Perception and Understanding.
25
See Tappolet, Emotions, Perceptions, and Emotional Illusions; Tappolet, Emotions, Values, and
Agency (Oxford:Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
26
Iunderstand normative reasons to be considerations that speak in favor of beliefs or actions.
See Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press,1998).
170 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
27
For the claim that the fearsome supervenes on the dangerous, see de Sousa, Rationality of
Emotion.
28
See Jones, Emotion, Weakness of Will,181.
29
The main options are a coherentist model according to which emotions and normative prin-
ciples have to be brought into reflective equilibrium (see Friedman, Autonomy and the Split-Level
Self ) and a foundationalist conception, which grant emotions a defeasible but foundational justifica-
tory power (see Tappolet, motions et Valeurs).
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 171
30
Jones, Emotion, Weakness of Will,190.
31
See Velleman, What Happens When Someone Acts?; Christine M. Korsgaard, The
Normativity of Instrumental Reason, in Ethics and Practical Reason, edited by Garrett Cullity and
Berys Gaut (Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1997); R. Jay Wallace, Three Conceptions of Rational Agency,
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (1999):219; Kieran Setiya, Reasons without Rationalism (Princeton,
NJ:Princeton University Press,2007).
32
Wallace, Three Conceptions of Rational Agency,219.
172 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
that the action expresses the agents commitment to what she calls regulative
guidance. Regulative guidance involves the on-going cultivation and exercise
of habits of reflective self-monitoring of our practical and epistemic agency.33
An action caused by emotions, or for that matter by any other reason-tracking
subsystem, thus manifests genuine agency just in case the agents dispositions
to reflective self-monitoring are such that she would not rely on that first order
sub-system were it reasonable for her to believe that it failed to reason-track.34
Thus, an agent who acts on, say, her anger might be responding to reasons
even if she acts against her judgment concerning what to do. The angry agent
is responding to reason if she has well-tuned self-monitoring habits, such that
she would not have relied on her anger if there had been reason for her to be-
lieve that her anger was misleading her. In other words, what is required for
reason-responsiveness is nothing but the exercise of well-tuned epistemic and
practical habits, that is, of what can be described as agential virtues.
This Agential Virtue Account, as I shall call it, is highly attractive. In the
remainder of this section Iwill provide what can be considered as a partial
defense of the account. More precisely, Iwill argue that it is not threatened
by a number of worries that have been or might be raised. The first volley of
worries is due to Sabine Dring. Dring explicitly criticizes Joness account,
and it is instructive to start with her arguments. According to Dring, the
main problem of Joness analysis is that it remains obscure how, in the case
of conflict between two reason-tracking sub-systems, the agent may decide
which sub-system is to be given preference.35 What Dring has in mind, just
as Jones, are cases of akrasia, that is, cases in which there is a conflict between
the conclusion of the practical reasoning of an agenther better judgment
on one hand and her motivation and intentional action on the other hand.
More specifically, she is thinking of cases of akrasia in which the practical con-
clusion of an agent and what she feels conflict, and it is the feeling that appears
to better fit the agents reasons.36 The classic example is that of Huckleberry
Finn, who is torn between his judgment that he ought to denounce Jim to the
slave hunters and his feelings for Jim. Dring asks:If Huck is mistaken in
the example, how could he have avoided the mistake?...What Huck needs to
know is whether he should here and now follow his sympathy or had better
stick to his judgment.37 Now, it clearly would have been useful for Huck to
know whether to follow his judgment or his feelings. The question, however,
33
Jones, Emotion, Weakness of Will,194.
34
Jones, Emotions, Weakness of Will,195.
35
Sabine Dring, Why be Emotional? in the Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion, edited
by Peter Goldie (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 2010),290.
36
See Alison McIntyre, Is Akratic Action Always Irrational? in Identity, Character and Morality,
edited by Owen Flanagan and Amlie Rorty (Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 1993); Nomi Arpaly and Tim
Schroeder, Praise, Blame and the Whole Self, Philosophical Studies 93 (1999):161188.
37
Dring, Why be Emotional?290.
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 173
38
See Niko Kolodny, Why Be Rational? Mind 114:181200.
39
Dring, Why be Emotional?287.
40
Dring, Why be Emotional?290.
41
Dring, Why be Emotional?291.
174 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
42
To be fair, it has to be noted that Dring explicitely states that subjective reasons are derivative
of objective reasons, and that they do not constitute a second class of normative reasons beyond objec-
tive reasons. Dring, Why be Emotional?287.
43
As McIntyre, Is Akratic Action Always Irrational? argues that this point can be made without
postulating external reasons, for an agent can be wrong about his own motivationalset.
44
See Velleman, What Happens When Someone Acts, 464465.
45
Velleman, What Happens When Someone Acts, 465. Cf. Wallace, Three Conceptions of
Rational Agency, 222, for a similarpoint.
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 175
self-monitoring that constitute agential virtues are in place. What the account
tells is that if the conditions that it spells out are satisfied, then the agent is in
charge, despite his being reluctant to admit it. This is, Ibelieve, an attractive
feature of the Agential Virtue Account.
Finally, let me consider a last worry. On the story proposed here, emo-
tions can inform us about our practical reasons, depending on how reliable
these emotions are. Moreover, undergoing an emotion and acting on its basis
can constitute responding to a reason, and it does constitute responding to
a reason when the relevant emotional disposition or dispositionsthe sub-
systemare well tuned. Accordingly, acting on the basis of an emotion can
amount to acting in light of ones reasons. But how could this be the case, one
might ask, if the agent is not aware of the reasons she has? And how could the
agent be aware of her reasons otherwise than by having beliefs or judgments
regarding those reasons? Another way to express the same worry is to claim
that reasons need to be transparent to the agent:to be motivated by a reason,
that is, to act for a reason, an agent needs to be aware of that reason, where
awareness is understood to require belief or judgment.46
In reply, one may be tempted to deny that awareness requires judgment
and appeal to the fact that emotions are conscious experiences. One could
thus claim that emotions allow us to be aware of values and hence of the
corresponding reasons. After all, nobody would deny that there are both
judgmental and perceptual ways to be aware of poppies and their shapes
and colors. So why not say that when fearing something we are aware of that
things fearsomeness? One worry here is that emotional experiences appear
to lack the phenomenal transparency that characterizes sensory perceptions.
The best way to describe my experience of red poppies is to talk about red
poppies. But it seems that this is not so with emotions. Arguably, the best way
to describe what it is like to undergo fear or anger or regret is not to refer to
the objects of these emotions and their properties. This suggests that when
undergoing an emotion we are not stricto sensu aware of the relevant evalu-
ative properties.
There is some leeway here, for in fact we quite often find ourselves describ-
ing what our emotions are about to describe what it felt to experience them.
Thus, we describe what were afraid ofthe huge hairy spider that suddenly
fell from the tree, for instanceto explain what we felt.47 Moreover, it should
be noted that the worry in question is mitigated by the fact that we commonly
46
See Melissa Barry, Realism, Rational Action, and the Humean Theory of Motivation, Ethical
Theory and Moral Practice 10 (2007):231242, 323; Maria Alvarez, Kinds of Reasons:An Essay in the
Philosophy of Action (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 2010), 25; Setiya, Reasons without Rationalism,
40. Setiya takes it as obvious that whenever we act for a reason, we not only believe but we also know
that we are acting for that reason:The second insight is that we know without observation not only
what we are doing, but why(40).
47
Thanks to Mark Nelson for suggesting thispoint.
176 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
form evaluative judgments on the basis of the emotions we feel. For instance,
when angry at someone because of some remark, we tend to judge that this
persons remark was offensive. Thus, emotions typically come with a dispo-
sition to make corresponding evaluative judgments. Finally, the claim that
the putative phenomenal transparency of emotions indicates that there is no
awareness of evaluative properties appears committed to the assumption that
the awareness of something needs to be explicitly articulated in terms of con-
cepts; it would only be when we form judgments about things that we can be
said to be aware ofthem.
Be that as it may, the very claim that an agent needs to be aware of a reason
whether that entails judgment or another kind of awarenessto be motivated
by that reason already appears too strong to be plausible. Switching to a case
that does not involve emotions, habitual actions can certainly be motivated
by reasons even though we are not aware of the reasons for which we perform
these actions when we perform them. Indeed, the whole point of the Agential
Virtue Account is to make room for actions that are not explicitly guided by
articulated reasons but nonetheless appear to exhibit full-fledged agency.
It might be replied that cases of habitual actions are quite different from
emotional actions.48 In the case of habitual actions, agents can readily recon-
struct the reasons behind what they are doing. Consider my habit of having
an espresso at ten oclock. It is easy for me to see that having an espresso at
ten oclock is not only pleasant but also useful in terms of productivity. By
contrast, we often are at loss when we try to reconstruct the reasons behind
actions motivated by emotions. This, it can be argued, is particularly striking
in Hucks case. From his point of view, it is bound to appear utterly unjustified
not to have denouncedJim.
It is important to recognise the difference between habitual and emotional
action. However, the contrast should not be exaggerated. Afirst point is that
there are cases of habitual actions in which it is less easy to reconstruct the
reasons behind what we are doing. We are all aware of some strange habits
we have, in favor of which we find nothing to say even on reflection. Indeed,
in some cases, acting out of habit can be in conflict with our better judgment.
This is a natural way to understand Davidsons famous teeth-brushing case.49
You are lying in your bed when you realize that you have forgotten to brush
your teeth. On reflection you conclude that you should just stay in bed and do
nothing about itthere is no harm in not brushing your teeth just this one
time, and getting up would spoil your calm. But off you go and brush your
48
Thanks to Karen Jones for raising this question.
49
See Donald Davidson, How is Weakness of the Will Possible? in Davidson, Essays on Actions
and Events (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1980; original publication1969).
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 177
teeth. It is to be expected that in such a case you will find it hard to reconstruct
the reasons behind your action.
The second point to make is that in fact we are often in a position to recon-
struct the reasons behind emotional action. Consider again Vellemans case
of the person who loses his temper when meeting with his friend.50 In the
case Velleman imagines, later reflection leads the protagonist to realize that
accumulated grievances had crystalized in his mind into a resolution to end
the friendship. Thus, the reasons for the burst of anger are in fact accessible
to the agent. According to Velleman, the fact that the reasons are accessible
to the agent is not sufficient to make it the case that the action is done for a
reason. In fact, the anger case is his main example of an action that is less than
full-blooded.
The Agential Virtue Account has a very different, and Ibelieve more plau-
sible, take on cases like this. The third and most important point, thus, is that
according to the Agential Virtue Account what counts is not so much the pos-
sibility of reason reconstruction as the exercise of agential virtues. The point
to emphasize is that the description of the case leaves open whether or not the
dispositions of reflective self-monitoring were in place. It is true that in the
absence of any reason to believe that the agent in question has such disposi-
tions, Velleman appears right when claiming that the action failed to involve
reason-responsiveness. However, we might easily imagine a case in which
being moved by anger expresses well-tuned dispositions, such that the agent
would not have relied on her anger if there would have been reason for her to
believe that her anger was inappropriate.
More would have to be to be said to spell out and fully defend the Agential
Virtue Account.51 Questions arise regarding the nature and functioning of the
dispositions of reflective self-monitoring. What exactly are these epistemic
and practical habitswhat Ihave called agential virtuesand how do they re-
late to epistemic and practical norms and goals? Also, one might wonder how
much room there is for an agent to cultivate and exercise such dispositions,
assuming that basic aptitudes and socialization are bound to be decisive fac-
tors. In particular, one might wonder whether the counterfactual description
in terms of what would the agent would have done had there been reasons
for her to believe something makes for a problematically circular account of
reason-responsiveness in that it explicitly refers to reasons. There are impor-
tant and difficult questions, but for now Iwill leave them aside and turn to
what the proposed account entails for autonomy theories.
50
See Velleman, What Happens When Someone Acts, 464465.
In this appeal to virtues, the account proposed is similar to Setiyas suggestion that good practical
51
reasoning can be specified only in terms of ethical virtues. See Setiya, Reasons without Rationalism.
178 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
As Inoted in the introduction, it is often taken for granted that emotions and
autonomy are at odds. Giving voice to this intuition, Laura Ekstrom writes:
We do not act autonomously in acting on passions, whims, and impulses be-
cause these overtake us; we are generally passive with respect to them, they
do not engage our understanding or capacity for reflective evaluation. We
make our lives more our own by examining such impulses and by acting in
accordance with our evaluations.52
If the picture Ihave sketched is on the right lines this negative conception
of emotions is not warranted. It can surely be acknowledged that in some cases
the undergoing of an emotion is a barrier to autonomy. Our emotions some-
times get things wrong and thus fail to track reasons. And acting on an emo-
tion might fail to consist in responding to reasons because agential virtues are
not in place. Quite generally, given their influence on action and thought, the
effect of emotions can be particularly pernicious. However, the wholesale re-
jection of emotions is not warranted. Insofar as emotions are perceptual expe-
riences of evaluative properties, they can, and sometimes do, inform us about
our practical reasons and hence play a crucial role in the assessment of our
normative principles. So it is deeply mistaken to suggest that critical reflection
is something that is independent of the emotions we feel and incompatible
with the fact that an emotion isfelt.
Furthermore, the wholesale rejection of emotions is misguided because
acting on an emotion can be acting in light of reasons we do have. Thus, to the
extent that reason-responsiveness is a central aspect of autonomy, emotions are
far from being at odds with autonomy. Autonomy accounts that place reason-
responsiveness at the core of autonomous agency have to accept emotions as
a potential source of autonomous actions. There might be some disagreement
as to what other ingredients autonomy requiressuch as psychological inte-
gration or a sense of our status as agents. But whatever the details of ones full
account of autonomous action, it has to be conceded that insofar as emotions
and reason-responsiveness are not at odds emotions and autonomy need not
be either.
Another implication of the account of emotions proposed here is that care
accounts of autonomy, or at least the version of such accounts according to
which emotions are essential to autonomy, should not be taken to be antithet-
ical to reason-responsiveness accounts.53 This is because on this version cares
52
Laura W. Ekstrom, Autonomy and Personal Integration, in Personal Autonomy, edited by J. S.
Taylor (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005),160.
53
In his later work, Frankfurt suggests that love is an essential feature of the self, but it is far from
clear that what he calls love involves emotions. See Harry Frankfurt, Necessity, Volition and Love
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,1998).
Emotions, Reasons, and Autonomy 179
54
David Shoemaker, Caring, Identification, and Agency, Ethics 114 (2003):94.
55
Shoemaker, Caring, Identification, and Agency, 103104.
56
Shoemaker, Caring, Identification, and Agency.
180 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
to reasons. Thus, if your dispositions are well tuned, your acting on the basis
of your cares consists in responding to reasons.
The lesson, then, is that insofar as emotions are central to care accounts of au-
tonomy based on care can make room for the intuition that reason-responsive-
ness is central to autonomy. Even though there is likely to be disagreement about
other putative ingredients of autonomy, the two kinds of accounts need not be
in disagreement as to the importance of reason-responsiveness in autonomy.
4.Conclusion
Acknowledgments
Earlier drafts of this chapter have been presented at the round-table on the ra-
tionality of emotions, Pacific APA, Seattle, 2012, organized by Marina Oshana;
at the conference on relational autonomy, organized by Catriona Mackenzie
and Natalie Stoljar, McGill, September 2012; at the Philosophy Institute,
Stockholm University; at the Department of Philosophy, York University; at
the Centre Interfacultaire en Sciences Affectives, University of Geneva; and
the Congress of the CPA, Victoria, 2013. For discussions and comments, Iam
grateful to Rachel Barney, sa Carlsson, John Christman, Julien Deonna,
Vincent Duhamel, Marilyn Friedman, Bruno Guindon, Nancy Hirshmann,
Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Karen Jones, Catriona Mackenzie, Colin MacLeod,
Diana Meyers, Mark Nelson, Graham Oddie, Jonas Olson, Marina Oshana,
Antoine Panaioti, Gopal Sreenivasan, Natalie Stoljar, Sarah Stroud, Jennifer
Szende, Fabrice Teroni, Joey van Weelden, and especially to the editors of the
volume, Andrea Veltman and MarkPiper.
{9}
For more than two decades, feminist philosophers have been developing im-
portant new conceptions of autonomy that take the sociality of human agency
appropriately seriously. Interestingly, this relational turn has at the same time
ushered in a new debate about the nature of autonomous agents attitudes to-
ward themselves as individual agents. Some relational theorists have argued,
for example, that a sense of individual self-worth1 or self-trust2 may be neces-
sary for autonomy. One important question this debate has raised is whether
or not the resulting conception of autonomy will be normatively neutral.3 For
purposes of this paper Iwill bracket that question and focus instead on the
relationship between autonomy and self-regarding attitudes themselves. What
has begun to emerge in the feminist literature is a conception of autonomy
in which the autonomous agent must stand in a special kind of relation to
herself.4 Ithink there is something deeply right about this idea. In this paper
Itry to flesh out one kind of self-relation that is required for autonomy and to
explain what it has to do with relationality of the more familiar, interpersonal
variety.
1
See Paul Benson, Feeling Crazy: Self-Worth and the Social Character of Responsibility, in
Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, edited by Catriona
Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2000),7293.
2
See Carolyn McLeod and Susan Sherwin, Relational Autonomy, Self-Trust, and Health Care for
Patients Who Are Oppressed, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, 259279.
3
See Paul Benson, Taking Ownership: Authority and Voice in Autonomous Agency, in
Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, edited by J. Christman and J. Anderson
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 101126; Benson, Feminist Intuitions and
the Normative Substance of Autonomy, in Personal Autonomy, edited by James Stacy Taylor
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 12442; John Christman, Relational Autonomy,
Liberal Individualism, and the Social Constitution of Selves, Philosophical Studies 117:12 (2004):143
164; Christman, Procedural Autonomy and Liberal Legitimacy, in Taylor, Personal Autonomy, 277
298; Andrea C. Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24:4 (2009):2649.
4
Of course, self-governance is itself a kind of self-relation. The idea Ipursue in this paper is that
the autonomous agent is self-governing at least in part in virtue of standing in another, conceptually
distinct sort of relationship to herself, namely, a relation of self-care.
182 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
1.Care
The recent literature on care has grown along two almost entirely separate
lines. One line focuses primarily on the place of care in morality and tends to
concern itself almost exclusively with care as an attitude toward other persons.
This strand has developed out of pioneering work in feminist ethics by Carol
Gilligan, Nel Noddings, Sarah Ruddick, and others and by now includes much
interesting work on dependency and disability as well.5 For the most part, this
body of work does not bear directly on issues of autonomy, though the strand
of Gilligans argument Idevelop later in this paper is an important (and gener-
ally overlooked) exception.
The other line of work is more immediately relevant to my project, focusing
as it does on the role of care in human agency or autonomy. This literature
tends to range more widely over care as an attitude toward objects, places, ide-
als, and so forth in addition to persons. It has been inspired at least in part by
Harry Frankfurts groundbreaking work on personhood and freedom of the
will, particularly in its later manifestations.6 In addition to Frankfurt himself,
5
See Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press, 1982); Nel
Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2003); Sara Ruddick, Maternal Thinking:Toward a Politics of Peace (Boston:Beacon
Press, 1995). On dependency and disability, see Eva Feder Kittay, Loves Labor (NewYork:Routledge,
1999). I would place Stephen Darwalls care-based analysis of welfare in this category as well. See
Darwall, Welfare and Rational Care (Princeton, NJ:Princeton University Press, 2002). Though it does
not directly address feminist issues, Darwall himself describes his work on welfare and care as inspired
partly by Noddings and other feminist theorists.
6
Harry Frankfurt, On Caring, in Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge:Cambridge University
Press, 1999), 155180.
Autonomy and Self-Care 183
7
See Agnieszka Jaworska, Caring and Internality, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74:3
(2007):529568; Jaworska, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism, in Naturalized
Bioethics: Toward Responsible Knowing and Practice, edited by H. Lindemann, M. Verkerk, and M.
U. Walker (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 80105; Jeffrey Seidman, Valuing and
Caring, Theoria 75 (2009): 272303. Though I do not examine it in this paper, David Shoemaker
develops a similar, care-based account in Shoemaker, Caring, Identification, and Agency, Ethics 114:1
(2003):88118.
8
Frankfurt, On Caring,160.
9
Frankfurt, On Caring,161.
10
Frankfurt, On Caring,131.
184 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
most distinctive move, in his later work, has been to argue that the commands
of love are at least as authoritative for us as the commands of duty or reason.
Indeed, since Frankfurt takes love to define our essential nature as persons
and to settle our final ends, it is reasonable to read his account as one on which
autonomy is ultimately grounded in love rather than in reason. On his view,
what we love has a distinctive claim to mark out our standpoint as persons or
at least what is most central to that standpoint. Since love is a species of caring,
the result is a view that links autonomy very clearly to care, via the internality
of cares to the self.11
In Caring and Internality, Jaworska accepts that an attitude is truly ones
own if it is internal to the will and also that our cares are invariably internal.
But she departs from Frankfurt by insisting that care is first and foremost an
emotional attitude and not just a commitment of the will. Jaworska argues
that Frankfurts volitional treatment of care and internality is too reflective:in
requiring agents to have a structure of attitudes about attitudes, Frankfurts
view (and other similarly hierarchical views) puts care beyond the reach of
agents who are not yet, or are no longer, cognitively sophisticated enough to
have such higher-order attitudes but who seem obviously to care about things
and to have, in that sense, a standpoint of their own. Young children and other
marginal agents (e.g., those in early stages of dementia) seem to be capable of
care, and their cares (like anyone elses) seem invariably to be internal tothem.
Jaworska draws on Michael Bratman for a revised Frankfurtian conception
of internality and on Bennett Helm for a more congenial account of care. From
Bratman she adopts the idea that an attitude is internal if it has as part of its
function to support the psychological continuities and connections that con-
stitute the agents identity and cohesion over time.12 Where she differs from
Bratman is in the range of attitudes that she thinks may perform this func-
tion. While Bratman focuses on plans, policies, and other distinctively reflec-
tive attitudes, Jaworska argues that any attitude, reflective or not, that plays the
relevant role should count as internal. At least some emotions, she argues, fit
thebill.
To understand her point, we must distinguish between primary and sec-
ondary emotions. Primary emotions, Jaworska explains, involve more or less
fixed patterns of emotional responses to specific, immediately sensed features
of ones environment, such as stereotypical reactions of fear, disgust, rage,
or surprise.13 These do not, in her view, play any special role in unifying our
11
What we love is a subset of what we cannot help caring about, in the aforementioned sense of
caring. When we love something, Frankfurt claims, we have a disinterested desire for its flourishing.
This desire, since we cannot help but have it, and cannot help but want to have it, sets boundaries on
our will that we willingly embrace. It determines what we can and cannot bring ourselves to choose and
do and in this way defines the contours of our will and our essential natures as persons.
12
Jaworska, Caring and Internality,552.
13
Jaworska, Caring and Internality,555.
Autonomy and Self-Care 185
14
Jaworska, Caring and Internality,555.
15
Jaworska, Caring and Internality,556.
16
Jaworska, Caring and Internality, 560. Object is to be understood broadly, as including not only
material objects and particular individuals but also states of affairs, sequences of events, places, ideals,
relationships, andmore.
186 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
explanatory gap, he argues, we must recognize that caring includes not just
emotional dispositions but also cognitiveones.
The various components of caring are, of course, linked in that they are
focused on a single object. But a caring agent might have a range of other
attitudes toward that same object without those attitudes being part of his or
her caring. Nor, Seidman argues, do the tonal and transitional commitments
identified by Helm suffice to pick out all and only the right attitudes, either.
Seidman points out that a sons irritation at his fathers humming may be ro-
bustly interconnected, both tonally and transitionally, with other attitudes to-
ward the father yet have nothing to do with the fact that he cares forhim.
According to Seidman, what does help unify the attitudinal patterns that
constitute care is the agents perception of the focal object as important. More
precisely, the fact that an agent perceives an object as important stands in an
explanatory relation to the attitudes that are constituents of her concern for
that object. To see an object as important (to oneself), Seidman argues, is to
see it as a source of practical reasons (for oneself).17 Seeing some object X as a
source of practical reasons does not entail actually believing it to be a source
of practical reasons. Sometimes our perceptions and judgments come apart.
But Seidman argues that seeing something in a certain way does, in normal
circumstances, where no countervailing beliefs defeat this disposition dispose
one to believe it is that way.18 Seeing some object X as importantseeing X as
a source of practical reasonsdisposes the agent to believe that X is a source
of practical reasons.
The fact that an agent sees X as a source of practical reasons, and is thus
disposed to believe that she has the reasons in question, explains certain of her
emotions, emotional dispositions, and desires as well as the rational patterns
among those emotions, and those emotions (the ones linked together by their
common explanation in perceptions of importance) are the ones that consti-
tute concern for the object in question. Other emotions (such as irritation at
ones fathers humming) are not explained by ones perception of the father as
important and thus are not part of caring for him. Seidmans point, in short, is
that we cannot identify the emotions, emotional dispositions, and desires that
constitute caring without appeal to perceptions of importance and the cog-
nitive disposition (to believe one has reasons) that these perceptions involve.
Thus amended, Seidman agrees with Jaworska that our cares are invariably
internal to us and have a legitimate claim to constitute the agents standpoint.
17
Jaworska seems to agree with at least this part of Seidmans claim, since she argues in Caring,
Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism that in acting on ones cares one acts on the percep-
tion of a reason. But as far as Iunderstand her position, she would resist the further idea that perceiving
something as a reason also disposes one to believe it is a reason. This disposition would be beyond the
cognitive capacities of some of the marginal but still (on her view) caring agents that she considers
minimally autonomous.
18
Seidman, Valuing and Caring,286.
Autonomy and Self-Care 187
Indeed, Seidman argues that the emotional and cognitive dispositions in-
volved in caring establish a more robust form of diachronic unity than the
policies and plans on which Bratman focuses. In addition to unifying agency
across time, Seidman argues that our concerns generate a diachronically uni-
fied subjectivity, or, as he also puts it, a temporally extended subject...with
a cognitive and emotional take on the world.19 This is important, Seidman
thinks, because when we ask what attitudes speak for the agent we really have
more in mind than just a locus of deliberation and action.20 Our concerns
may conflict with one another and with our self-governing policiesbut ac-
tion motivated by our concerns will nonetheless always be expressive of who
we are as subjects.21
2. Mental Freedom
There is much that seems promising about this view, as a view of what Ive
been calling authenticity. It gives a neat explanation of what unifies raw psy-
chic materials into a well-defined (even if complex or conflicted) subject,
with a take of its own, that endures across time. If autonomous choice or
action is fundamentally choice or action that expresses who the agent is, this
care-based account seems like a strong contender for telling us how to identify
a who in the first place. But there is a significant worry about this whole ap-
proach to the concept of self-governance:such views do not explain how being
just exactly who we are can sometimes constitute a failure of autonomy.
Within the framework of a purely authenticity-based account of autonomy,
this objection will not sound like a sensible one, for there is no conceptual
space between authenticity and autonomy on such views. But Ithink we must
make space if we are to do justice to pretheoretical intuitions about an im-
portant set of cases.22 The cases Ihave in mind are ones in which agents iden-
tify so thoroughly with their concerns that they are unable to entertain the
possibility that they might be mistaken or that their concerns might require
defense. Highly dogmatic agents are sometimes like this, and Ive argued that
deeply deferential agents share a version of the same agential pathology.23 Such
agents are impervious to ordinary forms of critical dialogue that most of us
19
Seidman, Valuing and Caring, 296. Concern is Seidmans term for the mental state we ascribe
to an agent when we say that she cares about something. See Seidman, Valuing and Caring,282.
20
Seidman, Valuing and Caring,296.
21
Seidman, Valuing and Caring,296.
22
Andrea C. Westlund, Reply to Benson, Christman, Rocha, and Stoljar, Symposia on Race,
Gender, and Philosophy 7:1 (2011):16, http://web.mit.edu/sgrp.
23
Andrea C. Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self: Is Deference Compatible
with Autonomy? Philosophical Review 112:4 (2003): 483523; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy,2649.
188 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
take for granted. We might aptly describe them as being in the grip of their
concerns, or perhaps as under the influence of their concerns. Acting under
the influence of a concern for which one does not hold oneself answerable is
intuitively incompatible with self-governance, even if it is consistent with the
demands of authenticity. In other words, autonomy and authenticity (at least
as the latter is usually conceived) may sometimes come apart.24
Jaworska seems to share this intuition, since she begins, in subsequent
work, to move away from a purely authenticity-based view.25 The autonomous
agent, she argues, guides her action in light of the reasons she sees (in virtue
of caring about certain things) to pursue or promote relevant ends. But some-
thing more is required:Our theory, she writes, must stave off the possibility
that seeing a reason would simply amount to being in the grip of the reason.26
Jaworska argues that autonomy requires what she calls mental freedom, and
that mental freedom is incompatible with being rigidly stuck in some in-
flexible emotional view or assessment of facts or reasons.27
I would agree with Jaworska that being mentally unfree is intui-
tively incompatible with autonomy and that being rigidly stuck in ones
identity-constituting concerns is incompatible with mental freedom. To be
stuck in a certain view of ones reasons (either for action or for emotion)
implies not just a benign stability or absence of change but also a problematic
inability to change. An agent unable effectively to revise or change her con-
cerns under any conditions seems intuitively unable to govern herself, even if
her choices and actions are determined by those very concerns. Perhaps she
has a self, but she does not seem to be doing much in the way of governing.
Of course, an inability to change ones view of ones reasons could be
explained in a variety of ways. One might lack certain critical reasoning or
other straightforwardly cognitive skills, and this would, plausibly, undermine
autonomy. Such skills are surely amongst what many philosophers now refer to
as competence conditions for autonomy. But straightforwardly cognitive skills
do not seem to be all that Jaworska has in mind. She claims, for example, that
the agent must be capable of imaginatively entertaining alternatives28 and
that she must be open to the possibility that further reflection would change
her view of what reasons she has. By reflection, Jaworska clarifies, she does not
24
Westlund, Reply to Benson, Christman, Rocha, and Stoljar. Later in the paper Iconsider a dif-
ferent conception of authenticity, proposed by Marina Oshana, which would be more closely aligned
with autonomy as Iunderstandit.
25
Jaworska, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism.
26
Jaworska, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism,95.
27
Jaworska, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism,97.
28
Jaworska, Caring, Minimal Autonomy, and the Limits of Liberalism. The ability to imagine
oneself or ones views as other than they are is a competence condition on autonomy that has been con-
vincingly defended by Catriona Mackenzie, Imagining Oneself Otherwise, in Mackenzie and Stoljar,
Relational Autonomy; Diana Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University
Press, 1989), 259279.
Autonomy and Self-Care 189
29
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self ; Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy.
30
Idiscuss some defeating conditions in Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy.
190 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
with being rigidly stuck, but it seems equally incompatible with a complete
lack of stability in ones concerns.
Fortunately, readiness to engage in potentially transformative reflection
does not imply readiness to capitulate at the least provocation. Our attempts
to answer for our concerns often, at least at first, take the form of self-defense
or self-advocacy. When faced with a challenge, we tend to want to commu-
nicate the value of what we take to be important, and the appropriateness of
giving it the place we do in our deliberative life. Though it is relatively easy to
veer into excessive defensiveness, there is a principled reason for self-advocacy
as a default strategy:we cannot be willing to give up our cares at the drop of
a hat, for this is incompatible with truly caring about the things we think we
care about. This imperative reflects an important kernel of truth in Frankfurts
thesis that care is a commitment of the will: in its desiderative dimension,
care requires more than simply having a desire (even a very strong one) and
more also than wholeheartedly endorsing that desire. It also means wanting to
continue to have the desire, even when one decides that it would be better, all
things considered, not to act on it. The impulse to self-advocacy reflects this
stabilizing dimension ofcare.
At the same time, though, for the agent genuinely to be mentally free, the
impulse to advocate for oneself must be moderated by an appropriate atti-
tude of humility. One must recognize that it is sometimes appropriate for
self-advocacy to give way to self-scrutiny and be prepared to let self-scrutiny
take its potentially transformative course when warranted. If one is not pre-
pared to do this, one is (once again) rigidly stuck in a way that cannot amount
to self-governance. It might help to think of the autonomous agent as possessed
of certain characteristic virtues, in a broadly Aristotelian sense:she must avoid
both an excess and a defect of answerability and openness and must know how
to be open and answerable to the right degree and in the right circumstances.
3.Self-care
and dispositions) focused on the first-order cares that Jaworska and Seidman
take to make up the agents standpoint orself.
Gilligan is best known for her path-breaking and controversial views about
gender and moral development. But the aspect of her work that is most rel-
evant to my argument has been much less widely discussed:it is the picture
she paints of moral maturity and, in particular, of the morally mature agents
relationship to her own choices. Many of the troubled girls and women she
interviews, particularly in her chapter on abortion decisions, seem at first to
speak from a position of compromised autonomy. They feel helplessly con-
strained by their understanding of what others want from them and often de-
scribe themselves as having no choice about what to do when faced with a
moral dilemma.31 Gilligan points out that, while the feeling of powerlessness
is very real for these women, it stems in large part from a confused abdication
of responsibility for their own responses to their situations. Instead of seeing
themselves as agents with a decision to make, they feel pushed and pulled by
the demands of others and can assert themselves in only relatively inchoate
ways. They do not see themselves as choosing whattodo.
But a number of Gilligans interviewees have transitioned out of this stage
of moral development, and what they say about the experience of coming to
terms with their agency is very interesting. Several of her subjects, for example,
dwell on the importance of taking care (or, as we sometimes say, taking pains)
with their decisions. One subject, for example, claims that when deciding what
to do one must take a critical view and be as conscious or awake as possible,
to consider all thats involved.32 Another stresses the importance of being
conscious of ones power or influence as a chooser and taking responsibility
for the consequences of ones choices, both for oneself and for others.33 Athird
emphasizes coming to terms with the fact that not all conflicts have a tidy or
obviously right resolution and that one must exercise judgment to the best of
ones ability and accept responsibility for the consequences of doing so.34 In
these and other similar passages, a common theme begins to emerge:moral
maturity requires recognition of ones power to influence outcomes by exercis-
ing choice, acceptance of what we might (in Rawlsian terms) call the burdens
of judgment, and willingness to take responsibility for exercising judgment in
31
For these women, any course of action other than the self-sacrificing one feels unthinkable and
the chosen course of action feels not so much chosen as inevitable. Notice, however, that the passivity
they experience does not seem to be an instance of Frankfurtian alienation from their motives. Though
Gilligans subjects are distressed by their situations, many of them do seem to identify with their self-
lessness, understood in terms of an overriding imperative to maintain relationships and serve others
needs. The problem, as Igo on to emphasize, is that they do not see themselves as choosing what to do,
even when they act in accordance with this imperative.
32
Gilligan, In a Different Voice,99.
33
Gilligan, In a Different Voice,139.
34
Gilligan, In a Different Voice,118.
192 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
35
Gilligan, In a Different Voice,67.
36
Michel Foucault, Ethics:Subjectivity and Truth (NewYork:New Press,1994).
37
Foucault, Ethics,231.
38
Foucault, Ethics,207.
Autonomy and Self-Care 193
be one of these alternative senses. She argues that to achieve moral adulthood
a woman must shift from a perspective of selfless goodness to one that empha-
sizes truthby which she seems to mean honesty about ones own needs and
desires, along with recognition of oneself as a proper object of caring attitudes.
The morally mature agent cares for herself (among other things) in the sense
that she treats her own interests as worthy of consideration, and she will seek
to minimize hurt to all involved, not just to others at the expense of herself.
But notice that the agent who cares for herself in this sensetreating her
own interests as worthy of considerationwill still face the challenge of inte-
grating her various concerns with one another and exercising judgment with
respect to their apparent claims. Even if one thinks ones own interests and
needs matter and must be taken into account, one can easily imagine being
paralyzed in cases of conflict or being rigidly stuck in some particular con-
ception of how competing claims should be handled. (Consider a well-known
example from Gilligans own research. When asked how to resolve a conflict
between self and other, eleven-year-old Jake doesnt miss a beat:You go about
one-fourth to the others and three-fourths to yourself.)39 Gilligans most
thoughtful interviewees, and Foucaults self-writers, recognize and thematize
the need to exercise judgment and to take responsibility for doing so. Their
attitudes, Isuggest, point to a distinctive kind of self-care that is focused on the
self in its deliberative or practicalmode.
What is it, then, to care for oneself in the practical sense? If we accept some-
thing like the JaworskaSeidman conception of care, then care of the self, like
care of anything else, will be constituted by a complex of emotions, desires,
and cognitive and emotional dispositions that are bound together by a percep-
tion of their focal object as a source of practical reasons. In this case, instead
of being focused on other persons, objects, or ideals, the attitudes involved
in self-care will be focused on elements of the caring agents own delibera-
tive perspective or standpoint and will be bound together by a perception of
that standpoint itself as a source of reasons (for the agent). Suppose we also
accept that ones standpoint is constituted by ones first-order cares (though
not, to be clear, the further idea that having ones choices determined by such
a standpoint suffices for autonomy). Self-care, then, would turn out to be a
higher-order attitude of care focused on the first-order attitudes of care that
make up ones subjective practical perspective. Caring about oneself would
mean, in a manner of speaking, caring about onescares.
One might object that while everyone cares about what she cares about (this
is a mere tautology), not everyone cares about herself. So the definition of
self-care Ive just offered must be wrong. But my claim is not that the self-caring
person, call her S, cares about herself simply in virtue of caring about X, Y, and
39
Gilligan, In a Different Voice,35.
194 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Z, things that (by hypothesis) she happens to care about anyhow. It is instead
that S cares about herself (in the sense at issue) if and only if she cares about
her caring attitudes: she has certain higher-order attitudes toward, and dis-
positions concerning, the clusters of emotions, desires, and dispositions that
constitute her first-order concerns for X, Y,andZ.
Even this claim could be interpreted in more than one way. The relevant
question might, for example, just seem to be whether ones emotions are apt
and well-proportioned, given that one sees X as important, or whether one
actually has the dispositions and desires that one who cares about X should
have. These questions take for granted the focus of the care and address the
quality of ones attitudes toward that object, targeting the possible discrepancy
between what one thinks one cares about and what one really does care about.
It opens up a space for assessing someones care as defective on its own terms,
and it makes possible the judgment that, if someones attitudes are defective
enough, they might not qualify as care atall.
This might be part of whats involved in care of the self, in the loosely
Foucaultian sense Ive been putting forth. But this interpretation of what it
is to care about caring doesnt yet address Jaworskas concern about mental
freedom. For even if someone cares about X badly rather than welleven if
she cares so badly that we are tempted to conclude that she doesnt truly care
about X at allit is possible for that person to be rigidly stuck in her view of
X as a (purported) source of reasons. But one cannot be rigidly stuck in such a
view of X if one is also concerned about that very way of viewing it, and this is
surely part of what it is to care about ones cares. Caring about ones first-order
concerns includes caring not just about the fit between ones emotions and
dispositions and what one sees as important but also about the question of
what one sees as important itself. More simply put, the agent who cares about
herself, in the sense Iwant to isolate, cares about her reasons.
So what is it to care about ones reasons? Itake it that a practical reason is
a consideration that favors some particular course of action or emotional re-
sponse on the part of the agent to whom it applies and that to see something
as a reason is likewise to see it as favoring some action or emotion. Favoring,
of course, is not an ideally perspicuous notion, but Ithink that a reason can be
(slightly) more precisely characterized as a consideration that may enter into a
viable defense or justification of a course of action or response. One who cares
about her reasons, then, is subject to a constellation of emotions, desires, and
dispositions focused on considerations she sees in this light, attitudes that are
jointly explained (following Seidman) by her perception of those consider-
ations as important. One who cares about her care for X, and thus about her
X-based reasons, sees her care for X as important and as the source of a dis-
tinctive set of reasons.
When an agent cares about her care for X, she will want to protect that
care from being too easily eroded. She will not, however, want to maintain
Autonomy and Self-Care 195
her perception of Xs importance (and her related sense of reasons) at any cost.
As Seidman points out, the kind of reasons one takes oneself to have, in virtue of
an objects perceived importance, will depend on the kind of thing that object is.
Apractical reason, Ive claimed, is a consideration that can enter into a viable de-
fense or justification of a particular action or emotional response. Ipropose that
one who cares about her reasons must be attuned to the suitability of her apparent
reasons for playing this justificatory role. More intuitively speaking, part of what
it is to care about our concerns is to be concerned for their aptness. Think of it this
way:only someone who doesnt care what she cares about could be untroubled
by a charge that a given care has been misplaced. Caring about ones concerns
counterbalances, to some degree, the cognitive disposition to take appearances of
reasons at face value. Perhaps more accurately, it defines some of the conditions
under which that disposition may be defeated.
One who does care what she cares about will be heartened by evidence that
supports her perception of X as important and troubled by signs that this per-
ception may instead be misleading. In the face of challenges to her X-based rea-
sons, she will be disposed either to advocate on their behalf or to revise or reject
them, depending on the perceived merit of the challenge. One who cares about
her reasons will desire that she see as reasons only things that are well suited to
playing their intended justificatory role, will have positive and negative emotions
in response to evidence that this is or is not the case, andperhaps most impor-
tantly, for our purposeswill be disposed to be rationally responsive to critical
perspectives on her (purported) reasons. In this way, she takes responsibility for
her reasons. Let us call this self-relation one of practical self-care.
40
Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy.
196 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
41
See Darwall, Second Person Standpoint. I have more to say about the relationship between
self-answerability and second-personal competence in Andrea C. Westlund, Autonomy, Authority,
and Answerability, Jurisprudence 2:1 (2011):161179.
42
Marina Oshana, Autonomy and the Question of Authenticity, Social Theory and Practice 33:3
(2007):411429. Oshana calls this an epistemic conception of authenticity. See Oshana, Autonomy
and the Question of Authenticity,412.
Autonomy and Self-Care 197
Foucault, Ethics,287.
43
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Andrea Veltman and Mark Piper for their very helpful
comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Iam also grateful for valuable feed-
back from participants in the Relational Autonomy Workshop at McGill
University in the fall of 2012, as well as participants in the 2013 Summer Retreat
on Love and Human Agency at Lake Tahoe. Ialso benefitted a great deal from
discussion with audiences at my Brady Lectures at Northwestern University in
the spring of 2013, and Ithank the Brady Program in Ethics and Civic Life at
Northwestern University for its support during the time in which Idid much
of my work on thispaper.
{ PartIV }
Feminists have been rightly concerned with questions surrounding the agency
status of people who appear to adapt to oppressive circumstances by alter-
ing their character in ways that seem to internalize that oppression. Much
fruitful discussion has taken place about those people, women in particular,
who seem to accept (or even claim to value) life situations that appear to the
critical observer to be stultifying and dominating and in that way incompat-
ible with autonomous agency.1 This vexing problem focuses our attention on
the seeming conflict in feminist sensibilities between, on the one hand, re-
specting the choices of actual women as well as being open to difference, and
on the other hand, decrying the oppressive social conditions that bear down
on women in thisway.
Interestingly, however, far less attention has been given to the ways that
people routinely reshape themselves in response to unforeseen and uncontrol-
lable circumstance in ways that sometimes undercut autonomy but at other
times do not. We have accidents, take risks that turn out badly in ways we are
unprepared for, undertake radically indeterminate projects such as having a
child or entering a relationship, and often fall victim to the decisions of others,
the operation of impersonal institutions, and simple natural events that deter-
mine the available course of our lives. Changes in life options can give rise to
changes in character, for example, learning to be accommodating to a partners
1
See, e.g., Paul Benson, Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization Social Theory and Practice 17
(1991):38408; Diana T. Meyers, Feminism and Womens Autonomy, in Gender in the Mirror:Cultural
Integrity and Womens Agency (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), chap. 1; Marina Oshana,
Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate, 2006); Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender,
Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2003); Anita Superson, Deformed Desires and Informed
Desire Tests, Hypatia 20:4 (2005):109126; Uma Narayama, Minds of Their Own:Choices, Autonomy,
Cultural Practices, and Other Women, in A Mind of Ones Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and
Objectivity, edited by Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt (Boulder, CO:Westview Press, 2001);
Andrea Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self:Is Deference Compatible with Autonomy?
Philosophical Review 112:4 (October 2003):483523.
202 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
2
Aclassic discussion of this issue is in Jon Elster, Sour Grapes (Cambridge:Cambridge University
Press,1983).
3
In both these cases Idiscuss only the subject herself, but of course the broader social and inter-
personal network within which these events and processes take place is crucial to our understanding
of the case. Imention such factors in the upcoming discussion. Also, all of the cases described in this
paper are distillations of actual stories.
Coping or Oppression 203
ideals about how their lives would go; in both cases, they rearranged their (pre-
sumably self-directed) projects and plans, indeed their senses of themselves,
in response to changes in life options that they did not choose and would not
have chosen. While of course there are numerous important differences be-
tween the cases, it is striking that we may have no hesitation in responding to
the first with admiration and the second with pity and perhaps disdain. More
to the point, we would not think that anything about the story of Abby (as told
here) indicates a lack of autonomy after her adjustment, but we may well see
Kaew as a straightforward case of the loss of autonomy or at least as problem-
atic. What account of autonomy can be given that picks out the key differences
between thesecases?
I will say more about these and related cases as we proceed. My plan here is
to examine a variety of approaches to diagnosing when alterations in character
and values mark a loss of autonomy and when such alterations count merely
as a healthy adaptation to constrained circumstances. After critically consid-
ering these approaches Iwill try to defend a broadly procedural approach to
self-government that, Iwill suggest, can account for processes of adaptation
of the sort being considered. However, my point is not to fully defend such an
account of autonomy but merely to refine this approach to include a condi-
tion that Iwill call reflexive self-affirmation, a notion akin to what some other
theorists have insisted on under the guise of self-worth and self-trust, though
not exactly in the form they have doneso.
One more important preliminary:the cases Idescribe are roughly drawn
to be sure, but more importantly judgments about these cases will perforce
be made from the equally underdescribed vantage point of detached philo-
sophical analysis. This way of proceeding, it must be emphasized, leaves out
two important factors in actual determinations of peoples self-government (or
lack thereof):one is their own voices in reporting their condition (and their
judgments about it); and another is a specification of the contexts in which
attributions of autonomy are in fact made, including the effect that those attri-
butions might have on the autonomy of the agent in question. Indeed, in this
latter category we should include reference to the dynamic interaction be-
tween those ascribing autonomy (as a classification) and the persons whose
autonomy is at issue. The contexts where such judgments are made, expressed,
and perhaps filed in official documents may have a direct effect on the state
of the person herself relative to her self-government. In my conclusion Iwill
return to these neglected aspects of such cases and discuss how attributions of
autonomy involve dynamic exchanges between observers and observed (or,
e.g., aid workers and clients, officials, and victim/survivors).4
4
It is also manifestly true that the picture of a person like Abby (and otherssee following) woe-
fully underdescribes the conditions of disability. See, e.g., Carolyn Ells, Lessons about Autonomy from
the Experience of Disability, Social Theory and Practice 27:4 (October 2001):599615.
204 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
The contrasts between Abby and Kaew are numerous, but my point was not
to draw any quick conclusions from our reactions to them. However, if we lay
out a certain array of types of cases of this sort, Ithink we will see a certain
asymmetry in our reaction that will prove instructive in refining our theoret-
ical accounts of self-government.
Consider two variations on the previouscases:
Bernice was also an active, athletic person who relished physical activity and had
aspirations similar to Abbys. She also had an accident that left her permanently
disabled. But unlike Abby, she never adjusted to her life in a wheelchair; she turned
to alcohol and never gave up the intense pain medication she was prescribed. She
was also bitter and resentful at losing out on the life she had always imagined.
At age forty she has now isolated herself from friends and support networks that
would have attempted to steer her into a lifestyle commensurate with her capaci-
ties. She is, in a word, consumed by resentment.
Parallel to this is the case of Irina, who like Kaew was forced into prostitution
and debt bondage. Like Kaew she was forced to remain in this life for an extended
period. Irina, however, never stopped resisting her condition. She always held a
fierce, though necessarily concealed, hatred of her captives and her life. She looked
for any means of escape, making complex and elaborate plans to hide money away,
venture out from the bar, and hopefully befriend a sympathetic and resourceful
friend who could help her escape. Alas, however, during the time we are consid-
ering here, she never foundone.
All of these cases are, again, terribly underdescribed.5 And because of their
brevity these descriptions cannot support very confident intuitive judgments
about how to classify these individuals in terms of their status as self-governing
agents. But my aim is to point out a general asymmetry that can be noticed,
I think, in our reactions to them that will motivate our theoretical discus-
sion:in the case of the two accident victims, it appears that acceptance, adjust-
ment, and adaptation in the case of Abby points toward seeing her as a case of
recovery of self-government, while Bernices resistance and refusal to adjust
points away from that judgment.6 But in the cases of Irina and Kaew the di-
rection of classification seems to be reversed. At first glance, at least, it seems
that that Irina retains a modicum of self-government just because she resists
5
One assumption about all four cases that should be mentioned is that all these individuals are
relatively autonomous when the events in the stories begin to unfold.
6
Again, Iam not saying with any confidence that we would agree that Bernice lacks autonomy
much more needs to be known about her to saybut clearly her resentment and resistance to her con-
dition make her less self-governing thanAbby.
Coping or Oppression 205
and resents her constraining condition, while Kaew might be seen as losing
her autonomy just because she has adapted to her condition and altered her
identity in responsetoit.
The array of cases of this sort is variegated in innumerable ways. However,
Iwant to point to two dimensions of contrast that suggest dividing them up
into four categories. First, there is adaptation or not. That is, Abby and Kaew
adapted to their circumstance in the sense that at least some aspects of their
identity and value scheme changed as a result of their constraining circum-
stances.7 On the other hand, Bernice and Irina did not adapt to their condi-
tion; they remained resentful and resistant, or so Iam describingthem.
Second, the sources of constraint are radically different in the two sets of
cases. In one, Iam stipulating that the events that gave rise to the constraint are
normatively neutral:the accidents that caused Abby and Bernices disabilities
were not anyones fault, nor can they be described as unjust in any straight-
forward sense. In contrast, the conditions of Kaew and Irina are manifestly
unjust, and oppressive as Iuse theterm.
What is interesting, and what Itake now as the pivot point for the remainder
of this discussion, is that our reaction to whether the persons self-government
is retained vis--vis her adaptation (or not) shifts depending on whether the
source of the constraining condition is unjust (or not). Or to put things the
other way around, our judgment about whether she is self-governing vis--
vis oppressive circumstances shifts depending on whether she adapts or not.
What Iwill argue, however, is that it is not the oppressive nature of the cir-
cumstances itself that determines this asymmetrical reaction; rather, it is the
particular ways that radically constrained life options operate on the capacity
for self-government and self-affirming practical identity of the agent herself.
Before discussing various approaches to these issues, it might be helpful
to set the stage with a brief discussion of the model of agency and practical
reason Iam relying on here and, by extension, what we mean by adaptation.
Autonomy involves basic skills and competences related to choice, delibera-
tion, action, and interaction. Several accounts of such skills have been given,
and clearly a broad range of competences is necessary for deliberate choice and
action to take place.8 Indeed, some theorists claim that autonomy requires only
competency skills, ones involving introspection, communication, memory,
imagination, analytical reasoning, self-nurturing, and resistance to pressures
7
Ilabel Abbys circumstance constraining for illustrative purposes. When adaptation is complete,
and especially when the physical and social environment is sufficiently accommodating, the word con-
straining may not be an apt descriptor for her life situation.
8
See, e.g., Diana Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press,
1989); Paul Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy, in Personal
Autonomy:New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Stacey Taylor (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005), 124142.
206 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
9
See, e.g., Meyers, Gender in the Mirror (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2002),2021.
10
For an argument to this effect, see John Christman, The Politics of Persons:Individual Autonomy
and Socio-historical Selves (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2009), chap.7.
11
Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). Marilyn
Friedman also sees autonomy as relative to our basic values. See Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics,
chap.1.
Coping or Oppression 207
now completely overtaken by her writing routine, her public readings, literary
discussions, and various other of her new lifes passions.12
But Ifocus here, somewhat myopically perhaps, on the changes in these per-
sons practical identity as a mode of mental functioning, orienting perception
and deliberation and grounding evaluative reflection, in the hopes that a fuller
picture that includes bodily components would be consistent with this level of
description. When the circumstances radically changed for people like Abby
and Kaew, a process began that resulted in a reordering of their values and
priorities, culminating in a new way of looking at and experiencing theworld.
12
It must be noted here, as many other theorists have emphasized, that the scenario Iam sketch-
ing also involves radical changes in forms of embodiment and that, insofar as intelligence, memory,
and identity are in large part constituted by somatic elements, Abbys bodily change has changed her-
self in quite literal ways (though Iam not claiming in metaphysical ways necessarilyshe is still the
same person in that sense). As many feminists have claimed, our bodies and their capabilities and
habits form who we are and help form our values and modes of reflection and action. See, e.g., Diana
Meyers, Decentralizing Autonomy: Five Faces of Selfhood, in Meyers, Being Yourself: Essays on
Identity, Action, and Social Life (Lanham, MD:Rowman and Littlefield, 2004); Catriona Mackenzie,
On Bodily Autonomy, in Handbook of Phenomenology and Medicine, edited by S. K. Tombs (The
Netherlands:Kluwer, 2001), 417439.
13
These classifications echo, though do not precisely mirror, distinctions in the literature between
externalist and internalist accounts. For discussion, see, e.g., Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy and
Society, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29:1 (Spring 1998):81102.
208 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
14
Oshana, Personal Autonomy and Society,86.
15
Christman, Politics of Persons, chap.8.
16
These different accounts Ihave in mind are from Catriona Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy,
Normative Authority and Perfectionism, Journal of Social Philosophy 39:4 (Winter): 512533; Paul
Benson, Taking Ownership: Authority and Voice in Autonomous Agency, in Autonomy and the
Challenges to Liberalism:New Essays, edited by J. Christman and J. Anderson (Cambridge:Cambridge
University Press, 2005), 101126; Andrea Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self:Is Deference
Compatible with Autonomy? Philosophical Review 112:4 (October 2003):483523; Joel Anderson and
Axel Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition, and Justice, in Autonomy and the Challenges
Coping or Oppression 209
views in insisting that autonomy requires more than merely the individual en-
joyment of a sense of normative authority, more also than granting oneself that
authority; it also requires external recognition by others of that authority, in
addition to being competent and reflective. Mackenzie claims that an agents
sense of herself as having a rightful claim to normative authority...[is] based
on intersubjective recognition by others. In this way, an agents status as hav-
ing normative authority over her values and decisions (what others have called
self-trust) has both first-personal and relational aspects.17 For views like
this one, the question of whether adaptation involves a failure of autonomy in
a structural sense is more nebulous.
Let us consider, then, how adding such an interpersonal recognition require-
ment may help us in our differential responses to the cases we have been consid-
ering. Specifically, let us focus on cases of what we can call resistant slaves. What
Imean are people like Irina who never cave in to the oppressiveness of their
conditions either by losing their oppression-independent self-understanding
or by losing their will to resist, even though no (nonsuicidal) opportunities to
express that resistance afford themselves. There are any number of variations on
such cases and variations along several dimensions. For instance, slave narra-
tives from the American South describe people who never lose their desire to be
free, but within the seemingly permanent circumstances of servitude they make
elaborate plans and develop projects they can truly call their own, for example,
their efforts to avoid being sold away from their children and spouses.18 As just
one example, consider a description by one Charity Bowery, a slave in North
Carolina, of her plans to save money to buy her children from herowner:
From the time my first baby was born, Ialways set my heart upon buying
freedom for some of my children. Ithought it was more consequence to them
than to me; for Iwas old and used to being a slave. But mistress McKinley
wouldnt let me have my children. One after anotherone after anothershe
sold em away from me. Oh, how many times that woman broke my heart!19
Such stories include descriptions of elaborate and complex struggles to
achieve such important goals, and they abound in accounts of slave life, a life
that surely fails to meet the structural desiderata of views like Oshanas as well
as the interpersonal requirements of some relational accounts.
to Liberalism: New Essays, edited by John Christman and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press), 12749.
17
Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy,514.
18
Most slaves had no ultimate power over these processes. But many had some, and even if they
had no ultimate sway over whether their wishes were carried out the fact that they maintained them
throughout their captivity is what is relevant here. See, e.g., John Blassingame, ed., Slave Testimony:Two
Centuries of Letters, Speeches, Interviews, and Autobiographies (Baton Rouge:Louisiana State University
Press,1977).
19
Blassingame, Slave Testimony,262.
210 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
In all such cases, two important factors remain in play. First, these agents
maintain a practical identity that is continuous with their pre- or nonoppres-
sion selves. Their value priorities and senses of themselves are not crushed by
their captivity, even if they are prevented from acting on them. Second, such
persons are without most if not all of the social conditions that many rela-
tional theorists require for autonomy. Iam not claiming that such people are in
any way fully autonomous, and externalist relational theories, such as Oshanas
and relational views like Mackenzies, may explain why not. But I do think
there is another sense of minimal autonomy that they do maintain, one that
importantly distinguishes them from those who are crushed by circumstance
into either internalizing the oppressive values structuring their domination or
losing completely any effective power to act on their own at all. My point so
far is merely that models of autonomy that stress structural injustice and those
that feature interpersonal recognition have not quite located that difference.
This last point may be too hasty, however, for we must ask further whether
and in what sense resistant slaves might experience the recognitional acknowl-
edgment that theorists such as Mackenzie and others say is necessary for au-
tonomy. This is a difficult question for many reasons. One reason is that it
may be difficult to discern what modes of recognition and respect are being
shown such people or what level of such respect they are recognizing, even in
cases where we may know a great deal about their situation and psychology.
Moreover, their situation picks up on an ambiguity in some recognitional ac-
counts, namely, whether acknowledgment of the normative authority of these
agents (for example) must be public or if it can be simply a kind of internal voice
that the persons in question can listen to and gain strength from. And if it must
be outwardly displayed, if signs and behaviors must show such recognition, who
must show it? The powerful people that have the most influence over the person
and her social environment? Or can it be similarly oppressed compatriots? If
the latter, or if (as some writers claim) the recognition can be a purely imagina-
tive one involving internalized voices by the agent herself, one wonders if such
recognition is too weak, in that even young children can experience a recogni-
tional acknowledgment from their dolls and invisible playmates in developing
a sense of themselves. And in other cases, recognition of deliberative capacities
is not yet deserved, no matter how much people claim it for themselves. Apre-
cocious eleven-year-old, for example, may claim full powers of independent
judgment for herself and even insist on being recognized as such, but others
may nevertheless recognize that such confidence is not quite merited asyet.20
Now many structural theorists have made it clear that internalized recogni-
tion, where a postulated community of compatriots that one engages with in
20
Paul Benson mentions this last point as a possible objection. See Benson, Taking Ownership,
n.63. Also, both Benson and other theorists in this literature have discussed the ambiguities Imention
Coping or Oppression 211
here. See, e.g., Benson, Taking Ownership; Andrea Westlund, Replies, Symposia on Race, Gender,
Race, and Philosophy 7:1 (Winter 2011), http://sgrp.typepad.com/sgrp/winter-2011-symposium-macken-
zie-poltera-and-westlund-on-autonomy.html.
21
See, e.g., Mackenzie, Relational Autonomy; Andrea Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility
for Self. See also Andrea Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 24:4:2649.
22
Charles Taylor, The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1991),3233.
23
Superson, Deformed Desires and Informed Desire Tests.
24
Narayan, A Mind of OnesOwn.
212 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
25
Superson, Deformed Desires,423.
26
See, e.g., Saba Mahmoud, The Politics of Piety (Princeton, NJ:Princeton University Press,2005).
27
Serene Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2011). For her criticism of proceduralist views, see Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Procedural
Autonomy, Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 10:2 (July 2009):169187.
28
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Procedural Autonomy, 177ff. See also Khader, Adaptive
Preferences and Womens Empowerment, chap.2. Khader cites Diana Meyers, Personal Autonomy and
the Paradox of Feminine Socialization, Journal of Philosophy 84:11 (1987):619628, as the source of the
view she discusses.
Coping or Oppression 213
they do not fail to do this in any way different from how those with nonadap-
tive preferences might. Moreover, there is no single life story that uniquely
picks out the personal history against which reflective judgments about cur-
rent desires are to be made, both in the normal case and for those with IAPs.29
First, however, it is not clear that life stories framed by practical identities
are as inaccessible as Khader suggests, as most people can readily express the
kind of person they are, their basic values, and the way theyve developed in
light of these values. Giving reasons for our actions demands as much. More
importantly, however, Khader argues against using a notion of autonomy that
relies on maintaining a sense of self-esteem. She argues that many who adapt
their preferences to conform to oppressive circumstances do not lack global
self-esteem in any sense. It is implausible, she writes, that most persons
with APs think they are unworthy human beings who cannot make claims on
others.30
However, in the view developed herein, where I argue that being unable
to be guided by a practical identity that one can affirm the value of through
ones actions and reflections indicates IAPs, does not rest on the assumption
that global self-esteem is the marker of nonadaptation. Iaccept that a persons
identity is segmented into overlapping practical self-conceptions (e.g., being a
father, a survivor, a caring person, a professional). What is required, however,
is that one must be guided by a self-understanding that reflectively expresses a
way of being one can accept without alienation. Khaders criticisms of proce-
dural views do not undercut that approach.31
What Ihave tried to show here, then, is that structural accounts that re-
quire just social relations or expressions of recognition do not adequately cap-
ture the difference between autonomy and adaptation we are seeking, however
powerful they may be for other purposes. Before moving on to a positive view,
however, let us consider one final discussion of autonomy that may shed light
on such judgments. Sarah Buss has recently argued that accounts of autonomy
that require self-reflection and internal control over first-order desires all fail
to fully account for what makes such desires ones own.32 She takes to task ac-
counts of autonomy (which can serve to confer accountability of the right sort)
that see it as an idealized form of agency control. Such views all fail to cap-
ture what is distinctive about autonomous agency because we can be authentic
29
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Procedural Autonomy,178.
30
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Procedural Autonomy,181.
31
Khaders arguments are quite thorough, and my discussion may well not adequately reflect their
nuance so the comments in the text must be taken as a summary judgment rather than a painstaking
argument. Also, she goes on to develop a view of IAPs based on the idea of flourishing which deserves
more discussion. Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment. For reasons laid on the rest
of this paper, however, it will be clear why Iwould reject such a perfectionist approach.
32
Sarah Buss, Autonomous Action: Self-Determination in the Passive Mode, Ethics 122:4 (July
2012):647691.
214 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
33
Buss, Autonomous Action.
34
Buss, Autonomous Action. The views she is referring to most directly are those of Harry
Frankfurt and Gerald Dworkin. For Dworkins views on procedural independence, see Dworkin, The
Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1990), chap.1.
35
Buss, Autonomous Action,658.
Coping or Oppression 215
person in the manic phase of what used to be called manic depression (bi-
polar disorder). When a person is so overtaken with an overflow of powerful
positive emotion that she appears not to be herself it is because that level of
positive intensity is seen to be (and lets imagine in the case it is) a force out of
synch with the normative frame definitive of the persons identity. When your
manic sister wants to hug you too much, too often, going on about how won-
derful you are, it can (sadly) become clear that she is in the grips of an episode.
Consider also a person on the drug ecstasy:he is intensely explaining to you
how awesome you are. None of these are counterflourishing actions or emo-
tions per se. What makes them suspicious is that they run counter to what the
person would normally do. They reveal the workings of psychic forces that are
out of synch with the persons identity.
More pointedly, however, the distinction between agency sustaining and
agency undermining causal factors, for Bussa distinction she describes as
turning on whether such factors contribute to basic human flourishingwont
help to explain our different reactions to people like Abby and the others. For
clearly the factors that caused both Abby and Bernice to readjust their aspira-
tions were harmfula terrible accidentbut the difference in their reactions
was, Iwould insist, a result of the methods they used to come to understand
and process those factors. Similarly, both Kaew and Irina are reacting to neg-
ative (counterflourishing) environmental factors, but they differ in their re-
action to them, a difference that marks their different status as autonomous
agents, Iwould suggest.
So although Buss may be right in what she says about a certain notion of
agencythere may well be multiple takes on agency available to us depending
on the purpose of assigning that label to peopleit wont help in our present
task. However, in the final section, where I make a general suggestion that
distinguishes the cases in question along the lines of a procedural account of
autonomy, it will be necessary to again take into consideration the challenges
Buss raises for similar such accounts in the literature.
Throughout this discussion I have been trying to shed some light on the
daunting problem of internalized oppression by focusing on more common-
place cases of adaptation and adjustment, even when that involves significant
shifts in ones value commitments and practical identity. In what follows Iwant
to discuss a procedural approach to autonomy that, with some amendments,
helps us focus on the aspect of those adjustments that allow self-government
to maintain or reestablish itself, in contrast with cases where it is undermined.
What Ipropose is to take onboard the claim many have made in similar theo-
retical contextsnamely, that autonomy must involve the (weakly substantive)
216 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
36
The argument concerning weakly substantive views of autonomy can be found in Sigurour
Kistinsson, The Limits of Neutrality:Toward AWeakly Substantive Account of Autonomy, Canadian
Journal of Philosophy 30:2 (2000):257286. For discussion of self-trust as a requirement of autonomy,
see, e.g., Benson, Autonomy and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91:12 (1994): 650668; Carolyn
McLeod, Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002); Trudy Govier,
Self-Trust, Autonomy and Self-Esteem Hypatia 8:1 (1993):99119.
37
That is, we do not go from the assumption that certain values are objectively valid to the con-
clusion that failure to grasp these values is a mark of a lack of competence, as some theorists do. See,
e.g., Susan Babbitt, Feminism and Objective Interests: The Role of Transformation Experiences
in Rational Deliberation, in Feminist Epistemologies, edited by Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter
(NewYork:Routledge, 1993), 2464. See also Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, in
Relational Autonomy, edited by Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2000), 94111.
Coping or Oppression 217
The historical approach to autonomy that Iand others utilize emphasizes the
diachronic nature of the agent and the procedures that mark self-government.38 My
attempt to defend an historical account utilized the condition of reflective accept-
ance of ones motives (without alienation) in light of ones history and in relation
to ones diachronically structured practical identity.39 The problem Buss and others
raise with this account is that acts of reflection, even the hypothetical reflection
Irequire, can themselves be manipulated and no account of adequate reflection
can be given that doesnt assume that we already know what self-governmentis.
I now see that the account of self-acceptance upon reflection is in cru-
cial ways undertheorized. On one hand it, from the critical self-reflection
views from which it arises, it may inherit the challenge of a regress and the
specter of voluntarism (despite attempts to avoid it). That is, either the acts of
self-reflection are themselves in need of self-ratification, or we must assume a
self-evaluation of its own attitudes without a basis. In addition to weakening
the attitude that confers agential status on lower-order motivations to aliena-
tion (rather than endorsement), Ialso insisted that the reflection need only be
hypothetical. Moreover, Ialso claimed that the reflection need not be deep in
the sense of considering a world where one did not have the attitude (since that
may be psychologically impossible for many autonomous agents) but only gen-
erally evaluative, where one considers the importance of the attitude, its impli-
cations for oneself and others, and its connections to other aspects of theself.
These moves add up to a picture that is really not a hierarchical view at all,
Inow see, at least not in the sense of postulating levels of mental activity that are
ordered in terms of their centrality to the self. Rather, saying that the autono-
mous person acts from motives that she would reflectively accept as part of her
practical identity is not to imply that the reflective self is more central somehow
to our agency but rather that acting from motives that can be self-reflectively
endorsed in light of ones practical identity themselves have a special status
(vis--vis authenticity). That is, in acting deliberately, one reflexively (not nec-
essarily reflectively) affirms the value of the practical identity that motivates and
justifies that act. In a manner akin to a recursive function, when one acts inten-
tionally one engages a practical identity that affords value to that choice and in
so doing reflexively reinforces the value of having that practical identity.40 Iact
as a certain type of person when Iact, and in so doing Irepeatedly reinforce the
value of being such a personat least when things are goingwell.
Reflection does play a role in this process because we are often called on to
reconsider our actions in light of our basic values. In particular, because of the
38
Other historical accounts include Al Mele, Autonomous Agents (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 1991); John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral
Responsibility (NewYork:Cambridge University Press,1998).
39
This is a highly truncated summary of the position. Christman, Politics of Persons, chap.7.
40
Cf. Keith Lehrer, Self-Trust:AStudy of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy (NewYork:Oxford,1997).
218 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
socially embedded nature of actions, we must coordinate our acts and reasons
with others, either by being called on to account for our actions and values in
ways that force us to reflect on them or by listening to the reflections of others
in acting with them or in response to them.41
But deliberate action for the self-governing agent may well be passionate,
committed, unflinching, and hence nonreflective in any given instance. This
does not mean, however, that such action is unthinking or not underwritten
by ones basic values (often quite the contrary). But it does mean that in acting
one engages the value orienting function of ones practical identity and in so
doing reaffirms that identity as worth having and acting upon. In this way
Iagree with Buss when she underscores the ways we are often passive in rela-
tion to the elements of our character that motivate and justify our autonomous
actions.
The model of intentional action Iutilize here relies a great deal on Korsgaards
self-constitution account of agency.42 On her view, when one acts intention-
ally one is guided by a standard of success or failure, which is given both by
the teleological structure of action (one chooses an action with a purpose in
mind) and by the evaluative organization of the practical identity that grounds
the choice. In this picture, acting is always value conferring in two directions.
When our actions are guided by our practical identities, we both project value
onto those actions and, reflexively, inherit their value in being their source.
Now Korsgaards picture of action and identity is much more detailed than
this and is embedded in a Kantian framework that Idont want to commit to
here (necessarily). Iwant merely to extract the central element of her view of
action, namely, that we constitute ourselves in action and reflexively affirm the
value of the identities that underwrite those actions when we choosethem.
There are, as has been suggested, important interpersonal and social ele-
ments to this process. I agree, but in a particular way that should be clari-
fied to retain the procedural status of the view. The nomenclature of practical
identities, the terms in which value orientation expresses itself, involves a rich
language of roles, social categories, and standards of behavior. We see our-
selves and act as a certain kind of person, such as being a mother or a teacher
or a Muslim or a woman, and those self-descriptors carry with them socially
structured expectations and motivations. These terms do not merely refer to a
set of values or propositionally structured commitments that one can say one
believes in (though those surely figure in our identities). Rather, these catego-
ries orient our way of seeing the world and prioritizing values and options to
41
These observations can be read as a partial response to some critics of my view. See, e.g. Diana T.
Meyers, Review of The Politics of Persons, Hypatia 27:1 (March 2011):227230.
42
Christine Korsgaard, Self-Constitution:Agency, Identity, and Integrity (Oxford:Oxford University
Press,2009).
Coping or Oppression 219
act.43 The core of the postulate of self-worth, Isuggest, is that those descriptors
can be understood as naming a life worthy of pursuit from ones own perspec-
tive. They are often self-validating in practical reflection because they stand in
for a host of interconnected values that, in turn, justify action. One need only
think, As a mother, Iput my childrens needs above my own and not feel the
need to further reflect (in the normal case) on whether it is a good thing to be
a mother of this sort.44
I say in the normal case because Iam describing here cases of nonalienated
self-affirmation. Alienation occurs when these feedback mechanisms break
down or cease to function, when affective concomitants to acting from ones
practical identity are in conflict or misaligned, when one feels shame or em-
barrassment, or when feelings of inner conflict undercut the usual motiva-
tional function of acting on your values. When these motivational feedback
effects do not line up this is a signal that the values are not yours in the proper
sense, that you are hiding something from yourself or feeling resistance to
an imposed or artificial (to you) set of values. But when alienation is not an
issue, acting from ones settled identity requires no overt reflective endorse-
ment from a detached viewpoint.
This is important because it encapsulates the way that social recognition
functions in the reflexive operation of self-affirmation. Intentional action is
motivated in part by a self-understanding under an evaluative identity cat-
egory; such a category is recognized in some publicly manifested way, as
self-validating, as worthy of pursuit. There need be no actual spokesperson,
as it were, for that value, but it must be publicly available in some way. This is
because a purely private category reduces to simply a set of desires, a nexus of
motives that are merely how one is but are not reflexively self-justifying in this
way. Of course these publicly available categories of affirmation need not be
instantiated in actual relations among peoplethis is the aspect of the struc-
tural accounts from which we are departing. Rather they must be available to
the agent to use to understand herself and to feel motivated to continue acting
in the way she understands herself to be. No one needed to actually tell Emily
Dickenson that she was a wonderful poet, but the idea of successful poet was
available to her to evaluate her commitment to her way of life and to help her
affirmit.
In the present context, it is important to note also some of those identity
categories might include things like rebel, outcast, prisoner, pariah, and slave.
43
Cf. David Velleman, Identification and Identity and The Centered Self in Self to Self
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2007), 253283.
44
This is akin to what Stephen Darwall, Two Kinds of Respect, Ethics 88:1 (October 1977):246
261, labels recognition self-respect. Also, I do not take up the details of these similarities or the
complexities of self-respect itself. For discussion see Robin Dillon, Self-Respect:Moral, Emotional,
Political, Ethics 107:2 (January 1997):226249.
220 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
45
Again, cf. Velleman, Centered Self, when he says, one must be able to intend to act in way one is
understood by others. The view Itake here resembles the approach in Benson, Taking Ownership, in
claiming that autonomy involves being in a position to answer for oneself see Taking Ownership,
101126. Aparallel similarity can be seen with Andrea Westlunds account.
46
Relevant here is the discussion in Susan Brison, Aftermath (Princeton, NJ:Princeton University
Press, 2002), chap.3, of how survivors of trauma must recreate self-narratives that include the trauma
itself.
47
Benson, Taking Ownership. For a similar account, see Westlund, Rethinking Relational
Autonomy.
Coping or Oppression 221
that effectively place ourselves in a position to answer for our actions. Benson
contrasts this with identity-based accounts of autonomy claiming that authen-
ticity of actions is secured when they relate to my identity as a caring, reflec-
tively willing creature. Benson argues that such theories are either too weak
(when reflective self-endorsement is merely apathetic or undeveloped) or too
strong (since many trivial or habitual actions would not pass the test but they
are clearly autonomous).
I will not reply to the criticisms Benson wields against my own view in this
context,48 but Iwant to point out how the procedural account Idefend here can
take onboard the requirement of reflexive self-acceptance that Benson insists
upon. Recall that the question we are trying to ask, in effect, is when a persons
responses to the constraints of her circumstances, whether caused by oppres-
sion or accident, are such as to undercut the self-affirmation (e.g., answerabil-
ity, self-ascribed normative authority) that is inherent in autonomous action.
Iam not sure how Bensons condition does that since it will depend greatly on
what we take to be the appropriate modes of answerability. If Bernices atti-
tude toward herself can be expressed as, Sure Idesire to get into this sodding
wheelchair each day, but that is only because of that damned accident; its a
situation Ideeply hate, then it seems clear that she fails to value her normative
position adequately, and she does so because of the origins of that position.
But we do not want to demand complete acceptance of the constraints that
circumscribe ones motivational structure, for then none of us would pass the
test for autonomy:we all can say that we would aspire to different things if
there were no (or fewer) barriers in front of us. The question is:when does the
weight of the constraints on our existence effectively undercut the authenticity
of our self-endorsements; when are we simply slaves of our condition?
This question points to the mysterious core of many accounts of
self-governing action:the phenomenon of owning the motivational and eval-
uative structure that issues in action, of seeing it as ones own. One element of
this phenomenon is clear enough, namely, that one sees ones motives as worth
having, but another is left obscure, namely, seeing them as mine. But what is
this my having that is operatinghere?
Bensons claim is that being answerable is an active process. However, de-
spite his guidance on what should be meant by this, it merely may end up
restating this mystery, Ithink, for he admits that the activity in question need
not involve reflective choice (though it must be purposeful).49 Reflecting on
the condition of Bernice forces us to ask where the point is when the fact that
48
See also Paul Benson, Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization, Social Theory and Practice 17
(1991):385408. For a version of my view that attempts to avoid these criticisms, see Christman, Politics
of Persons, chap.7.
49
Benson, Taking Ownership,113.
222 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
50
Korsgaard, for example, says that a practical identity is a normative conception of the self
containing ones guiding principles: it is a description under which you value yourself. Christine
Korsgaard, Sources of Normativity (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1996), 101. This is ambig-
uous between self-acceptance and self-celebration Ithink.
51
For a rich account of such a process, see Brison, Aftermath.
224 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
a relevant description) that provides reasons for actions, plans, and ongoing
projects.
In cases of internalized oppression, the actual diagnosis of the retention of
autonomy may be difficult or impossible to make, but that may be due to the
indeterminacy of what practical identity category is operative for the person.
Is a person like Kaew, for example, best seen as one who embraces the identity
of a resilient survivor and who engages in prostitution because her life options
limit her to such choices as a method of, say, providing for her family? If so,
then if other conditions of autonomy are met we should not withhold that
label to her. However, if we are suspicious, as Superson is in the case of veiling,
that acceptance of the identity category that requires such behavior could not
but be the result of a self-abnegating identity, then we can label the person
heteronomous. But this is not due to anything inherently degrading or undig-
nified about that behavior itself, independent of its effect on the persons sense
of self-worth.
To sum up, to help sort out whether those who adapt to their circumstances by
seemingly internalizing oppressive conditions in which they live are autono-
mous or not, Iasked us to consider contrasting cases among those who have
and have not made such self-alterations. Those contrasts, Iclaimed, suggested
an asymmetry in our judgments about whether adapting to constraining cir-
cumstances indicates a loss of autonomy or its reestablishment. Iargued that
the structural character of those conditions alonewhether the source of the
constraint was unjust actions or conditions or merely an accidentwas not
the crucial determinant of whether autonomy is preserved. Though Idid ac-
knowledge that relational and interpersonal dynamics of the situation are rel-
evant to that determination; I merely insist that this necessity is contingent
upon the contribution to the full functioning of the procedural requirements
of autonomy.
I claimed, however, that a procedural account of autonomy could help ex-
plain these asymmetries by including a requirement of reflexive self-affirmation
along the lines that other relational theorists in the literature have suggested,
but Iclaimed that such a view is not constitutively relational except in the in-
direct manner in which value categories (in terms of which a person develops
a self-affirming practical identity) are acknowledged somehow in the social
landscape as marking a life worthy of pursuit. I argued that this social ele-
ment is required not because of the intrinsic value of those relations or those
pursuits but because of the social-psychological effect that such public accept-
ance has on the ability of a person to be reflexively self-affirming. But it is
this latter condition that marks autonomy, and it admits of great variability in
Coping or Oppression 225
the dynamic of public affirmation, as the cases of the rebel and resistant slave
indicate.52
I want to close here by emphasizing the way accounts of autonomy should
include reference to the need for persons themselves to participate in the very
determination of their autonomy status. That is, the sites where the attribu-
tion of autonomy operates often exhibit power dynamics that make not only
the expression of a persons practical identity (for example) but also its very
determination difficult. A person may be unclear what value category best
describes the struggles she is engaged in, and whether or not she is autono-
mous may turn on whether she can make that determination and secure a
sense of self-worth that comes withit.53
This is more than an epistemological issue. It is not merely that our theo-
retical account of autonomy is complete, and we merely must be careful when
attempting to discover if its conditions are met in a given case. Rather, the
dynamics of interaction at the site where autonomy determinations are most
crucial are noninstrumentally relevant to whether or not the person is in fact
autonomous. This is because people often need helpful interlocutors (e.g.,
carers, therapists, aid workers, friends) to help establish the practical orien-
tation that organizes their reflective practices. In this way, autonomy is also
relational.54
How theoretically described conditions must be established by actual
social practice is a complex topic that I want merely to gesture at here.55
However, I want to close this discussion with an insistence that models of
self-government include desiderata that rely on persons actual participation
and self-expression to determine the presence of those desiderata. In this way,
52
This last point echoes views developed by Diana Meyers in a different context, when she argues
that what she calls value-saturated accounts of autonomy fail to accommodate cases where people
in oppressive circumstances can sometimes exercise autonomy in strategically negotiating their lives
within those circumstances. Moreover, she argues that such views must be sensitive to the ways that
the voice with which a person may try to express her reaction to her condition is not heard or under-
stood by the listening public or surrounding others, making a condition of external recognition of the
persons value orientation a problematic requirement. See Diana T. Meyers, Feminism and Womens
Autonomy:The Challenge of Female Genital Cutting, Metaphilosophy 31:5 (2000):469491.
53
For a sensitive account of this dynamic, see Catriona Mackenzie, Christopher McDowell, and
Eileen Pittaway, Beyond Do No Harm: The Challenge of Constructing Ethical Relationships in
Refugee Research, Journal of Refugee Studies 20:2 (May 2007):299319.
54
In this way Iagree with Elizabeth Ben-Ishai when she argues that ascribing autonomy to per-
sons affords them a status that is required for self-government, even in cases where their capacity for
self-government is apparently lacking or marginal. Idisagree, however, that such ascription is constitu-
tive of autonomy (rather than causally contributory to it) for reasons similar to my departure from the
aforementioned relational accounts. See Ben-Ishai, Sexual Politics and Ascriptive Autonomy, Politics
and Gender 6:4 (2010):573600.
55
For one attempt to elaborate on this point, see John Christman, Relational Autonomy and the
Social Dynamics of Paternalism, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice (Special Issue, forthcoming).
226 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
the persons voice, aided by a cooperative social context that elicits that voice
in effective ways, is central to the determination of her autonomy.
Acknowledgments
1
Hanna Rosen, Who Wears the Pants in This Economy? New York Times Magazine, August
30,2012.
2
See, e.g., Diana T. Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1989); Paul Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994): 650668;
Catriona Mackenzie, Imagining Oneself Otherwise, in Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives
on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, edited by C. Mackenzie and N. Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2000), 124150 (and in general all articles therein).
228 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
in the light of that ideology. Ann Cudd says that oppression creates deformed
desires, in which the oppressed come to desire that which is oppressive to
them...[and] ones desires turn away from goods and even needs that, absent
those conditions, they would want.3
Sandra Lee Bartky describes an example of this process in her analysis of
the phenomenology of oppression. Through what she calls the interiorization
of the fashionbeauty complex, agents come to believe oppressive norms that
tie appearance to self-worth.4 Bartky says that repressive satisfactionsthat
is, deformed desiresfasten us to the established order of domination, [to]
the same system...produces false needs and that false needs are produced by
the denial of autonomy.5 These remarks suggest that desires that reinforce
ones own oppression are morally problematic because they are formed by
agents with impoverished autonomy. The oppressive conditions are respon-
sible for the desires, not the agent herself.6
Theorists of oppression propose that oppression is distinctive because it a
group harm. Oppression occurs when a group suffers systematic injustice due
to institutional structures or background social practices.7 Paradigm examples
of oppression are systematic injustices suffered by groups whose members
share social identities, for instance those of class, gender, race, sexuality, or dis-
ability. Although oppression employs the notion of group disadvantage, agents
who are members of oppressed groups are also harmed as individuals. Cudd
identifies both material and psychological harms of oppression.8 For instance,
racial segregation in the United States is a material and economic injustice that
3
Ann E. Cudd, Analyzing Oppression (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2006),181.
4
Sandra L. Bartky, Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression
(NewYork:Routledge, 1990),39.
5
Bartky, Femininity and Domination,42.
6
Anita Superson, Deformed Desires and Informed Desire Tests, Hypatia 20 (2005): 109126;
Superson, Feminist Moral Psychology, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Fall 2012 Edition);
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/feminism-moralpsych/>.
7
Ifollow authors such as Iris M. Young, Five Faces of Oppression, reprinted in Rethinking Power,
edited by T. Wartenberg (NewYork:State University NewYork Press, 1992), 17495; Sally Haslanger,
Oppressions: Racial and Other, in Racism in Mind, edited by M. P. Levine and T. Pataki (Ithaca,
NY:Cornell University Press, 2004), 97123; Cudd, Analyzing Oppression. These authors give accounts
of oppression that focus on systematic harm to groups; on these accounts, individuals who suffer harms
of oppression are harmed in virtue of their group membership. Haslanger points out that oppression
can be perpetrated by agents, or it can be structural; that is, systematic disadvantage to a group can
occur as a result of social practices even in the absence of agents or legal institutions that intentionally
perpetrate the oppression. Although here Itake systematic harm to a group and concomitant harm to
individuals in virtue of their group membership as sufficient for oppression, Iwish to leave open the
possibility that single agents or nongroups could suffer oppression. Hence, Ileave open the question
of whether systematic harm to a group is necessary for oppression. Ialso do not employ the notion
of autonomy in the definition of oppression. Cf. Daniel Silvermints position on which he claims that
oppression obtains when an individuals autonomy or overall life prospects are systematically and
wrongfully burdened. Silvermint, Oppression without Group Relations, unpublished manuscript,
Montral, Canada,5.
8
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 229
9
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression,183.
10
Superson, Deformed Desires and Informed Desire Tests. Superson claims that choosing
or preferring ones own oppression is analogous to choosing slavery; it is making a special kind of
moral mistake. Although Superson characterizes her position using a Kantian interpretation of an
informed desire test, her argument suggests that she is committed to a strong substantive account
of autonomy in which the contents of the preferences or values that agents can form or act on au-
tonomously are subject to direct normative constraints. Paul Benson, Feminist Intuitions and the
Normative Substance of Autonomy, in Personal Autonomy:New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its
Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited by James Taylor (Cambridge:Cambridge University
Press, 2005), 133. As Benson points out, in Natalie Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,
in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, I conflated this strong substantive account with a
strong normative competence condition of autonomy. Although deformed desires would be counted
as nonautonomous due to their contents on strong substantive accounts, it is less clear whether agents
who have deformed desires would fail a normative competence condition. For a fuller explanation of
different versions of substantive account, see Natalie Stoljar, Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy,
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Summer 2013 Edition); http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
sum2013/entries/feminism-autonomy/.
11
James S. Taylor, Practical Autonomy and Bioethics (NewYork:Routledge, 2009), 71. Indeed, Cudd
says that adaptive preference is another term for deformed desire. Cudd, Analyzing Oppression, 180181.
230 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
that he doesnt want the grapes after all. Elster takes this to be an unconscious
and nonautonomous process that he calls adaptive preference formation.12
The unconscious accommodation of desires to feasible options often occurs in
conditions of oppression. For example, a girl raised in a patriarchal household
may come to prefer domestic chores because other nontraditional options are
not feasible forher.13
Scholars of development ethics also employ the notion of adaptive prefer-
ence formation.14 Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen focus on agents habit-
uation to conditions of severe deprivation.15 On the face of it, deprivation and
oppression are not the same injustice. Oppression occurs in affluent societies
in which people are not typically victims of severe economic deprivation. The
young girls described in the opening quote are members of a group that is
subject the patriarchal oppression but they live in conditions of relative afflu-
ence.16 It is plausible, however, that agents in conditions of severe deprivation
in the developing world are members of a group that is subject to economic
oppression. In their own cultural context, they may also suffer oppression as
women or as members of particular ethnic minorities. As we will see, there are
sufficient similarities among the two sets of examples to treat them together
for purposes of an analysis of autonomy.
There are two main challenges to the position that preferences that are
adapted to the circumstances of oppression are deformed and constitute au-
tonomy impairments. The first, articulated recently by Serene Khader, claims
that even if desires for oppressive conditions are morally problematic in some
sense, this is not because they are autonomy deficits.17 Khader identifies a
category of inappropriately adaptive preferences that are morally problem-
atic mainly because they are inconsistent with the flourishing of the agent
who forms the preference.18 However she argues that adaptive preferences
are not autonomy deficits on either procedural or substantive accounts of
12
Jon Elster, Sour GrapesUtilitarianism and the Genesis of Wants, in Utilitarianism and Beyond,
edited by A. Sen and B. Williams (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1992), 219238; Elster, Sour
Grapes:Studies in the Subversion of Rationality (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,1983).
13
Donald Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences, Philosophical Studies 142
(2009):307324,309.
14
Serene J. Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2011),10.
15
See, e.g., Amartya Sen, Gender Inequality and Theories of Justice, in Women, Culture, and
Development:AStudy of Human Capabilities, edited by M. Nussbaum and J. Glover (Oxford:Clarendon
Press, 1995), 259273; Martha Nussbaum, Women and Human Development:The Capabilities Approach
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens
Options, Economics and Philosophy 17 (2001):6788. Note that the phenomenon of adaptive prefer-
ence formation was invoked by Elster, Sen, and Nussbaum to critique preference utilitarianism.
16
I am grateful to Daniel Silvermint for discussion of this point and to Daniel Silvermint and
Daniel Weinstock for helpful conversations about Khadersbook.
17
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment.
18
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,51.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 231
19
For reflective endorsement see Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2003). For nonalienation see John Christman, The Politics of Persons: Individual
Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2009).
20
For a detailed explanation of this distinction, see Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar,
Introduction: Refiguring Autonomy, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, 334; Stoljar,
Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy. There are additional ways of dividing up theories of autonomy.
For example, procedural theories may be either internalist, requiring only internal psychological con-
ditions to spell out autonomy, or externalist, requiring additional historical conditions that are external
to agents present internal psychological states. Alfred Mele, Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control
to Autonomy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995). Other externalist theories are not proce-
dural and employ, for instance, the notion of adequate options (Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988)) or socio-relational conditions (Marina Oshana, Personal
Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK:Ashgate, 2006)). The latter externalist positions may also require
a background moral theory to spell out precisely the external conditions that are incompatible with
autonomy. Thus, externalist theories are often substantive as well. Ileave these complexities asidehere.
21
Uma Narayan, Minds of Their Own:Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices and Other Women,
in A Mind of Ones Own. Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, second edition, edited by L. Antony
and C. Witt (Boulder, CO:Westview, 2002), 418432.
22
H. E. Baber, Adaptive Preference, Social Theory and Practice 33 (2007):105126.
232 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
preferences should not be defined using the notion of autonomy. They are
formed through psychological processes and should be defined using psy-
chological criteria. Nevertheless, I argue that on several prominent theories
of autonomy, both procedural and substantive, the adaptive preferences of
concern to feminist theorists (deformed desires) will count as impairments of
autonomy.23 Idistinguish two models of adaptive preferences, both of which
originate in Elsters work. The first, the psychological processes model, proposes
that adaptive preferences are produced by a distinctive causal and psycholog-
ical process. On this model, it is the flawed process that is responsible for the
autonomy impairment. The second, the freedom to do otherwise model, char-
acterizes adaptive preferences as adjustments that occur when options that
agents would choose under other or better conditions are excluded from their
feasible set. On this model, it is the limitation of free agency or freedom to do
otherwise that is responsible for the autonomy impairment.
Sections 1 and 2 address the claim that adaptive preferences are not au-
tonomy impairments. Ifirst consider adaptive preferences construed on the
psychological processes model and argue that historical, procedural theo-
ries of autonomy have the prima facie resources to count deformed desires
as autonomy impairments through the device of procedural independence.24
However, I claim that procedural independence cannot fully explicate why
deformed desires are autonomy impairments without importing a back-
ground moral theory into the procedural account. Thus, deformed desires are
counterexamples to procedural accounts of autonomy that employ a morally
neutral test. Section 2 addresses the second model that claims that deformed
desires are adaptive in a problematic sense because they fail a freedom to do
otherwise test. Iargue that this test is a moral one and moreover that agents
whose preferences fail this test are precisely those agents who count as hav-
ing impaired autonomy on well-known substantive accounts of autonomy.
23
Khader seems to have recently modified the objection saying that adaptive preferences sometimes
revealthough need not revealcompromised autonomy. Serene Khader, Must Theorising about
Adaptive Preferences Deny Womens Agency? Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (2012):302317,312.
24
Ileave aside structural and internalist forms of procedural theory, such as that offered by Harry
Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
For Frankfurt, a sufficient condition of local autonomy is (appropriately understood) endorsement
or wholehearted identification at a time with a preference or desire. There are objections to this kind
of theory. See, e.g., Stoljar, Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy. Moreover, as David Zimmerman,
Making Do:Troubling Stoic Tendencies in an Otherwise Compelling Theory of Autonomy, Canadian
Journal of Philosophy 30 (2000):2553, 25, points out, Frankfurts position risks being committed to an
unpalatable consequence, namely, that acting freely is a matter of making do, that is of bringing one-
self to be motivated to act in accordance with the feasible, so that personal liberation can be achieved
by resigning and adapting oneself to necessity. Zimmermans interesting point needs further exami-
nation, but it does suggest that Frankfurts theory is the wrong place to look for an explanation of the
nonautonomy of adaptive preferences.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 233
Iconclude therefore that Khader is wrong to claim that the adaptive prefer-
ences of concern to feminists are not autonomy deficits.
Sections 3 and 4 turn to the second challenge claiming that what are called
deformed desires are not deformed but instead are rational accommodations to
bad options. Iargue in Section 3 that, even if many adaptive preferences are the
products of a rational costbenefit analysis that is endorsed by the agent, this
does not settle the question of whether the decision is autonomous. Autonomy
theorists often distinguish between the competency and the authenticity
dimensions of autonomy25 or the mental capacities required for autonomy and
additional conditions such as adequate significant options.26 The ability to en-
gage in a costbenefit analysis may be sufficient to establish some version of
rational competency, but it does not follow that the product of this process sat-
isfies the further criteria necessary for autonomy.27 Section 4 attempts to dispel
the worries underlying arguments against classifying adaptive preferences as
autonomy impairments.
25
See, e.g., Christman, Politics of Persons.
26
See, e.g., Raz, Morality of Freedom.
27
Iargued for this position in Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition.
28
Elster, Sour Grapes, 219. See also David Zimmerman, Sour Grapes, Self-Abnegation and
Character Building, Monist 86 (2003):220241; Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences; Ben
Colburn, Autonomy and Adaptive Preferences, Utilitas 23 (2011):5271, for explications of thisidea.
29
Elster, Sour Grapes,221.
234 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
from this tension takes places through some causal mechanism, such as
Festingers reduction of cognitive dissonance, we may speak of adaptive
preference change. The process then is regulated by something like a drive,
not by a conscious want or desire.30
On this model, adaptive preferences are formed by a distinctive psycho-
logical process. The agent unconsciously turns away from a preference that
they would otherwise have had to avoid the unpleasant sense of frustration
or cognitive dissonance that accompanies having preferences for inaccessible
options.31 The process can occur both in cases of preference change, such as that
of the fox, and preference formation, such as girls in patriarchal households
who unconsciously turn away from inaccessible nontraditional options. The
model does not employ the concept of autonomy in the definition of adaptive
preference formation. Rather, adaptive preferences are thought to be nonau-
tonomous because a blind and unconscious causal mechanism appears to
be incompatible with autonomy; it is not intentional or under the agents con-
trol.32 The psychological processes model also does not justify the claim that
feminists often seem to endorse, namely that desires for oppressive conditions
automatically count as deformed and nonautonomous. If a girl who is raised
in a patriarchal household comes to prefer domestic roles over other options,
her preference could be the result of learning and experience (autonomous) or
the result of adaptive preference formation (nonautonomous):one cannot tell
from the preferences alone whether they have been shaped by adaptation.33
The question therefore is whether the process of formation of the preferences
corresponds to an autonomy-undermining process.
Critics of Elster point out that it is implausible that blind and unconscious
processes of preference formation are always incompatible with autonomy.
Donald Bruckner considers an agent whose spouse dies. After a period of
mourning, she gradually relinquishes the preference to have significant expe-
riences with the spouse and acquires a preference to have these experiences
with a new spouse.34 It seems that, preferences that are the products of un-
conscious causal mechanisms are not necessarily nonautonomous despite the
fact that they are formed behind the agents back. Further, Bruckner employs
empirical evidence to argue that adaptive preferences can help to promote
a valuable life because adapting to ones circumstances can be conducive to
30
Elster, Sour Grapes,224.
31
Zimmerman, Sour Grapes, 221222, notes that the process could be sub-personal rather than
unconscious. Inote this possibility but do not consider ithere.
32
If it is not intentional action, it seems that it cannot be autonomous because even if intentional
action is not sufficient for autonomous action, it is necessary.
33
Elster, Sour GrapesUtilitarianism and the Genesis of Wants,225.
34
Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences; see also Colburn, Autonomy and Adaptive
Preferences,57.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 235
35
Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences, 314315.
36
Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences, 318319.
37
Bruckner, In Defence of Adaptive Preferences,319.
38
Christman, Politics of Persons.
39
Christman, Politics of Persons, 124125. Christman quotes from Shane Phelan, Getting
Specific:Postmodern Lesbian Politics (Minneapolis:University of Minneapolis Press, 1996),5253.
40
Christman, Politics of Persons, 155156.
41
Christman, Politics of Persons,144.
236 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
preferences were formed? No doubt young women who adopt traditional fe-
male roles would think it entirely appropriate that they were taught to do so by
their mothers. As Paul Benson argues, in cases in which oppressive norms are
very deeply ingrained it is not plausible to think that the agent would repudiate
or feel alienated from desires based on the norms even after reflecting on their
process of formation.42
Moreover, on Christmans account, forming a different preference in a
situation of reduced options to avoid or eradicate actual (or counterfactual)
cognitive dissonance may well be a paradigm case of autonomous preference
formation. By hypothesis, the foxs desire for the grapes, combined with their
unavailability, led to alienation. Hence, in resolving the cognitive dissonance
by repudiating the desire for the grapes, the fox eradicates his alienation and
seems to achieve autonomy on Christmans account. Similarly, the adaptive
preference of girls for traditional female roles (by hypothesis) is the result of
the inaccessibility of nontraditional options in the patriarchal context. Girls
turn away from inaccessible nontraditional options in part to avoid the frus-
tration of desiring the inaccessible. Hence, alienation would accompany the
inaccessible, rejected preference, not the one the agent actually adopts. On
Christmans view, the preference for the traditional, feasible, option is the
autonomousone.
One option for Christman would be to bite the bullet:since alienation is not
or would not be experienced by agents whose preferences are unconsciously
adapted to oppressive conditions, these preferences are not autonomy impair-
ments. However, there may be further resources available on his historical and
procedural account that will help to demarcate autonomous adaptive prefer-
ences from nonautonomous ones.43 The hypothetical reflection condition, al-
though it purports to offer a historical condition of autonomy, actually requires
only that the agent reflect in the present about the historical formation of her
desires. Procedural theorists have noticed that critical reflection in the present
is not sufficient for autonomy and claimed that present reflection must not
be the product of a distorted causal mechanism leading to its formation.44 As
Khader herself points out, an independence of mind or procedural inde-
pendence condition has been considered a necessary condition of autonomy
on standard procedural accounts.45 For instance, Gerald Dworkin argues that
42
Paul Benson, Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization, Social Theory and Practice 17
(1991):385408.
43
Iam grateful to Mark Piper for suggesting this possibility.
44
Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1988); Mele, Autonomous Agents.
45
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 74. Khader goes on to ask whether
various conditions mentioned in procedural theories of autonomy would count adaptive preferences as
nonautonomous, but she does not explore procedural independence. She does discuss Elsters idea that
adaptive preference formation is an unconscious process that operates behind the agents back under
the heading life-planning as personal history (85). However, her objection to this possibility seems
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 237
off the mark. She writes, Thinking of [adaptive preferences] this way commits us to a dubious meta-
physical position...that there is one authoritative narrative about why a person forms a preference at
the moment that it happens (85). Ido not believe that Elster is presupposing this metaphysical com-
mitment. He is claiming that there is a psychological and theoretical difference between unconscious
(adaptive) causal mechanisms and deliberate, conscious and plannedones.
46
Dworkin, Theory and Practice of Autonomy,18.
47
Christman, Politics of Persons, 147,155.
48
John Christman, Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom, Ethics 101 (1991):343359,354.
49
Christman, Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom,353.
50
Arecent discussion of adaptive preference formation explicitly adopts the position that adaptive
preference formation is an unconscious process that violates procedural independence. Ben Colburn,
Autonomy and Adaptive Preferences, argues that an independence test fails when the formation of a
preference is subjected to covert influence. Like subliminal influence, covert influence is a mechanism
that produces desires in agents through a process in which the agent is not aware of the causal expla-
nation of her preferences.
51
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,78.
52
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,81.
238 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
notes that this woman seems committed to her values and reflective about the
ways her values inform her decision to malnourish herself. Hence, Khader
thinks there is no autonomy deficit on procedural accounts that employ a
critical reflection condition. However, on the account Iam now considering,
being reflective in the present is not sufficient for autonomy. The question is
whether the preference to deprive oneself of food due to the internalization of
misogynistic norms is procedurally independentthat is, whether the influ-
ence on the formation of the preference constituted coercive persuasion or was
reflection-distorting due to insufficient exposure to alternative possibilities or
some other factor.
Whether or not a preference fails a test of procedural independence is
in principle a case-by-case question. However, if theorists of oppression are
correct, we can make some general claims about the desires of members of
oppressed groups:they are often formed by processes that are coercive:in-
doctrination, manipulation and adaptation to unfair social circumstances.53
Thus, prima facie, the desires of members of oppressed groups for their own
oppression fail a test of procedural independence such as that of coercive
persuasion.
Procedural accounts of autonomy therefore potentially employ condi-
tions that would classify adaptive preferences as autonomy impairments. The
problem for such accounts is whether the processes that violate procedural
independence, like coercive persuasion, can be spelled out in a satisfactory
way without importing background moral conditions. Cudd argues that a
purely empirical account of coercion is unsatisfactory because it cannot dis-
tinguish between a hard choice and a forced choice.54 Similarly, to flesh out
the reflection-distorting influences that correspond to lack of minimal educa-
tion or inadequate exposure to alternatives, we need some normative account
of what counts as minimally satisfactory education or adequate alternatives.
Therefore, although procedural theorists can explain how desires for oppres-
sive conditions are nonautonomous, the explanation comes at the expense of
maintaining the moral neutrality of their own theory.
53
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression,183.
54
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression, 126129. Iam therefore in broad agreement with Khader when she
says that procedural theories need to be [supplemented] with a theory of the good. Khader, Adaptive
Preferences and Womens Empowerment,95.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 239
55
Elster, Sour Grapes,228.
56
Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options,6869.
57
Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options,6869.
240 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
the extent to which they want what human beings have a right to have.58 The
freedom to do otherwise condition must therefore be understood as a moral
condition. If agents preferences are accommodated to external options only
because the options are limited by unjust social circumstances, their prefer-
ences are shaped by necessity in a way that restricts their freedom.
For Nussbaum, adaptive preferences are morally problematic in situations
in which agents face a morally inadequate set of options. In such circum-
stances, when preferences are accommodated to the options, and agents do
not desire what they have a right to have, their autonomy is impaired. Thus,
for Nussbaum, adaptive preferences are morally problematic precisely because
they are (substantive) autonomy deficits. In response to this kind of position,
Khader proposes a perfectionist definition of adaptive preferences. Aprefer-
ence is inappropriately adaptive when it is inconsistent with a persons basic
flourishing, formed under conditions non-conducive to basic flourishing,
and would not have been formed under conditions conducive to basic flour-
ishing.59 Agents like Vasanti satisfy the definition and have inappropriately
adaptive preferences. But Khader claims that such preferences do not corre-
spond to autonomy impairments even on substantive accounts of autonomy.60
Let me address Khaders argument by focusing on her discussion of Joseph
Razs substantive theory.61 Raz proposes that autonomy requires adequate ex-
ternal options in addition to mental ability and independence from coercion
and manipulation by other agents.62 For example, he describes a hounded
womana woman on a desert island who is hounded by a wild animal and
has to spend all her time and energy planning for survival. The woman has a
variety of options in addition to the mental abilities necessary for planning,
but the options she has are inadequate. For one thing, they are dominated
by her one overpowering need and desire to escape being devoured by the
beast.63 For another, having adequate options is understood by Raz as a moral
58
Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options,79.
59
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,51.
60
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 95106.
61
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 99102, also discusses other possible
substantive approaches to spelling out the notion of autonomy such as substantive autonomy as being
motivated by good norms. This label is misleading because being motivated by good norms does not
name a conception or theory of autonomy but rather a piece of evidence that a theory of autonomy
will have to explain. For example, Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition, claims that many
feminists think that, when agents are motivated by false and oppressive norms, the agents autonomy is
called into question. Igo on to make a conditional claim:if we accept this intuition, then a strong sub-
stantive theory of autonomy will need to be invoked to explain it. As mentioned already, my discussion
at the time did not properly distinguish between two possible substantive theories:a strong substantive
account that is content based; and a (strong) normative competence account. As Iargue here, Istill
think that a substantive account of autonomy is needed to explain why desires for ones own oppression
seem to be autonomy impairments. But Ido not now think this has to be a strong substantive account
that is contentbased.
62
Raz, Morality of Freedom,369.
63
Raz, Morality of Freedom, 374376.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 241
64
Raz, Morality of Freedom,378.
65
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 102. Emphasisadded.
66
Raz, Morality of Freedom,411.
67
Ihave based my discussion on one possible reconstruction of Khaders argument. Her remarks
are very brief, so Imay have misunderstood what she has in mind. Here is another possible reconstruc-
tion:she seems to take Razs position as equivalent to a strong substantive view that employs normative
constraints on the content of preferences. She claims that adaptive preferences cannot be defined using
contents alone. (This is correct; a preference for bullfighting may be or may not be adaptive and non-
autonomous.) Hence she may be saying that adaptive preferences do not correspond to the category
of nonautonomous preferences on Razs account because the latter is a content-based account. Ithink
however that the analysis of Raz as offering a content-based account is mistaken. As we saw, he thinks
that autonomous agents can have preferences with bad or immoral content. Hence his account is sub-
stantive in a different sense from strong substantive accounts. The moral constraints are derived from
the notion of adequate options, not from the immorality of the content of agents preferences.
242 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
prefer ones severely limited options (i.e., adapting ones preferences to ones
feasible option set) corresponds to exercising impaired autonomy.
In general, adaptive preferences as Khader defines them would count as
autonomy deficits on Razs adequate options test. On her account, basic flour-
ishing or well-being is defined using a minimal, vague and cross-culturally ac-
ceptable conception of the good.68 It is clear that, if an agent lacks the options
required for minimal flourishing, she would also be deprived of morally ad-
equate options. Thus, a preference that is formed only because better options
are inaccessible to the agentthat is, a preference that would be classified as
adaptive on Khaders definitionalso would be classified as nonautonomous
on Razs approach to autonomy.
Khader acknowledges that adaptive preferences on her model are likely to
be ruled nonautonomous on Razs account because they are shaped by inad-
equate options. But she claims that calling [adaptive preferences] autonomy
deficits and incorporating a conception of the good into autonomy leads us to
policies that are decidedly illiberal.69 She worries that if we characterize adap-
tive preferences in response to oppression, poverty, and deprivation as lacking
autonomy, this will license coercive governmental policies that will override
the voluntary choices of such agents, thereby compounding their oppression
and deprivation. Thus, Khaders main objection to characterizing adaptive
preferences as autonomy deficits is a moral one.70 I postpone discussion of
moral objections to Section4.
Up to now, the discussion has focused on the intersection of Razs account
of autonomy and the adaptive preferences of agents in conditions of severe
deprivation. It may be more difficult to invoke Razs theory to account for the
deformed desires of agents in affluent societies. Notice first, however, that
while oppressed people in Western countries often live in conditions in which
minimal flourishing is possible, it does not follow that the conditions required
for minimal well-being rise to the level of adequate options. Second, as Raz
and others point out, autonomy comes in degrees. The options of members of
oppressed groupsfor education, housing, social services, medical care, em-
ploymentare often compromised by comparison with the options of mem-
bers of groups that are not oppressed.
Consider a phenomenon that Cudd describes as oppression by choice.71
Cudd observes that in a labor market in which the average wage for women is
significantly less than it is for men, it might be rational for a mother rather than
68
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,103.
69
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,103.
70
Cf. Ann Cudd, Review of Khaders Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,
Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2012, http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/27280-adaptive-prefe
rences-and-women-s-empowerment/.
71
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression, 146153.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 243
72
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression,150.
73
Narayan, Minds of TheirOwn.
244 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
best alternative that is available to the agent under the circumstances. When
the best alternative is inaccessible, it is rational to choose second best.74
The different versions of the challenge diverge in an important respect.
Baber, whose focus is to provide a defense of preference utilitarianism against
Nussbaums critique, argues that many preferences that are called adaptive
are not in fact genuine preferences at all. Choices in response to what she calls
a raw deal may not be what agents really prefer. On the other hand, feminist
critics like Narayan (and Khader), whose focus is to defend womens agency,
claim that preferences for sexist norms or bad circumstances are genuine pref-
erences. In many cases these preferences are reinforced by other goals that the
agent takes to be valuable. Khader discusses women who opt for genital cut-
ting or clitoridectomy. She points out that often women are motivated by the
wish for community belonging and social recognition, in particular by the goal
to promote the marriageability of their daughters.75 Similarly, the aforemen-
tioned preference for malnourishment of the Javanese woman is reinforced by
religious conviction. Womens preferences seem genuine when considered in
conjunction with these other factors.
Narayan and Baber do, however, offer parallel arguments for the ration-
ality of putative deformed desires. Agents living under oppression or deprived
conditions are capable of utility maximization; they are capable of engaging
in costbenefit analyses that weigh up the options available and of making
a choice among options on the basis of this analysis. In particular, they note
that most agents rank bundles of options, not options in isolation. Consider
Narayans example of a community of women in India, the Sufi Pirzadi, who
live in relative purdah (seclusion) within the home and are expected to veil
when they are in public.76 These women acknowledge that purdah severely
limits their education and mobility and has the effect of making them de-
pendent on male members of the community. But they also explicitly recognize
benefits, for instance, that veiling signifies womanly modesty and propriety
and their superior standing vis--vis other Muslim women.77 She argues that
due to their cultural and religious context these women cannot separate out
preferences that limit their movement and promote their dependence from
those that promote the piety and modesty that they value:the options come
as a bundle.
Baber makes the same point in her analysis of Vasanti. She points out that
Vasanti may prefer a bundle of options including abuse and having a roof over
her head over a bundle that contains no abuse and being on the street. It is
not irrational to choose the former bundle but rather an example of rational
74
Baber, Adaptive Preference.
75
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 100101.
76
Narayan, Minds of Their Own,420.
77
Narayan, Minds of Their Own, 420421.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 245
calculation under oppressive conditions in which the agent gets some advan-
tages and forgoes others:
We might with equal justification understand Vasantis decision as the result
of a utility calculation given a reasonable assessment of her options and the
probabilities of various outcomes. Vasanti recognizes that given her circum-
stances, staying in an abusive marriage is her best bet if she wants to have
a home and basic necessities:even if she would rather avoid getting beaten,
she is prepared to take on that cost in order to avoid her least preferred out-
come:homelessness and destitution.78
Thus, for both Baber and Narayan, putative deformed preferences are not de-
formed but rather instances of the exercise of rational agency in which agents
rank bundles of options under difficult circumstances.
Baber offers a second argument as well:although Vasanti and other agents
may appear to have preferences for oppressive conditions, in fact we cannot
infer that they prefer what they choose:making the best of a raw deal when
no other alternatives are available is not the same as preferring it.79 Consider
the fox. According to Baber, the foxs preferences have not changed; he is only
pretending to himself that he does not value or want the grapes. If a bunch
of grapes suddenly became accessible to him, he would jump at them, and
hence, his preference for the grapes persists.80 The fox engages in a rational
process of settling for second best. The foxs possible options are (1)grapes and
no felt frustration, (2)no grapes and no felt frustration, and (3)no grapes and
felt frustration.81 Although the fox cannot have the best option (1), he pre-
fers serenity over felt frustration and thus eradicates the felt frustration that
comes with continuing to want the grapes. Similarly, Vasanti does not really
prefer domestic abuse. She would jump at a better situation were it accessible
to her. But staying under her husbands roof and putting up with the abuse is a
rational choice because it is better than the alternative, namely, no abuse and
homelessness.82
These arguments contain two basic ideas. The first denies that the desires
of agents who endorse apparently harmful practices such as clitoridectomy or
practices in which their rights are curtailed such as purdah are deformed. On
the contrary, these agents are rational choosers with complex motivations who
are making the best of the circumstances in which they find themselves. The
second idea is that there is a difference between what the agent chooses and
78
Baber, Adaptive Preference, 113114.
79
Baber, Adaptive Preference,114.
80
Preferences are understood as behavioral dispositions, not occurrent feelings. Baber, Adaptive
Preference,312.
81
Baber, Adaptive Preference,111.
82
Baber, Adaptive Preference,114.
246 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
seems to prefer, and what they really prefer. Since many agents like Vasanti, if
offered better options, would jump at them, what they choose is not what they
really prefer. It is a compromise in the face of a terrible situation in which what
they really prefer is inaccessible tothem.
One can agree with both of these ideas. Yet neither establishes that agents
like the Sufi Pirzadi, Vasanti, or for that matter women in Western contexts
who appear to adapt to oppressive conditions are autonomous. Engaging in
a costbenefit analysis may be sufficient for formal rationality yet insufficient
for autonomy.83 As we have seen, theories of autonomy typically distinguish
between competency conditions and additional conditions such as authen-
ticity or availability of adequate options. Thus, it is possible that the agents
under consideration satisfy competency and formal rationality conditions yet
nevertheless fail to be autonomous. For the same reasons, Babers argument
that agents like Vasanti make rational choices that might enhance their sub-
jective well-being given their options is also not incompatible with attributing
lack of autonomy to Vasanti and agents like her. The ability to improve ones
well-being under conditions in which ones options are curtailed is not equiv-
alent to exercising autonomy.
Indeed, not only is Babers analysis not incompatible with attributing an
autonomy impairment, it also provides an implicit argument that the choices
of agents like Vasanti are not autonomous. In effect, Baber is distinguishing
between apparent and true preferences.84 She thinks that reversible adaptive
preferences are not true preferences and that the true preferences are re-
vealed by the behavioral dispositions to jump at alternative better options.
Hence, the fox and Vasanti are deceiving themselves about what they truly
prefer. Many theories of autonomy, however, would consider self-deception
and autonomy incompatible. For instance, Diana Meyers argues that one of
the skills required for agents to be autonomous is that of self-discovery; agents
who are blind to their own true preferences are not exercising this skill and
are not autonomous.85 The reversibility of a preference therefore would be evi-
dence that it is not autonomous because reversibility suggests that it is merely
apparent not real. (Indeed, this may be the intuition behind Elsters original
classification of adaptive preferences as reversible and nonautonomous and
hence unlike the irreversibleand autonomouspreferences that come about
through learning.)
Other theories suggest that apparent self-deception is compatible with
autonomy, but only if self-deception occurs in the service of right reasons.
For example, Henry Richardson argues that an agent is autonomous if she
83
Stoljar, Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition.
84
Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options, 73, discusses this line of thought while
referencing John Harsanyis distinction between manifest and true preferences.
85
See, e.g., Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice,47.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 247
oppressed] will prefer oppression to justice or subordination to equality, rather they will prefer the
kinds of social roles that tend to subordinatethem.
90
The Srey Mom example is taken from Nicholas D. Kristof, Bargaining for Freedom, NewYork
Times, January 21,2004.
91
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment, 130, argues that preferences such
as that for malnourishment could enhance the interests or well-being of the agent, for example,
self-depriving behavior often elicits actual rewards.
92
Cf. Elster, Sour Grapes,221.
93
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,98.
94
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,100.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 249
95
Nussbaum, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Options, 74; Baber, Adaptive Preference,
114,126.
96
Mele, Autonomous Agents.
97
See, e.g., Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,33.
98
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,11.
99
Narayan, Minds of Their Own, 422, refers to a remark of Catherine MacKinnon that womens
agency is pulverized.
250 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
100
For inadequate moral options, see Raz, Morality of Freedom. For socio-relational conditions, see
Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society.
101
Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society,2.
102
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,103.
103
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,104.
104
See, e.g., Raz, Morality of Freedom.
Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation 251
illness or religious values. Suppose a person with a mental illness lacks the
competencies required for full autonomy. From a liberal perspective, there is
no justification for subjecting this person to any sort of coercive policy unless
she is likely to harm herself or others. Similarly, preferences against certain
forms of life-saving medical intervention can be based on religious beliefs.
Jehovahs Witnesses think that blood transfusions are contrary to biblical
injunctions. Even if a theory of autonomy judges this religious conviction to
be the result of indoctrination and hence (for instance) to be incompatible
with the requirement of procedural independence, there is no justification for
subjecting Jehovahs Witnesses to coercive policies to change their convictions.
Coercive intervention such as enforced blood transfusions may be justifiable,
but only as a last resort to preventharm.
Khader seems to accept that the harm principle potentially could provide a
justification of a coercive policy. She writes that we should focus on changing
cultural practices only when they cause some sort of [serious] harm or wrong
to individuals.105 In the case of genital cutting, for example, there is wide var-
iation among physical practices as well as among social benefits that ensue.
The practice does not always constitute serious harm.106 Khader is right to say
that the mere fact that an agents endorsement of the practice of genital cutting
is driven by a cultural belief that is false and misogynistic does not provide a
justification for coercive intervention. But there is stronger position running
through Khaders critique: namely, that noncoercive policies, if their aim is
to change peoples cultural beliefs or conceptions of the good, are never per-
missible because cultural beliefs and conceptions of the good are delivered by
autonomous agency.107
This position is implausible. Although liberals (especially proponents of
procedural theories of autonomy) put a lot of weight on respecting individual
agents conceptions of the good, nevertheless they endorse the value of au-
tonomy and some version of the harm principle. Since some conceptions of the
good are harmful or inconsistent with agents own autonomy, not all concep-
tions of the good are equally valuable. As Catriona Mackenzie argues, ruling
out coercive political means for promoting autonomy...does not entail ruling
out other political means for encouraging citizens to pursue valuable goals
for example, incentive and reward schemes...; health promotion campaigns;
funding subsidies for the arts, and so on.108 Indeed, since autonomy is a value
105
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,101.
106
Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Womens Empowerment,101.
107
Khader seems to thinks that noncoercive interventions are permissible to promote, for example,
deliberative aspects of agency, but these would fall short of policies whose aim is to change conceptions
of thegood.
108
Catriona Mackenize, Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism, Journal
of Social Philosophy 39 (2008):529.
252 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
liberals endorse, noncoercive policies that attempt to promote the value of au-
tonomy may be a requirement of justice on liberal political theories.109
Conclusion
In this chapter, I set out to examine the consequences for autonomy of the
phenomenon of adaptive preference formation in which the oppressed come
to desire that which is oppressive to them.110 Feminists often seem to sug-
gest that internalized oppression ipso facto impairs autonomy and that the
notion of adaptive preference offers support for that conclusion. The preced-
ing discussion has shown that the situation is more complicated. Adaptive
preferences are not autonomy deficits by definition, and neither is it the case
that all unconscious accommodations to feasible options count as autonomy
impairments. On the other hand, many of the adaptive preferences of concern
to feminists are autonomy impairments. Iargued that even if adaptive prefer-
ences are not deformed but rather rational and reasonable decisions in the
face of oppression, this does not show that they are autonomous. Preferences
adapted to oppressive conditions fail the tests introduced by both procedural
and substantive theories of autonomy. The key reason that they fail these
testswhether it is a test of procedural independence or an adequate options
testis that the moral constraints faced by members of oppressed groups due
to their oppression reduce their psychological freedom.
Acknowledgments
For helpful discussion and comments, Iam indebted to Mark Piper, Andrea
Veltman, my fellow contributors to this volume, and the other participants in
the workshop Relational Autonomy:10 Years On, held at McGill University
in September 2012. Iam also grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities
Research Council of Canada for a grant that supports my research on autonomy
and oppression, and for a second grant that made the workshop possible.
109
Iam grateful to Catriona Mackenzie for many discussions that have helped me think through
theseideas.
110
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression,181.
{PartV }
In August 2011, my wife gave birth to our first child, our daughter, Helena. We
soon found that we had little time or energy to reflect on much beyond the
question of how best to manage the learning curveoften joyful, just as often
overwhelmingforced upon new parents. But when we could reflect, our
thoughts revolved frequently around the central question of how best to meet
the immense responsibility, not just of raising a child, but also specifically of
raising a daughter in a society still saturated with gender-based inequalities of
many powerful kinds. Although not under any illusions that parental instruc-
tion alone, however enlightened, is sufficient to counteract the widespread
and entrenched institutional obstacles to gender equality, we were (and re-
main) convinced that proper parental instruction can go a long way toward
putting girls on the best footing for their future struggle for personal develop-
ment and social equality. But how best to go about this? How best to raise our
daughter in a manner that encourages her future autonomy but at the same
time informs her understanding of her gender in a way that is supportive of
the wider aims of feminism itself? As preparations for this volume proceeded,
these concerns gradually came to the fore of my reflections and prompted me
to write on precisely these topics. My goal in this paper is to argue for a form
of gender socialization for daughters, mediated by parental instruction, that
is best suited to achieving the twin goals of enhancing daughters future au-
tonomy and instilling in them a view of what it means to be a woman in such
a way that they will grow to be strong advocates of the social cause of gender
equality. In the remainder of these introductory comments, Iwish to set out
the problems discussed in this paper more carefully. I will then proceed to
256 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
canvass and consider three strategies for a feminist theory of female gender
socialization and argue for the form of female gender socialization that Ibe-
lieve holds out the best promise of meeting the vital goals mentionedabove.
Traditional female socialization processes tend to be autonomy subverting
for women.1 Women are often taught to be subordinate to men, to focus on
feeling rather than thinking, and to confine their attentions to the home.
Girls are presented with stories and images in entertainment and the media
that support the notion that women should be largely focused on gaining ac-
knowledgment from men and should identify their true selves with their
outward appearance. These factors, and many more like them, combine to
tend to make women more submissive, less confident in themselves, and faced
with diminished opportunities for self-development and self-expression. The
result of these factors is the creation of an inequality between the autonomy
prospects for men and women that is disadvantageous for women. Let us
call this the autonomy gender inequality problem. Overcoming this problem
requires initiatives at several levels.2 Among these initiatives, one central chal-
lenge for feminists is to outline a strategy for parentally guided gender so-
cialization that will attenuate the autonomy gender inequality problem. Girls
should be gender socialized in a way that supports and enhances their future
autonomy rather than hindersit.3
It is clear that a solution to the autonomy gender inequality problem should
be part of a feminist theory of gender socialization (henceforth GS). But it is
also the case that a theory of GS that is autonomy supporting does not consti-
tute a complete feminist theory of GS. Afeminist theory of GS also requires
an account of how girls should be raised to view being female in a manner
that is supportive of feminism. In short, it is not evident that raising a girl in
an autonomy-enhancing manner will, by itself, lead her to view her femaleness
in a feminism-supporting way. Hence, in addition to containing a solution to
the autonomy gender inequality problem, a feminist theory of GS must also
include resources for teaching girls to be supportive of the values contained
in feminism in a manner that advances feminist aims in society. Assuming
that both of these aspects are necessary for a feminist theory of GS, however,
1
Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, translated and edited H. M. Parshley (London: Lowe
and Bridone, 1953); Janet Shibley Hyde and Nicole Else-Quest, Half the Human Experience: The
Psychology of Women, eighth edition (Belmont, CA:Wadsworth, 2013); Diana Meyers, Self, Society, and
Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1989); C. Renzetti and D. Curran, Sex-Role
Socialization, in Feminist Philosophies, edited by J. Kourany, J. Sterba, and R. Tong (Upper Saddle
River, NJ:Prentice Hall,1992).
2
Beauvoir, Second Sex, 680682.
3
It should be noted that many theorists who have dealt with what I am calling the autonomy
gender inequality problem have not described it as a problem of autonomy per se. Often the pres-
ence or absence of other qualities will be pointed out: qualities such as subordination, oppression,
and reduced opportunities. But all of these negatively affect the future autonomy of women and are
included as part of the autonomy gender inequality problem in the presentwork.
Raising Daughters 257
4
Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1988); Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice; Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics
(NewYork:Oxford University Press,2003).
5
For discussion of the question of whether autonomy possession requires normative commit-
ments, see, e.g., Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics; Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society
(Aldershot, UK: Ashgate Publishing, 2006); John Christman, The Politics of Persons: Individual
Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,2009).
6
See Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth, Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition, and Justice, in
Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism:New Essays, edited by John Christman and Joel Anderson
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2005), 127149; Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society.
258 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
not possess autonomy are heteronomous; these persons lack the aforemen-
tioned capacities and as a result generally live according to determinations that
do not stem from their authentic selves. Such persons include those who are
blindly conforming, brainwashed, or easily manipulated. While not all persons
are actually autonomous, virtually all personswith the exception of the irre-
deemably pathological or handicappedpossess the potential for a minimum
level of autonomy.7
I understand feminism to be an intellectual and social movement with
the goal of achieving justice for women in relation to all social institutions.8
Feminism fundamentally seeks equality for women. It is premised on the view
that women possess status and importance at least equal to men and hence
deserve equal rights and opportunities. Given that there are many forms of
feminism, however, and that some of these forms are at odds with one another,
it is necessary to further specify that Iam predominantly conceiving feminism
at it has been developed in the liberal tradition, and specifically in the tradition
of egalitarian liberal feminism.9 The upshot of this conception is that women
are entitled to the conditions that allow for full social equality as men, and
that achieving this goal requires both that women are enabled to develop per-
sonal autonomy and that women are empowered to be coauthors of the social
conditions under which they develop and live.10 Anatural concomitant of a
commitment to feminism of this kind is the view that girls should be raised in
such a way both as to secure the best chances for their personal autonomy en-
hancement and to be prepared to be vigorous social advocates for the equality
and freedom of all women.11
7
I assume that autonomy of this kind is metaphysically possible. See Catriona Mackenzie and
Natalie Stoljar, Introduction:Autonomy Refigured, in Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on
Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie and Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2000), 331; Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics. This possibility involves the assumption that
it is meaningful to speak of an authentic self and that it is possible to know ones authentic self (although
it is not necessary to assume that it is possible to know it perfectly). Ialso assume that autonomy of this
kind is not especially uncommonthat most people experience at least marginal increases in this kind
of autonomy as they mature from childhood to adulthood.
8
Sally Haslanger, Nancy Tuana, and Peg OConnor, Topics in Feminism, in Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Summer 2013), edited by Edward N.Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/
entries/feminism-topics/.
9
For an overview of the many forms of feminist theory, see Josephine Donovan, Feminist
Theory: The Intellectual Traditions (New York: Continuum Publishing, 2012). For different feminist
approaches to political theory specifically, see Noelle McAfee, Feminist Political Philosophy, in The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011), edited by Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.
edu/archives/win2011/entries/feminism-political/.
10
For more details, see Amy R. Baehr, Liberal Feminism, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2012), edited by Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/
feminism-liberal/.
11
For the sake of economy, in what follows Iwill use the term feminism to refer specifically to egal-
itarian liberal feminism.
Raising Daughters 259
12
Cf. Kate Millet, Sexual Politics (London:Granada Publishing,1971).
13
Contra Catherine MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge, MA:Harvard
University Press, 1989). It might be said that I am also arguing against Sally Haslanger, Gender
and Race:(What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Them to Be? Nous 34:1 (2000):3155, insofar as
she has defined gender with basic reference to facts of inequality. But this critique would be incor-
rect: Haslangers work contains the caveat that she is defining gender to aid in the achievement of
a particular practical purpose. Her conception of gender is pragmatic and ameliorative; she is not
attempting to provide a real definition of gender.
14
Although I deny strict gender realism, I assume that the category of gender is relatively uni-
fied insofar as it satisfies the demands of resemblance nominalism. See Natalie Stoljar, Essence,
Identity and the Concept of Woman, Philosophical Topics 23 (1995):261293; Stoljar, The Politics of
Identity and the Metaphysics of Diversity, in Proceedings of the 20th World Congress of Philosophy,
Vol. VIII, edited by Daniel Dahlstrom (Bowling Green, OH:Bowling Green State University, 2000).
I assume that sex and gender are distinct, contra Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the
Subversion of Identity (New York: Routledge, 1999), 43. I assume that the sexgender distinction
is useful, contra Genevieve Lloyd, The Man of Reason: Male and Female in Western Philosophy
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984); Elizabeth Grosz, Volatile Bodies: Toward a
Corporeal Feminism (Bloomington:Indiana University Press,1994).
15
Beauvoir, Second Sex; Millet, Sexual Politics; Sally Haslanger, Ontology and Social Construction,
Philosophical Topics 23 (1995):95125.
260 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
seem that we can have one ideal or the other but not both. We can raise girls
to be autonomous (but then we cant predetermine key aspects of their value
systems), or we can raise girls to view gender in a way that is supportive of
feminism (but such inculcation seems to rob them of autonomy, at least on
some accounts).
I believe, though, that this is a pseudo-problem. First, the objection may rest
on a misunderstanding. It is not being suggested that girls ought to be raised
in a manner that is autonomy supportive and will result in the inculcation of
a particular value system no matter what. This would constitute a straw man
of the theory being sought. The desire is rather to see if it is possible to have
autonomy-supportive gender socialization coupled with instruction in the
nature and value of gender that tends to be supportive of feminism or presents
feminism in a reasonable, plausible light. Second, the incoherence charge is
vulnerable to reductio problems. If the development of autonomy were incom-
patible with the teaching of any particular values, then no one would be auton-
omous, since everyone is raised (more or less by social necessity) to believe
that some things are to be valued and that some things are not. But that cant be
right:autonomy might not be automatically achieved by all, but it is achieved
by many, to some degree at least. So it must be possible to raise someone in
an autonomy-supportive way while teaching them that particular values are
plausible or reasonable. What is required to have GS that is supportive of both
autonomy development and feminism is a commitment to teaching the com-
petencies that comprise autonomy and to presenting a feminist conception of
gender as a plausible view that has a number of strong reasons in its support.
Although young girls do not possess the autonomy capacities to reflect criti-
cally on the conception of gender they are being taught, these abilities grow
with their autonomy competency, until they are able to decide for themselves
whether to endorse feminist-supportive teachings. To deny that this is possible
is, in effect, to deny the possibility of autonomy. Again, everyone begins life
as entirely heteronomous and gradually obtains greater autonomy potential.
People go on to actualize this potential to varying extents. The move toward
greater self-government and independence of thought is difficult, but it does
happen, even against the background of forms of upbringing that are stringent
or stifling.
3. The Options
Non-gendered socialization
NGS has a classic standing in feminist studies. Gayle Rubin argues that femi-
nists should seek to create a genderless (though not sexless) society, in which
ones sexual anatomy is irrelevant to who one is, what one does, and with
whom one makes love.16 According to Richard Wasserstrom, a properly sex-
ually assimilated society would be one in which the gender system is repudi-
ated. In such an ideal society, persons would not be socialized so as to see
or understand themselves or others as essentially or significantly who they
were...because they were either male or female.17 And Susan Moller Okin
argues in Justice, Gender and the Family that a feminist reading of Rawlss
Theory of Justice suggests that if those in the Original Position didnt know
their sex they would probably opt for a genderless society: A just society
would be one without gender.18
Although various forms of NGS are possible, at present I wish to focus
on a particularly robust form of NGS. According to this conception, NGS
holds that gender has no normative importance of any kind. On this view, the
psychological-social aspects of gender are nothing more than arbitrary social
constructs, yet they have become infused with normative importance and
have been used to promote unjust endsmost tellingly, the subordination of
women. Recognizing this arbitrariness, this view holds that we should do away
with the notion that the norms associated with gender generate any demands
for maintenance, loyalty, or uptake of any kind. The very notion of gender dif-
ference is to be abolished. Some humans have different organs than others, but
that is as far as the matter oughttogo.
16
Gayle Rubin, The Traffic in Women:Notes on the Political Economy of Sex, in Toward an
Anthropology of Women, edited by Rayna R. Reiter (NewYork:Monthly Review Press, 1975),204.
17
Richard Wasserstrom, On Racism and Sexism, in Todays Moral Problems, edited by Richard
A.Wasserstrom (NewYork:Macmillan Press, 1979),26.
18
Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (NewYork:Basic Books, 1991),171.
262 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
19
An example of NGS in action can be found at Egalia, a preschool in Stockholm, Sweden. Cordelia
Hebblewaite, Swedens Gender-Neutral Pre-school, BBC News Europe, http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/
world-europe-14038419. The teachers there actively work against instilling in children expectations
based on gender in several ways. They avoid using the pronouns him or her when speaking to chil-
dren, instead referring to them as friends, by their first names, or as hen (a genderless pronoun bor-
rowed from Finnish). The schools books are devoid of traditional presentations of gender roles. All the
children are encouraged to choose from toys of all kinds, including those not traditionally associated
with their gender. Boys are free to dress up and play with dolls; girls are free to play with toy tractors.
Egalia is state funded and is proving popular in a country known for its passion for social equality.
Raising Daughters 263
play on womens behalf. Rather, women should seek as far as possible to live,
think, and behave like men, for this is the path to empowerment, equality,
self-expression, dynamic creativity, robust self-government, and flourishing.
In TMGS, girls are taught to be direct and willful, to play aggressively, to
seek out and be comfortable in positions of social leadership, to be creative,
to have social ambitions, and to expect to be part of the machinery of social
power. In short, according to this approach all children should receive the
same GS, both in terms of methods and content. This is the only way to pro-
vide all children, girls and boys, with the greatest chance of living the best life
possible.
Stoljar, Essence, Identity and the Concept of Woman; Stoljar, Politics of Identity.
21
264 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
projects that speak to their gender. Living as a woman, it could be said, has
definite prudential value for the women who do so. Yet on this view woman-
hood is not the most significant fact about a womans normative status. More
important still is the basic condition of being human, or of being a person, or
of being a rational being. The normative grounding for womens basic rights
to equality in RFGS is the stance that one would expect to be associated with
feminists who espouse a sameness approach to feminism.22 On this approach,
women may be distinct in various ways, and embracing this distinctiveness
can be important for the quality of womens lives. However, the ground of
womens rights to equal opportunities and treatment is not to be found in the
value of being a woman as such; it is to be found in a quality that women share
with men alike. Girls raised in accordance with RFGS will acknowledge their
gender but place deeper ethical import elsewhere:Yes, Im a woman, and this
has a value of its own, but more importantly, Ideserve equal treatment because
Iam a person [or, e.g., rational individual or autonomous agent].
As we have seen, this approach allows for significant diversity amongst
the life paths that particular women may take. As such, general commonal-
ties among women are not conceived as binding on what a woman must be.
In RFGS, a woman may choose to become just about whatever she wants.
Following from this inclusivity, parents employing RFGS will raise their chil-
dren to have skills, habits, and resources that have wide formal value, in facili-
tating the successful pursuit of as many different forms of life as possible.
Last, RFGS holds that girls ought to be taughtproudlyto be girls and
ought to be trained to be effective advocates for women. This does not imply
that all girls raised in RFGS should be taught that they must become public
social figures leading the fight for equality, though, for this would run counter
to the very inclusiveness of this approach to GS. Part of the inclusiveness of
this approach is to teach girls that there are many ways to advocate for women.
Certainly leadership in feminist social activism is one path, but there are oth-
ers as well. The teacher or professor who is not intimidated by aggressive male
students or a largely male administrative body, the businesswoman who does
not laugh at misogynistic jokes from her coworkers, the aspiring carpenter
who is not deterred by the absence of women in her chosen trade, or the
homemaker who firmly insists that her unpaid work is at least as important as
paid forms of laborall of these are forms of advocacy for women. If there are
general constraints associated with RFGS, they are only these:that girls will be
raised to be widely competent and prepared for many different possible forms
of life, that they will be taught that there are many valuable ways of being a
woman and that they will be instructed in such a way as to foster the strength
Cf. Martha Nussbaum, Human Capabilities, Female Human Beings, in Women, Culture and
22
Development: A Study of Human Capabilities, edited by Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover
(NewYork:Oxford University Press, 1995), 61104.
Raising Daughters 265
23
Paul Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91:12 (1994):650658.
24
Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy and Society, Journal of Social Philosophy 29 (1998):81102.
25
Charles Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences:Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge:Cambridge
University Press, 1985), 187210; Jurgen Habermas, Individuation through Socialization:On George
Herbert Meads Theory of Subjectivity, in Habermas, Postmetaphysical Thinking:Philosophical Essays,
translated by William Mark Hohengarten (Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 1992); Anderson and Honneth,
Autonomy, Vulnerability.
266 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
bring their pressure to bear on women, but this could be mitigated by a con-
sistent and systematic parental policy in support of diversity. Moreover, there
is nothing in NGS that necessarily works against parental inculcation of com-
petency conditions such as personal discipline, logical aptitude, moderate
skepticism of outside influences, or proactivity in the prosecution of ones life
plan. NGS is hostile to the system of gender roles, associations, and statuses
that characterize traditional Western society, but this hostility does not essen-
tially involve skepticism about the capacities mentioned. Indeed, it is likely
that NGS would promote a more robust inculcation of the same, since girls
raised in such a mannerone that radically opposes an entrenched aspect of
social lifewould require training in just these sorts of abilities to hold fast
to their convictions against the potent general currents of gender conformity.
There are strong objections to NGS, however. For one thing, there is reason
to believe that girls raised in NGS face dangers in relation to developing a
strong sense of self-worth. Such girls run sharply against the conventional
grain and would likely be belittled and combated on several fronts for their
repudiation of the significance of gender roles and norms. There is empirical
evidence to suggest that the distress caused by the experience of gender non-
conformity can lead to self-doubt, which, if internalized, can prompt uncer-
tainty about ones right to flaunt convention and can eventually lead in some
children to a reduced sense of self-esteem.26 And there is also evidence to sug-
gest that girls whose behavior is not geared toward social approval will face
reduced popularity.27 If a sense of self-esteem or self-worth is important for
autonomy possession, as many authors have argued, then such a result would
likely undermine autonomy.28
However, the force of this objection should not be overestimated. First, on
the plausible view that traditional forms of GS reliably lead to women having
reduced autonomy capacity, forms of GS that may hold dangers for the devel-
opment of self-worth but that also have resources for addressing the autonomy
gender inequality problem might still be overall preferable, as containing
better chances for girls to develop autonomy. Second, the influence of parental
26
J. Block and R. W. Robins, A Longitudinal Study of Consistency and Change in Self-Esteem
from Early Adolescence to Early Adulthood, Child Development 64 (1993): 909923; S. K. Egan
and D. G. Perry, Gender Identity:AMultidimensional Analysis with Implications for Psychosocial
Adjustment, Developmental Psychology 37 (2001): 451463; R. A. Josephs, H. R. Markus, and R. W.
Tafarodi, Gender and Self-Esteem, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 63 (1992):391402; A.
Thorne and Q. Michaelieu, Situating Adolescent Gender and Self-Esteem with Personal Memories,
Child Development 67 (1996):13741390; Meenakshi Menon, Does Felt Gender Compatibility Mediate
Influences of Self-Perceived Gender Nonconformity on Early Adolescents Psychosocial Adjustment?
Child Development 82:4 (2011):11521162.
27
Hunter College Womens Studies Collective, Womens Realities, Womens Choices
(NewYork:Oxford University Press, 1983),153.
28
See, e.g. Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth; Catriona Mackenzie, Imagining Oneself
Otherwise, in Mackenzie and Stoljar, Relational Autonomy, 124150.
Raising Daughters 267
29
M. H. Richards, I. B. Gitelson, A. C. Petersen, and A. L. Hurtig, Adolescent Personality in Girls
and Boys:The Role of Mothers and Fathers, Psychology of Women Quarterly 15 (1991):6581.
30
Linda L. Lindsey, Gender Roles:ASociological Perspective (Upper Saddle River, NJ:Prentice-Hall,
1997),27.
31
Richard Udry, Biological Limits of Gender Construction, American Sociological Review 65:3
(2000):454.
268 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
32
Haslanger, Gender and Race, 33,36.
270 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
policy of this kind would have the best practical chance of securing wide con-
sent and motivating womens action on a widefront.
It may perhaps be objected that enacting this suggestion might hurt the
cause more than it helps. After all, in the face of widespread social injustice,
sometimes it is best to buck even the deepest points of convention. Wouldnt
the kind of reasoning tendered previously, applied, say, to slavery, suggest that
we ought to maintain the category slave for similar reasons? Yet while Iagree
that a radical repudiation of conventional wisdom might be necessary in some
circumstances, Iam not convinced that this is appropriate here. For one thing,
the analogy with slavery is strained at best. The category slave is inherently
subordinate, while the category woman is not. Hence, maintaining the cate-
gory woman would not entail the continuation of an inherently unjust social
category. More broadly, decisions regarding the solution of social ills ought to
be determined by the particulars of the case. In the case of social inequality
toward women, Iwould argue, in accordance with the considerations given
already, that the goals of the feminist movement are best satisfied by main-
taining the category woman as real and distinct. Doing so would by no means
require maintaining the traditional role associations, psychological profiles, or
differential claims regarding status that have undermined the feminist cause,
but it would increase the likelihood that fewer women would feel alienated
from the movement devoted to their very liberation and that women could
productively rally around their very gender identity in furtherance of their
just aims. For these reasons, Iconclude that NGS, while theoretically poised to
support the feminist cause, holds considerable practical dangers for feminism
and therefore fares poorly in relation to practical support for the feminist ide-
als that it was designed to facilitate.
Although these considerations are institutional in scoperelating as they
do to the establishment of a policy for broad and effective feminist social ac-
tivismit should not be thought for that reason that they are unsuited to the
far more local decision faced by parents regarding how to raise their daugh-
ters. If the practical arguments given already have bite, there is no reason to
think that they would not inform parents judgments about the best form of
GS to apply when raising their daughters or the particular manner in which
daughters are raised. Parents committed to the goals of autonomy and fem-
inism wish for their daughters to flourish in the world as it exists, and this
requires providing sound practical advice for understanding and interacting
with the broad currents of social activism in which their daughters will live. It
makes no small difference to the nature of a daughters upbringing to be told
that gender categories have no significance whatsoeveror, for that matter,
that there is real practical value in maintaining that they do. Such instruction
will certainly play a powerful role in how a girl understands and interacts with
her peers and with gendered social conventions and norms and will influence
a girls judgments about what a commitment to feminist ideals demands of her
Raising Daughters 271
and other women. Parents who wish for their daughters potentially to become
strong advocates for feminism cannot afford to overlook broader consider-
ations such as those given before when they will have a direct bearing, not
only on how they raise their daughters but more importantly on what their
daughters cometobe.
In sum, then, Ihold that NGS faces strong challenges as a feminist theory
of GS, both because of concerns about its ability to be supportive of womens
autonomy and because of concerns relating to its practical effectiveness in
underwriting the desirable feminist goal of securing widespread and effective
practical action in support of womens equality.
33
Beauvoir, Second Sex, 681682.
34
Beauvoir, Second Sex,687.
35
Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice,190.
272 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
36
Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice, 191192.
37
Beauvoir, Second Sex,338.
38
Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences, 187210; Evelyn Fox Keller, Reflections on Gender
and Science (New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1985); Patricia Huntington, Toward a Dialectical
Concept of Autonomy, Philosophy and Social Criticism 21 (1995):3755.
39
Iris Marion Young, Humanism, Gynocentrism, and Feminist Politics, in Theorizing
Feminisms:AReader, edited by Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2005), 174187.
Raising Daughters 273
short, TMGS will likely result in the development of strong leaders of social,
political, and economic institutions and of feminism generally.
Yet there are some respects in which one might be reasonably critical of
the extent to which TMGS supports feminism. Some of these issues have been
explored already in relation to NGS. First, TMGS is premised on the idea that
traditional notions of femininity are to be avoided. Lives devoted exclusively to
mothering, or more generally to the loving care of others, or to homemaking,
or indeed to any kinds of living that are characterized by what might be called
quiet compassion are judged by the background normative commitments of
TMGS as worthy of disparagement and even hostility, as precisely the ways
of living that have historically worked to facilitate womens subordination to
men. TMGS repudiates these ways of living as forms of collaboration in wom-
ens oppression. Yet while it cannot be doubted that these forms of life have
contributed to womens oppression, values and practices based on the repudi-
ation of traditional forms of femininity might work to undermine feminism by
alienating broad swaths of women who associate with these ways of living. It is
important to avoid understating the potential effects of propagating the view
that the feminist movement is hostile to traditional forms of femininity. Told
that their commitment to these forms of life constitutes an insidious form of
unwitting collaboration with the forces of social injustice, many women may
elect to keep their distance fromor even fightthe feminist movement out
of a desire for ideological self-preservation.
Moreover, TMGS implies that women ought to assimilate their value sys-
tems, social expectations, and behaviors to traditional forms of masculinity.
The implicit upshot of this recommendation is the idea that the category
woman, while not empty of distinctive content, is empty of any desirable or
commendable content. Woman becomes a symbol for an unworthy form of
weakness that is to be avoided. By contrast, man becomes a symbol for forms
of life and valuation that are truly valuable. Such a consequence contains the
practical problem that women are deprived of basing possible activism on be-
half of women in anything that is valuable about being a woman. One may still
fight on behalf of the abstract claims of justice or perhaps on behalf of women
qua individuals or persons; but the very category woman whose weal is sought
through social action threatens to become little more than a symbol of an ob-
stacle that needs to be overcome. In this way, a powerful potential resource for
securing communal accession and social action is lost:the category woman is
not a rallying point for women; rather it becomes a threat.
The upshot of these concerns is practical in character. A more effective con-
ceptual practice in garnering wide and effective support for the feminist cause
might be instead to maintain the notion that the category woman is distinctive
and valuable in its own right. One is far more likely to fight effectively when
one is fighting for ones kin and community, conceived as worthy of fighting
for on its own merits.
Raising Daughters 275
40
Butler, Gender Trouble.
276 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
variety of available life options, and will tend to develop a sense of self-worth
grounded in an appreciation both of the value of their gender and their basic
moral standing as persons.
RFGS has many advantages in relation to support for feminism as well. First,
as mentioned already, one of the goals of RFGS is to produce committed, com-
petent advocates for feminism (with the understanding, noted already, that
this advocacy can take different forms, depending on a womans nature and
life choices). Second, RFGS maintains and celebrates the category woman
considerably broadened in its sense, of coursewhich serves the practical
purpose of rallying support for feminism. RFGS favors as inclusive a home
for women as possible, provided it is grounded in gender equality. As argued
earlier, allowing for this has the considerable practical virtue of giving women
a sense of kin and community that is seen as positive and worth fightingfor.
However, unlike TMGS, RFGS will not introduce practical or normative
worries associated with exclusion of conceptions of womanhood (beyond the
exclusion of normative conceptions of womanhood that do not underwrite the
basic commitment to womens equal worth and entitlements, of course). In its
broad inclusive purview, women of many kinds and natures will be welcome.
Of all of the forms of GS thus far considered, in fact, RFGS will have the broad-
est appeal and hence will have the potential for organizing and maintaining
the widest base of support.
All of these advantages speak in favor of RFGS as a promising strategy in
relation to engendering positive, broad, and sustained support for feminism.
However, the primary objection to RFGS relates precisely to its inclusive-
ness. It might be argued that this form of GS, in its broad acceptance of a wide
variety of different valid conceptions of what it means to be a woman, lacks a
unified conception of womanhood that delimits the parameters of woman-
hood itself. Feminism, it could be argued, has practical and theoretical need
of a conception of womanhood that has a relatively clear and definable exten-
sion. Without this, the feminist cause loses its distinctiveness as a unified cause
on behalf of women. From this point of view, RFGS engenders a degenerate
form of feminism, one that collapses into a mealy, confused, and potentially
contradictory congeries of all of the above that precludes coherent female
self-understanding and diminishes the possibility of unified action on behalf
ofwomen.
This objection would be problematic, Ibelieve, if RFGS had this effect. But
it can be plausibly argued that it does not. RFGS has resources to provide the
kind of unity to the category of womanhood that is necessary to ground a
broadly encompassing understanding of what it means to be a woman and to
motivate unified social action. The key here is to remember that RFGS contains
and propagates the idea that women are to be understood as grouped together
by general shared features, including biological similarities, a shared history of
similar ways of living, and a shared experience of social oppression, largely at
278 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
the hands of men. These identity conditions are specific enough to delimit the
vast majorityif not allof those who consider themselves women but, im-
portantly, are general enough to allow for a wide variety of more specific ways
one can conceive what women are or ought to be. In addition, the normative
basis of RFGS serves as a unifying ground for social action:however various
are the ways women live and experience the world, all women are clearly called
to unite on behalf of resisting, in various ways, the social institutions that con-
tribute to womens oppression. On the basis of these features of RFGS, then,
Iwould suggest that the worry that RFGS is too inclusive can bemet.
On the basis of these considerations, Iconclude that RFGS stands as the most
attractive option for a feminist theory of GS. RFGS fares exceedingly well both
in terms of its potential for raising girls with the best chance for autonomy
development and in terms of its worth as underwriting a broadly inclusive,
practically effective, widely unified feminist movement. It supports a concep-
tion of what it means to be a woman that engenders solidarity while recogniz-
ing and celebrating difference and remains strong and unapologetic in its call
for reform of the social institutions informed by gender conceptions.
6. Concluding Remarks
One of the most important tasks for any parent who espouses feminist ideals
is the task of raising daughters. Although a proper upbringing is not perfect
insurance against problems stemming from institutionalized gender inequali-
ties, parental instruction is the beginning of a girls experience of the world
and has pride of place as the oldest root of a girls theoretical and normative
commitments. One of the most important parts of this upbringing is gender
socialization itself. Improper forms of GS hold the risk, not only of damaging
a girls prospects for future autonomy but also of undermining, through the
personal and social implications of its teachings about what it means to be a
woman, feminist causes themselves. If we are to discharge our commitments
to raising our daughters in a manner supportive both of their future autonomy
and of feminism, we need a feminist theory of GS that pays due heed to both
of these commitments and justifies its prescriptions in a manner that is both
rationally compelling and realistic, given the state of the society as we findit.
In this chapter Ihave argued that both the goal of womens autonomy en-
hancement and the normative commitments and social goals of egalitarian
liberal feminism are best satisfied by a form of GS that involves raising girls
firmly in the commitment that women deserve equal treatment as men, that
Raising Daughters 279
contains the notion that the category woman is to be maintained in its own
right as identifying and celebrating a distinctive form of life and yet remains
widely inclusive in terms of what it means to be a woman, and that locates the
fundamental ground for gender equality in womens membership in a nor-
matively significant category that is shared with men:the category of rational
agents, or autonomous individuals, or simply persons. If this conclusion has
merit, the remaining task assumes all the more importance:to apply theory to
life, and raise our daughters conscientiously according to the theorys prescrip-
tions, secure in the conviction that they deserve our best efforts to prepare
them to advocate for a cause whose nobility and urgency cannot be reasonably
doubted.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Andrea Veltman and all of the participants in the McGill
University workshop Relational Autonomy:Ten Years On for their extremely
helpful comments and feedback on this chapter. Iwould also like to thank my
wife, Pia Antolic-Piper, for discussing these ideas with me, for giving birth to
our daughter, and for being an amazingly devoted and inspiring mother.
{13}
1
Some of the literature on meaningful work focuses on eudemonistic dimensions of meaningful
work, that is, on the potential of work to contribute to human flourishing by developing or exercising
capabilities or skills, by fostering independent judgment in performance of tasks, or by integrating con-
ception and execution for a feeling of personal satisfaction at work. See, e.g., James Bernard Murphy,
The Moral Economy of Labor:Aristotelian Themes in Economic Theory (New Haven, CT:Yale University
Press, 1993); Adrian Walsh, Meaningful Work as a Distributive Good, Southern Journal of Philosophy
32 (1994): 233250. In a monograph I am now working on, provisionally titled Meaningful Work,
Iargue that meaningful work has several dimensions, and eudemonistic dimensions of meaningful
work are integral but not exhaustive in an account of what makes work meaningful. In addition to
being eudemonistically meaningful, work can be meaningful in serving a purpose, creating something
of enduring value, reflecting personal life goals or values, or integrating otherwise disparate elements
of a workers life. Developing or exercising human capabilities in eudemonistically meaningful work
exhibits agency, but as Iunderstand it agency extends beyond developing or exercising human capabili-
ties to encompass, for instance, expressions of values, principled commitments, character, personality,
creativity, or individuality; agency at work stands in contrast with observation, passivity, merely fol-
lowing orders, or feeling likeacog.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 281
2
In Meaningful Work, Iam broadly interested in work in its relation to human flourishing, which
requires the realization of human capabilities and the possession of a plurality of goods. My focus
here is work in relation to autonomous agency, which I understand to be a component of human
flourishing. For a good discussion of the components of human flourishing, see Douglas Rasmussen,
Human Flourishing and Human Nature, in Human Flourishing, edited by Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D.
Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1999), especially121.
3
For a fuller list of goods that attach to work, see Andrea Veltman, Is Meaningful Work Available
to All People? in Philosophy and Social Criticism, forthcoming. Consider also what one occupational
psychiatrist writes:It is possible that no single activity defines adulthood more specifically than work.
To a large extent work influences how and where an individual lives, it affects social contacts and
family activities, and it provides a title, role, and environment that shape and reinforce an individuals
identity. Nick Kates, Barrie Greiff, M.D., and Duane Hagen, M.D., The Psychosocial Impact of Job Loss
(Washington, DC:American Psychiatric Press, 1990), 185. See also the work of Al Gini, such as A. Gini
and T. Sullivan, Work:The Process and the Person, Journal of Business Ethics 6 (1987):649655.
4
E. F. Schumacher, Good Work (NewYork:Harper and Row, 1979),50.
5
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2003),19.
282 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
6
Consider, e.g., what Ruth Cavendish, Women on the Line (London:Routledge & Keegan Paul,
1982), writes about her experience working in a car parts factory in England: on the assembly line
we couldnt do the things you would normally not think twice about, like blowing your nose or flick-
ing hair out of your eyes; that cost valuable secondsit wasnt included in the layout so no time was
allowed for it. In any case, your hands were usually full (41). The women ran the line, but we were
also just appendages to it. The discipline was imposed automatically....We just slotted in, like cogs in
a wheel. Every movement we made and every second of our time was controlled by the line...(107).
7
Taylorism is the idea that workplace managers increase efficiency, productivity, predictability,
worker accountability, and control over working processes by extracting knowledge and skills from
workers, subsequently reducing worker skill and knowledge to simple and discrete formulate so that
production can be performed by men who are of smaller caliber and attainments and who are therefore
cheaper than those required under the old system. F. W. Taylor, Shop Management (NewYork:Harper
& Brothers Publishers, 1912),105.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 283
8
His Holiness the Dalai Lama, How to Practice the Way to a Meaningful Life, translated and edited
by Jeffrey Hopkins (NewYork:Atria Books, 2002), 35. From the Catholic tradition, Pope Leo XIII gives
a similar thought in writing that it is shameful and inhuman, however, to use men as things for gain
and to put no more value on them than what they are worth in muscle and energy. John Budd, The
Thought of Work (Ithaca, NY:Cornell University Press, 2011),59.
9
Thomas Hill, Dignity and Practical Reason in Kants Moral Theory (Ithaca, NY:Cornell University
Press, 1992),3846.
10
As Hill, Dignity and Practical Reason, 39, writes, A review of Kants repeated use of humanity
in a person in The Metaphysics of Morals and elsewhere strongly suggests that, contrary to the usual
reading, Kant thought of humanity as a characteristic, or set of characteristics, of persons.... Humanity
is contrasted with our animality; and it is said to be something entrusted to us for preservation.... Its
distinguishing feature is said to be the power to set ends.
284 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
11
Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by H. J. Paton (NewYork:Harper &
Row, 1964), 9798; 97 Hill, Dignity and Practical Reason,40.
12
John White, Education and the End of Work: A New Philosophy of Work and Learning
(London: Cassell 1997), 48, defines autonomous work as a form of activity whose end-product is
chosen as a major goal of an autonomous agent; cf. 510. Acondensed version of the argument of
this book appears in White, Education, Work and Well-being, Journal of Philosophy of Education 31:2
(1997):233247.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 285
product has not been chosen as a major goal; heteronomous work is work
that one is constrained to perform for any number of reasons that do not stem
from ones own personal goals, such as needing money for other life goals,
satisfying others expectations, or even following Gods directive.13 As John
White observes, most work done in the world is heteronomous. People work
because they must, and what most people do at work does not meet reflectively
held personal life goals. In Section 2, Ireturn to the concept of autonomously
chosen work in addressing the notionwhich Ifind dubiousthat an autono-
mous choice to enter an agency-depriving occupation lends moral credence to
the working arrangement.
Particularly for those whose work lacks internal rewards or whose work
in itself is not a personal life goal, the hope of earning a livelihood or pro-
viding for a family provides purpose to work and a point to what one endures
on the job. Although earning an income does not itself entail full economic
independence, an income and associated benefits can provide a measure of
independence and a source of pride, self-respect, and dignity. These virtues
issue from work both in the respect that work represents a social contribution
and in the respect that work enables a person to avoid relying on others, which
places her under the will of others whose goodwill could potentially cease at
any time. Among others, Paul Gomberg notes that lacking recognition as an
economic contributor undermines personal dignity and self-esteem and that
in the United States this moral and psychological pain has not been distributed
equally across races:In the United States for the past 50years, black people
have suffered twice the rate of unemployment as whites. The scars of this as-
sault on peoples dignity are deep in many neighborhoods.14
The concept of autonomy as economic independence is entangled with
notions of autonomy no longer fashionable, as feminist philosophers have
duly critiqued conceptions of autonomy as independence as drawn from
male biographies and bound up with socially atomistic conceptions of human
beings. Some also observe that an ideal of autonomy as economic self-reliance
is manipulated in political rhetoric and used to justify denying welfare assis-
tance to poor women, whose need to raise young children renders ideals of
independence and self-sufficiency unattainable. Lorraine Code writes that in
the politics and rhetorics of social welfare...an assumed equality of access to
social goods, that requires no advocacy, underwrites the belief that failure to
achieve autonomy is a social sin.... Reliance on social services slides rhetor-
ically into a weakness, a dependence on social advocacy that, paradoxically,
invitesand receivesjudgments of moral turpitude.15 Insofar as a regulative
13
White, Education, Work and Well-being,234.
14
Paul Gomberg, How to Make Opportunity Equal: Race and Contributive Justice (Malden,
MA:Blackwell, 2007),70.
15
Lorraine Code, The Perversion of Autonomy and the Subjection of Women: Discourses of
Social Advocacy at Centurys End, in Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency
286 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
and the Social Self, edited by Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University
Press, 2000),194.
16
Diana Meyers, Self, Society and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1989),
12, distinguishes personal autonomy from economic autonomy, where the latter represents an ideal of
financial self-sufficiency that people seek to prevent the possibility that others might gain power over
them through their needs. If one can take care of oneself, one is beholden to no oneneither to the
state nor to any other individual. Thus, one is at liberty to live as one chooses. Friedman, Autonomy,
Gender, Politics, 4749, also writes that, although there is a superficial resemblance between philo-
sophical conceptions of personal autonomy and conceptions of independence and self-sufficiency in
popular understanding, personal autonomy and financial independence are distinct notions. On her
account, financial independence is related to personal autonomy as a condition that can promote the
realization of autonomy, but financial independence is no constitutive part of autonomy, nor is it
causally sufficient forit.
17
Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2006), 87, identifies
financial self-sufficiency as one of several social-relational properties of autonomy, arguing that a level
of economic autonomy that enables a person to be independent of others is a requirement of personal
autonomy. Simone de Beauvoir similarly acknowledges economic independence as a component of
womens liberation.
18
See Eva Feder Kittay and Ellen K. Feder (eds.), The Subject of Care: Feminist Perspectives on
Dependency (Lanham, MD:Rowman and Littlefield, 2002), particularly Iris Marion Young, Autonomy,
Welfare Reform and Meaningful Work,4060.
19
As given in social commentary such as Robert Greenwald (dir. and prod.), Wal-Mart:The High
Cost of Low Price (Brave New Films,2005).
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 287
in the most degrading sense of the term; that is, workers become tools of profit
for others.20 So it is not the case that a social sin of failing to achieve self-reliant
independence falls on women or men who fail to work enough but rather that
a social sin falls on corporations that net enormous profits and that can afford
to pay adequate wages and benefits but instead place profit ahead of people.
Finally, if the notion of autonomy as economic independence remains dated
and problematic, it also remains perversely relevant in illuminating an appre-
ciable dimension of oppression in relation to workone distinct from autono-
mous work as freely chosen and from autonomous agency in work itself.
For a picture of work that permits neither economic autonomy nor autono-
mous agency in work, the reader may consider the work portrayed in Fast
Food Women, in which filmmaker Anne Lewis records women employees
whose nearly every move behind the counter and in the kitchen is predeter-
mined by management, including the number of times a skillet is shook and
the number of times pieces of chicken are rolled in batter. At KFC, the func-
tion of the female employee is to count to seven as she shakes a skillet and to
count to ten as she rolls chicken in batter, on the assumption that it is best for
quality control, and ultimately for company profit, that fast food women be
relieved of the need to think or make judgments about cooking.21 Managers of
a Druthers restaurant in Whitesburg, Kentucky, comment in the film that the
work is not the sort that a married man would seek out, in part because it does
not pay a living wage and carries no benefits. Rather, the work is suitable for
a woman who will derive a sense of accomplishment from completing a job
while following orders and whose father or husband perhaps has good pay and
benefits through his coal-mining occupation or other work.22
20
Consider here the work of journalists such as Barbara Ehrenreich, Nickel and Dimed:On (Not)
Getting By in America (NewYork:Henry Holt and Company,2001).
21
When interviewed in Anne Lewis, Fast Food Women (Appalshop Film, 1991), Barbara Garson
contrasts the skill and flair exhibited in the work of a short order cook in a local diner of the 1950s with
the Tayloristic principles of the late twentieth-century fast food industrywhich essentially extract
skills and knowledge from an original cohort of workers and transfers them into machines, systems,
programs, and sets of rules for new employees, so that workers who are cheaper and more expendable
need only follow beeps and buzzers, pull knobs, and turn cranks or perform other insignificant and
mechanical movements of limbs. The short-order cook might whistle at work or swear at work but in
any case exhibited a personality while at work; even if his or her work were largely routine, its details
and execution were not predetermined and regimented by management. Similarly, in giving a portrait
of his mother as a waitress, Mike Rose, The Mind at Work: Valuing the Intelligence of the American
Worker (NewYork:Penguin Books, 2004), chap.1, suggests that waitressing permits skill, flair, and
judgment, as waitresses develop and rely on complex memory and navigation skills and create order
amid lunchtime chaos. But in the chain restaurant of the twenty-first century, even flare itself can be-
come regimented when the dialogue and attitudes used for taking customer orders becomes scripted
and when waiters and waitresses are asked by management to select a dozen pins and buttons to wear
at work to exhibit flair.
22
Lewis, Fast FoodWomen.
288 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
23
Murphy, Moral Economy of Labor,2.
24
Murphy, Moral Economy of Labor, 4.According to recent empirical studies on income and hap-
piness, in the contemporary United States $75,000 is the level of income above which increases in
income cease to correlate with increased experiences of happiness. Below $75,000 (which is still quite
high relative to what many workers earn), a lack of money brings both emotional misery and low life
evaluation, according to Princeton University professors Angus Deaton and Daniel Kahneman. See D.
Kahneman and A. Deaton, High Income Improves Evaluation of Life but not Well-Being, Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 107:39:1648916493.
25
Arthur Kornhauser, Mental Health of the Industrial Worker:ADetroit Study (NewYork:John
Wiley & Sons, 1965)269.
26
As characterized by M. J. Zickar, Remembering Arthur Kornhauser: Industrial Psychologys
Advocate for Worker Well-Being, Journal of Applied Psychology 88:2: 363369; M. Tausig and R.
Fenwick, Mental Health in Social Context (NewYork:Springer, 2011),3.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 289
27
Kornhauser, Mental Health of the Industrial Worker, 252, 269270.
28
Kornhauser, Mental Health of the Industrial Worker, 266268.
29
Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society, Journal of Social Philosophy 29:1 (Spring
1998):82.
30
As Kornhauser, Mental Health of the Industrial Worker, writes, Many interrelated characteris-
tics of jobs contribute jointly to the comparatively high or low average mental health of occupational
groups.... By far the most influential attribute is the opportunity the work offersor fails to offerfor
use of the workers abilities and for associated feelings of interest, sense of accomplishment, personal
growth and self-respect(263).
290 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
31
Melvin Kohn and Carmi Schooler, Work and Personality (Norwood, NJ:Ablex Publishing, 1983),
esp.103.
32
Kohn and Schooler, Work and Personality, 33. Rather than using the term autonomous agency,
Kohn and Schooler use the concept of self-direction, looking at occupational self-direction in relation
to several facets of workers personalities and social positions. Although the central concepts and topics
of Kohn and Schoolers work do not fit squarely into the philosophical literature on autonomy, Ibelieve
there is enough conceptual overlap that the work of Kohn and Schooler bears relevance to certain ques-
tions that concern philosophers of autonomy.
33
Adina Schwartz, Meaningful Work, Ethics 92 (1982):634. Iam indebted to Schwartz partic-
ularly for her work in drawing together a case that work bears a formative influence on the worker.
As I discuss at length in my book on meaningful work, however, I disagree with Schwartz on the
role that the state should play in creating opportunities for meaningful work. Schwartz argues that we
should ask for government measures to effect rearrangements in industrial employment and to enforce
a moral imperative that no one should be employed in purely routine occupations that stunt autono-
mous development. See, e.g., Schwartz, Meaningful Work, 645. In contrast, Iargue that the formative
thesis need not entail that we call upon the state to minimize meaningless work or promote meaningful
work, and Iexamine other ways social institutions can promote meaningfulwork.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 291
34
Beate Roessler, Meaningful Work:Arguments from Autonomy, Journal of Political Philosophy
20:1 (2012):82.
35
Roessler, Meaningful Work,83.
36
Richard Lippke, Work, Privacy and Autonomy, Public Affairs Quarterly 3:2 (April 1989):44.
37
Lippke, Work, Privacy and Autonomy,43.
38
John Rawls, Political Liberalism, paperback edition (NewYork:Columbia University Press, 1996),
lix. Rawls repeats the idea in Law of the Peoples (Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press, 1999),
50. See also Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press, 1971), 440ff. On
the importance of self-respect and self-worth for autonomy, see, e.g., Paul Benson, Free Agency and
292 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
and, in particular, from the judgments of our associates concerning the worth
of our activities: unless our endeavors are appreciated by our associates it
is impossible for us to maintain the conviction that they are worthwhile.39
Although in A Theory of Justice Rawls suggests that nonworking social life can
provide social esteem for worthy endeavors, in turn providing a social basis
of self-respect,40 he shifts in The Law of the Peoples and in the introduction
to the paperback edition of Political Liberalism to suggest that, in particular,
opportunities for meaningful work are needed to provide a social basis for
citizens self-respect. As Jeffrey Moriarty interprets this shift, Rawls comes to
reject an assumption at play in A Theory of Justice that meaningful work pro-
vides but one avenue for a social basis of self-respect, which presumably could
be achieved in leisure activities for those whose work fails to provide a sense
of self-worth; at the time of his later works Rawls instead believes that we
cannot merely hope that if people cannot find meaningful work, they can get
self-respect from other activities, such as chess or softball.41
To be sure, work is not the only avenue by which a person can achieve
self-respect, enjoy the exercise of realized capacities, or experience autono-
mous self-expression. It is possible that some people may acquire these basic
goods in leisure activities, although the empirical literature indicates that such
a possibility is slim:people tend to apply the habit developed at work to their
leisure: mindless work leads to mindless leisure whereas challenging work
leads to challenging leisure.42 But in any case a mere possibility that a person
can live a richly autonomous life without eudemonistically meaningful work
is hardly sufficient ground for an argument concerning questions of work and
social justice, which beckon us to consider what social structures are likely
to produce or encourage in human persons. The possibilityadvanced by
Whitethat rich self-centered fainants can live autonomously and find per-
sonal fulfillment in a round of leisure activities avails very little in my mind.43
Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994):650668; Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth, Autonomy,
Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice, in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays,
edited by John Christman and Joel Anderson (NewYork:Cambridge University Press,2005).
39
Rawls, Theory of Justice, 440, cf.544.
40
Rawls, Theory of Justice,442.
41
Moriarty, Rawls, Self-Respect, and the Opportunity for Meaningful Work, Social Theory and
Practice 35:3 (July 2009):450.
42
Murphy, Moral Economy of Labor, 4. Likewise, Kornhauser, Mental Health of the Industrial
Autoworker, 267, notes that the leisure activities of factory workers in routine jobs tend to be narrow
and routine, with little indication of self-development and self-expression or devotion to larger social
purposes:many appear to be groping for meaningful ways to fill their spare time but with little con-
ception of the possibilities and with inadequate preparation or stimulation.
43
White, Education, Work and Well-being, 241. On the whole, White advances an argument
against writers like myself that autonomously chosen work is not a central element of the good life;
he believes the possibility of living well without autonomous work should be reflected in social policy,
which should encourage a wide variety of ways of life in which autonomous work mightor might
notfind a place(241).
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 293
44
An integral connection between work and self-respect is argued for in a number of empirical
and philosophical literatures. Moriarty, Rawls, Self-Respect, and the Opportunity for Meaningful
Work, 457n30, compiles a helpful list of literatures.
45
Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice:ADefense of Pluralism and Equality (NewYork:Basil Blackwell,
1983), 165. Walzer is here giving a point made by Stewart E. Perry, San Francisco Scavengers:Dirty Work
and the Pride of Ownership (Berkeley:University of California Press, 1978),7.
46
For but one example, consider the words of a former McDonalds griddle man interviewed in
Barbara Garson, The Electronic Sweatshop (NewYork:Simon and Schuster, 1988), 17, 20:They called
us the Green Machine, says Jason Pratt, recently retired McDonalds griddle man, cause the crew
had green uniforms then. And thats what it is, a machine. You dont have to know how to cook, you
dont have to know how to think. Theres a procedure for everything and you just follow the proce-
dures.... You follow the beepers, you follow the buzzers and you turn your meat as fast as you can. Its
like Itold you, to work at McDonalds you dont need a face, you dont need a brain. You need to have
two hands and two legs and move em as fast as you can. Thats the whole system. Iwouldnt go back
there again for anything. For a classic critique of dehumanizing aspects of automated and unskilled
work in the twentieth century, see Harry Braverman, Labor and Monopoly Capital, 25th anniv. ed.
(NewYork:Monthly Review Press,1998).
294 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Some readers will see this point as Marxist since Marx critiques industrial
forms of work as mutilating human persons into fragments and calls on the po-
tential of work to offer a person an objectification of his individual humanness
in the world. But the previous point would be better catalogued as a Kantian
critique of Taylorism, and it is important to observe that the basic idea that work
bereft of individual agency dehumanizes the person derives from a variety of
intellectual traditions,47 and one does not need to be schooled in Marxism to
appreciate it. When Studs Terkel interviewed workers for his tome Working, he
compiled a collection of experiences of dehumanization in jobs that diminish or
restrict the potential of workers to conceive, plan, imagine, solve problems, or
otherwise think creatively or constructively or move about freely atwork:
Im a machine, says the spot-welder. Im caged, says the bank teller, and
echoes the hotel clerk. Im a mule, says the steelworker. A monkey can do
what Ido, says the receptionist. Im less than a farm implement, says the
migrant worker. Im an object, says the high fashion model. Blue collar and
white call upon the identical phrase:Im a robot.48
I would argue that what is fundamentally at play here is not merely that work-
ers are discontented, as Terkel himself suggests, but rather also that as a human
activity working has a basic ambiguity of agency and utility, insofar as work
simultaneously allows one to conceive and carry out projects, thus exercis-
ing agency, as well as to feel useful in serving needs and desires, thus exer-
cising utility. When elements of human agency and freedom are taken from
work, work degenerates from a meaningful experience of feeling oneself useful
through an engagement of ones mind or body in the world, into an experience
of feeling like a cog in a machine, or like a robot, an animal, or an implement.
Work can feel meaningless for several reasonsincluding a futile outcome,
an apparent lack of purpose, or a failure to engage an individuals talents, intel-
lectual capabilities, or artisan skillsbut among the several facets of mean-
ingless work, dehumanization and degradation stand out in undermining a
meaningful experience of work. This dehumanization issues partly from a pro-
liferation of automation in working life, which requires not that an employee
act as a person exercising human capabilities but only that she use her voice,
her hands, or her legs, as determined by a system.49 But dehumanization and
47
Consider the arguments of Adriano Tilgher, Homo Faber:Work through the Ages (Chicago:Henry
Regnery Company, 1930); Schumacher, Good Work; or Pope John Paul II, Laboren exercens, Encyclical
Letter, 1981.09.14.
48
Studs Terkel, Working:People Talk about What They Do All Day and How They Feel about What
They Do (NewYork:W.W. Norton & Company, 2004 [1972]), xixii.
49
Even as automation creates jobs that are hardly set up for the exercise of individual worker in-
genuity, pockets of ingenuity, creativity, and accomplishment can nevertheless emerge even in the con-
text of performing automated work. Factory workers interviewed in Barbara Garson, All the Livelong
Day:The Meaning and Demeaning of Routine Work (Garden City, NY:Doubleday, 1975), ixxvi, report
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 295
on varied creative maneuvers they intersperse throughout the workday to achieve moments of inge-
nuity and feelings of purposefulness and fulfillment, such as allowing work to pile up to experience a
few minutes of purposeful exertion in catching up, which creates opportunities for minor goals and
fulfillments. But upsurges of worker creativity and purposeful exertion amid conditions of speed,
heat, humiliation, [and] monotony likely demonstrates not that working on an assembly line pro-
vides meaning or fulfillment but, rather, that the human need for exercising agency, for reaching goals,
for displaying some measure of individuality, and for feeling that one accomplishes a task creatively
are basic enough in human well-being that workers find opportunities for these needs even on an
assemblyline.
50
As in the job of a washroom attendant, whose function is to wait on people in restrooms and
to dispense towels and toiletries. One washroom attendant employed for fifteen years at the Chicago
Palmer House, Louis Hayward, describes the physical work of waiting on men in restrooms as an
automatic thing....It doesnt require any thought. Its almost a reflex action. Iset my toilet articles up,
towelsand Im ready. Terkel, Working, 106. In its social function, he believes his work serves to bol-
ster the egos of bathroom visitors:when a man visits the restroom and receives an acknowledgment
from the attendant, it builds his ego up a little bit.... Im building him up(107).
51
The point is suggested by Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice, 165, who writes of jobs that are hard
in the sense of being harsh, unpleasant, cruel, difficult to endure that they are like prison sentences
296 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
in that people do not look for them and would not choose them if they face minimally attractive
alternatives:This kind of work is a negative good, and it commonly carries other negative goods in its
train:poverty, insecurity, ill health, physical danger, dishonor and degradation. And yet it is socially
necessary work; it needs to be done, and that means someone must be found to doit.
52
Gomberg, How to Make Opportunity Equal,23.
53
Gomberg, How to Make Opportunity Equal,2324.
54
As in the widely used ethics textbook James Rachels and Stuart Rachels, The Elements of Moral
Philosophy, 7th ed. (NewYork:McGraw-Hill, 2012), 138139.
55
For a discourse on the intelligence and agency required for nonroutinized manual work, see
Matthew Crawford, Shop Class as Soulcraft: An Inquiry into the Value of Work (New York: Penguin
Press, 2009); Mike Rose, The Mind at Work: Valuing the Intelligence of the American Worker
(NewYork:Penguin Books, 2004). For Crawford, the satisfactions of useful work accrue particularly
to skilled practitioners of manual arts, like carpentry, plumbing, and motorcycle and car repair. Since
these forms of work are necessarily situated in a particular context, they are inherently resistant to
forms of external managerial or corporate control that undermine human agency and make work
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 297
employment, not all exercise agency in employment, and not all are equally
exploited. And focusing on an exercise of autonomous agency in an initial
choice of employment obscures ways work can itself undermine or enhance
autonomous agency.
To be clear then, it is not the fact of being utilized as an instrument of pro-
duction that is itself at issue. Being instrumental in producing, serving, creat-
ing, and fabricating lies in the nature of workinga fact also revealed through
meditation on the meaning of employmentwherein one often finds satisfac-
tion in making oneself useful, being purposeful, or being a means of achieving
something of value. Rather, it is being used extensively as a tool, an implement,
an object or a body, wherein a person is not also simultaneously expressing
agency, which is dehumanizing. It is also dehumanizing to be treated as an ex-
pendable resource or to toil in a system as a nonthinking tool of production for
several hours a day, which after time damages the body and mind and depletes
intelligence and other human capabilities. When the working day is limited
and one has opportunities to flourish outside of eudemonistically meaningless
work, perhaps being a tool of production at work need not be felt as altogether
dehumanizing. However, there are some for whom oppressive work effectively
predominates life, as when one labors at eudemonistically meaningless work
for sixteen hours a day, whether at one job or two, and here a person is likely to
feel depleted of humanity or human vitality, and effectively transformed into a
means for others. Oppression at work clearly comes in degrees.
It is also interesting to consider, as Imentioned above, that some interpret-
ers of Kant argue that in giving an imperative to treat humanity as an end
an never as a mere means, Kant himself lays emphasis on respecting the hu-
manity in persons, that is, on respecting the rational and autonomous abilities
within persons. Thomas Hill observes Kant repeating that respecting people
as ends requires treating the humanity in a person as an end and never as
a mere means.56 The familiar dictum of treating persons as ends represents
an abbreviation of treating humanity in persons as ends, Hill argues, and for
Kant humanity represents a characteristic of persons, whose distinguishing
features include the rational capabilities of setting ends and forming goals. In
interpreting the principle of humanity formulation of the categorical impera-
tive, Allen Wood also writes that the basic issue for Kant is that we disrespect
vulnerable to dehumanization and degradation. Building and fixing are embedded in a community
in which the individual worker remains responsible for his or her own work and in which excellence
at work comes with the exercise of judgment, the making of a social contribution, the feeling of pride
in ones work, and the transformation of objective reality by ones own hands. Nonroutinized manual
work demands intelligence; the physical circumstances of the jobs performed by carpenters, plumbers
and auto mechanics vary too much for them to be executed by idiots. One feels like a [person], not like
a cog in a machine (5253).
56
Hill, Dignity and Practical Reason, 3846,10.
298 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
humanity in placing things of lesser value ahead of our rational nature, which
constitutes our humanity and which is an end in itself.57
What would it require of a human community to treat the humanity in a
person as an end? In the context of work, it would entail that a goal of work be
the development or exercise of the rational, autonomous, and agential capa-
bilities of a person and that diminishing these gifts as a means for achieving
economic values of profit or productivity or increasing efficiency is outside
moral bounds. That is, the full realization of a moral imperative to treat the
humanity in a person as a end would entail a revolution in modern economic
life, which as presently structured often demands not that work serve the end
of developing and exercising human capabilities but that the worker adapt
himself to the needs of the workwhich means, of course, primarily to the
needs of the machine.58 It may be hard to fathom such a moral departure from
present economic realities. But, as we know, implementing the categorical im-
perative can entail such radical transformations in human practices that, in a
specific historical moment in which people are enveloped and enculturated
in immoralities, meeting moral demands can appear bewilderingly near im-
possible. As Wood writes, the formula of using humanity as an end and never
only as a means is rather like the Sermon on the Mount...whose demands
require such a radical departure from our customary practices and accepted
attitudes toward ourselves and others that we are at first perplexed when we
try to apply them.59
Some may see this call for ethical transformation in economic life as simply
tantamount to rejecting capitalism and calling for communism or Marxism
in its stead. In response, Inote that Marx provides one rich source of criti-
cism of meaningless work in capitalist economies, but pigeonholing criticism
of meaningless work as Marxist overlooks a few facts. First, it overlooks the
convergence of a plurality of philosophical and religious traditions around the
importance of work in realizing part of the human good. Second, this pigeon-
holing overlooks the possibility for meaningful work in the context of capi-
talist employment relationships. The question of whether capitalism contains
an inherent proclivity toward depriving people of autonomous agency depends
partly on the ethical values paired with it and partly on whether the pursuit
of profitability, productivity and efficiency is pure and unbridled, or limited
and tempered by a respect for autonomy and other human values. Third, iden-
tifying meaningful work with communism overlooks the variegated realities
of alienated labor under communist conditions: as James Bernard Murphy
observes, in both capitalism and in communism the worker is often treated
as a mere instrument, a factor of production, rather than as the subject of his
57
Allen Wood, Kants Ethical Thought (NewYork:Cambridge University Press, 1999),143.
58
Schumacher, Good Work,3.
59
Wood, Kants Ethical Thought,139.
Autonomy and Oppression atWork 299
or her work.... When Charlie Chaplin satirized the mindless monotony of the
assembly line in Modern Times (1936), he was denounced in the United States
as an enemy of capitalism and in Russia as an enemy of socialismand in a
sense he was guilty on both counts.60 In essence, promoting modes of working
life that provide opportunities for people to flourish reaches beyond tradi-
tional bifurcations between capitalism and communism, implanting ethics at
the seat of economic life and requiring respect for the exercise of agency in
workinglife.
If it is bewildering to imagine economics structured around a goal of
human development, I think it is also edifying to consider the bounds of
moral progress that workplaces have already achieved in some quarters of
the world in the twenty-first century. Consider, for instance, that it is now
commonplace to maintain as workplace idealsand to instantiate in practice
in varying measuresrational and fair hiring processes, nondiscriminatory
and harassment-free workplace environments, equitable wages and freedom
from threats, and abuse and profanity while on the job. According to histo-
rian Stanford Jacoby, not one of these ideals was in place in the United States
over a century ago, when the dominant mode of the production of commodi-
ties was the factory system, in which foremen used close supervision, abuse,
profanity, and threats to motivate faster and harder work and in which work
was highly insecure, very poorly paid, fraught with pay inequities and ethnic
discrimination, and not uncommonly secured through nepotism, favoritism,
and bribery.61 Some of us live in a workplace utopia in comparison with the
factories of the late 1800s, at which time it would have been difficult to see
possibilities for the sort of change that is now a becoming reality, and it should
not therefore be said in thinking about working life as we know it that work
just is what it is. Appreciating moral progress in working life highlights abili-
ties of human communities to transcend and reinvent workplace structures
and leads us toward a position of open-mindedness in entertaining long-range
60
Murphy, Moral Economy of Labor, 34. The prologue to Murphy, Moral Economy of Labor pro-
vides important clarification on the relationship between Taylorism and communism. Murphy notes,
for instance, that the detailed fragmentation of skilled labor into monotonous routine that once sym-
bolized the horrors of capitalism became the basis of Soviet industry from Vladimir Lenin through
Leonid Brezhnev. Indeed, Taylorism was more pervasive in Soviet Russia than it ever was in the United
States (3). Further, Murphy observes that the similar quality of the experience of work for the worker
in both capitalist and socialist systems leads apologists for both systems to emphasize distribution
and exchange rather than the dignity of work. For example, one leading Marxist theoretician, John
Roemer, says that if we were to focus on the labor process we would be forced to the bizarre conclusion
that socialist countries exploit workers just as much as do capitalist countries (3). See also Braverman,
Labor and Monopoly Capital.
61
Jacoby The Way It Was: Factory Labor before 1915, in Employing Bureaucracy: Managers,
Unions, and the Transformation of Work in the 20th Century, rev. ed. (NewYork:Columbia University
Press,2004).
300 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
I would especially like to thank Mark Piper and Erin Tarver for helpful com-
ments on an earlier draft of this paper. This paper has also been enriched
by discussions at the Relational Autonomy Workshop organized by Natalie
Stoljar and Catriona Mackenzie, held in Montreal in September 2012, and at
the conference on Work and Human Development organized by Nick Smith
and Jean-Philippe Deranty, held in Sydney in September2011.
62
Veltman, Meaningful Work, manuscript.
{14}
1.Introduction
1
Laurence H. Tribe, Abortion: The Clash of Absolutes (New York: W.W. Norton & Company,
1992),104.
2
According to the Guttmacher Institute, 3 percent of unmarried white women gave up their
babies for adoption from 1982 to 1988; fewer than 2percent of unmarried black women gave up their
babies for adoption during this time and earlier; and none of Hispanic women in the sample reported
giving up their babies for adoption. Tamar Lewin, Fewer Children Up for Adoption, Study Finds,
New York Times, February 27, 1992, http://www.nytimes.com/1992/02/27/US/fewer-children-up-
for-adoption-study-finds.html.
3
The Campaign to Outlaw Abortion, New York Times, March 29, 2013, http://www.nytimes.
com/2013/03/30/opinion/the-campaign-to-outlaw.abortion.html?hp&_r=18.
302 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Dalrymple signed a bill that bans abortions based solely on genetic abnormalities
or on the gender of the fetus.4 Personhood bills, which would extend legal protec-
tion to zygotes, have been introduced in Oklahoma and Mississippi. In Kansas,
Republican governor Sam Brownbeck indicated that he would sign virtually any
measure declaring that life begins at fertilization, and then he signed a person-
hood bill.5 An abortion rights advocacy group, the Guttmacher Institute, which
classifies states as hostile, middle ground, or supportive of abortion rights, reports
that in the southern United States while only a handful of states were classified
in 2000 as hostile there is now a solid wall of hostility, from Virginia down to
Florida and over to Texas and Oklahoma.6
Despite the power of Tribes argument, if we argue in favor of abortion rights
on the grounds he suggests alone, then it will be difficult to address the National
Center for Men, for instance, which believes that men are entitled to some say
over decisions that profoundly affect their livesnamely, the freedom to choose
to be a father. In a 2007 court case, Dubay v.Wells, the Center backed Matthew
Dubay, who sued his girlfriend after she became pregnant when the two had sex.
Prior to the pregnancy, Dubay told her that he was not ready to have children,
and she said that was fine, since she was infertile and using birth control just in
case. When she discovered that she was pregnant, she wasnt willing to have an
abortion. After giving birth to a girl in 2005, she obtained a court order requir-
ing Dubay to pay $500 a month in child support. Dubays lawsuit contended that
men have a constitutional right to avoid procreation. Mel Feit, the Centers di-
rector, said, Theres such a spectrum of choice that women haveits her body,
her pregnancy. Im trying to find a way for a man also to have some say over
decisions that affect his life profoundly.7 This Michigan case was called the Roe
v.Wade for men. Although it was a case about whether child support laws vio-
late Equal Protection by applying only to men, conservatives hoped to seize on
it to gain control over abortion in both directions and to overturn Roe v.Wade.
As things turned out, the judge dismissed the case in 2006. The National Center
for Men appealed, but the appeals court said that the 14th Amendment does not
deny the State the power to treat different classes of persons in different ways.8
4
Dave Thompson, North Dakota Governor Signs Heartbeat Abortion Ban, Chicago Tribune, March
26, 2013, http://articles.chicagotribune.com/2013-03-26/news/sns-rt-us-usa-abortion-northdakota.
bre92pOua-20130326_1_heartbeat-bill-supporters-of-abortion-rights-restrictive-abortion-law.
5
DeAnn Smith and Stephen Mayer, Kansas Lawmakers Could Vote Friday on Tough
Anti-abortion Bill, April 5, 2013, http://www.kctv5.com/story/21891968/Kansas-lawmakers-could-v
ote-Friday-on-tough-anti-abortion-bill.html. The bill states that life begins at fertilization and bans
sex-selection abortion and was signed on April 5, 2013 (CBS EveningNews).
6
Abortion Laws in the South:Cutting away at Roe v.Wade, March 16, 2013, Economist http:www.
economist.com/news/United-States/21573594-rest-south-not-far-behind-strict-new-law-arkansas
-cutting-away-roe-v.
7
Judith Graham, Unwilling Father Tests Mens Rights, Chicago Tribune, March 10,2006.
8
Dubay v.Wells, 506 F.3d 422 (6th Cir.; 2007); Wikipedia, Dubay v.Wells, 506 F.3d 422 (6h Cir.;
2007), http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Dubay_v._Wells.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 303
Ironically, this case for so-called mens rights is not one prohibiting womens
right to abortion but enforcing abortion when the father does not want children.
Whatever the motive, and even though the lawsuit failed, the case makes clear
the feminist objection that the state, through its institutions and practices, uses
womens bodies as vessels for its own or mensends.
Significantly, this case makes it very clear, or so Ishall argue, that the right
to bodily autonomy must be central in any argument for abortion rights. Tribe
himself makes a great deal about bodily autonomy. But he seems to lean in
the direction of nonliberal, or less individualistic, feminists, who advocate the
centrality of motherhood, and away from liberal feminists, who advocate the
centrality of bodily autonomy and other individualistic values.9 One advantage
of the nonliberal feminist view is that if parenthood is the supreme value, then
a woman has a right to decide whether she is to become a parent even if her
doing so does not involve her body in any significant way. Any argument about
abortion rights would apply equally to in vitro development of a child as well
as to the mothers rights over the child once it is born. But if bodily autonomy
is the supreme value, then we will need a separate argument about a mothers
right over the fetus in such cases. The key issue in the standard case of fetal
development is the mothers rights over the fetus when the fetus is in her body.
If we leave bodily autonomy out of, or make it secondary in, our arguments
about abortion, we jeopardize its significance in arguments about rape, sexual
harassment, female genital mutilation, woman battering, and fetal harm cases.
Yet a significant part of our analysis of why these behaviors are wrong is that
they deny womens bodily autonomy. It is important, then, for feminists to
supplement the argument about the right to become or not to become a parent
with an argument about the right to bodily autonomy.
Interestingly, if supporters of the prolife10 or antichoice position really
do oppose enforced abortion, Dubay v.Wells should force them to examine
9
According to Martha Nussbaum, Feminist Critique of Liberalism, in Sex and Social Justice,
edited by Nussbaum (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 1999), personhood, autonomy, rights, dig-
nity, and self-respect are the terms of the liberal Enlightenment (56). One of the charges cited by
Nussbaum and made by feminist against the liberal tradition is that it is too individualistic in fo-
cusing too much on the dignity and worth of the individual and thereby diminishing the value of
community and social entities such as families, groups, and classes (56, 58, 59). Nussbaum defends
liberalism against this charge, arguing that the separateness of persons is a basic fact of human life
(62), and is at the root of making the individual the basic unit for political thought:each person has a
course from birth to death that is not precisely the same as that of any other person.... Each person is
one and not more than one....Each feels pain in his or her own body....(62).
10
Iput this term in quotes because most people who claim to be prolife about abortion are not
prolife about other issues. Only 11percent of Americans hold a consistent ethic of life position, op-
posing legalized abortion and capital punishment, for example. Seventy-nine percent of prolife
Republicans and 85percent of prolife Tea Party identifiers who say abortion should be illegal in all or
most cases also support the death penalty. See Robert P. Jones, Like Perry, Most Pro-Life Americans
OK with Death Penalty, Washington Post, September 15, 2011, https://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/
figuring-faith/post/like-rich-perry-most-pro-life-americans-ok-with-death-penality/2011/09/15/
304 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
whether it is just the abortion part that they oppose (which makes this case no
different from that of a woman willingly undergoing an abortion) or whether
their opposition is also to the use of womens bodies in this way (which means
that they actually do see the value of the right to bodily autonomy and that
to be consistent they should acknowledge it in other cases as well). Tribe and
many other feminists believe that the prolife position is really about control-
ling women and about race,11 not about the rights of fetuses, since its advocates
are more stirred up when women gain advances in society, or when women
voluntarily have sex (i.e., are guilty) and contraception fails,12 and so on, or
when more white women than black women have abortions.13 This is because
the prolife position is inconsistent on its position on the value of fetal life.14
What does it mean to say that someone has a right to bodily autonomy?
What does this right consist in, and when does it trump other rights in con-
flict cases? These are difficult questions to answer, and in this paper I hope
only to tease out a bit what this right might amount to, by taking as my starting
point an account offered by Judith Jarvis Thomson in her famous article on
abortion.15
It is noteworthy that standard accounts of personal autonomy or autonomy
of the will tend to leave out discussion of the body and focus instead on condi-
tions that are necessary and/or sufficient for self-determination. Sarah Buss
gIQA06XUIX=blog.html. The data come from the Millenials, Religion, and Abortion Survey conducted
between April 22 and May 8, 2011, using a random sample of three thousand adults.
11
In Nazi Germany, the Third Reich banned the production and distribution of contraceptives in
1941. By 1943 the penalty for performing an abortion on a woman who was genetically fit was death.
But by 1938, Jews were defined as falling in the category of being genetically defective, and the state
readily granted abortions for women in this group. See Tribe, Abortion,5960.
12
Tribe, Abortion, notes that some people believe that while abortion should be allowed in cases of
rape, it should not be in cases of contraceptive failure because the woman volunteered in the sense
that she chose to have sex and run the risk of pregnancy. He finds it curious that there is not a wide-
spread sentiment among those who generally oppose abortion rights that abortion should be allowed
in cases of contraceptive failure, since taking contraception means that the woman does not want to
be pregnant. Tribe asks, Does this not suggest that such opponents of abortion come to their views
about the immorality of abortion not in response to the voluntary nature of the womans pregnancy but
in response to the voluntary nature of the sexual activity in which she has engaged? And does this not
in turn suggest that such antiabortion views are driven less by the innocence of the fetus...than by the
supposed guilt of the woman?(132).
13
Tribe, Abortion, notes that in the 1800s there was an increase in abortion rates among mar-
ried, white, middle-class Protestant women and that by 1860 the birth rate among white Americans of
British and northern European descent declined significantly in comparison to new immigrants who
were predominantly Catholic. Physicians who supported abortion restrictions warned of race suicide,
and fear of this was more widespread than religious antiabortion sentiment(32).
14
Tribe, Abortion, 231, 232, 236237, notes that virulent opponents to abortion such as Randall
Terry, the originator of Operation Rescue, explicitly connect their opposition to abortion with their
desire to put women back in traditional roles. He notes that our society is inconsistent in its thinking
on fetuses and frozen embryos and on fetal development and childabuse.
15
Judith Jarvis Thomson, A Defense of Abortion, Philosophy & Public Affairs1:1 (Autumn
1971):4766.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 305
notes that most autonomy theories have in common the notion that autonomy
consists in the agents endorsing or identifying with her action.16 Much of the
current debate centers on the benefits and disadvantages of procedural and
substantive theories of autonomy. Yet these theoretical debates emphasize the
will, not the body. Discussions about bodily autonomy appear mostly, as one
might expect, in the medical ethics literature (e.g., on reproductive technolo-
gies, organ donation and sale, euthanasia, and abortion), but we can also find
them in feminist critiques of traditional autonomy theories (e.g., on deformed
desires or adaptive preferences) and the feminist literature on rape, woman
battering, and the like and how these acts stifle womens autonomy. In her
feminist critique of notions of bodily autonomy found in the medical ethics
literature, Catriona Mackenzie argues that this literature has overwhelmingly
supported what she calls the maximal choice view, which in essence amounts
to the view that autonomy reduces to choice, which is a matter of our sub-
jective preferences, no matter their content.17 This is an individualistic view
of autonomy, one that favors maximizing control over ones body and having
freedom to dispose of it as one chooses. This view, Iwould add, fits squarely
into traditional accounts of autonomy by incorporating the body in terms of
the agents preferences and desires. Bodily autonomy, then, can be viewed as
an extension of autonomy of the will through satisfaction of preferences and
desires relating to thebody.
But this conception of bodily autonomy might not satisfy feminists, who
have critiqued traditional accounts of autonomy, and have developed what
has been called relational autonomy. Relational autonomy theories are distin-
guished by their focus on the autonomous agent, in particular, on the rich and
complex social and historical contexts in which the agent is embedded.18 They
aim to develop an account of autonomy that is characteristic of agents who are
emotional, embodied, desiring, creative, and feeling, as well as rational crea-
tures.19 Along these lines, Mackenzie develops an account of bodily autonomy
that espouses the liberal and libertarian values found in the medical ethics lit-
erature yet grounds these values not in bodily ownership but in what she calls
ones bodily perspective. These values are (1) the right to noninterference
16
Sarah Buss, Autonomy Reconsidered, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1994): 95121; Peter
A. French, Theodore Ed. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein (eds.), Midwest Studies (Notre
Dame:University of Notre Dame Press, 1994),95.
17
Catriona Mackenzie, Conceptions of Autonomy and Conceptions of the Body in Bioethics, in
Feminist Bioethics:At the Center, On the Margins, Jackie Leach Scully, Laurel E. Baldwin-Ragaven, and
Petya Fitzpatrick, eds. (Baltimore, MD:Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010),7190.
18
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, Introduction: Autonomy Refigured, in Relational
Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, edited by Catriona
Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2000), 21. The workshop on re-
lational autonomy for which this paper was written was held to celebrate the ten-year anniversary of
this anthology.
19
Mackenzie and Stoljar, Introduction,21.
306 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
(the right to be free from intrusion on ones body without ones consent), and
(2)the right to bodily self-determination (the right to decide what happens
in and to your body, which, Mackenzie notes, cashes out as a right to deter-
mine what you can do with your bodyincluding sex selection, genetic en-
hancement, and organ salemore extensively, and she believes incorrectly, on
liberal and libertarian medical ethics accounts). Mackenzie, borrowing from
Paul Ricouer, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Kant, argues that it is because my
body is the medium through which Ilive my life that Imust have a right to de-
termine what happens in and to my body.20 Our consciousness is not separate
from our body; rather, we see the world from the perspective of our body.21
Iwould add two points. First, our bodies as much as our minds shape who
we areoften others react to us and treat us in certain ways because of some
feature of our bodies, including our perceived gender, ethnicity, and ableness
and whether we are obese or thin, attractive or unattractive, and so on, and we
see ourselves in terms of how others see us and react to us because we often
internalize social perceptions. Second, we come into the world and go out of it
with our body. Because your body is yours alone in the sense that only you in-
habit it,22 there is a way your life and your death are necessarily and inevitably
solitary events, no matter who surrounds you. Martha Nussbaum defends the
individualism of liberalism on the grounds of the necessary separatism of per-
sons and the fact that we each feel pain and pleasure in our own bodies only.
These preliminary points speak to the significance of the body for morality in
general and specifically for any full account of autonomy.
The account of the right to bodily autonomy that Idefend here is relational
in the sense that it is nuanced by feminist concerns. However, my starting point
in defending this right is Thomsons article, and many of us would characterize
her view of the right to bodily autonomy as falling squarely in the liberal or lib-
ertarian tradition that Mackenzie criticizes. Iactually do not think these views
are at odds with each otherindeed, liberalism/libertarianism and feminism
share a concern for the body that seems to come from the same place. When
many feminists discuss rape, woman battering, female genital mutilation, pre-
natal harm, and abortion, to name a few, they espouse a hands-off view that
might be defended with the libertarian assumption of self-ownership of the
body.23 The underlying view is that women are not fetal containers, nor do men
own womens bodies.
20
See Catriona Mackenzie, On Bodily Autonomy, in Handbook of Phenomenology and Medicine,
S.K. Toombs (ed.) (The Netherlands:Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001), 417439.
21
Mackenzie, Conceptions of Autonomy,8081.
22
Iam going to avoid discussing controversial personal identity theorieshere.
23
For a discussion of the libertarian principle of self-ownership, see, e.g., David Sobel, Backing
away from Libertarian Self-Ownership, Ethics 123 (October 2012):3260.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 307
24
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,54.
25
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,53.
26
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 53. Even though ownership of the body grounds a right to
defend ones body against things happening in and to it, Thomson argues elsewhere that a right to
self-defense is not absolute. For example, you cannot deflect a trolley heading toward you onto a by-
stander, nor can you shoot a bystander who will then fall on the trolley and stop it from killing you,
nor can you do something that results in a bystanders death to spare your own life. All of these acts
display a lack of respect for persons, treating them as if they were not there. Thomson, Self-Defense,
Philosophy & Public Affairs 20:4 (Autumn 1991):289, 291. It is beyond the scope of this paper for me to
argue when the right to bodily autonomy, as part of the right to self-defense, can be overridden.
27
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 52. Emphasisadded.
28
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,53.
308 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
And strictly speaking, Thomsons view in this paper is that you do not waive
the right to determine what happens in and to your body; rather, you just
let someone use your body for atime.
The right to bodily autonomy plays a pivotal role in Thomsons three
analogies about pregnancy, and she argues that in certain cases it trumps
other rights, including even the right to life. In the violinist analogy, which
compares enforced pregnancy resulting from rape to having to stay hooked
up to a violinist who is attached to you without your consent, the mothers
right to bodily autonomy overrides the right to life of the fetus. Because
pregnancy was the result of rape, in no sense did the mother give the fetus a
right to use her body. In the house analogy, which compares enforced preg-
nancy in cases where the mothers life is at stake to being trapped in a house
with a rapidly growing child who will crush you to death, the mothers right
to life overrides the fetus right to life because the mothers prior existence
and the fact that the fetus uses her body for its existence break the tie be-
tween the two innocent lives. The mothers prior existence and prior right
to her body is decisive in just the same way that ones owning property is
decisive over someone elses wanting it:an older brother who owns a box of
chocolates that he does not share with his younger brother has a prior claim
to them. In the people-seed analogy, which compares enforced pregnancy
in cases of contraceptive failure to having to allow the people-seed that takes
root in your upholstered furniture to develop in your house, the mothers
right to bodily autonomy overrides the fetus right to life even when the sex
is voluntary but when the mother has taken precautions against pregnancy.
Since she has done so, she does not give the fetus a right to use her body.
Thomson concludes that in cases of rape, the mothers life being at stake,
and contraceptive failure, abortion is morally permissible.
I find Thomsons analogies entirely persuasive, but I think that her re-
liance on the right to bodily autonomy allows her to draw even stronger
conclusions than she does. Here Iwant to focus on the following two cases
where Ithink that Thomsons conclusion is weaker than it need be:(1)the
woman whose pregnancy lasts only one hour and is the result of rape; and
(2)the woman who in her seventh month of pregnancy wants an abortion
so she wont have to postpone a trip. These cases are Thomsons own, but
Ibelieve that her conclusions about them are weaker than the ones she can
draw by invoking the same premise about the right to bodily autonomy.
Ibelieve that this right has more trumping power than Thomson defends.
Iuse these cases as a springboard for developing further the right to bodily
autonomy, though of course Icannot defend a full-fledged theory here. My
aim is to put forward and then offer some precursory defenses of some
principles about this right. Thomson herself does not defend this right but
merely appeals to it in her paper, though elsewhere she argues that it is one
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 309
29
See Judith Jarvis Thomson, Trespass and First Property, in The Realm of Rights (Cambridge,
MA:Harvard University Press, 1990), 205226.
30
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,60.
31
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,61.
310 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
pregnanciesthey say that its someones life, its no big deal to be pregnant
for nine months, most women are fine during pregnancy, so you ought to do
it. But consider what Thomson says in her Henry Fonda example, that if all
Ineed to save my life is for Henry Fonda to touch his cool hand on my fevered
brow, Ido not have a right against him that he fly in from the West Coast to
do this for me, though it would be frightfully nice of him to do so. But if all
he has to do is walk across the room and touch my fevered brow, then it would
be indecent of him to refuse.32 Why would the mothers refusing to carry a
fetus to term, even for an hour, when it is the result of rape, be self-centered,
callous, and indecent, when Henry Fondas refusing to hop on a plane and
cross the country to touch my fevered brow not be indecentin fact, it would
be frightfully nice of him to do so? Surely carrying a fetus that is the result
of rape even for one hour is much more onerous than flying across country.
As Margaret Little perceptively argues, forced gestation is an evil of unwanted
occupation, or an invasion of the self, which is neither reducible to the evil of
medical risks of pregnancy nor merely a different way of talking about the evil
of interference with the mothers plans.33 Pregnancy, whether or not it is the
result of rape, involves a sharing of ones very body, heart, and soul, whose sac-
rifices are measured not in degrees of risk but in degrees of intertwinement.34
No such intimacy is involved in the Henry Fonda case, and forced intimacy
is obviously not something it is indecent to reject. My first principle about
bodily autonomy is this:You shouldnt be required to do anything with your
body when the prior act that put you in the position you are in was against
your will. Iwant to support this principle with a Kantian analysis of respect
and degradation.
As is familiar, Kant believed that all rational, autonomous beings possess
dignity and are deserving of respect, which for Kant means that they are to
be treated as ends in themselves and never merely as means to an end.35 Our
rationality, or better, our capacity for rationality, is what makes us persons and
distinguishes us from inanimate objects and nonhuman animals. Our capacity
for rationality is marked by the fact that we have the ability to make plans
and have goals, interests, and reflective desires. We ought to respect these in
other rational beings by, for example, not putting our own interests and re-
flective desires ahead of those of others (e.g., by not aiding the needy when
we are able to), or discounting the plans of others (e.g., by falsely promising
to repay borrowed money and not letting the lender decide whether to give
32
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,61.
33
Margaret Olivia Little, Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate, Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice 2 (1999):304.
34
Little, Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate, 305. Little rightly notes that her view is
noticeably absent from the philosophical literature and urges the development of an ethic of intimacy.
35
Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by James W. Ellington
(Indianapolis:Hackett, 1981 [1785]), 36, AKA 428429.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 311
it to you in the first place), and the like. In virtue of our humanity, we ought
to respect each person as a potential co-legislator of morality and engage in
conduct only on which we could expect all reasonable people to agree. To do
otherwise is to make an exception for yourself by treating another rational
being as a mere means to your ends, behavior to which another would not au-
tonomously consent.
Lets apply this analysis first to rape and then to enforced pregnancy.
Acommon feminist analysis of rape explains rape as an act in which the rapist
attempts to degrade his victim by considering her to be an inferior being,
merely an object to be used for mens sexual pleasure or control.36 According
to Jean Hampton, rape conveys the attitude that women are even lower than
chattel; they are mere objects that are there to be used whenever the male feels
the need to do so but not beings with the capacity for rationality who ought
to be respected as ends in themselves. Hampton classifies rape as a moral in-
jury, which she defines as damage to the realization of a victims value through
behavior that diminishes, or, attempts to lower, the victims value.37 She agrees
with Kant that a persons intrinsic value, the value she has as a person, cannot
actually be lowered or degraded or for that matter raisedwe are equal in
virtue of our humanity, as ends in ourselves.38 Rape is morally injurious not
just to its direct victim but to all women. This is because rape sends the mes-
sage to all women, that they are the kind of human beings who are subject to
the mastery of people of the rapists kind, namely, men.39 Rape thus diminishes
all womensvalue.
One way to parse this analysis of rape is along the lines of an individual
account of autonomy. Kant ties respect for persons to their capacity for ra-
tionality and not anything bodily, but the body might factor in in terms of a
persons having interests or reflective desires (e.g., not mere bodily appetites,
but desires about whether to eat or drink and for which reason) relating to her
body that are indicative of the capacity for rationality. Because rape is an act
against a persons will, it disrespects her desires or interests having to do with
36
See Jean Hampton, Defining Wrong and Defining Rape, in A Most Detestable Crime, edited by
Keith Burgess-Jackson (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 1999), 118156; Susan Griffin, Rape:The
All-American Crime, in Feminism and Philosophy, edited by Mary Vetterling-Braggin, Frederick A.
Elliston, and Jane English (Totowa, NJ:Littlefield, Adams, 1981), 313332. Griffin says that rape is an
act of aggression in which the victim is denied her self-determination and is a form of mass terrorism
because the victims are chosen indiscriminately. See also Catharine MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist
Theory of the State (Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press, 1989), esp. chap.9; MacKinnon, Desire
and Power, in Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law, edited by Catharine MacKinnon
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987). MacKinnon says that men have been knowers;
mind; women have been to-be-known, matter, that which is to be controlled and subdued, the acted
upon(55).
37
Hampton, Defining Wrong and Defining Rape,132.
38
Hampton, Defining Wrong and Defining Rape,127.
39
Hampton, Defining Wrong and Defining Rape,135.
312 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
how her body is treated, specifically, her desires and interests about whether to
have sex, with whom, and under which conditions.
Alternatively, we might parse this account of rape along the lines of a rela-
tional autonomy and make the Kantian case stronger, for it is not just interests
you have regarding your body that are at stake, but bodily integrity. Iwant to
suggest that all of your interests are interests of you as a personyour interests
attach to youand your person is housed in your body.40 This is why you have
bodily integrity. Rape is not just an act of ignoring or discounting or thwarting
your interests about your body; rather, it is a violation of your very person,
through your body, and as such it is a violation of your bodily integrity. This
analysis explains in a better way than the earlier one why rape is an act against
your will, specifically, using your body against your will. Rape is not just an act
that goes against an interest you have regarding how your body is treated, but
it is about how your whole person is treated.41 It sends a message not just that
a certain interest you have does not count but that you are the kind of being
whose interestsany and all of themdo not count. This analysis allows for a
deeper sense of the account of rape being against yourwill.
Rape is a violation of the right to bodily autonomy in a way that attempts to
degrade its victim. It seems that if rape attempts to turn a woman into an in-
ferior beingnothing more than a body or body part or sex object to be used
for mens pleasure or controlthen a womans right to bodily autonomy, if it
means anything, allows her to affirm, through the right to abortion, that she is
not such a being. It allows her to affirm what someone has attempted to take
away from her. When someone uses your body against your will, he treats you
as not being a member of humanity. Enforced pregnancy, some feminists have
argued, treats women as if they were mere fetal containers, not full-fledged
members of humanity.42 If the woman does not want to carry to term a fetus
resulting from rape, then she should not be required or deemed indecent if
she does not subject her body to this intrusion against her will. By being free
from morally bad judgment when she exercises her right to bodily autonomy
through abortion, she is able to assert her bodily integrity, herself as a whole
person, at base, her humanity. Whats more, since rape sends a message of deg-
radation to all women, when a woman asserts her humanity in this way, she is
40
This account was inspired by Helga Vardens explanation of why, for Kant, from the point of
view of justice we have to consider the relation between my person and my body as analytic, as a nec-
essary unity. See Helga Varden, A Feminist, Kantian Conception of the Right to Bodily Integrity:The
Cases of Abortion and Homosexuality, in Out from the Shadows:Analytical Feminist Contributions
to Traditional Philosophy, edited by Sharon L. Crasnow and Anita M. Superson (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 2012),35.
41
This analysis might reflect Catriona Mackenzies account of relational autonomy.
42
See Laura M. Purdy, Are Pregnant Women Fetal Containers? in Reproducing Persons:Issues
in Feminist Bioethics, edited by Laura M. Purdy (Ithaca, NY:Cornell University Press, 1996), 88105.
Purdys paper is mainly about whether and the extent to which women have duties to their fetuses, but
presumably she would argue along similar lines about enforced pregnancy.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 313
at the same time attempting to shrug off the degrading stereotypes associated
with women:that they are nothing more than sex objects or mere bodies for
mens use. The time that pregnancy lasts has no relevance to this argument:if
someone uses your body against your will in ways that attempt to reduce your
humanity, morality should allow you to reassert your humanity, to in effect
send the message that neither you nor members of your kind are the kind of
beings that can be treated this way.43 This is true whether pregnancy lasts nine
months or one hour. Thus, there is nothing indecent or callous about a woman
who seeks to abort a fetus that reminds her of the rapists attempt to degrade
her. At best, the woman would be frightfully nice to carry the fetus toterm.
43
We might even argue that you have an obligation, out of self-respect, to reassert your humanity.
For this kind of view, see Thomas E. Hill, Jr., Servility and Self-Respect, in Dignity, Character, and
Self-Respect, edited by Robin S. Dillon (NewYork:Routledge, 1995), 7692 (reprinted from Monist 57
(1973):87104).
44
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,6566.
45
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 65,64.
314 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
agent goes out of his way, at some cost to himself, to help one in need of it.46 As
an example, Thomson cites the Kitty Genovese case, where Genovese was mur-
dered while twenty-eight people watched or listened without helping hera
Good Samaritan, Thomson notes. Then she immediately corrects herself and
says that a Splendid Samaritan would have rushed out and assisted Genovese
against the murderer.47 Thomsons shift to what a Splendid Samaritan would
have done is explained by the size of the sacrifice involved, which in this case
is a risk of death for yourself.48
For any act involving Good Samaritanism or better, there is no require-
ment that the agent do it. Thomson notes that Henry Fonda would be a Good
Samaritan, performing an act of kindness but not anything required that you
can claim against him as your due, were he to fly in from the West Coast to
touch your fevered brow.49 She says the same about the violinist who needs to
stay hooked up to your body to use your kidneys for his continued life:it is a
kindness on your part, and not something you owe him.50
Next on the hierarchy come acts that are indecent not to perform yet do not
correspond to any rights violation and thus are not owed by you to another
agent. These are acts of Minimally Decent Samaritanism. Iunderstand moral
requirements to rank just below acts of Minimally Decent Samaritanism in
the hierarchy. Iwill address moral requirements first, since Thomson draws
out their significance by comparing them with acts of Minimally Decent
Samaritanism. Morally required acts, unlike the others so far mentioned, cor-
respond to rights. One example of a morally required act comes in with the
case of the two brothers who are jointly given a box of chocolates, but the
older brother takes them all and refuses to give any to the younger brother. The
younger has a right to them, so the older one is unjust and violates an obliga-
tion in not giving his brother his fair share.51 Sharing the chocolates is morally
required because the younger brother had a right to the chocolates. In con-
trast, you are not unjust if you unplug yourself from the violinist because he
had no right against you to use of your body,52 even if unplugging him means
that he dies. Unless you gave him a right to use your body, you are not morally
required to let him use it. Similarly, the woman who becomes pregnant from
rape or due to contraceptive failure does not have an obligation to carry the
fetus to term because she did not invite it in or give it a right to use her body,
and it has no right against her for use of her body. Obligations corresponding
46
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,62.
47
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,6263.
48
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,63.
49
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 55,65.
50
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,56.
51
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,5657.
52
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,57.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 315
with rights fall below acts that are indecent in you not to performyou ought to
perform the former; morality requiresit.
Now consider Minimally Decent Samaritanism, acts that it should be morally
indecent not to perform. Carrying a one-hour pregnancy to term, sharing your
chocolates with your brother when they were given only to you and he wants
some, Henry Fondas walking across the room to touch your fevered brow, let-
ting the violinist use your kidneys for one hour, and not requesting an abortion
in the seventh month to avoid postponing a trip are cases of Minimally Decent
Samaritanism.53 Thomson says that you ought to perform such acts in the sense
that it would be indecent to refuse.54 Thomson distinguishes these cases, and this
sense of ought, from cases of moral obligations, which correspond with rights.
She argues against those who believe that the ought of minimal decency gener-
ates a right:...it seems to me to be an unfortunate loosening of what we would
do better to keep a tight rein on.55 Rights are generated differently, independent
of the oughts of minimal decency, but on the basis of someones having a clear
entitlement to something (e.g., ownership of ones body or a box of chocolates).56
The ought of obligation follows from this, whereas the ought of indecency
follows from how easy it is to provide someone with something.57 Thomson notes
that, except where there is a right to demand it, nobody is morally required to
make large sacrifices of health and other interests and concerns, even to keep an-
other person alive.58 Still, oughts of minimal decency are oughtswe cannot
claim that the fetus who comes into existence from rape has a right to use the
mothers body even for a one-hour pregnancy but only that the mother ought
to let it use her body for this short time because she would be self-centered, cal-
lous, indecent to refuse. Thomson notes that the complaints are not less grave;
they are just different.59 That is, they are both ways you ought to act, but the
ought is grounded in a requirement in one case, and in minimal decency, in
the other case. The ought of minimal decency is binding in a way that makes
the act impermissible, but its impermissibility does not derive from its being a
moral requirement or duty. Although Thomson is not explicit about this, we
can discern from the cases that Minimally Decent Samaritanism is in the class
of acts of Samaritanism whose degree of goodness depends on the amount of
sacrifice involved. Obligations corresponding with rights do not:indeed its a
rather shocking idea that anyones rights should fade away and disappear as it gets
harder and harder to accord them to him.60 But since Minimal Moral Decency is
53
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 60, 61, 5960,6566.
54
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,60.
55
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,60.
56
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,60.
57
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,61.
58
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,6162.
59
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,61.
60
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,61.
316 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
61
Ido not take issue with Thomsons criterion for determining degrees of Samaritanhood.
62
Tribe, Abortion,103.
63
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), Pregnancy Complications, February 5,
2013, http://www.cdc.gov/reproductivehealth/MaternalInfantHealth/PregComplications.htm.
64
Amy Mullin, Reconceiving Pregnancy and Childcare:Ethics, Experience, and Reproductive Labor
(NewYork:Cambridge University Press, 2005),61.
65
American Pregnancy Association (APA), Pregnancy Complications, 2013, http://american-
pregnancy.org/pregnancycomplications.
66
CDC, Pregnancy Complications.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 317
67
Mullin, Reconceiving Pregnancy,60.
68
CDC, Pregnancy Complications.
69
Ann Cudd, Enforced Pregnancy, Rape, and the Image of Woman, Philosophical Studies 60:12
(SeptemberOctober 1990):4759,53.
70
To be clear, Iam not saying that the indecency charge is overridden by competing moral claims
but that it should not be leveled to beginwith.
71
Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality, Philosophy & Public Affairs 1:3 (1972):229243.
Singers principle is that If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without
318 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
are even more stringent than Thomson sets out. They would require both the
woman in the seventh month of pregnancy who wants to take a trip and the
rape victim whose pregnancy lasts only one hour to carry their pregnancies to
term as well as other pregnancies when the mother does not suffer harm com-
parable to the fetus death.72
Although many of us find Singers general principle plausible, Ibelieve that
when it comes to using our bodies to carry out the prevention of something
bad, the demands of morality are less stringent than this principle sets out.
And the more intimately our bodies must be used, the less stringent the moral
demand. Of course, pregnancy is exactly the kind of case where a womans
body is used most intimately in carrying out any moral demand made by the
fetus situation. As Margaret Little puts it, there are significant qualitative dif-
ferences between gestating and giving money to Oxfam: There are special
facets to a decision about charity when the beneficence is a matter of sharing
ones body, heart, and soul, not just ones pocketbook or general energies, when
the sacrifice is measured, not in degrees of risk, but in degrees of intertwine-
ment.73 For this reason, pregnancy is more sacrificial than being hooked up to
a violinist, which is more sacrificial than donating blood or getting vaccinated
against contagious diseases.74 Any of these is more sacrificial than donating
money to Oxfam, simply because of the degree of bodily involvement.
Why does use of the body matter so much to the demands of morality?
Thomson makes several remarks that speak to its significance:
No doubt the mother has a right to decide what shall happen in and to her
body; everyone would grant that.75
If anything in the world is true, it is that you do not commit murder, you
do not do what is impermissible, if you reach around to your back and un-
plug yourself from that violinist to save your life.76
...the mother owns the house.77
Women have said again and again This is my body.78
My own view is that if a human body has any just, prior claim to anything
at all, he has a just, prior claim to his own body.79
For nobody has any right to use your kidneys unless you give him such
a right...80
thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it (231). Iowe
this example and the objection it makes to my view to Samantha Brennan.
72
Ido not know if Singer would say this because he does not address this in hispaper.
73
Little, Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate,305.
74
Samantha Brennan and Heather Douglas provided the examples.
75
Thomson, Defense of Abortion, 48,50.
76
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,52.
77
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,53.
78
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,53.
79
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,54.
80
Thomson, Defense of Abortion,55.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 319
Because you own your own body, have a just prior claim to it, and are the
only one who can give some a right to use it, the right to bodily autonomy
has high trumping power. Again, Ibelieve that the significance of the body
lies with the fact that you are your body:it is the vehicle through which you
live your life.81 Susan Brison cites Jean Amry, who claims that the boundar-
ies of my body are also the boundaries of my self.82 Both Brison and Laurence
Thomas, in their work on bodily trauma experienced in rape or child abuse,
further explain this insight. According to Thomas, a rape victim suffers the
psychological scar of having a profound sense of diminished personal agency.83
The sense of personal agency, which Thomas believes is acquired under favor-
able conditions in ones adult familial environment rather than at birth, is
absolutely central to being an adult, and at least partially captures the force of
my in my body.84 It is the sense in which one has a great deal of control over
things that happen to ones body in ones social interactions:To have a sense
of personal agency is to have the conviction that, well beyond cases of sheer
bodily harm, there are things which a person ought not, and so will not, do to
or with ones body, or observe ones doing with ones body, without ones con-
sent.85 According to Thomas, rape, childhood sexual abuse, and other similar
bodily traumas shake the victims sense of personal agency at its core in such
a way that the victims beliefs about her self become skewed, causing her to
suffer a radical diminution of her self.86 Although Thomas denies that the pain
of rape is conceptually related to having suffered a bodily injury, the reality
is that the diminution of the sense of self is carried out through an attack on
onesbody.
I would add to Thomass account that having a sense of personal agency
is to see oneself as a valid member of a moral community, a being who is
owed a certain treatment including respect for her body. Along these lines,
Brison argues that recovering from bodily trauma experienced in rape is a
matter of being reconnected with humanity in ways that you value.87 Physical
trauma inflicted by another can change ones perception of ones own body, by
81
Thomson speaks of owning your own body, but I think you are your body. She might agree,
explaining that the fact that you are your body underlies your ownership of it. Ileave aside the debate
between being your own body and owning it. For a discussion of ownership, see Jennifer Church,
Ownership and the Body, in Feminists Rethink the Self, edited by Diana Tietjens Meyers (Boulder,
CO:Westview Press, 1997), 85103.
82
Susan Brison, Outliving Oneself:Trauma, Memory, and Personal Identity, in Meyers, Feminists
Rethink the Self,18.
83
Laurence Thomas, The Grip of Immorality:Child Abuse and Moral Failure, in Reason, Ethics,
and Society: Themes from Kurt Baier, edited by J. B. Schneewind (Chicago, IL: Open Court, 1996),
144167.
84
Thomas, Grip of Immorality,152.
85
Thomas, Grip of Immorality,152.
86
Thomas, Grip of Immorality,153.
87
Brison, Outliving Oneself,2829.
320 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
reducing the victim to flesh or a mere object,88 causing her to perceive her body as
an enemy or a site of increased vulnerability,89 to disassociate from her body or to
have an intense awareness of her embodiment,90 to experience traumatic memo-
ries through her body (e.g., racing heart, crawling skin, or being immobilized),91
and to distance ones self from ones bodily self.92 Victims of bodily trauma need
to remake their selves, to reconnect their self that existed prior to trauma with
the self they come to be through their trauma. This cannot be accomplished in
isolation from others but only in a community of trustworthy persons, particu-
larly those who are also survivors of trauma and who will listen to their story and
engage in mutual empathy with them.93 Through this process, the victim finds
some aspects of her lost self in another person and is able to reconnect with it and
remake her self as one, surviving as an autonomous self.94 This process confirms
the victims humanity.95
I conclude from this discussion that the body is the vehicle through which you
live your life, it plays a significant role in the identity of the self, and it is integrally
bound up with having a sense of personal agency or being a member of humanity
or the moral community. These factors give backbone to Thomsons belief that
the body is so important that only you can give someone else a right to use your
body and in turn to why the demands of morality are lessened accordingly with
the degree of involvement of the body required to carry them out. Ioffer the fol-
lowing principle:
The stringency of the demands of morality are dependent on the degree of the
involvement of the body in carrying them out; an act that is otherwise a duty
can be an act of at least Good Samaritanism commensurate with the degree of
bodily involvement necessary to fulfillit.
Lets return to the indecency charge mounted against the woman who wants
a late-term abortion to avoid postponing a trip, since this still needs defense.
Perhaps it is not just the amount of sacrifice but also a kind of commitment the
mother makes to the fetus that grounds Thomsons indecency charge.96
88
Brison, Outliving Oneself,18.
89
Brison, Outliving Oneself,1617.
90
Brison, Outliving Oneself,20.
91
Brison, Outliving Oneself,17.
92
Brison, Outliving Oneself,20.
93
Brison, Outliving Oneself,29.
94
Brison, Outliving Oneself, 30. Since regaining autonomy involves dependence on others,
Brison calls hers a relational account of autonomy.
95
Brison, Outliving Oneself,28.
96
Whether this is Thomsons view is unclear, and she certainly does not state it as such. The un-
derlying issue is under what conditions the mother gives the fetus a right to use her body. We know
that in cases of rape and contraceptive failure the mother does not give the fetus this right. We might
infer, then, that when sex is consensual and when the woman (or couple?) does not take contraceptive
measures because she intends to get pregnant, then if she does become pregnant, she gives the fetus a
right to use her body. But the case at issue (which does not involve rape or contraceptive failure) is one
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 321
of mere indecency, not one where the fetus can claim a right against the mother, so there is something
else besides consent and intention that gives the fetus a right to use the mothersbody.
97
Janet Gallagher, Prenatal Invasions and Interventions: Whats Wrong with Fetal Rights,
Harvard Womens Law Journal 10 (1087): 31, quoting John Robertson, Procreative Liberty and the
Control of Conception, Pregnancy, and Childbirth, Virginia Law Review 405 (1983):437.
98
Gallagher, Prenatal Invasions, esp.4648,910.
99
See Sara Ann Ketchum, Liberalism and Marriage Law, 264276. In July 1998, the National
Clearinghouse on Marital and Date Rape reported that in seventeen states there are no exemptions
from rape prosecution granted to husbands under the law. But thirty-three states still have some
exemptions from prosecuting husbands for rape usually with regard to the use of force, http://ncmdr.
org/state_law_chart.html.
322 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
carry through in a way defined by her assailant in date rape.100 The idea is
that the woman forms a contract or makes an agreement through her be-
havior and that the contractor is entitled to demand that she uphold it. Lois
Pineau argues against this view, noting that casual, nonverbal behavior, such
as eye contact, smiling, and blushing are imprecise and ambiguous and can
be misinterpreted and thus do not constitute a contract.101 Such a contract,
according to Pineau, is grounded in the myth that men cannot turn off their
sexual arousal but women can, so it is womens responsibility not to provoke
the irrational in men.102 Men can rightly expect the contract to be fulfilled
by using their natural aggression to see to it that it does. Pineau contrasts
the sexual contract with legal contracts that are normally upheld only if the
contractors are clear on what they agreed to and have enough time to think
about whether this is what they want, the terms are usually written out or the
expectations are well known due to tradition and are enforced only by the
law, not private individuals. Consider, for example, the contracts we make
when buying a car or ahouse.
Pineau is making two points here. First is an epistemological point, that
behavioral cues should not constitute the basis of any contractnodding your
head doesnt mean you contract to buy this house, kissing doesnt mean you
contract to sex, and carrying a fetus for seven months doesnt mean you con-
tract to carry it to term. Second, a moral point, is that Pineau doubts whether
sexual contractsand, Iwould add, any bodily contractscan even be made
because behavior in fact does not entail a commitment but believes that even if
they could, the terms would not be enforceable.103 The right to bodily autonomy
should protect against any such contract involving ones body. Pineau dislikes
the contract model because it requires a strong act of refusal to overcome the
presumption of consent, which essentially allows another person to decide
what happens in and to your body. Pineau favors a communicative model that
is based on the notion that there are noncommunicative sexual encounters
that women would not find reasonable to consent to. Pineaus model puts the
burden on the man to show that he got the womans consent when the sex
was of the kind that it would not be reasonable for women to consent to. It
presumes the right to bodily autonomy because the man would have to get the
womans consent to further stages of foreplay and to intercourse by checking
with her throughout rather than assuming that her consent to some sexual be-
havior entails a commitment or contract to have intercourse.
100
Lois Pineau, Date Rape:AFeminist Analysis, Law & Philosophy 8 (1989):217243.
101
Pineau, Date Rape,229.
102
Pineau, Date Rape,227.
103
Pineau, Date Rape,230.
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 323
104
George W. Harris, Fathers and Fetuses, Ethics 96 (April 1986):594603.
105
It has been estimated that in 87percent of counties in the United States it is not possible to ob-
tain an abortion because it is heavily restricted or banned in publicly funded facilities or because coun-
seling for it is banned. Rachel Weiner, No Choice:87% of U.S. Counties Have No Access to Abortion
Clinic, Huffington Post, July 3, 2009, http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2009/06/02/no-choice-87
-of-us-counti_n_210194.html.
324 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
Acknowledgments
For very useful comments, I thank the audiences at the following venues
where Ipresented earlier versions of this paper:Society of Value Inquiry at
the American Philosophical Association, Relational Autonomy Workshop
held at McGill University, Society for Analytical Feminism conference held
at Vanderbilt University, Southwestern Ontario Feminist Philosophers
Right to Bodily Autonomy and the Abortion Controversy 325
In recent decades, the values of autonomy and well-being have been very in-
fluential in western bioethics. Discussions regarding autonomy often focus
on two moral dimensions: the internal capacity of the patient to form and
make decisions consistent with her values and goals; and the freedom from
external coercion and other undue interference in making such decisions. In
discussions of end-of-life care, many have argued that a commitment to re-
spect autonomy and to promote beneficence requires health-care professionals
(HCPs) to facilitate the peaceful or dignified death of competent patients who
find their terminal or disabling conditions intolerable. Since treatment refusal
and withdrawal of life support can often hasten a patients death but are le-
gally and ethically acceptable when requested by competent patients, the more
recent controversies focus on the question of allowing other forms of medi-
cally assisted death, such as physician-assisted suicide or active euthanasia, for
similarly competent patients. Legalizing such procedures, proponents argue,
would support or further patients rights to make decisions about their lives
and well-being in the most compassionate and benevolentways.
Informed by feminist accounts of relational autonomy, this paper will argue
that the individualist and minimalist conceptions of autonomy that are often
used to support a right to medically assisted death often neglect the broader
contextual factors contributing to peoples loss of hope and may thus be inad-
equate in ensuring that end-of-life decisions truly promote their agency and
well-being. In particular, this paper will examine how peoples sociopolitical
environment and interpersonal relationships affect or even frame the way they
experience their impairments and related sufferings. While many bioethicists
focus their concerns on third-party involvement in facilitating suicide, Iwill
argue that we need to look at the broader societal assumptions about life with
impairments and how these attitudes and our social structure may affect peo-
ples quality of life, their decision-making processes, and their desire to die.
In examining various forms of professional assistance that would likely lead
to the death of the person with impairment, this paper will explore how a
Autonomy and Ableism 327
society that has not yet overcome ableism should consider such socioenvi-
ronmental issues in determining peoples potential right to medically assisted
death. Even if lingering oppressive powers of an ableist society are not directly
coercive, they can affect peoples thoughts about their alternatives in such a
way that certain options such as living with mechanical or human assistance
are not considered as viable and other decisions about ending ones life must
be made. In adopting an individualist and minimalist approach to autonomy,
the common philosophical approach regarding medically assisted death may
be prematurely neglecting many complex factors that contribute to peoples
decision-making process. In critically evaluating how the ableist ideology may
impose various forms of oppressive influence that can restrict peoples ability
to reflect on their value system and choose their desired life-sustaining sup-
port and end-of-life treatments accordingly, this paper nonetheless cautions
against treating people with impairments as a separate class of people who are
categorically less capable to assess their situation.
1
Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by Lewis White Beck (Indi
anapolis:Bobbs-Merrill,1959).
2
John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Peterborough:Broadview,1999).
328 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
coerce rational beings even for their own good is to paternalistically treat them
as if they lacked the capacity to shape their own livesit is to deny them their
moral status as persons.
The primacy of respect for autonomy in Western bioethics was initiated
as a response to research atrocities such as the Nuremberg experiments and
the Tuskegee syphilis study, particularly in relation to how the individuals in-
volved were subjected to harm without their knowledge, understanding, or
agreement. The ideas of self-determination and well-being have subsequently
been adopted in the literature on health-care delivery in the face of evolv-
ing individual/civil rights and rising consumer empowerment. Concerns have
been raised regarding medical paternalism, where HCPs withhold informa-
tion from or make value judgments and clinical decisions on behalf of patients
allegedly for the latters own good. The principle of respect for peoples au-
tonomy, particularly when expressed in terms of formal consent requirements
and privacy regulations, establishes parameters and expectations for HCPs in
their conduct with patients. As modern medical science and technology come
with risks, limitations, and errors, these legal mechanisms structure HCPpa-
tient relations and regulate what professionals can or cannot do to patients.
Protection of autonomy is considered particularly crucial in health-care
settings because illnesses and injuries are physically and emotionally chal-
lenging for many patients, especially when the diagnoses are unexpected or
grim or when the potential for adverse effect from medical treatment and
abuse of power is high. Such protection ostensibly helps to promote patients
agency by ensuring that they understand the risks and benefits of available
therapeutic options and have the freedom to choose between or refuse these
interventions according to their own values.3 As feminist bioethicist Susan
Sherwin points out, patients are often worried about their situation and are
ignorant of the particulars of various treatment alternatives, which gener-
ally make them dependent on the care and goodwill of others.4 HCPs, on
the other hand, are presumably more knowledgeable about their conditions,
and their professional recommendations often determine whether patients
would have (affordable) access to diagnostic and therapeutic procedures that
can provide further information, minimize pain, restore health, or improve
functioning and extend life. Given that HCPs are inadvertent gatekeepers of
information and resources, there is an inherent power hierarchy in the HCP
patient relationship, making patients particularly vulnerable to manipulation
or even coercion by their caregivers. While many conscientious HCPs would
3
Leigh Turner, Bioethics and End-of-Life Care in Multi-Ethnic Settings: Cultural Diversity in
Canada and the USA, Mortality 7 (2002):285301.
4
Susan Sherwin, A Relational Approach to Autonomy in health Care, in The Politics of Womens
Health:Exploring Agency and Autonomy, edited by Susan Sherwin (Philadelphia:Temple University
Press, 1998),1947.
Autonomy and Ableism 329
traditionally treat patients according to the clinicians judgment, with the be-
nevolent assumption that patients who lack medical expertise would not know
what clinical alternative is best for them, it is now generally acknowledged in
Western bioethics that health-care decisions are not simply clinical decisions.
They have important implications on various aspects of the patients personal,
professional, social, and family life. This is especially the case for patients who
are terminally ill:that is, they are expected to die within six months from their
conditions. For some of these patients, aggressive interventions may sustain or
slightly prolong their life without restoring or maintaining their functioning
or quality of life. In some situations, the interventions may even aggravate the
patients pain and suffering. As more medical options are now available, each
with its own set of benefits and burdens for the patients and their loved ones,
it is increasingly difficult for HCPs who have limited contact with patients
under very specific circumstances to determine which available option is most
compatible with the latters value system and priorities. This is especially so in
diverse societies, where patients may have different cultural values and beliefs
regarding what causes illness, how it can be cured or treated, and who should
be involved in the process. Astrong principle of respect for patient autonomy
is thus necessary to counter medical paternalism, particularly toward those
who are most vulnerable or socially disadvantaged. Consent requirements for
treatment, advance directives, and hospital policies regarding resuscitation
and other aggressive interventions are formalized measures that allow patients
more control in health-care and end-of-life planning.
5
Tom Beauchamp and James Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. (NewYork:Oxford
University Press, 1994),121.
6
Catriona Mackenzie and Wendy Rogers, Autonomy, Vulnerability and Capacity:APhilosophical
Appraisal of the Mental Capacity Act, International Journal of Law in Context 9 (2013):3752.
330 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
7
Sherwin, A Relational Approach to Autonomy in Health Care, 26; Tom Beauchamp and James
Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics,123.
8
Uma Narayan, Minds of Their Own:Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices and Other Women,
in A Mind of Ones Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, edited by Louise Antony and
Charlotte Witt (Boulder, CO:Westview Press, 1993),429.
9
Mackenzie and Rogers, Autonomy, Vulnerability and Capacity,39.
Autonomy and Ableism 331
10
Dan Brock, Life and Death:Philosophical Essays in Biomedical Ethics (Cambridge:Cambridge
University Press, 1993),206.
11
Tania Salem, Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting AutonomyOr Medicalizing Suicide?
Hastings Center Report 29 (1999):3036.
12
Brock, Life and Death,280.
13
Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, Tim Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis
Thompson, The Philosophers Brief, NewYork Review of Books 27 (1997):4147.
332 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
consider their lives to be not worth living due to the suffering brought on by
their impairments or terminal illnesses.
The autonomy argument for medically assisted death generally appeals
to patients rights to refuse any procedure that counters their value sys-
tem and priorities, even if that may result in the patients death. Refusal of
life-sustaining interventions, especially in situations where a person is termi-
nally ill, is now generally considered noncontroversial and is widely accepted
as a fundamental component of patients rights to informed refusal. Taking
such a position for granted, many now extend the autonomy argument to
challenge the alleged moral distinction between actively killing a terminally
ill or disabled patient and letting such an individual forego life-sustaining
procedures, both of which can foreseeably lead to imminent death.14 While
withdrawing or refusing these interventions may facilitate a swift and pain-
less death in some cases, it may not offer comfort for others with degenera-
tive conditions who would have to endure a slowly deteriorating and dying
process. Some argue that, when death is accepted or even desired by patients
as a way to end their burdensome existence, whether due to their terminal
illness or impairments, the autonomy argument that allows him or her to
forego life-extending measures also supports giving them life-ending assis-
tance. The assumption is that quality of life determination is subjective, such
that only the patients themselves can determine if continued life in severely
compromised and debilitated states is acceptable. According to this view, if
people believe that their impairments or conditions are rendering their lives
unbearable and if medical technology cannot cure their defects or halt
their deterioration, they should be allowed to end their intolerable suffering
and have control over the timing and circumstances of death in ways they
see fit, including via assisted suicide or active euthanasia. While some have
argued that these procedures require third-party involvement and thus are
not simply matters of self-determination, they do not generally question the
capacity of the person in forming such desires and the voluntariness of the
decision itself, unless there are clear signs that the patient suffers from severe
mental illness (e.g., depression).15 They only question the claim that others
have the obligation to assist in bringing on or hastening the dying process
according to the patients wishes.16
14
Lance Stell, Physician-Assisted Suicide:To Decriminalize or to Legalize, That Is the Question,
in Physician Assisted Suicide:Expanding the Debate, edited by Margaret Battin, Rosamond Rhodes, and
Anita Silvers (NewYork:Routledge, 1998), 225251.
15
Stell, Physician-Assisted Suicide, 225251.
16
Daniel Callahan, When Self-Determination Runs Amok, Hastings Center Report 22
(1992):5255.
Autonomy and Ableism 333
In the age of patient-centered care, respect for autonomy and privacy requires
that we take the wishes of patients seriously in facilitating their decisions re-
garding life-sustaining interventions. It is often assumed that state sanctions
and individual coercion are the main barriers to peoples autonomy and that
removal of such forces will allow people to freely reflect on their priorities and
values, to form their own preferences, and to realize their life plans in ways
they deem appropriate.
However, Iwish to argue that the individualist and minimalist framework
is too narrow and misses the significance of other external powers. It does not
address how many subtle and yet powerful forms of influenceparticularly
the social structure and institutional framework that promote certain ideolo-
gies and reject othersdetermine peoples available options and shape their
decision-making processes. The individualist view tends to take restriction of
autonomy as a dyadic matter between two individualsone who is dominant
(e.g., physician) and another who is subordinate (e.g., patient). It presupposes
that decisions that are not unduly restricted by the dominant agents actions
are autonomous and thus should be respected. It also focuses on individual
actions or interactions rather than social practices, unless those social prac-
tices have been formalized or codified by law, such as sanctions against eutha-
nasia. In the context of medically assisted death, the individualist-minimalist
framework focuses on whether people have all the information to make their
end-of-life decisions rather than how various forms of medically assisted
death may reflect larger structural issues such as health-care delivery, the pro-
fessionalpatient relationship, the ethos of the medical profession, and the
definition of extraordinary care. In arguing for lifting prohibitions on certain
forms of medically assisted death, many take it for granted that competent
people with all the relevant information should be allowed to make their own
decisions regarding whether or how todie.
The minimalist notion of autonomy is attractive in a liberal democratic soci-
ety because it diminishes the possibility of paternalism, especially in situations
where power hierarchy dominates the relational structure, such as health care.
In respecting peoples expressed choices as the default position, it adopts a rel-
atively value-neutral position and prevents premature intervention in peoples
lives even when we disagree with their decisions. Nonetheless, in health care
and other arenas, power and domination are not simply or always elements of
individual actions.17 Rather, they are also structural phenomena, the intended
17
Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press,1990).
334 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
or unintended product of the actions of many people that are value laden and
shape others choices. The dyadic modeling of power and autonomy misses
the impact of the larger social structure and ideology in determining patients
value frameworks and available options, including what constitutes quality of
life, what technologies are considered mainstream, and what risks are deemed
acceptable.
While the popular rhetoric regarding patient autonomy leads many to as-
sume that patients determine their desired procedures, health-care systems
are structured in such a way that patients do not have much control over their
health-care pathway. Patients diets, diagnostic or check-up schedules, access
to specialists and technologies, and discharge plans are determined not based
on patients preferences or values but primarily on lab or bed availability, cost
benefit considerations, professionals convenience, and insurance coverage.18 It
is often the accumulation of these quotidian decisions, about which permis-
sion is rarely requested, that predetermines the subsequent clinical options
and outcomes wherein patient consent is finally sought under tight time con-
straints. Patients routinely behave as they do in the health-care setting partly
because of how medicine is practiced or delivered, as determined by clinicians,
administrators, politicians, funding agencies, and various regulatory bodies.
They make decisions in various manners because of the presumed epistemic
privilege and bureaucratic power that professionals hold and according to
these clinicians expectations, even though medical staffs generally do not do
anything special to cause patients to adopt or change their actions. Patients
recognize quickly that acting against professionals recommendations even out
of careful self-reflection can get one labeled as being noncompliant or difficult
rather than being autonomous and acting in self-determiningways.
In other words, patients actions and decisions are embedded within a com-
plex set of social relations, practices, expectations, and policies that structure
their selfhood and can significantly affect their ability to exercise autonomy
with respect to their choices.19 Given that patients decision-making processes
and considerations often incorporate intrinsically relational or social content,
it is impossible to assess patient autonomy without critically evaluating how
or whether the interconnected social, political, and health-care structural
frameworks may foreclose or expand certain opportunities or predetermine
how individuals approach various health-care situations.20 Marilyn Friedman,
for example, cautions that social conditions can affect a persons ability to act
according to ones reflectively affirmed values and that the individualist view
neglects how the collective action and ideology often shape the way people
18
Richard Friedenberg, PatientDoctor Relationships, Radiology 226 (2003):306308.
19
Sherwin, Relational Approach to Autonomy in Health Care,32.
20
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (eds.), Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on
Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (NewYork:Oxford University Press,2000).
Autonomy and Ableism 335
evaluate their options by making some alternatives more costly than others.21
The individualist and minimalist approach does not ask how the social system
and our economic resources may need to be (re)organized and (re)distributed
to ensure that people have meaningful opportunities to critically reflect upon
their priorities, freely develop attitudes toward them, and make health-care
decisions that would realize their life plans accordingly.
Some notable cases may help shed light on how the individualist and mini-
malist approach to autonomy fails to capture the complexities of a patients de-
cision to seek medically assisted death. Larry McAfee and Kenneth Bergstedt,
who became quadriplegic after a motorcycle accident and swimming accident
in 1985 and 1969, respectively, sought court authorization to turn off their res-
pirators years after their accidents.22 Neither McAfee nor Bergstedt was termi-
nally ill or experiencing abrupt physical decline, and they both could live for
many more years with respiratory support that had become an integral part of
their existence. Nonetheless, their respective courts presumed that the quality
of life brought on by these individuals impairments was poor and thus found
that it was reasonable for them to think of their situation as hopeless, useless,
unenjoyable, and frustrating. Since McAfee and Bergstedt were presumably
competent adults who were not directly coerced by anyone to choose death,
their respective courts appeared to have adopted the individualist-minimalist
approach of autonomy and determined that the plaintiffs had the right to
refuse artificial methods to extend their lives, which they presumed were full
of suffering.
Another example, while not battled in court, brought up similar social is-
sues around peoples alleged desire to die. Dan Crews, an Antioch man who
became quadriplegic from a car accident at age three, made national news in
2010 when hein his mid-20sasked his health-care providers to remove his
ventilator. Despite having been paralyzed from the neck down for over twenty
years, Crews reported having a happy childhood. The family won a lawsuit and
received a $4million trust to take care of Crewss medical expenses; they also
built an accessible home.23 Crews was an honors student in high school and
21
Marilyn Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, and Politics (NewYork:Oxford University Press,2003).
22
Vicki Michel, Suicide by Persons with Disabilities Disguised as the Refusal of Life-Sustaining
Treatment, HEC Forum 7 (1995): 121131; Anita Silvers, Protecting the Innocents from
Physician-Assisted Suicide:Disability Discrimination and the Duty to Protect Otherwise Vulnerable
Groups, in Battin etal., Physician Assisted Suicide, 133148.
23
Susan Donaldson James, Quadriplegic Dan Crews Swamped with Letters: Dont Die, ABC
News, December 7, 2010, http://abcnews.go.com/Health/quadriplegic-swamped-letters-begging-p
ull-ventilator-die/story?id=12324809#.UWz0dcpvAR9.
336 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
earned an associates degree. However, the trust money ran out because he out-
lived his life expectancy. When his medical bills of more than $300,000 threat-
ened foreclosure on the familys home, Crews feared he would be moved to a
nursing home. Short of having someone generous enough to help pay his medical
bills, he wanted help to die so that his family could sell the house and be settled
financially.24 Crews requested his health-care team to turn off his respirator, but
he was deemed clinically depressed and incapable of making such a decision after
he made threats toward his care team. He explained that anyone in his situation
would be depressed. (There has not been further media report of his status in the
last two years.)
A right to refuse life-prolonging interventions is important in modern health
care and ought to be respected when demanded by competent individuals who
have reflected on all their options and found such interventions too burdensome.
Such requests by terminally ill patients and their families have become a routine
part of discussions about the goals of care at the end of life. While many simply
consider these situations matters of basic civil liberty, Icontend that even these
situations are often fraught with value-laden and stereotypical assumptions about
life with impairments. Missing in these discussions are the larger social contexts
that fail people with impairments and contribute to their suffering. In acknowl-
edging peoples despair and their desire to seek death, we need to explore the var-
ious factors that contribute to peoples hopelessness. The desire to die on the part
of McAfee, Crews, and Bergstedt was embedded within a complex set of social re-
lations, policies, and circumstances that foreclosed preferred independent living
options most people without impairment take for granted. While an altered life
is presumably most difficult soon after one becomes impaired, it is important
to note that none of these men sought to die soon after becoming quadriplegic.
McAfee, Bergstedt, and Crews all lived with their impairments for years and
wanted to die only when their support resources became so severely restricted
that they had no feasible means to continue living what they considered to be a
minimally decent life, making death appear the only plausible means to end their
despair and suffering. With good nursing support covered under his insurance
plan and a van customized with a lift and locks for his wheelchair, McAfee was
able to rejoin societyhe could ride to the grocery store, the occasional movie,
or a basketball game. However, a few years later his insurance ran out and he was
put into institutional care out of state and then shuffled into a hospital because of
his restrictive Medicaid coverage. With no hope of ever living in the community
and retaining some control over his life, McAfee wanted todie.25
24
Christian Farr, Quadriplegic Prefers Death to Nursing Home, NBC Chicago, April 12, 2011,
http://www.nbcchicago.com/news/health/dan-crews-119740714.html.
25
Peter Applebome, An Angry Man Fights to Die, Then Tests Life, NewYork Times, February
7, 1990, http://www.nytimes.com/1990/02/07/us/an-angry-man-fights-to-die-then-tests-life.
html?pagewanted=all&src=pm.
Autonomy and Ableism 337
26
Michel, Suicide by Persons with Disabilities,126.
27
McKay v.Bergstedt, 801 P2d 617 (Nev. 1990),628.
338 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
A look at another court case, brought forth by Elizabeth Bouvia, can shed
further light on how a relational approach to autonomy is more equipped in
addressing the complexities around the formation of a desire to seek death
in an ableist environment. In 1983, Bouvia, a twenty-six-year-old social work
graduate student with severe cerebral palsy and degenerative arthritis, admit-
ted herself to a psychiatric hospital in California as a suicidal patientshe
wanted professional help to starve to death. Bouvia had lost her motor func-
tions and was dealing with a miscarriage, financial hardship, and a failing mar-
riage. Despite her graduate training in social work, she was told that she would
never be employable.28 As people with depression have a tendency toward
global negative thinking, Bouvias psychiatrist thought that the young woman
was making a bad decision at a very bad time and that her wish to die could
diminish or change with time and treatment.29 When the hospital staff refused
to abide by her wishes and threatened to force feed her, Bouvia went to court
with the help of the American Civil Liberties Union (ACLU). The court deter-
mined that the state had viable interests in preserving life, preventing suicide,
protecting third parties, and maintaining the ethical standards of the med-
ical professions. It denied her judicial assistance to starve herself to death and
authorized feeding via a nasogastric tube.30 Bouvia checked out of the hospital
28
Michel, Suicide by Persons with Disabilities,127.
29
Mary Johnson, Right to Life, Fight toDie.
30
Bouvia v.County of Riverside, No. 159780 (Riverside Super. Ct.1983).
Autonomy and Ableism 339
to starve herself, but she changed her mind later after discussions with friends
and was admitted to a county rehabilitation facility.
In 1986 Bouvia went to court again to have her feeding tube removed. The
court denied her request, but the Appellate Court overturned the decision.
While the latter court insisted that it did not assess the motive behind Bouvias
decision to refuse nourishment, it agreed that Bouvia, lying helplessly in bed,
unable to care for herself, may consider her existence meaningless.31
It is interesting to note that, while Bouvia expressed that she would rather
be dead than live like this, she also explicitly said she never wanted to die.32
She stated that physically she was feeling all right, fine, OK, or that people
could say [she is] doing OK.33 Nonetheless, the Appellate Court and main-
stream commentators continued to consider Bouvias assertions of a desire to
die, albeit inconsistent, as evidence that the woman was making a reflective
and autonomous choice. They expressed sympathy towards Bouvia, whom
they thought was in a pitiful state and living a life of helpless dependency.34
There was no discussion of the social and relational contexts within which
Bouvia formed her judgments, nor was there investigation of why or how
Bouvias wishes to die wavered at times. The Appellate Court determined that
given Bouvias low quality of life, her right to refuse life-extending interven-
tions superseded the states interests. Nonetheless, as was the situation a few
years prior, after Bouvia was granted the right to starve to death she aban-
doned her plan, this time claiming that she could not stand the pain and was
worried that her slow starvation would bring too much grief and guilt to the
staff at her facility.
Bouvias ultimate decision to continue living in her condition begs for the
question of whether the rhetoric around respect for her autonomy is an ableist
ideology in disguise. The Appellate Court and various commentators readily
accepted her inconsistent desire to die at face value, perhaps because that de-
sire harmonizes with their own perception that the primary problem for such
individuals is the unbearable experience of a permanent disability (and/or
dependence on life aids) and that death is the solution.35 If Bouvia did not
31
Bouvia v.Superior Court, 179 Cal. App.3d 1127, 1135, 225 Cal. Rptr. 297, 299300 (1986).
32
Mary Johnson, Right to Life, Fight to Die:The Elizabeth Bouvia Saga, Ragged Edge, January
February 1997, http: www.raggededgemagazine.com/archive/bouvia.htm; Beverly Beyette, The
Reluctant Survivor:9 Years After Helping Her Fight for the Right to Die, Elizabeth Bouvias Lawyer
and Confidante Killed HimselfLeaving Her Shaken and Living the Life She Dreaded, Los Angeles
Times, September 13, 1992, http://articles.latimes.com/1992-09-13/news/vw-1154_1_elizabeth-bouvia;
Elizabeth Bouvia, The Desire is Still There to Die, Lodi News-Sentinel, April 14, 1987, http://news.
google.com/newspapers?nid=2245&dat=19870414&id=7Bc0AAAAIBAJ&sjid=qDIHAAAAIBAJ
&pg=6843,5967547.
33
Beyette, Reluctant Survivor.
34
William Raspberry, Quadriplegics Life is Hers Alone to LiveAnd Also Hers to End, Spokane
Chronicle, April 7, 1986, http://news.google.com/newspapers?nid=1345&dat=19860407&id=_vpLAAA
AIBAJ&sjid=vvkDAAAAIBAJ&pg=2623,1367027.
35
Gill, Suicide Intervention for People with Disabilities.
340 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
have impairments but confirmed that her miscarriage, failing marriage, and em-
ployment and financial hardship contributed to her loss of hope in life, many
would likely have taken her previous psychiatrists testimony more seriously and
considered her intent to die as signs of depression or social problems and thus po-
tential grounds for support or intervention. The courts neglect of these consider-
ations in its decision reflects the prevailing ableist attitude that having a disability
is a sensible reason for committing suicide that requires no further investigation.
Ironically, when Bouvias own ACLU lawyer committed suicide a few years later,
she said that she was not convinced that he couldnt have gotten help. Like many
others holding an ableist ideology, Bouvia also seemed to think that impairments
were more legitimate than other reasons for one to desire death. She said she
could understand if her lawyer had tried everything and there was no way out
or if he had cancer or some physical ailment. But he had a lot to live for.36
Bouvias view of her own situation in comparison to that of her attorneys
coincides with mainstream evaluations of life with and without impairments,
respectively. Her different reactions to her and her lawyers respective death
wishes suggests that the young woman may have internalized societys rejection
and devaluation of people with impairments, such that she did not recognize
or resist the oppressive forces of ableist ideology.37 Even as dependency is a nat-
ural and unavoidable part of the human condition, dominant social structure
continues to espouse individual self-sufficiency as a norm and an ideal, such
that technological and human assistance to daily living is often interpreted by
HCPs and others to indicate an unacceptably low quality of life. McAfee and
Bergstedt relied on respiratory support as part of their daily livingsuch me-
chanical assistance had become commonplace for them. Nonetheless, as Carol
Gill points out, in a society where professionals attach words such as radical,
extraordinary, and even futile to breathing and feeding supports people use
each day, medical professionals and health-care administrators often decide
themselves what people with impairments need and define what constitutes
excessive needs.38 International epidemiological measures that quantify the
functional, financial, and other impact of various health problems, such as the
disability-adjusted life years (DALY), incorporate as purported fact the view
that disability and its consequences lower quality of life.39 Not only do these
quasi-scientific measures and HCPs opinions influence intervention recom-
mendations as well as resource and service eligibilities,40 they also impact how
36
Beyette, Reluctant Survivor.
37
Carol Gill, Suicide Intervention for People with Disabilities:ALesson in Inequality, Issues in
Law and Medicine 8 (1992):3753.
38
Carol Gill, Disability, Constructed Vulnerability, and Socially Conscious Palliative Care,
Journal of Palliative Care 22 (2006):183191.
39
Jerome Bickenbach, Disability and Life-Ending Decisions, in Battin etal., Physician Assisted
Suicide, 123132.
40
Anita Ho, Trusting Experts and Epistemic Humility in Disability, International Journal of the
Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 4 (2011):103124.
Autonomy and Ableism 341
the rest of us assess and in turn affect the quality of life of people with various
kinds of impairment.
When such structural considerations frame the daily experience of people
with impairments and their interactions with the health-care system, the rhet-
oric around autonomy in medically assisted death may not capture the full
context of many peoples decision-making processes, their subsequent choices,
and social responses to such requests. The aforementioned court cases suggest
that peoples perceptions about their quality of life and their corresponding
wishes regarding their preferred forms of end-of-life care are not isolated med-
ical decisions. While many bioethicists and advocates for access to medically
assisted suicide frame the debate as matters of clinical decisions that should fall
under the rubric of informed consent and refusal, Icontend that preferences
regarding medically assisted death are not purely, or even primarily, medical
decisions. They are part of broader evaluations and decisions determined in
terms of peoples general access to various opportunities to flourish, including
their ability to maintain a multidimensional existence composed partly of sig-
nificant relationships, goals, and values. As Tom Shakespeare points out, even
individual choices are situated in social contexts, and a duty to promote au-
tonomy requires assurance that those contexts are supportive of peoples deci-
sions in the widest possible sense.41 McAfee and Bergstedt both fought to stay
out of restrictive institutional care that further limited their social relationships
and employment opportunities. Crews was worried that his family members
would lose all their possessions. Aright to discontinue life-sustaining inter-
ventions, especially when these individuals were not terminally ill, does not
address these underlying issues of restricted opportunities that are essential to
promote autonomy. Force feeding as a form of suicide prevention also did not
address the social conditions and ableist ideology that contributed to Bouvias
belief that her life was so burdensome that death was perceived to be the only
or best means to end suffering.
The intertwining social and relational factors that frame peoples desire to
die remind us that we need to clarify the cause of peoples suffering to pro-
vide appropriate relief. Studies show that hopelessness is an essential element
of unbearable suffering, and patients perceive their suffering to be unbear-
able not solely because of their medical conditions or symptoms. Nonclinical
concerns regarding the loss of social significance, communicative problems,
living arrangements, quality of care, being a burden on others, and loneliness
also contribute to peoples suffering.42 The question is partly whether the larger
41
Tom Shakespeare, The Social Context of Individual Choice, in Quality of Life and Human
Difference:Genetic Testing, Health Care, and Disability, edited by David Wasserman, Jerome Bickenbach,
and Robert Wachbroit (NewYork:Cambridge University Press, 2005), 217236.
42
Marianne K. Dees, Myrra J. Vernooij-Dassen, Wim J. Dekkers, Kris C. Vissers, and Chris van
Weel, Unbearable Suffering: A Qualitative Study on the Perspectives of Patients Who Request
Assistance in Dying, Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (2011):727734.
342 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
system sees life with impairment and dependency as equally worthy and pro-
vides appropriate opportunities for people to flourish and retain or regain hope
according to their particular contexts.43 Even when patients are afflicted with
terminal illnesses, hope and flourishing do not necessarily require reversing the
medical conditions. In the context of mortal beings, hope and flourishing are also
about being supported in various interdependent relationships and recognizing
ones full humanity regardless of ones level of functioning. As Jerome Bickenbach
points out, when an individual chooses death as the only viable way to escape
an intolerable situation partly brought on by the social environment, it seems
perverse and unfair to say that this is an expression of self-determination or
autonomy.44
The social context in which people make end-of-life decisions does not simply
affect the feasible options available to them. It also affects the agents development
of her capacity to engage in a reflective process in which decisions are formed.
As many feminists have noted, social relationships and historical conditions can
either facilitate or stunt the development of autonomy.45 When there is a lack
of a supportive environment to facilitate and encourage such development, it
is difficult to ascertain whether peoples choices, including decisions to forego
life-extending interventions or to seek assistance to die, are the results of op-
pressive socialization. Like oppressive gender socialization that can curtail some
womens ability to develop the capacity for critical reflection, ableist ideology that
treats a life with impairment as categorically worse off than one without impair-
ment can impede some peoples capacity to form the self-trust and self-confidence
that are essential to possessing and exercising autonomy, especially if they do not
have other strong social or familial support networks.46 When people devalued by
the mainstream society are also deprived of the opportunities to develop the nec-
essary level of self-trust to gain and use their reflective skills effectively, they may
not be able to exercise autonomy even when they are invited to make an unco-
erced choice regarding their care goals. Such devaluation may hinder peoples
ability to critically explore their positive commitment to their particular beliefs
43
Eva Kittay, Loves Labor:Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency (NewYork:Routledge,1999).
44
Bickenbach, Disability and Life-Ending Decisions,128.
45
Diana Tietjens Meyers, Self, Society, and Personal Choice (NewYork:Columbia University Press,
1989); Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, and Politics.
46
Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, and Politics, 97; Carolyn McLeod and Susan Sherwin, Relational
Autonomy, Self-Trust, and Health Care for Patients Who Are Oppressed, in Mackenzie and Stoljar,
Relational Autonomy, 259279.
Autonomy and Ableism 343
47
Andrea Westlund, Rethinking Relational Autonomy, Hypatia 20 (2009):2649; Paul Benson,
Taking Ownership:Authority and Voice in Autonomous Agency, in Autonomy and the Challenges
of Liberalism: New Essays, edited by Joel Anderson and John Christman (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2005), 101126.
48
McLeod and Sherwin, Relational Autonomy, Self-Trust,262.
49
Harry Frankfurt, The Faintest Passion, Proceedings and Addresses of the APA 66 (1991):316.
50
John Christman, Autonomy and Personal History, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20
(1990):124; Christman, Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom, Ethics 101 (1991):343359.
51
John Christman, The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves
(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2009), 155156.
344 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
reached her personal and private decision after long and careful thought.52
She did not claim to have resisted the process of forming her desire to die.
She explicitly acknowledged an awareness of services and options available but
stated that she did not want to utilize all of them. Nonetheless, even if Bouvias
choice was possibly rational given her dismal outlook or that she did not psy-
chologically resist or struggle with her decision, it does not necessarily follow
that her decision was autonomous. Her decision might have been an adaptive
one, formed as a result of internalized oppression that was so deep-seated that
it prohibited the agent to recognize its presence and force, letalone resist it. In
other words, her wish to die might have been a deformed desire.53
Echoing many feminists focus on care and interdependent relationships in
identity and character formation, many disability activists have attempted to
counter the stereotypical mainstream view that dependency and vulnerability
are abhorrent or undignified forms of living. Some of these activists believed
that it was the social contexts that made death seem desirable to Bouvia when
such an option would not have been preferable under circumstances of social
equality.54 Bouvia might have come to see the ableist environment as the limits
within which she could make her choices or become accustomed to whatever
she saw as her lot in life. The fact that her reasoning coincided with many
ableist norms when she acknowledged feeling physically fine during the
court battle demands a deeper exploration of her motivational system. Even
if Bouvia truly had adopted such values as her own, we still need to ask if
that might have been the result of her treating ableist norms as natural and
formulating desires based on such norms. As Diana Tietjens Meyers argues,
acting in a way that coincides with oppressive norms raises questions about
the agents autonomy but does not settle them.55
Carolyn McLeod and Susan Sherwin also remind us that members of op-
pressed groups are inclined to accept societys devaluing of their personal
worth on an unconscious level and to doubt their own worth.56 It is worth not-
ing that various ableist norms seemed to be built into the workings of Bouvias
motivational system and sense of self-worth. Bouvia held many beliefs that
conform to various stereotypical norms regarding life with impairments. More
importantly, she did not appear to be fully aware of or have had critically eval-
uated such external norms and their potential impact on her own assessment
of her life. She did not resist the thought of herself as being trapped in a use-
less body and found the constant use of a machine or help from another
person at times humiliating and disgusting.57
52
Johnson, Right to Life, Fight toDie.
53
Ann Cudd, Analyzing Oppression (NewYork:Oxford University Press, 2006), 180183.
54
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression,180.
55
Diana Tietjens Meyers, The Feminist Debate over Values in Autonomy Theory, in this volume.
56
McLeod and Sherwin, Relational Autonomy, Self-Trust,262.
57
Johnson, Right to Life, Fight toDie.
Autonomy and Ableism 345
58
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression; Paul Benson, Free Agency and Self-Worth, Journal of Philosophy
91 (1994):650668.
59
Cudd, Analyzing Oppression, 180183.
60
Andrea Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self: Is Deference Compatible with
Autonomy? Philosophical Review 112 (2003):483523.
61
Westlund, Selflessness and Responsibility for Self,485.
346 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
On the other hand, the fact that Bouvia considered her life as one without
dignity raises questions of whether her decision-making process demonstrated
self-governance. Bouvias responses expressed an attitude that appeared to
deny or efface herself. Despite her legal quest, she did not appear to have a
strong sense of trust in her own social standing as a person who should be
treated with respect and dignity62it was unclear that she respected herself
as a moral agent. She seemed partly impervious to the disability activists line
of questioning regarding how life with impairments can still be fulfilling, only
repeating her message that her life had little to no value. Bouvia appeared to
derive no confidence or happiness from her identity. She lacked what John
Christman called self-acceptance and viewed her life with disgust and con-
tempt. She could not maintain a diachronic practical identity under which she
considered her life as worthy of pursuit while negotiating through stultifying
constraints. She fought through the psychological pain of her existence with
resignation and bitterness and could not reflexively affirm her outlook on her
options. Her responses thus seemed to undercut the self-affirmation that is in-
herent in autonomous action or a self-governing mode of existence.63
The context within which Bouvia came to see her life as one without dig-
nity raises questions about the autonomy of her requests to seek medically
assisted death. Bergstedts decision to remove his respiratory support due to
his worry of having no means to live outside of an institutional setting may
be reasonable given his wish to remain in the community, but it did not rep-
resent his true values, goals, and desires. Their respective situations remind
us that peoples desire for medically assisted death is shaped by broader fa-
milial, social, economic, historical, and cultural contexts, some of which have
reinforced the idea that a life with impairments is burdensome or even not
worth living. An ableist social context and its associated environmental bar-
riers contribute to an inequality of autonomy among people,64 suggesting that
a minimalist approach to autonomy may neglect various relational and sys-
temic factors that can contribute to peoples alleged desire to die. There is no
sufficient statistical evidence to suggest that impairment and low quality of
life are inevitably linked or that a life with impairment is globally worse than
one without impairment. In fact, when asked about their quality of life, people
62
Mackenzie and Rogers, Autonomy, Vulnerability and Capacity,45.
63
John Christman, Coping or Oppression:Autonomy and Adaptation to Circumstance, in this
volume.
64
Bickenbach, Disability and Life-Ending Decisions,126.
Autonomy and Ableism 347
with impairments often report a quality much higher than that projected by
people without impairments.65 As our examples have shown, some people
with impairments who seek assisted death would want to live if social support
and opportunity-enhancing arrangements were available, even if their physi-
ological condition were to remain unchanged, suggesting that factors beyond
ones physical conditions can have significant impact on ones quality of life.
Granting their request to die may end their suffering, but it does not neces-
sarily respect their true desire or deal with the social causes of their despair.
Despite these ableist concerns, the question remains as to whether we should
treat people with impairments differently from people without impairments
regarding their life-ending preferences. In discussions of medically assisted
death, some prominent philosophers reject the application of the autonomy
argument specifically for people with impairments, arguing that these people
constitute a vulnerable group that requires special protection.66 While people
without impairment are presumed to have had the appropriate environment to
develop the capacity to make their own reasoned choices regarding end-of-life
care, those with impairments are presumed to be vulnerable. They are believed
to be at an increased risk of harm to self and others and thus allegedly re-
quire special procedural safeguards. As a lawyer representing the Canadian
federal government warned the British Columbia Court of Appeal in March
2013 regarding physician assisted suicide, people with impairments and other
vulnerable patients may be at risk of being coerced to kill themselves. The fed-
eral lawyer appeared concerned that people with impairments are, as a class,
incompetent to assess and protect their own well-being.
Putting aside the issue of whether it is always possible clearly to distinguish
between two classes of patients, particularly in end-of-life cases, there are ques-
tions about whether correcting an ableist sociocultural framework requires
special protection for all people with impairments regarding medically assisted
death. As Ihave argued elsewhere,67 we need to acknowledge the impact of an
ableist social structure on peoples despair, and to ensure that the autonomy
language used in support for medically assisted death does not mask various
barriers of oppression. McAfee and Bergstedt did not want to diethey simply
did not want to live with severely restricted social support. The ableist socio-
cultural framework often precludes certain options from being considered and
reshapes a persons value system. Any autonomy-based argument for support-
ing medically assisted death must consider such complexities.
65
Ron Amundson, Disability, Ideology, and Quality of Life: A Bias in Biomedical Ethics, in
Quality of Life and Human Difference: Genetic Testing, Health Care, and Disability, edited by David
Wasserman, Jerome Bickenbach, and Robert Wachbroit (New York: Cambridge University Press,
2005), 101124.
66
Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, Thomas Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis
Thomson, The Philosophers Brief, NewYork Review of Books 27 (1997):4147.
67
Ho, Individualist Model of Autonomy, 204205.
348 Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender
68
Silvers, Protecting the Innocents, 135.
Autonomy and Ableism 349
Acknowledgments
For critical and constructive feedback on prior versions of this paper, Ithank
participants from the Relational Autonomy: 10 Years On workshop organ-
ized by Natalie Stoljar and Catriona Mackenzie. In particular, I would like
to express my deepest gratitude toward the coeditors of this volume, Andrea
Veltman and Mark Piper, for their insightful comments and suggestions. All
remaining errors are mine and minealone.
{ Index }
ableism, 338342 142, 172; rational, 59, 245; of rape victims, 319;
abortion: bodily autonomy and, 10, 301309; reason-responsiveness and, 178; reflective,
late-term, 313324; length of pregnancy and, 36, 217; respect for, 5, 10, 99, 101, 106, 231, 349;
309313; pregnancy complications, 316317; self-constitution account of, 218; self-creative,
rape, 309313 65; self-respect and, 3; self-writing and, 192;
Abortion: The Clash of Absolutes (Tribe), 301 social and relational character of, 1, 4, 6, 75,
abstract individualism, 80 89, 93, 96, 181, 195, 208, 338; successful, 145;
accountability, 19, 3536, 38 womens, 96, 111112, 114, 138, 211, 244, 249;
ACLU (American Civil Liberties Union), 338339 work and, 280285, 287290, 293297, 299;
active self, 77, 81 unified across time, 187
adaptation: defined, 206; oppression, 207215 agential ownership, 118119
adaptive preferences: deformed desires as, Agential Virtue Account, 172177, 179
229; Double Axis Thesis and, 128, 131132; agential voice and authority, 105112
internalized oppression and, 137138; agentic skills, 121124, 126, 131, 139
Khaders theory of, 9, 132, 140; in oppressive akrasia. See weakness of will
circumstances, 5, 9, 201203 alienation, 213, 217, 219, 222, 235236
adaptive preferences formation: bad options, Ali, Hirsi, 81
choosing among, 243248; coercion, 248252; American Civil Liberties Union (ACLU), 338339
freedom to do otherwise model, 238243; American Enterprise Institute, 147
overview, 9, 227233; psychological processes Amry, Jean, 319
model, 233238 analytical skills, 121
adoption, 301 Anderson, Elizabeth, 28
affective states, 167 Anderson, Joel, 19, 37
affiliation, defined, 34 answerability, 9, 19, 32, 3536, 109112, 115, 119,
agency: adaptation and, 202, 249; authentic, 124126, 134140, 188190, 192, 196, 221, 345
211212; authority and, 93, 106, 108, 140; applied ethics, 2
autonomous, 8, 11, 89, 9396, 99101, 103106, Aristotle, 255, 283
108, 112113, 128, 132, 138, 140, 152, 178, 180, Arjomand, Homa, 148
189, 195, 205206, 213215, 217, 220, 249, 251, Astell, Mary, 71
281284, 287290, 293298; brainwashing and attitudes, 184187
manipulation and, 214; capitalism and, 298; authentic self, 3, 32, 95, 106, 164, 257258, 265,
care and, 182, 191; control over ones body and, 267268, 272273
319; dialogic interaction and, 211; distinguished authenticity: conditions of, 1718, 21, 92, 103,
from autonomy, 249; emotions and, 8, 170172, 257, 265, 343; conditions of autonomy, 183,
178, 180, 184185, 189, 214; end-of-life decisions 206, 233, 235, 246, 257, 267; conditions of
and, 326, 348; environment and, 214; epistemic, self-governance, 24, 3032, 40; honesty with
172; feminist scholarship and, 4, 62, 87, 95, oneself and, 196; mental freedom and, 187190
201; free, 179, 232; full-fledged, 165, 171, 176, authority, 8, 9094
212, 281; gender socialization and, 94; general autonomous agency in work, 288290
account of, 173; global characteristics of, 92, autonomous personhood, 44, 59, 90, 216217, 289
250; human flourishing and, 214215, 283; autonomously chosen work, 284285
local characteristics of, 92; membership in a autonomy: in bioethics, 333335; of body, 10;
moral community and, 319320; moral, 348; care-based analyses, 18; choices and, 8;
oppositional, 114; oppression and, 2, 46, 9, competency, 122, 126, 139, 260, 276; concept of,
88, 93, 103, 201, 211, 214, 231, 244, 249250, 338; 39, 61, 164165; defined, 12, 45, 78, 141, 257, 265;
passivity and, 214; of patients, 328; practical, dimensions of, 56; economic independence,
352Index
epistemic values, 120, 125126, 127, 135 freedom to do otherwise model, 232, 238243
equal pay for equal work, 157 free will and autonomy, 165, 185
equality: in capabilities theory, 29; disability Freudian psychoanalysis, 70
activism and, 344; gender, 29, 142, 157, 159, Freud, Sigmund, 63
255, 258, 262, 264, 271, 275, 279; as a goal of Friedman, Marilyn: autonomy, defined by,
liberalism, 43, 45; moral, 157; of opportunity, 27, 77; concept of autonomy, 7; on emotions,
30, 285, 388; value of, 5, 43 167; financial insecurity, 145; limitations of
ethical theory, 2 opportunities, 2; nonrelational theories, 8889;
eudemonistically meaningless work, 280281, oppressive norms, 129; personal autonomy,
293300 95; philosophical conceptions of autonomy,
evaluative identity categories, 219220, 224 45; relational autonomy and independence,
exploitation: bioethics and, 26; economic or 42; self-made men and women, 83; social
financial, 145, 282; feminism and, 153 conditions and reflective values, 334; women as
external critical perspectives, 131 capable of own rights of full moral agency, 156
Frye, Marilyn, 3
Fast Food Women (Lewis), 287 full-fledged or full-blooded agency, 165, 171
Feeling Theory, 168
Feit, Mel, 302 Gallagher, Janet, 321
feminine model of relational autonomy, 67 Gates, Bill, 51
feminine psychoanalytical development, 7 gender conformity, 117
feminism: autonomy and, 2, 710, 83, 141143, gender, defined, 259
150153, 156159, 270, 278; embodiment gendered socialization: autonomy-supportive,
and, 306; defined, 142, 258; liberal, 258, 259260; defined, 259; definitions and
278; sameness approach to, 264; relational assumptions, 257259; evaluation of options,
autonomy and, 78, 62, 77 265278; forms of, 260265; gender norms and,
feminism commitments: agential voice and 227233; non-gendered socialization, 261262,
authority, 105112; autonomy, 150153; cultural 265271; overview, 910, 255257; revisionary
and religious patriarchy, 146150; democratic feminine gender socialization, 263265, 275
participation, 102104; gender socialization, 9, 278; traditional masculine gender socialization,
255261, 265, 2704, 277; human development, 262263, 271275
153156; internalized oppression, 9496; gender identity, 6466
objections to, 157158; overview, 78, 8789, Gender in the Mirror (Meyers), 5
141143; social commitments to inclusion, gender oppression, 2, 4, 5, 20, 24, 227, 229. See
96102; social-relational power and authority, also oppression
9094; wage labor, 143146 gender psychology, 70
feminist intuition, 9495, 116118 gender-specific discipline of boys and girls by
financial insecurity, 144145 mothers, 68
first-order cares, 191, 193, 195 gender system, 268270
first-order desires, 183, 213 Genovese, Kitty, 314
Flathman, Richard, 80 Gill, Carol, 340
Flax, Jane, 61, 67, 68 Gilligan, Carol: on care, 182; moral maturity, 190
flourishing, 116, 132, 214215, 230, 240242, 263, 193, 197; object relations theory, 61; relational
276, 281, 283, 293, 300 autonomy, 69
Forbes Magazine, 51 global autonomy, 1920, 2324, 249250
Foucault, Michel: care of the self, 190, 192194, global self-esteem, 213
197; on freedom, 7677 Globe and Mail (Canadian newspaper), 148
Frankfurt, Harry: autonomous decision making, Gomberg, Paul, 285, 296
343; autonomy and, 87; commitment of the Good Work (Schumacher), 281
will, 190; hierarchical model of free will, 165; government, role of, 50, 54
identification of will, 18; personhood and Groundwork for a Metaphysics of Morals
freedom of the will, 182184 (Kant), 284
freedom: concept of, 62; conditions of
self-determination, 17, 2527; defined, 76; of habitual actions, 176
international movement, 25; negative liberty, Hampton, Jean, 311
26; relational autonomy and, 7, 7678; role of, Harding, Sandra, 6162, 67, 69
7176 harm principle, 251
Index 355
will: commitment of, 190; freedom of, 182184; work: autonomous agency in, 288290; autonomy
free will, 165, 185; identification of, 18 and, 280284; dehumanization of, 283300;
Winnicott, D. W., 67, 68, 69 equal pay for, 157; heteronomous, 284285;
Wolff, Jonathan, 155 identity and, 291; impact on autonomous
Wollstonecraft, Mary, 71 capabilities, 10; as key to success, 5253;
womanhood: NGS view of, 267; RFGS view of, meaningless, 280281, 293300; self-respect
264, 275; TMGS view of, 273, 274275; value and, 291293; social recognition, 38
system of, 114
women: harm suffered by, 60; Ludicrous Young, Iris Marion, 272
Argument and, 163164
Wood, Allen, 297, 298 Zerilla, Linda, 63