07 Birney Sternberg
07 Birney Sternberg
07 Birney Sternberg
perspective. In M.E. Lamb & M.H. Bornstein (Eds.), Cognitive Development: An Advanced
INTRODUCTION
Although the study of cognitive and intellectual development is often seen as quite separate and
distinct from, say, social development, emotional development, and moral development, few
researchers would disagree that development draws from a multitude of cognitive, non-cognitive,
and situational facets that together, the processes involved in social, emotional, moral, as well
as cognitive development, determine at least to some extent how closely an individuals global
potential is realized (Neisser et al., 1996). Even within the group of researchers who study
cognitive and intellectual abilities and their development, different approaches and
methodological paradigms have been used. These approaches have at times been thought to be so
distinct that they have been considered as separate domains of investigation. Whereas it might be
convenient and expedient to parcel the study of cognition and its development into manageable
pieces, it is also important to recognize that these pieces are often just part of the full cognitive
development story. There have been various calls over the years to try to integrate the findings
from the different approaches to conceptualizing cognition (e.g., Ackerman, 1987; Cronbach,
1957; Hunt, 1980; Sternberg, 1977). When attempting this, one is pressed to recognize the large
emerge clearly when only a single methodological approach is used. In this chapter, we attempt
to review a selection of theories, findings, and issues that span methodologies which we believe
are significantly related to the development of cognitive abilities. Some of the theories and
psychology (i.e., Piagetian theories). Other theories are more contemporary (i.e., development of
conceptualizations of development (i.e., the relation between concept formation and creativity).
We feel this breadth provides for a deeper appreciation of the multifaceted issues that influence
cognitive development.
We have separated the chapter into five sections. The first section reviews briefly what is
considered the traditional developmental perspective of cognitive abilities. The second section
considers some of the theorizing and findings in cognitive development from the information-
processing tradition. These types of theories were built on a metaphor of the mind as a computer
(Sternberg, 1990) and emerged following a general dissatisfaction with the ability of the
behaviorist movement of the 1960s to sufficiently account for variability in learning. Over time
the computing mind analogy was extended to try to model the massive parallel processing
believed to take place in the human brain (e.g., McClelland, Rumelhart & Hinton, 1986;
Rumelhart, 1990), while at the same time reflecting known psychological limitations in working
memory (e.g., Halford & Wilson, 1980; Halford, Wilson & Phillips, 1998) and knowledge-
acquisition processes (Anderson, 1982). Research in this area has seen considerable growth in
large part due to the active involvement of multidisciplinary teams of researchers that have
scientists and engineers, and philosophers. The great advances and espoused potentials also
subsumes much of the infrastructure of what was once considered Piagetian and then neo-
The third section explores some of the findings from psychometric studies of cognitive
and intellectual development using correlational methodologies that attempt to identify and map
out the constellation of cognitive abilities. Much of what is known about intelligence and
Cognitive Development 4
cognitive abilities is due to psychometric studies. This is due in part to the immense importance
placed on the outcomes of psychometric testing by its stakeholders. Because the correlational
methodology of psychometric studies focuses on prediction (partly for construct validation, and
partly as an end in itself), this area of research has been of applied interest for selection decisions
in education, military institutions, and training in corporate and other government organizations.
The psychometric approach has been and continues to be influential in expanding our view of
intelligence and cognitive development and in modeling relations with other non-cognitive
factors such as personality, motivation, and knowledge (e.g., Ackerman, 1996; Ackerman &
Beier, 2003). Whereas psychometric theories have been instrumental in mapping the range of
different abilities, the differential approach underlying these theories has been less useful in
eliciting an understanding of the intellectual processes involved (Deary, 2001; Lohman & Ippel,
1993).
two theories, those of Sternberg (1997) and of Gardner (1993). These theories integrate aspects
In the fifth and final section, we explore some relatively recent findings from approaches
processing, creativity, and a well-developed capacity for social, emotional, and moral reasoning.
Piaget
Piaget [1896-1980] is arguably the most influential researcher of all times within the area
of cognitive-developmental psychology (Bidell & Fischer, 1992). He began his work in cognitive
Cognitive Development 5
became interested in childrens answers to intelligence-test items. Piaget asserted that researchers
could learn as much about childrens intellectual development by examining their incorrect
answers to test items as by examining their correct answers. By observing childrens errors in
reasoning, Piaget determined that coherent logical systems underlie childrens thinking. These
systems differ from the systems adults use. To understand development, these systems and their
distinctive characteristics must be identified. With this interest, Piaget proceeded to write about
Development of knowledge and abilities were, according to the Piagetian account, the result of
the individual constantly interacting with the environment in an attempt to maintain a balance
between his or her current needs and understandings, on the one hand, and the demands of the
environment, on the other. Piagets theory embraces two biological antecedents of cognitive
development, specific heredity and general heredity. Specific heredity takes several forms. One
aspect of specific heredity is the automatic behavioral reaction, or reflex. All members of a
species, with the exception of those with defects, inherit the same physical mechanism that
creates the reflex. The presence of a stimulus activates this mechanism which, in turn, causes the
reflex. For example, the sucking reflex in human infants is necessary for infants survival. An
infant does not need to be taught how to suck, and the response will enable the infant to eat. If an
object (the stimulus) touches the infants lips, the infant will automatically respond with sucking
(the reflex). These reflexes are significant in the first few days of an infants life. After that
Cognitive Development 6
initial period, the infants interactions with the environment (i.e., experience) modify the reflexes
follow a genetically determined course for the growth of physical structures. This physical
mature, various activities are able to emerge. For example, as children age, their brains grow and
their muscles become stronger. Childrens ability to speak emerges as their brains grow
(MacWhinney, in this textbook). Also, as their leg muscles strengthen, they gain the ability to
walk, which allows them to explore the world (Adoph & Berger, in this textbook). According to
Piaget, physical maturation, coupled with experience and other factors, is necessary for
maturation and experience (e.g., Halford, 1993), the extent that the effects of maturation and
experience are dissociable has been an issue of continued debate. This is epitomized in the
identification of precocity the case in which a childs level of performance is beyond what
would be expected given his or her developmental level. Precocity is contentious because the
relative distribution of maturation versus experience has many applied implications, particularly
for early education (e.g., at what age will the cognitive architecture be in place to enable a given
concept to be understood and mastered). Precocity, as we will show below, has also been the
The second biological factor in Piagets theory is general heredity. General heredity
comprises two basic inherited tendencies, or invariant functions that govern interactions of the
individual with the environment: organization and adaptation. The first process, organization, is
exist, there is a tendency toward combining these representations into a higher-order, integrated
scheme. Schemes are structures of knowledge and, in the Piagetian account, are the building
accommodation. Assimilation is the process of fitting information from new experiences into
take account of new information. Although assimilation and accommodation occur at the same
time, the balance of each is determined by the specific situation. Cognitive structures and hence
abilities are seen as a result of the childs (and later adults) attempts to organize experience in a
coherent way (Bidell & Fischer, 1992; Case, 1992b; Piaget, 1950; Sattler, 1992).
psychological structures result. These structures, called schemes, change as a child matures.
Some schemes are innate, but most are not and are based largely on experience. For example,
Piaget refers to the sucking reflex as the sucking scheme. However, thumb sucking is not
innate because, although sucking is a reflex, the act of moving the thumb to the mouth is learned.
When children do not change very much, they assimilate more than they accommodate.
Piaget referred to this steady period as a state of cognitive equilibrium. During periods of rapid
cognitive change, however, children are in a state of disequilibrium, in which they accommodate
more than they assimilate. They find that they frequently have to modify their current schemes
due to an influx of new information. Piaget referred to this back-and-forth movement from
schemes (Piaget, 1985). Schemes that are similar and occur in the same developmental time
Cognitive Development 8
period cluster together to form stages (Tanner & Inhelder, 1956). In terms of intellectual
development, the Piagetian theory proposes four major developmental stages (or periods)
through which the child progresses. These are the: (1) sensorimotor period, (2) preoperational
period, (3) concrete-operations period, and (4) formal-operations period. These stages reflect the
gradual reorganization of basic cognitive processes and operations that facilitate (or at least
Sensorimotor development (birth to 2 years). The first stage, the sensorimotor period, is
divided into six substages because so much change occurs in childrens first 2 years of life.
Piaget believed that children are born with little knowledge about the world and a limited
capacity to explore it. Because they need an effective way to modify their early schemes, Piaget
asserted that infants use a circular reaction. Such reactions originate when infants accidentally
generate a new experience because of their own motor activity. Through a process of trial and
error, infants try to repeat the occurrence over and over. The circular reaction strengthens into a
scheme for the child. Two other abilities that Piaget cited as occurring in the sensorimotor period
are play and imitation. They have important roles in consolidating old schemes and developing
new ones. Piaget viewed play as a form of assimilation. Through play, children rehearse current
schemes simply for pleasure. Piaget also associated imitation and accommodation. By imitating
others, children copy and learn behaviors that are not in their inventory of schemes.
In Substage 1: Reflexive Schemes (birth to 1 month), the various reflexes with which the
infant is born are the initial sensorimotor schemes, and therefore, the building blocks for later
and more complex schemes. For example, a newborn will suck when presented with a nipple, but
the newborn may also appear to suck when no stimuli are present.
Cognitive Development 9
ability to gain simple motor control through primary circular reactions. In this stage, infants also
experience some anticipation (e.g., sucking behavior is displayed, in anticipation of being fed, as
soon as the child is placed in the mothers arms), and play and imitation make their first
Substage 3: Secondary Circular Reactions (4 to 8 months) are responses on the part of the
infant that produce responses from objects or people. Children begin to display diverse motor
skills, learning to manipulate objects, sit up, and crawl. These skills direct their attention away
from themselves and toward the environment. When children at this age discover an exciting
behavior, such as banging a toy against a table, they will repeat this action. They also have a
8-month-old children are able to retrieve objects that are partially hidden, but not completely
hidden. Children at this age can also anticipate where to look for an object. For example, if an
infant drops a toy, the infant will anticipate where it will land, even if the descent of the toy was
begin to coordinate their schemes to build more complex action sequences. As a consequence,
infants become more skilled at two cognitive abilities object permanence and goal directed
behavior. Infants are more skilled at understanding that objects truly continue to exist when they
are not in view. Therefore, when an object is completely covered by a cloth, the infant will lift
the cloth off and grasp the object. However, if the object is moved under a different cloth (B), the
infant will continue to look under the original cloth (A). Piaget concluded that 8- to 12-month-
olds make this AB (or A not B) search error because they cannot sustain a clear image of the
Cognitive Development 10
object after the object is removed from their sight. In substage 4, a child will engage in goal-
directed behaviors. At this point, infants have had a great deal of experience with various
schemes and are therefore able to coordinate several schemes using an overarching goal to solve
a variety of problems. Piaget considered this coordination to be the first real intelligent behavior
concerned only with themselves; they now have true interest in their surroundings. As a result,
they have circular reactions tertiary ones that are novel, creative, and experimental, and that
allow them to explore the world. Children now deliberately vary their repetitions to produce
different outcomes. For example, infants will devote time to experimenting with a block and a
hole, varying the orientation of the block until it fits the hole.
This experimentation with different types of objects provides a child at this substage with
a better understanding of object permanence. The child will no longer make the AB search error
because the child will search in several places until he or she finds the hidden object.
create mental representations, which includes the ability to use mental terms, symbols, and
images to refer back to previously experienced events and objects. Children can now solve
problems using mental representations instead of using circular reactions. For instance, suppose a
child gets a toy stuck in the slats of a crib. A child younger than 18 months would move and pull
the toy in a random manner until the toy comes loose. A child in substage 6 would study the
Cognitive Development 11
situation and find a systematic way of loosening the toy, as if the child were mentally
With the ability to represent objects and events mentally comes deferred imitation the
ability to repeat the behavior of a model who is no longer present. Children at this age are able to
imitate new behaviors without the numerous trials of a substage 5 child. When the model is
absent, the child can reenact the previously learned behavior. It is assumed here that mental
representation also ushers in the beginnings of pretend play. Shortly before their second birthday,
children start to pretend to act out familiar activities, such as eating and sleeping.
Preoperational period (2 to 7 years). The most noticeable change that children undergo
from the sensorimotor stage to the preoperational stage is their tremendous increase in
representational activity. Piaget recognized that language is an individuals most flexible means
of representation. By thinking in words, individuals can deal with the past, present, and future at
the same time and create powerful images of reality (Miller, 1993). However, Piaget did not
consider language as creating higher forms of cognition. Instead, although the details were never
clearly explained, Piaget believed that experience with sensorimotor activity leads to mental
generally agree that toddlers understand that pictures stand for real objects. In fact, even young
infants can recognize the similarities between pictures and their represented objects (e.g.,
DeLoache, Strauss, & Maynard, 1979) and their differences (e.g., Slater, Rose, & Morrison,
1984).
Cognitive Development 12
Young children do, however, run into some confusion with more difficult problems. For
instance, suppose a child is watching a television show containing a helium balloon and then is
asked, If I take the top off the TV and then I shake it, would a real balloon come floating out
into the room? The majority of 3-year-olds would say yes. However, when explicitly taught
about the differences between photos of objects, videos of objects, and real objects, many more
of them would answer correctly (Flavell, Flavell, Green, & Korfmacher, 1990).
which emerges around the age of 2 years. Its development has been written about extensively by
researchers, including Bretherton (1984), Fein (1979), Garvey (1990), and Vygotsky (1978).
Piaget (1951) viewed pretend play as an opportunity for a child to exercise symbolic schemes.
This view is now considered too narrow because research shows that pretend play also
contributes to a childs social and cognitive skills (Singer & Singer, 1990). Children who spend a
great deal of time in sociodramatic play pretend play with others tend to be more socially
competent (Burns & Brainerd, 1979; Connally & Doyle, 1984) and more imaginative and
creative (Dansky, 1980; Pepler & Ross, 1981). Pretend play comes from separating behaviors
and objects from their actual use and using these behaviors and objects for play. For instance, a
child eats dinner at dinnertime, in the kitchen, and usually when hungry. However, when
pretending to eat dinner, a child can do so at another time, in another place, and in another
egocentric with respect to their symbolic viewpoints. They believe that everyone elses thoughts,
feelings, desires, and perceptions are the same as theirs (Piaget & Inhelder, 1956). Piaget claimed
that egocentrism is also responsible for childrens erroneous and inflexible thinking. Because
Cognitive Development 13
they are unable to consider other peoples points of view, they do not always accommodate in
operational stage, their thought resembles adult thought more so than the thought of a
sensorimotor or a preoperational child, because their reasoning becomes more flexible, logical,
and organized, and thus more powerful (Piaget & Inhelder, 1969). This period is marked by the
acquisition of operations. Prior development has placed the groundwork for this achievement.
Children in the sensorimotor stage learned to interact physically with the world; preoperational
manipulate their mental representations internally. Operations are characterized by their ability to
be reversed and to be organized with other operations into greater systems. Children acquire
taking; and spatial operations, including comprehension of distance, time, velocity, and space.
However, concrete-operational children can think only about concrete information. Their
operations fail when applied to abstract ideas. Although their problem-solving ability
mushrooms, they cannot do certain types of abstract reasoning. This ability is acquired in the
formal-operations stage.
Formal-operational period (11 years onward). This stage is characterized by the ability
to operate on operations because adolescents and near-adolescents can now think abstractly
(Inhelder & Piaget, 1958). Three main capabilities arise: reasoning with abstract possibilities,
to look for the solution to conceptual problems by manipulating the data with their logical
concrete-operational skills. They seek the one real answer. By contrast, formal-operational
Cognitive Development 14
adolescents and adults tend to work in the opposite direction: They start with possible solutions
and progress to determine which is the real solution, called reasoning with abstract possibilities
Formal-operational thinkers inspect the given data, form some hypothesis about what
possibly could be the correct explanation, deduce whether it logically can occur in reality, and
then test their theories to see whether their predictions hold. This is called hypothetico-deductive
reasoning. If any of these steps fall short, the process is reiterated. These theories are conceptual
entities constructed by abstract thinkers after careful analyses of the problem situations. These
testing each one individually against reality. Concrete-operational thinkers look only for a factual
relation between a single proposition and reality. A formal-operational thinker goes one step
further and reasons about the logical relations that exist between two or more propositions.
Piaget dubbed this more abstract form of reasoning interpropositional (Flavell et al., 1993).
Cross-cultural studies of Piagetian tasks in the 1960s and 1970s showed that people in
many cultures do not seem to achieve formal operations without schooling (e.g., Ashton, 1975;
repealed the claim that his stages are universal, because achieving formal operations is dependent
on experience with the specific scientific thinking found in science classes and is thereby not
stages. To Piaget, stages occur at roughly the same ages for different children, and each stage
builds on the preceding stage. Stages occur in a fixed order and are irreversible: Once a child
enters into a new stage, the child thinks in ways that characterize that stage, regardless of the task
domain, the specific task, or even the context in which the task is presented. Other theorists (e.g.,
Beilin, 1971; Gelman, 1969), including some neo-Piagetians (e.g., Case, 1992a), would disagree
with this view, suggesting that there may be greater flexibility in the cognitive-developmental
progression across tasks and task domains than Piaget suggested. Much of the criticism of
Piagets theory has to do with the inflexibility of his proposed stages and uses of evidence of
precocity as support.
For example, Piaget asserted that object permanence develops from manipulating objects,
a skill he believed emerges in substage 4. Yet, all his tests of object permanence involve infants
reaching for objects. Using reaching tests may underestimate infants conceptual abilities
because the infants failure to respond correctly may be due simply to infants immature motor
systems (Baillargeon, 1993; Diamond, 1990; Mandler, 1988). In Piagets tests, the infant has a
difficult task of removing the cover before grasping the object. Regardless, Piaget concluded
from these tests that young infants are lacking the ability to represent objects mentally. Later
Baillargeon & DeVos, 1991), which used a method to study object permanence that did not
require the infant to reach for an object (habituation/ dishabituation task), infants as young as 3
months showed indications of object permanence. This finding, combined with the findings of
Spelke (1991; Spelke, Breinlinger, Macomber, & Jacobson, 1992), lends credence to the
Cognitive Development 16
hypothesis that young infants fail Piagets original tests because the tests require behaviors of
which the infants are not yet capable (e.g., reaching). Research suggests that infants probably
have some understanding that hidden objects continue to exist, and that this understanding comes
months earlier than Piaget had thought, and may even be present from birth. Similar evidence of
apparent precocity that questions the immutability of other stages and operations such as mental
representation and problem solving, has also been presented (see Lutz & Sternberg, 1999, for
Fundamental Criticisms
developmental processes result from children's adaptations to their environment, he held that
internal maturational processes, rather than environmental contexts or events, determine the
children's perception of the environment, of the child's prior experiences with the task and the task
materials, and even of the experimenter's presentation of the task itself may lead to apparent
unevenness in cognitive development. Although Piaget allowed for some differences across task
domains through a construct he called horizontal dcalage, the mechanism underlying this construct
was never clearly explained, and in the context of the theory, it seemed to be an after-the-fact
Consistent with this fact, theorists and researchers have questioned Piaget's interpretation
regarding what causes difficulty for children in certain Piagetian tasks. Piaget's theory
emphasizes the development of deductive and inductive reasoning, and Piaget held that
limitations on children's ability to reason cause their difficulties in solving particular cognitive
Cognitive Development 17
tasks. Different theorists have suggested that other kinds of limitations may at least partly
influence children's performance on Piagetian tasks. Such limitations include children's motor
coordination, as well as working memory capacity (e.g., Bryant & Trabasso, 1971; Kail, 1984;
Kail & Park, 1994), memory strategies (Siegler, 1991), or verbal understanding of questions
The evidence cited against Piagets theory often refers to childrens inconsistent abilities
to perform well on tasks believed to be beyond their stage of development. However, Thelen and
Smith (1994) presented an approach to development that assuages many of the apparent
problems for Piagets theory. In particular, Thelen and Smiths dynamic-systems approach, in
which discontinuities occur as part of the natural interaction of nonlinear dynamic systems
(systems with highly complex physical properties in this case, children and their environment),
predicts the very kinds of conflicting performance seen in children on the verge of stage
transition. Indeed, Thelen and Smith pointed out that instability is necessary for new abilities to
develop a system must contain variability in its behavior for new behaviors to be selected.
Furthermore, this disequilibrium is part of the natural interaction of the nonlinear dynamic
systems involved in childrens interactions with their environment. Thus, the dynamic systems
progress through stages, but not strictly via maturation. Research on the non-linear development
of mathematical skills supports such a dynamic view of development (Rittle-Johnson, Siegler, &
Alibali, 2001).
These ideas notwithstanding, even adolescents and adults do not show formal-operational
thinking under many circumstances (Neimark, 1975). They often seem to think associatively
rather than logically (Sloman, 1996). In 1972, Piaget modified his own theory to acknowledge
Cognitive Development 18
that the stage of formal operations may be more a product of an individual's domain-specific
In sum, Piagets descriptions of infant development and the research methods he used are
commendable and historically important, but the theory he originally posed has not endured.
Although substantial biological maturation occurs at each of Piaget stages, maturation is seen
primarily as a necessary but not sufficient condition for the development of many cognitive
skills. Learning experiences derived from optimal interactions with the environment help to
determine the full extent of the development of cognitive abilities (Bidell & Fischer, 1992;
Halford, 1999; Piaget, 1950). In fact, learning experiences, particularly those in which the
complexity of the environment is mediated by a teacher, are considered by many to be not only
advantageous, but crucial to cognitive development (e.g., Feuerstein, 1979; Lidz, 2000;
Vygotsky, 1962).
Limitations of Piagets theory as described above (see also, Lutz & Sternberg, 1999;
Sternberg & Powell, 1983) led to subsequent extensions and advances on many of Piagets
original conceptualizations (e.g., Carey, 1985; Case, 1985, 1992b; Halford, 1993; Pascual-Leone,
but focus more within a framework of working memory development. We review two related but
somewhat quite distinct approaches as espoused by Case and by Halford, and then consider the
Case. Case (1985, 1992a), like Piaget, proposed that children move through four
developmental stages. The types of mental representations children can form and the types of
responses they give characterize these stages. In the first stage, sensorimotor operations,
Cognitive Development 19
childrens representations consist of sensory input, and their responses to this input are physical
concrete mental images, and their responses can produce additional mental representations. In
the next stage, logical operations, children have the abilities to represent stimuli abstractly and to
respond to them with simple transformations. The final stage, formal operations, differs from the
previous stage in that children continue to represent stimuli abstractly, but they can now execute
change. In one of Cases demonstrations of the existence of this ability, he placed children of
different ages at one end of a balance beam. Case showed the child that if the balance beam were
pushed down, it would ring a bell. A young infant would only be able to follow visually the
beam's movements. Older infants between 4 and 8 months would be able to push down the beam
and ring the bell, thereby coordinating two actions visual tracking and hand movements
instead of one isolated activity as before visual tracking. An even older child, between 8 and 12
months, would be able to incorporate another property in a modified version of this problem,
when the bell was moved out of the childs sight and placed on a different part of the beam.
Finally, 12- to 18-month-old children were able to succeed when the problem required the child
to push the beam up instead of down. Younger children were not able to reverse the learned
action, as they consistently pushed the beam down and became upset when the bell would not
Cases explanation for older childrens success on the final problem was that the problem
contains two units, the pushing of the beam and the ringing of the bell, which are separate
enough for older children to be able to see their reversible relation. The children are able to see
Cognitive Development 20
that, when one end of the beam goes down, the other end goes up, and vice versa. Within Cases
theory of development, the execution of this behavior shows that a child has the ability to form
subgoals (pushing beam) to reach a final goal (ringing bell). The behaviors that lead up to a
childs success on a given problem illustrate cognitive change. To reach a goal, a child must
either draw on learned strategies or formulate new ones. Childrens collections of strategies
expand as they mature. They gain mental capacity and the ability to deal with more and more
information. In this respect his theory is similar to Halfords theory of relational complexity. We
Halford et al.: Relational complexity theory. Similar to Case, Halford and his associates
(Halford, 1993; Halford & Andrews, 2004; Halford, Baker, McCredden, & Bain, 2005; Halford,
et al., 1998) view cognitive development as the result of the differentiation of working memory
that facilitates the capacity to deal with tasks of increasing complexity. In their account,
(1998) argued that capacity limitations are best conceptualized not simply as a count of the
pieces of information that can be stored and manipulated in working memory, but that the
complexity of relations between these pieces of information is crucial. Hence, the theory has
What does a relation look like? Consider for example the comparison of size. Halford
(1993) argued that size comparison requires a binary relation between has two pieces of
information (or arguments, in the authors parlance), as might be represented by: LARGER-
THAN (elephant, mouse). This is read as, elephant is larger than mouse, where elephant and
Cognitive Development 21
mouse are the two arguments that form the relation, LARGER-THAN. Ternary relations have
components. The more arguments or pieces of information that are required to instantiate a
relation, the greater the cognitive complexity of the task and the greater the demand placed on
There are at least four types of evidence that have been used to provide support for the
relational complexity theory. These are: (1) age-of-attainment evidence the finding that tasks of
similar relational complexity have similar median ages at which levels of performance become
better than chance (Andrews & Halford, 2002; Bunch, Andrews, & Halford, 2007; Halford,
Andrews, Dalton, Boag, & Zielinski, 2002; Halford, Bunch, & McCredden, 2007); (2) dual-task
studies the finding that secondary (dual) task deficits increase as relational complexity in the
primary task increases (e.g., Foley, 1997; Foley & Berch, 1997; Halford, Maybery, & Bain,
1986; Maybery, Bain, & Halford, 1986); (3) neurological correlates of relational reasoning the
finding that increasing relational complexity of tasks is associated with increased activation in
regions of the brain associated with executive function, the main processing component of
working memory (e.g., Kroger et al., 2002; Waltz et al., 1999); and (4) perceived or subjective
workload ratings the finding that increases in relational complexity are associated with
perceived increases in cognitive demand (Andrews & Halford, 1995; Boag, Neal, Halford, &
development, and it is appropriate to consider the context in which this evidence is acquired in
more detail.
Cognitive Development 22
Andrews and Halford (2002, p. 161) argued that a conceptual complexity metric, such as
provided by relational complexity theory, has much to offer the investigation of cognitive
them appear to have the advantage of simplicity, but they provide no way of comparing
tasks for their conceptual complexity. Thus superficially dissimilar tasks, such as
turn out to be equivalent in conceptual complexity. Apparently similar tasks may be very
different in complexity. A complexity metric can help to resolve this issue by identifying
tasks that are at the same levels of complexity and separating them from lower and higher
levels of complexity.
To investigate their claim, Andrews and Halford (2002) considered the performance of
children on a number of superficially dissimilar task that have similar levels of complexity. We
consider two of their tasks as examples, transitivity and class inclusion. Their transitive inference
task required children to order colored-squares (e.g., red, green, blue, yellow, pink) so that they
were consistent with separately presented premises that described the correct order of the squares
(e.g., red is above green; green is above blue; blue is above yellow; yellow is above pink). The
binary version of the task required children to construct a five-square tower in which the order of
the squares was consistent with the premises. The ternary version required children to determine
which of two non-adjacent squares (i.e., green and yellow) would be higher up the tower. This
second version of the task required the integration of two separate premises in working memory
(green is above blue; blue is above yellow), and this type of reasoning has been shown to entail
greater cognitive demand than simple (binary) ordering of adjacent elements (Maybery et al.,
Cognitive Development 23
1986).
The class-inclusion task requires recognition of the fact that the relation between a
superordinate class (e.g., fruit) and two or more subordinate classes (e.g., apples and non-apples)
is asymmetrical. That is, while all members of a subclass (apples) can be included in and share
the properties or attributes of the superordinate class (fruit), the reverse does not necessarily hold
all fruit do not have the same properties as apples. Andrews and Halford (2002) argued that a
capacity to process ternary relations is required to understand this type of asymmetry. Therefore,
although a task requiring this reasoning is clearly different from, say, the ternary version of the
transitive inference task, they are similar in the complexity of the relations that are entailed.
Consistent with the relational complexity theory, the authors showed that the median age at
which the superficially dissimilar ternary tasks were mastered is in fact similar. Furthermore, in
terms of cognitive development, the average proportion of participants succeeding on the ternary
tasks at each age-level were approximately 15.5% of 3- and 4-year olds, 48.3% of 5-year olds,
70.2% of 6-year olds, and 77.8% of 7- and 8-year olds. Thus it was concluded that the capacity
Halford et al. (1998) argued that relational-complexity theory is not a stage theory in the
way other neo-Piagetian theories might be considered to be (Case, 1985; Pascual-Leone, 1970).
However, as we have just described, mastering a particular level of relational processing has
been aligned with ages-of-attainment that are similar to Piagetian stages (Halford, 1993) on what
are often called Piagetian tasks. This finding has been cited as evidence to support relational
complexity theory. The crucial difference, it would seem, is at least two-fold. First, development
is conceptualized by relational complexity theorists as being more gradual and less explicitly
for relational processing that coincides with age, than as the development of specific skills or
operations per se. This is not to say that specific skills and knowledge are not important in
relational complexity theory; they are. Differences in strategies can result in marked differences
in the complexity of the processing. It is therefore very important to ensure that an appropriate
methodology is in place to take knowledge into consideration (see Andrews & Halford, 2002, for
Knowledge and the development of working memory capacity. The types of errors made
implications for cognitive theory testing (e.g., Lohman & Ippel, 1993; M. J. Roberts, 1993). For
instance, various modifications of Piagets balance-beam task have been useful in exploring the
interplay between knowledge and cognitive capacity in complex reasoning. In another version of
the balance-beam task (we have already considered one version as used by Case, 1985, 1992a),
individuals are required to indicate whether a beam with various weights at certain distances on
each side of a fulcrum will balance (see for example, Halford et al., 2002; Siegler & Chen,
2002). An algorithmic approach to determining whether the beam will balance is to calculate the
product of weight and distance on one side of the beam and to compare this with the product of
weight and distance on the other side. Such a strategy is demanding of working memory
resources. Young children (< 7 years) typically resort to considering fewer dimensions. Is this
difficulty a result of lack of knowledge or limited cognitive capacity? The answer is probably
both. Although it is clear that relations among weight, distance, and balance can be discovered
Halford et al. (2002) argued that more complex relations (among weight, distance, and
balance) can be represented as age and working memory capacity increase, consistent with the
Cognitive Development 25
predictions of relational complexity theory (Halford, 1993). However, adults have also been
observed to have difficulty with the balance-beam task (even though capacity is presumably less
of an issue). This difficulty tends to indicate that knowledge and experience are also important
Although neo-Piagetian research has provided many insights into the sequential
development of childrens long-term understanding of basic logical reasoning (e.g., Carey, 1985;
Case, 1985, 1992b; Halford, 1993; Pascual-Leone, 1970; Schliemann & Carraher, 2002), it is not
always clear that development is as regular and sequential as these theories might imply.
Research in mathematical abilities, for instance, has shown that skill development can be quite
chaotic and non-linear (Rittle-Johnson et al., 2001). The theories we have discussed so far have
been predominately concerned with describing and explaining cognitive development. An area of
cognitive science research that is less frequently aligned with traditional conceptualizations of
development focuses on the process of knowledge acquisition and information processing, rather
than development per se. Part of the reason that development can be quite chaotic and non-linear
may be due to differences in available knowledge and experience that lead to both different
strategies for information processing and further knowledge acquisition. We consider some of
the theorizing in these areas next and argue that this work has indirect but important implications
Cognitive-processing theories tend to focus on task and person characteristics that relate to
learning and lead to differences in performance (e.g., novices versus expertise; Chi, Glaser &
Rees, 1982; Shafto & Coley, 2003). They are not necessarily explicitly linked to cognitive
Cognitive Development 26
maturation through childhood (although some are). They have often been developed using adult
by what are referred to as computational models. These models attempt to formalize cognitive
theories using advanced mathematics and statistics (e.g., Braine, 1990; Johnson-Laird, 2001;
Johnson-Laird, Byrne, & Schaeken, 1992; Rips, 1983, 1994; Simon & Halford, 1995). There are
important differences between the models in terms of the level and type of formalization as well
as the psychological theory on which they are based. What is common to each is an attempt to
model the effect of task characteristics on reasoning and problem solving while taking into
knowledge. That is, there is a concerted attempt to specify a theory of reasoning sufficiently
detailed to be able to identify and methodologically differentiate the specific task characteristics
that mediate performance (Embretson, 1995, 1998; Embretson & Gorin, 2001).
The impact of these complex theories is far reaching. Taken to their extreme (i.e., with
the psychological limitations removed), computational information-processing models are all but
indistinguishable from the artificial intelligence models that are the basis of many computer-
financial markets. They all try to characterize the often-complex interactions between
components of the environment such as the phonology of an utterance or the subtle fluctuations
financial success).
Sternberg (1977), who decomposed the classical analogy task (A:B::C:?) into elementary
performance components. The types of components or process that have been investigated in this
Cognitive Development 27
task include the encoding of problem details, inference making processes, mapping of inferred
relations, as well as processes related to the application, comparison, and justification of the final
response. The general strategy of this research was to specify an information-processing model
of task performance and to propose a parameterization of this model so that each information-
characteristics. Recall that Case regarded cognitive change as the ability to deal with more and
more elements of a problem. The change in ability was seen as a change in the efficiency of
processing. That is, reminiscent of classic working memory models in which separate storage
and processing components are proposed (Baddeley & Hitch, 1974) and consistent with resource
theory (Kahneman, 1973; Norman & Bobrow, 1975), Case proposed that total processing space
(TPS) was a resource that could be flexibly allocated to either processing (i.e., operating space,
OS) or storage (short-term storage-space, STSS) that is, TPS = OS + STSS. After infancy, total
processing space was considered to be relatively constant over age. Case argued that the
demands for operating space actually declined with age because of the increase in processing
efficiency. Given the closed nature of the proposed system, this served to free short-term storage-
space. Hence the empirical research that demonstrated an increase in short-term memory span
with age was attributed to more efficient processing. This was considered the main factor
responsible for cognitive development (Case, Kurland, & Goldberg, 1982; Halford, 2002).
Cognitive Development 28
It is important to comment on the unitary nature of the processing system that resource
theory might be assumed to propose, given what is presented in the previous paragraph. First,
most researchers now accept the existence of multiple resources, rather than a single resource
(e.g., Wickens, 1991). Second, even though resource theory has served as the dominant metaphor
for limited capacity theories such as those proposed by Case and by Halford, its utility has been
questioned. Navon (1984) argued that resource theory should be considered only as a metaphor
for information-processing because it cannot differentiate between the effects of processes that
compete for a common resource and the effect of output interference generated elsewhere in the
system. That is, differentiation of the cognitive architecture is often identified by the
characteristics of tasks that interfere with each other and those that do not. For instance, the
finding that certain visual processing tasks did not interfere (in terms of accuracy and response
times) with phonological processing tasks leads to the postulation of separate visual- and
auditory-processing systems (Baddeley, 1986). Tasks that interfere with each other are assumed
to require a common system of resources, and, hence, freeing up resources in one task should
result in better performance in the other. Navon argued that dual-task deficit, as this interference
is known, can be accounted for without imposing the additional baggage of resource theory (such
as the need to postulate additional resources when interference is not complete). Oberauer and
Kliegl (2001) suggested that decay (temporal loss of information in working memory) and
interference are sufficient to account for limits in working memory without additional constructs
factor that impacts on the assessment of a developing cognitive system. The evidence that
working memory develops with age does not necessarily mean that development entails a
Cognitive Development 29
quantitative change of a single entity, such as resources. Fry and Hale (2000, p. 6) described
some evidence [that] suggests that there may be qualitative changes in working memory
function prior to entering the first grade. In particular, under some circumstances younger
children prefer to use different mnemonic strategies than older children (emphasis added). Part
of this qualitative change is seen to be a function of pre-school childrens preference for visual
processing rather than phonological processing. This preference changes as the focus of
experience at school becomes more verbally based. The potential role of knowledge and
experience are once again implicated in the relation between development and capacity and the
apparent increase in efficiency of the cognitive system. Research therefore tends to support a
multi-component perspective of working memory, not only in terms of the differentiation of the
storage systems, but also in terms of the differentiation of the central executive and its relation
best epitomized by the early work of Newell and Simon (1972) and that of Anderson and his
(Anderson, 1982, 1983, 1990; Anderson & Lebiere, 1998; Anderson & Schunn, 2000; Rumelhart
entail the assimilation of new information into the network as a series of declarative facts or
productions. During the early stages of skill acquisition, this declarative information can be used
to facilitate successful problem solving without the need to access (or possess) context-specific
Cognitive Development 30
strategies. With each successful application of the information, links between appropriate nodes
are strengthened. Unsuccessful applications result in the links between nodes being weakened.
Together, these experiences can be brought to bear on new information and new problems to
facilitate a more automatized set of procedures that can be implemented with increasing
efficiency to acquire new information and to solve problems (Schunn & Reder, 2001) this is
procedural knowledge. For instance, a child learning a new mathematical rule relating the area of
a rectangle to the product of its length and breadth will store this information in the semantic
network as a declarative fact. Links from this fact to other personally relevant types of
information are likely to be developed at the same time for instance, the table is a rectangle,
squares are like rectangles, and the area of a square is length length. With experience,
appropriate links will be reinforced and inappropriate ones weakened. Within the ACT
framework, procedural knowledge is represented by a large number of rule-like units that are
referred to as productions (Anderson & Schunn, 2000). Production rules are condition-action
units (i.e., IFTHEN rules) that specify the cognitive actions that are the responses to certain
problem-solving conditions.
For instance:
thereby facilitate subgoaling (e.g., IF multiply, THEN, and so on). The centrality of
productions in this theorizing has meant that the framework is sometimes referred to as a
production-system.
Cognitive Development 31
found in the concept of a schema. Schematic knowledge is highly context specific (Quilici &
Jong & Ferguson-Hessler, 1996; Rittle-Johnson et al., 2001) and procedural knowledge, in
addition to what has been referred to as situational knowledge, which provide cues to when
knowledge should be used (Cheng & Holyoak, 1985; de Jong & Ferguson-Hessler, 1996).
of the domain, but this high contextualization can also come at a cost. It may place constraints on
the availability of certain information and in some cases can produce near-transfer failure the
unexpected failure to transfer knowledge from one context to a similar one in the same domain
(Woltz, Gardner ,& Gyll, 2000). That is, situation cues can become so entrenched with task
performance that even slight changes in the nature of the task can produce failure because the
in intelligent behavior are the result of variations in system efficiency and flexibility in selecting
and applying appropriate rules to problem solving (Just & Carpenter, 1992). For instance, in the
simulated air-traffic control task described by Kanfer and Ackerman (1989) and an application of
the ACT framework, Schunn and Reder (2001) showed that, although people may appear to
possess similar strategies for allocation of task resources, there are individual differences in the
ability to appropriately select from the available strategies in response to feedback from the
environment (i.e., success or failure in landing aircraft). Schunn and Reder argued that these
differences in strategy adaptivity are associated with differences in reasoning ability and
Many of the theories so far discussed have been criticized as being too reductionistic and
as being incapable of accounting for individual differences in strategy use (e.g., M. J. Roberts,
Schaeken & d'Ydewalle, 1999; Schunn & Reder, 2001), others have arguably pursued an even
greater degree of reductionism in attempts to identify the very basic and implicit processes of
cognition. One such area where considerable research has been invested explores how categories
and concepts form and develop (e.g., Markman & Gentner, 1993; Murphy & Medin, 1985;
Posner & Keele, 1968). For instance, what are the processes involved in the development of an
understanding that a Doberman, say, is a member of the dog family, that dogs are part of an even
larger superordinate category of mammals, and so on? In general, the research questions how
different branches and nodes within and between trees of knowledge become related to each
prototypes (Posner & Keele, 1968). Prototypes are defined as a generalized conceptualization of
an entity that consists of the typical attributes associated with the most commonly found
instances of the entity (prototypical entities are, in effect, averages, and like statistical averages,
they may not actually occur in practice). Given the shared experiences of most people through
mass education and popular media, prototypes tend to be relatively consistent from one
individual to another, although not completely so, particularly within a given culture. A
prototype of a dog, say, may be a medium-sized animal that has four legs, is brownish in color,
has a wagging tail, and do forth (Chi, 1997). The ease in classifying a new previously unseen
Cognitive Development 33
instance of the dog category will be determined partly by how typical the attributes of the new
dog are. That is, the likelihood of assigning some example to a category depends on the
similarity of the example to the category representation (Medin, Goldstone, & Gentner, 1993, p.
254). For instance, a Labrador is likely to be more readily recognized and classified as dog than a
Toy Poodle because many of the attributes of a Labrador are more similar to the common
conceptualization of dog. In much the same way, a whale might be more readily, although
incorrectly, identified as a fish, rather than as a mammal, because certain attributes of whales are
not typically associated with mammals (e.g., they live in the ocean and swim). Furthermore,
beliefs about whether one entity of a category (e.g., tuna) has a certain property (e.g., disease X),
given that another entity of the category (e.g., goldfish) has the same property (disease X), vary
as a function of how similar the two entities (tuna and goldfish) are perceived to be (Medin et al.,
Much of the research in this area has been conducted under the experimental/cognitive
direct effect of experience and expertise (Shafto & Coley, 2003), although not exclusively so. As
children learn and experience more, their knowledge base expands and new or unseen instances
(entities) are not only classified into one or more categories, but the categories themselves may
continually be modified by experience. This is not unlike the processes of accommodation and
assimilation proposed by Piaget. In other words, category definitions and concepts expand and
narrow to accommodate new information and new attributes. This process is ongoing and
continues into adulthood. For instance, the list of attributes of mammals might be expanded to
include some qualifications stating that whales are in fact mammals that breathe air and have live
This line of research has focused on identifying the processes and nature of knowledge
acquisition. However, the findings also have direct implications for the investigation of more
complex reasoning (Coley, Hayes, Lawson, & Moloney, 2004) and cognitive development. For
example, the analogical reasoning involved in the classic A:B::C: ? type-problem (where ? is D,
components (A, B, C, D, E, F, and G). These relations and attributes often belong to overlapping
categories that sometimes differ in hierarchical levels. This knowledge may be necessary for
There are numerous factors that need to be considered to determine the correct response
(coop). The relation between horse and stable will need to be considered. So will the different
categorical (hierarchical) levels between the response options (e.g., sty, coop, and stable are
knowledge about the relations and categories, and of course, individuals will need to have had
the opportunity to acquire this knowledge. This opportunity can vary quite substantially both
Over and above the opportunity to learn, individuals differ in their basic capacity to
acquire and represent knowledge and then to draw on this knowledge for future reasoning (Just
& Carpenter, 1992; Schunn & Reder, 2001). There is also recognition of the role of individual
differences from within cognitive research in concept formation. Chi (1997), for instance, argued
that one component of creativity entails flexible movement between branches and nodes of
categorical trees of knowledge. Moving within levels of one tree tends to be reasonably straight-
forward. For instance, re-classifying a whale as a mammal rather than as a fish can be
Cognitive Development 35
accomplished gradually over time with experience, or through direct mediated instruction from a
respected and more knowledgeable other (e.g., teacher, peer, or parent). However, re-
representing entities from one tree to another tends to be more difficult because different trees,
especially those that are fundamentally different, are considered to be different ontologically (in
philosophical terms, ontologies (or ontological trees) are structures of knowledge that have an
entire hierarchy of categories that are fundamentally different from each other. The attributes of
such trees are referred to as ontological attributes (see Chi, 1997, for further discussion of the
important distinction. Chi (1992) argued that ontological attributes are not modifiable, either
physically or mentally. Yet other types of attributes that are not fundamental may be modified.
That is, once an entity is classified into a particular categorical tree into a particular framework
of knowledge it inherits all the ontological attributes associated with that tree or framework.
Moving from one tree to another is difficult because all the basic ontological attributes associated
with the entity need to be modified to move between trees (Chi, 1997). The typical outcome of
an attempt to reconceptualize entities across ontological boundaries is, for all intents and
purposes, nonsensical. Chi (1997, p. 218) argued that one can move between branches of a tree
that have a common ontology and be able to conceptualize a statement such as, A dog is
purple. One attribute of the category dog is color. Although purple may be a false instantiation
of the color of dogs (at least as far as we currently know), the statement makes sense. With
sufficient factual support, it could result in a minor restructuring of the concept/category of dog
without changing the ontological attributes associated with dogs in general (and other entities
Cognitive Development 36
within the tree). However, if, as suggested by Chi (1997), we cross over between trees and try to
situation. We cannot make sense of this statement without reconceptualizing many of the
citizens in the late 1800s, when evolutionary theorists began to argue that humans are not as
distinct from non-human primates and other animals as was once believed. That is, rather than
being conceived of as two distinct categorical trees (humans vs. others) consisting of distinct and
separate ontological paths and attributes, humans and other animals began to be considered as
inhabiting different levels of the same ontological category. Similarly, one can imagine the
difficulty of people at the time when Galileo and others shook the religious and scientific
thinking of the day and argued that the Earth was not the center of the universe and that it, in
fact, revolved around the sun, rather than vise versa. Arguably, both these conceptual changes
had massive rippling effects throughout science and society, as the full implications of changing
ontological categories became more and more evident and the cognitive dissonance generated by
new information and previously held (and conflicting) beliefs was reconciled (e.g., the
implications of evolutionary theory on religious beliefs still cause concern in many parts of the
world today).
Chi (1997) to be a candidate for a core component of creativity. It is a difficult and cognitively
demanding process that entails a certain degree of knowledge and experience, but it is also a
process that requires the flexibility to appreciate and apprehend the full implications of changing
the underlying associations with ontological attributes. To the extent that there are individual
Cognitive Development 37
differences in flexibility, or creativity, one might also expect individual differences in at least
two areas. First, there may be individual differences in the knowledge required to modify the
representation of the entity (e.g., when new information becomes available that refutes the
original classification of an entity). Second, there may be individual differences in the cognitive
capacity or flexibility of individuals in seeing how new and disparate pieces of information can
be combined in novel ways to generate a new and insightful solution to an old problem (e.g.,
information that conflicted with the view that the sun revolves around the Earth).
This latter requirement, the capacity for flexible thinking, is probably the most
the analytical skill necessary to assimilate multiple perspectives. Traditional ability theories (e.g,
working memory theories) are in a good position to account for some of this difficulty. For
instance, the process theories described earlier, such as relational complexity theory (Halford et
al., 1998), may be useful in the analysis of the difficulty or complexity of different types of
ontological shifts and re-classification (e.g., Halford, Andrews, & Jensen, 2002, using the
relational complexity theory, account for the difficulty of cognitive processing in class inclusion
tasks and hierarchical classification tasks which exploit the products of concept-category
formation processes). However, as the above examples also demonstrate, there are other
demands (social, cultural, motivational) that can also influence the likelihood of creative ideas
being supported and further developed. Sternbergs (1997) theory of successful intelligence,
particularly that part of the theory related to creative intelligence, has been used to account not
only for the analytical demands of the creative process, but also for the practical skills required
Both Darwin and Galileo were under intense pressures of the time not to report their
creative ideas. Defying this pressure required considerable courage, as well as practical
intelligence to know when and how best to sell their ideas. The theory of successful intelligence
(Sternberg, 1997) formalizes an explicit role for creativity that, with further development and
research, may provide an individual-differences framework for exploring the type of flexibility-
viewing processes at different levels of focus. Although it is true that, alone, much of the basic
research described in this section is probably too reductionistic and ecologically weak to be of
any use in directly predicting successful cognitive development (and success in life), it is
invaluable in providing insights into future applied research. Traditionally, there have been only
Psychometric theories attempt to identify the full constellation of cognitive abilities and to map
the interrelations between them. Given this focus, psychometric theories have typically tended to
be somewhat agnostic to the underlying processes of the abilities that have been identified
(Deary, 2001; Lohman & Ippel, 1993). However, much is being done to link process theories of
abilities (e.g., working memory theories) and development with psychometric theories (e.g.,
Cowan et al., 2005; Unsworth & Engle, 2007).We turn now to the area of psychometric
development.
Cognitive Development 39
ABILITIES
Many different definitions of intelligence have been proposed over the years (see, e.g.,
"Intelligence and its measurement: A symposium", 1921; Sternberg & Detterman, 1986). The
to extend this definition by suggesting that there is a general factor of intelligence, often labeled
g, which underlies all adaptive behavior (Brand, 1996; Jensen, 1998; see essays in Sternberg &
Grigorenko, 2002). As we describe briefly below, the consensual notion of intelligence as ones
ability to adapt to ones current situation or environment has been formalized by Sternberg
practical intelligence (Sternberg et al., 2000). This has been done in a way that is quite distinct
In many psychometric theories, including those most widely accepted today (e.g., Carroll,
1993; Gustafson, 1994; Horn, 1994), a number of differentiable but variously related mental
abilities are proposed. The positive interrelation between these abilities that people strong in
one area also tend to be strong in others is used as evidence to support the proposed
hierarchical nesting of these abilities under one or more general cognitive ability factors at
successively greater levels of specificity. In fact, most psychometric theories, described in more
detail elsewhere (Brody, 2000; Carroll, 1993; Embretson & McCollam, 2000; Herrnstein &
Murray, 1994; Jensen, 1998; Sternberg, 2000), use evidence from correlational research to
As an example of how correlational evidence is used for construct validation and theory
building, consider the common distinction that has been empirically identified between verbal
and visual-spatial abilities. Different verbal measures (e.g., vocabulary, sentence comprehension)
tend to be more correlated with each other than with visual-spatial measures (e.g., paper folding,
mental-rotation). The converse is also true different visual-spatial measures tend to be more
highly correlated with each other than with verbal ability measures. In factor analysis, an
advanced statistical technique based on correlations (Hartmann, Pelzel, & Abbott, in this
textbook), this would result in the identification of two separate factors, a verbal and a visual-
spatial factor. The separation of factors is used as evidence that the measures tap distinct
constructs. However, research has also shown that even though verbal and visual-spatial abilities
are separable, the correlation between the measures of each ability is not exactly zero. This
pattern of varying but positive correlation persists across many cognitive measures (i.e., the so-
called positive manifold). This manifold has been cited as evidence that there is something real
Exactly how the common variation in cognitive performance is partitioned is one major
way psychometric theories are differentiated. Some argue that a higher-order general ability
construct (g) that variously determines performance in each of the specific lower-order abilities
is the most parsimonious account for this commonality (e.g., Herrnstein & Murray, 1994; Jensen,
1998). Carroll (1993) suggested that three levels (narrow, broad, and general) are needed to
capture the hierarchy of abilities, whereas Cattell (1971) suggested two levels were especially
important. In the case of Cattell, nested under general intelligence are what he referred to as fluid
intelligence (Gf) and crystallized intelligence (Gc). Fluid intelligence is skill in reasoning in
novel ways. Typical tests of Gf, such as Ravens progressive matrices, entail the ability to induce
Cognitive Development 41
relations and deal with various levels of abstraction. Crystallized intelligence is ... a type of
broad mental ability that develops through the investment of general intelligence into learning
through education and experience (Carroll, 1993, p. 599). Crystallized abilities are therefore of
the kind considered to be the main manifestation of education, experience, and acculturation.
Extensions of the Gf-Gc theory include a range of other broad and specific abilities, including
those associated with memory, visuo-spatial abilities, and speed of processing (e.g., R. D.
Some psychometric theorists believe that, relative to ones peers, intelligence is fixed
relatively early in life between 5 and10 years of age after which it tends to remain stable (see
Bjorklund, 1995; Neisser et al., 1996). The stability beyond this period is seen by some as an
epiphenomenon (Cattell, 1987; McArdle, Ferrer-Caja, Hamagami, & Woodcock, 2002). Cattell
(1987), for instance, argued that the apparent stability of intelligence is the necessary outcome of
aggregating across multiple abilities that have different developmental trajectories. That is,
Cattell, and also Horn (1988), argued that, whereas both Gf and Gc rise through youth until early
adulthood, Gf reaches its peak relatively early (15-20 years) and later declines at a relatively
rapid rate. Gc, in contrast, tends to continue increasing well into the 60s and 70s. This research
has been extended. For instance, McArdle et al. (2002) showed a range of differences in the
developmental trajectories of the various cognitive abilities and academic knowledge assessed by
the Woodcock-Johnson tests (Woodcock & Johnson, 1989). Different developmental trajectories
are also cited as evidence for separable factors and the diminutive importance of g.
Psychometric test scores administered after about 5 years of age tend to be reasonably
predictive of later abilities and achievement (Bjorklund, 1995; Sattler, 1992). At younger ages,
the stability and predictive utility of ability estimates is substantially weaker, particularly for
Cognitive Development 42
individuals in the average or superior levels (Chen & Siegler, 2000; Sattler, 1992). For infants,
better predictors of future abilities than are reasoning measures, although the correlations are
typically modest (Bornstein & Colombo, 2010). One explanation for the lack of predictive power
differentiated with age and experience (Carroll, 1993; Halford, 1993). Generally, after this
period, psychometric test scores become stable and follow the trajectory described above. The
question remains, do psychometric test scores sufficiently represent the abilities needed to adapt
Sternberg (1985, 1998a, 1999a) and an increasing group of others (e.g., Ackerman &
Beier, 2003; Ericsson, Krampe, & Tesch-Rmer, 1993; Gardner, 1993) have argued that the
psychometric definition of intelligence has become (or always was) too narrow to provide a
reasonable account of performance in real-world settings, the settings in which many of the
measures were originally designed to assess. The restriction, we believe, is partly due to the
analytical abilities) and partly due to the inadequacies of available methodologies to fully
accommodate multidimensional and complex traits (Birney & Sternberg, 2006). Research on
practical and creative intelligence (Sternberg, 2003c; Sternberg et al., 2000), social intelligence
(Cantor & Kihlstrom, 1987; Kihlstrom & Cantor, 2000; Sternberg & Smith, 1985), and
emotional intelligence (Goleman, 1995; Mayer & Salovey, 1993; Salovey & Mayer, 1990) is
trait theories (e.g., Borsboom, Mellenbergh, & van Heerden, 2003) and measurement (e.g.,
Linacre, 1989; Michell, 1999; Wright, 1999) will further strengthen the methodological
Cognitive Development 43
foundations to accommodate even more refined empirical research into these complex traits.
Already, considerable work has been invested to demonstrate that it is possible to not only assess
creative and practical intelligence (e.g., Birney, Grigorenko, & Sternberg, 2004), but also to
develop effective educational interventions that exploit students range of creative, practical,
analytical, and memory abilities (e.g., Grigorenko, Jarvin, & Sternberg, 2002; Sternberg, Torff,
& Grigorenko, 1998; Williams et al., 2002). Much of this thinking forms the foundation for the
The theoretical basis for the developing expertise model is Sternbergs (1985, 1997,
2003c) triarchic theory of successful intelligence. According to this theory, intelligence is, in
part, the ability to achieve success in life through a balance of analytical, creative, and practical
function of the ability to recognize and capitalize on ones strengths and to correct or compensate
for ones weaknesses. Fitting in with this view is the broad conceptualization of intelligence and
intellectual achievements as forms of developing expertisethey can be developed, just like any
other forms of expertise. The theory of developing expertise conceptualizes abilities as a set of at
least five cognitive competencies in varying stages of development (Sternberg, 1998a, 1999a,
2003a). (1) Metacognitive skills are related to skills required for recognizing, defining, and
representing the problem; for formulating strategies and resource allocation; and for planning,
monitoring, and evaluating success of a chosen strategy. (2) Learning skills or knowledge-
acquisition skills are the skills that are necessary to know which information in a problem to
attend to (i.e., to encode); to know which existing information to select for comparison with the
Cognitive Development 44
new information; and to know how to combine new and old understandings to solve the problem
analytical, creative, and practical thinking skills is necessary to optimize success (Sternberg,
1997). (4) Knowledge is not only an outcome of development, but it is also necessary for future
development. Knowledge in both declarative and procedural forms is necessary. (5) The
determining element is having sufficient motivation to bring these skills to bear on problem
solving. Without sufficient motivation, abilities remain inert. Hence motivation is the driving
Past experiences and differences in personality will influence levels of motivation in any
given context and ultimately determine the opportunities that children (and then adults) have to
develop certain abilities and expertise (Ackerman, 1996; Ackerman & Beier, 2003). Parents and
teachers are significant determinants of the experiences of young children (Ceci, Ramey, &
Ramey, 1990). They are also likely to have some impact on whether the child perceives these
motivation. Over time, the developing child has increasingly more choice in the types of
experiences he or she engages in, and a more complex array of factors starts to play on levels of
motivation (e.g., developing interests, peer pressure, financial and romantic rewards). The five
components of the developing-expertise theory all interact fully in context as the novice works
toward expertise through deliberate practice (see Ericsson et al., 1993, for a discussion on the
role of deliberate practice). For instance, motivation drives the application of metacognitive
skills. These skills in turn facilitate learning, which enables not only ones level of expertise to
increase, but also the efficiency with which these skills will be implemented in the future.
Multiple Intelligences
Cognitive Development 45
Gardner (1993, 1999) does not view intelligence as a single construct. Instead of
speaking of multiple abilities that together constitute intelligence, like some other theorists,
Gardner proposed a theory of multiple intelligences, in which eight distinct intelligences function
somewhat independently but may interact to produce intelligent behavior. The types of
interpersonal, intrapersonal, and naturalist. Gardner (1999) also speculated on the possible
functioning. Nevertheless, these systems can interact to produce intelligent performance. For
example, novelists rely heavily on linguistic intelligence but might use logical-mathematical
intelligences separately may produce a profile of skills that is broader than would be obtained
from, say, measuring verbal and mathematical abilities alone. This profile could then be used to
evidence from multiple sources and types of data. The evidence includes (but is not limited to)
the distinctive effects of localized brain damage on specific kinds of intelligences, distinctive
patterns of development in each kind of intelligence across the life span, exceptional individuals
Gardners view of the mind is modular. Modularity theorists believe that different
abilities can be isolated as they emanate from distinct portions or modules of the brain. Thus, a
major task of existing and future research on intelligence is to isolate the portions of the brain
responsible for each of the intelligences. Gardner has speculated about some of these relevant
portions, but hard evidence for the existence of separate intelligences has yet to be produced.
Cognitive Development 46
One might argue that the culmination of the skills and abilities we have so far reviewed in
this chapter leads not only to the development of effective analytical, critical, creative, and practical
thinking, but also to some sense of wisdom. It is to this concept that we turn to in the final section.
Wisdom has, amongst other things, been defined as the power of judging rightly based on
knowledge, experience, and understanding. Reaching a wise decision involves a balancing act of
intrapersonal, interpersonal, and extrapersonal interests. In turn, short- and long-term interests
Intelligence and creativity are necessary, but not sufficient skills for wisdom. Furthermore,
wisdom is not simply the application of intelligence in creative ways, but rather the more highly
evolved form of successful intelligence. It is not enough to have an understanding of the situation
at hand, but rather it is necessary to have the ability to dynamically consider different
perspectives to the mutual benefit of all those involved. This balancing act requires the
application of values with the intent of achieving a common good (Sternberg, 1998b). In this
Wisdom is related to other cognitive abilities, but is also unique. In particular, it is related
(Sternberg, 2003c, 2007). Indeed, Baltes built his widely accepted theory of wisdom around the
concept of knowledge about the pragmatics of life (Baltes & Staudinger, 2000; Baltes,
Staudinger, Maercker, & Smith, 1995). We consider five characteristics of wisdom: knowledge,
Cognitive Development 47
metacogntion, creativity, practical intelligence, and social intelligence, and then consider some
First, wise thinking requires knowledge, but a major part of wisdom is tacit, informal
knowledge of the kind learned from hands-on experience, not the kind of explicit formal
knowledge taught in schools. One could possess book smarts or excel in the classroom, yet
show little or no wisdom because the kind of knowledge one needs to be wise is typically not
found in books or in the type of teaching found in most schools. That is, wisdom requires not
simply the kind of knowledge and analytical thinking emphasized in schools or measured on
tests of academic achievement. Rather, wisdom requires the analysis of real-world dilemmas
where clean and neat abstractions often give way to messy, disorderly, and conflicting concrete
interests.
developing expertise, wisdom also seems related to metacognition because the metacomponents
involved in wisdom are similar or identical to those that follow from other accounts of
metacognition (Campione, Brown, & Ferrara, 1982; Nelson, 1999; Sternberg, 1985). In wisdom,
as in other types of thinking, one especially needs to be aware of ones own thought processes.
allocating resources to the solution of these problems, and so forth. These skills are used in
wisdom, as they are in other types of thinking, but in wisdom they are especially important in
Third, wisdom is related to creativity. Creative people often tend toward extremes,
although their later contribution may be more integrative (Gardner, 1993). Creative thinking can
often be brash, whereas wise thinking is balanced. This is not to say that the same people cannot
Cognitive Development 48
be both creative and wise. It is to say, however, that the kinds of thinking required to be creative
and wise are different and thus will not necessarily be found in the same person. As Gardner
(1993) suggested, creative people may not be wise, and they may even be foolish in their
dealings with other people. Moreover, teaching people to think creatively (see Sternberg &
(2003c) intuition can offer alternative solutions by allowing the individual to read between the
lines, as well as the ability to understand and interpret their environment. Creativity allows the
wise thinker to generate novel solutions in situations that cannot be resolved by defined and pre-
existing heuristics. Wise thinking must be creative to generate a novel and task-relevant high-
quality solution involved in the balancing of interests. Novelty, task-appropriateness, and quality
mathematical proof but have no particular characteristics of wisdom. The proof does not
Fourth, although practical thinking is closer to wisdom than are analytical and creative
thinking, it is also not the same as wisdom. Wisdom is a particular kind of practical thinking. It
(1) balances competing intrapersonal (ones own), interpersonal (others), and extrapersonal
(larger) interests, (2) over the short and long terms, (3) balances adaptation to, shaping of, and
selection of environments, in (4) the service of a common good. People can be good practical
thinkers without being wise, but they cannot be wise without being good practical thinkers. Good
practical thinking is necessary but not sufficient for the manifestation of wisdom (Sternberg,
2003c).
Cognitive Development 49
Fifth, wisdom also seems to be related to constructs such as social intelligence (Cantor &
Kihlstrom, 1987; Kihlstrom & Cantor, 2000; Sternberg & Smith, 1985), emotional intelligence
(Goleman, 1995; Mayer & Salovey, 1993; Salovey & Mayer, 1990), and interpersonal and
intrapersonal intelligences (Gardner, 1993, 1999). Again, there are also differences. Social
intelligence can be applied to understanding and getting along with others to any ends for any
purposes. Wisdom seeks out a good outcome through a balancing of interests. Thus, a sales
person who figures out how to sell a worthless product to a customer might do so through using
social intelligence to understand the customers wants, but has not done so to achieve a mutually
beneficial end.
Social and emotional skills are important parts of wisdom. But making wise judgments
processing the information to achieve a balance of interests and the formulation of a judgment
that make effective use of available information to achieve a common good. Moreover, wisdom
may require a balance of interpersonal and intrapersonal intelligences, but it also requires an
understanding of extrapersonal factors, and a balance of these three (often conflicting) factors to
attain a common good. Thus wisdom seems to go somewhat beyond these theoretically distinct
kinds of intelligences as well. Perhaps the most salient differences among constructs is that
wisdom is applied toward the achievement of ends that are perceived as yielding a common
good, whereas the various kinds of intelligences we have mentioned may be applied deliberately
toward achieving either good ends or bad ones, at least for some of the parties involved. It is
interesting that the conception of wisdom proposed here is substantially closer to Chinese than to
American conceptions of intelligence (Yang & Sternberg, 1997a, 1997b). One of the words used
To a large extent, the development and display of the attributes described in this section
is a decision over which one has substantial control, not merely some kind of innate set of
predispositions. That is, wisdom is in large part an active decision to use ones intelligence,
creativity, and knowledge for a common good (Sternberg, 2007). Thus, the development of
wisdom entails the application of many of the attributes that have been discussed in this chapter.
It entails the application of cognitive abilities; it entails the application of knowledge; and it
entails the application of creativity. But most importantly, wisdom entails the development of a
mindset or habit to be motivated to understand things from diverse points of view across time
CONCLUSION
In this chapter we have considered just a small selection of the many theories that have been
proposed to describe and account for the development of a range of cognitive and intellectual
abilities. We have attempted to broaden our view beyond the areas that are typically considered
central to cognitive development in the hope that we can demonstrate the complexity of the
issues that are involved, and provide evidence for an increased emphasis on integration. We have
We believe that each approach invariably draws more heavily on the others than what has
often been recognized. Psychometric theories model individual differences in a broad range of
abilities and have indeed provided much of what is currently known about intelligence.
However, even though the psychometric approach has continued to be immensely influential in
various educational, military, and commercial applications, it is not currently well equipped for
theories are typically restricted to describing the changing constellation of abilities over time
(e.g, differentiation of abilities with age and changing developmental trajectories), with little
acquisition processes and the development of such constructs as working memory capacity. This
approach is subsuming much of the traditional Piagetian notions of development. However, there
capacity, and psychometric constructs such as fluid and crystallized intelligence, as well as the
role of creative and practical abilities. This is particularly true given that many information-
changes in the cognitive system (e.g., increase in available resources), and that such change may
turn out to be more chaotic, non-linear (recursive), and based on qualitatively different uses of
knowledge and experience than what has thus far been modeled.
could be considered the middle ground on cognitive development, we believe that a complete
understanding of the cognitive developmental process will not be obtainable from either these
approaches, nor in fact from any other single approach in isolation of other research. As such, we
have presented research on such enigmatic constructs as concept development, creativity, and
wisdom. We believe that future theorists of cognitive development may wish to take these
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
An earlier version of this chapter (Birney, Citron-Pousty, Sternberg, & Lutz, 2005) was co-
authored by Donna Lutz; we acknowledge her sections on Piaget from the previous edition that
REFERENCES
Ackerman, P., & Beier, M. E. (2003). Trait complexes, cognitive investment, and domain
competencies, and expertise. (pp. 1-30). Cambridge, UK.: Cambridge University Press.
Press.
Anderson, J. R. (1990). The adaptive character of thought (Vol. 1). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Anderson, J. R., & Lebiere, C. (1998). The atomic components of thought. Mahwah, NJ:
Anderson, J. R., & Schunn, C. D. (2000). Implications of the ACT-R learning theory: No magic
Andrews, G., & Halford, G. S. (1995). Working memory capacity and the comprehension of
relative clause sentences. Paper presented at the 3rd Conference of the Australasian
Andrews, G., & Halford, G. S. (2002). A cognitive complexity metric applied to cognitive
Baddeley, A. D., & Hitch, G. J. (1974). Working memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The Psychology
of Learning and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory (Vol. 8, pp. 47-89). New
Baddeley, A. D., & Logie, R. H. (1999). Working memory: The multiple-component model. In
maintenance and executive control (pp. 28-61). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Baillargeon, R. (1993). The object concept revisited: New directions in the investigation of
Baillargeon, R., & DeVos, J. (1991). Object permanence in young infants: Further evidence.
orchestrate mind and virtue toward excellence. American Psychologist, 55, 122-135.
Baltes, P. B., Staudinger, U. M., Maercker, A., & Smith, J. (1995). People nominated as wise: A
Ford & G. B. Flamer (Eds.), Measurement and Piaget (pp. 172-196). New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Bidell, T. R., & Fischer, K. W. (1992). Beyond the stage debate: Action, structure, and
Birney, D. P., Citron-Pousty, J. H., Sternberg, R. J., & Lutz, D. J. (2005). The development of
Developmental science: An advanced textbook (5th ed., pp. 327-358). Mahwah, NJ:
Birney, D. P., Grigorenko, E. L., & Sternberg, R. J. (2004). An application of the many-facet
at the Annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association, San Diego,
CA.
Birney, D. P., & Sternberg, R. J. (2006). Intelligence and cognitive abilities as competencies in
Boag, C. C., Neal, A., Halford, G. S., & Goodwin, G. (2000). Comparing measures of cognitive
complexity: Cognitive psychology applied to air traffic control. Paper presented at the
Essex, England.
Bornstein, M. H., & Colombo, J. (2010). Infant cognitive functioning and child mental
Borsboom, D., Mellenbergh, G. J., & van Heerden, J. (2003). The theoretical status of latent
Brand, C. (1996). The g factor: General intelligence and its implications. Chichester, England:
Wiley.
Bryant, P. E., & Trabasso, T. (1971). Transitive inference and memory in young children.
Bunch, K. M., Andrews, G., & Halford, G. S. (2007). Complexity effects on the childrens
Burns, S. M., & Brainerd, C. J. (1979). Effects of constructive and dramatic play on perspective
Campione, J. C., Brown, A. L., & Ferrara, R. (1982). Mental retardation and intelligence. In R. J.
Sternberg (Ed.), Handbook of human intelligence (pp. 393-490). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Cantor, N., & Kihlstrom, J. F. (1987). Personality and social intelligence. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Carroll, J. B. (1993). Human cognitive abilities: A survey of factor-analytic studies. NY, New
Case, R. (1992a). The mind's staircase: Exploring the conceptual underpinnings of children's
(Eds.), Intellectual development (pp. 161-196). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Case, R., Kurland, M., & Goldberg, J. (1982). Operational efficiency and the growth of short-
Cattell, R. B. (1971). Abilities: Their structure, growth and action. Boston: Houghton Miffin.
Cattell, R. B. (1987). Intelligence: Its structure, growth and action. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science
Publishers.
Ceci, S. J., Ramey, S. L., & Ramey, C. T. (1990). Framing intellectual assessment in terms of
Chen, Z., & Siegler, R. S. (2000). Intellectual development in childhood. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.),
Cheng, P. W., & Holyoak, K. J. (1985). Pragmatic reasoning schemas. Cognitive Psychology, 17,
391-416.
Chi, M. T. (1992). Conceptual change within and across ontological categories: Examples from
Chi, M. T., Glaser, R., & Rees, E. (1982). Expertise in problem solving. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.),
Advances in the psychology of human intelligence (Vol. 1, pp. 7-75). Hillsdale, New
Coley, J. D., Hayes, B. K., Lawson, C., & Moloney, M. (2004). Knowledge, expectations, and
Connally, J. A., & Doyle, A. B. (1984). Relations of social fantasy play to social competence in
Cowan, N., Elliott, E. M., Saults, J. S., Morey, C. C., Mattox, S., Hismjatullina, A., et al. (2005).
On the capacity of attention: Its estimation and its role in working memory and cognitive
Cronbach, L. J. (1957). The two disciplines of scientific psychology. American Psychologist, 12,
671-684.
Cognitive Development 58
Dansky, J. L. (1980). Make-believe: A mediator of the relationship between play and associative
de Jong, T., & Ferguson-Hessler, M. (1996). Types and qualities of knowledge. Educational
DeLoache, J. S., Strauss, M. S., & Maynard, J. (1979). Picture perception in infancy. Infant
Diamond, A. (1990). Developmental time course in human infants and infants monkeys, and the
neural bases of, inhibitory control in reaching. In A. Diamond (Ed.), The development
and neural bases of higher cognitive functions (pp. 637-669). New York: New York
Academy of Sciences.
Embretson, S. E. (1995). The role of working memory capacity and general control processes in
Embretson, S. E., & Gorin, J. (2001). Improving construct validity with cognitive psychology
Embretson, S. E., & McCollam, K. (2000). Psychometric approaches to the understanding and
Ericsson, K. A., Krampe, R. T., & Tesch-Rmer, C. (1993). The role of deliberate practice in the
Feuerstein, R. (1979). The dynamic assessment of retarded performers: The learning potential
assessment device theory, instruments, and techniques. Baltimore, MD: University Park
Press.
Flavell, J. H., Flavell, E. R., Green, F. L., & Korfmacher, J. E. (1990). Do young children think
Flavell, J. H., Miller, P. H., & Millar, S. A. (1993). Cognitive development (3rd ed.). Englewood
Foley, E. J., & Berch, D. B. (1997). Capacity limitations of a classical M-Power measure: A
Fry, A. F., & Hale, S. (2000). Relationships among processing speed, working memory, and
Gardner, H. (1993). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences. New York: Basic
Books.
Gardner, H. (1999). Intelligence reframed: Multiple intelligences for the 21st century. New
Ginsburg, H., & Opper, S. (1979). Piaget's theory of intellectual development. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Goodnow, J. J. (1962). A test of milieu effects with some of Piaget's tasks. Psychological
Monographs, 76.
Grigorenko, E. L., Jarvin, L., & Sternberg, R. J. (2002). School-based tests of the triarchic theory
Demetriou & A. Efklides (Eds.), Intelligence, mind, and reasoning: Structure and
Blackwell.
Halford, G. S., & Andrews, G. (2004). The development of deductive reasoning: How important
Halford, G. S., Andrews, G., Dalton, C., Boag, C. C., & Zielinski, T. (2002). Young children's
Halford, G. S., Andrews, G., & Jensen, I. (2002). Integration of category induction and
Halford, G. S., Baker, R., McCredden, J. E., & Bain, J. D. (2005). How many variables can
Halford, G. S., Bunch, K. M., & McCredden, J. E. (2007). Problem decomposability as a factor
in complexity of the dimensional change card sort task. Cognitive Development, 22, 348-
391.
Halford, G. S., Maybery, M. T., & Bain, J. D. (1986). Capacity limitations in children's
Halford, G. S., & Wilson, W. H. (1980). A category theory approach to cognitive development.
Halford, G. S., Wilson, W. H., & Phillips, S. (1998). Processing capacity defined by relational
Herrnstein, R. J., & Murray, C. (1994). The bell curve. New York: Free Press.
multivariate psychology (2nd ed., pp. 645-685). New York: Plenum Press.
Horn, J. L. (1994). Theory of fluid and crystallized intelligence. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), The
Inhelder, B., & Piaget, J. (1958). The growth of logical thinking from childhood to adolescence:
An essay on the construction of formal operational structures. New York: Basic Books.
Jensen, A. (1998). The g factor: The science of mental ability. Westport, CT:
Praeger/Greenwood.
434-442.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., Byrne, R. M., & Schaeken, W. (1992). Propositional reasoning by model.
Kail, R. (1984). The development of memory in children (2nd ed.). New York: Freeman.
Kail, R., & Park, Y. (1994). Processing time, articulation time, and memory span. Journal of
Kanfer, R., & Ackerman, P. (1989). Motivation and cognitive abilities: An integrative/aptitude-
657-690.
Kihlstrom, J. F., & Cantor, N. (2000). Social intelligence. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), Handbook of
Kroger, J., Sabb, F. W., Fales, C., Bookheimer, S. Y., Cohen, M. S., & Holyoak, K. (2002).
Press.
Lidz, C. S. (2000). Theme and some variations on the concepts of mediated learning experience
Lohman, D. F., & Ippel, M. J. (1993). Cognitive diagnosis: From statistically based assessment
Test theory for a new generation of tests (pp. 41-70). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.
Lutz, D. J., & Sternberg, R. J. (1999). Cognitive development. In M. H. Bornstein & M. E. Lamb
Markman, A. B., & Gentner, D. (1993). Structural alignment during similarity comparisons.
Mayer, J. D., & Salovey, P. (1993). The intelligence of emotional intelligence. Intelligence, 22.
McArdle, J. J., Ferrer-Caja, E., Hamagami, F., & Woodcock, R. W. (2002). Comparative
longitudinal structural analyses of the growth and decline of multiple intellectual abilities
McClelland, J. L., Rumelhart, D. E., & Hinton, G. E. (1986). The appeal of parallel distributed
Medin, D., Goldstone, R. L., & Gentner, D. (1993). Respects for similarity. Psychological
Miller, P. H. (1993). Theories of developmental psychology (3rd ed.). New York: Freeman.
Murphy, G. L., & Medin, D. (1985). The role of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological
Review, 92.
Navon, D. (1984). Resources - A theoretical soup stone? Psychological Review, 91, 216-234.
Chicago Press.
Neisser, U., Boodo, G., Bouchard Jr., T. J., Boykin, A. W., Brody, N., Ceci, S. J., et al. (1996).
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Oberauer, K., & Kliegl, R. (2001). Beyond resources: Formal models of complexity effects and
age differences in working memory. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 13, 187-
215.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1970). A mathematical model for the transition rule in Piaget's developmental
Pepler, D. J., & Ross, H. S. (1981). The effects of play on convergent and divergent problem
Piaget, J. (1950). The psychology of intelligence (M. Piercy & Berlyne., Trans.): Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Piaget, J. (1951). Play, dreams, and imitation in childhood. New York: Norton.
Piaget, J. (1972). Intellectual evolution from adolescence to adulthood. Human Development, 15,
1-12.
Piaget, J. (1985). The equilibration of cognitive structures: The central problem of intellectual
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1956). The child's conception of space. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Cognitive Development 66
Posner, M. I., & Keele, S. W. (1968). On the genesis of abstract ideas. Journal of Experimental
Quilici, J. L., & Mayer, R. E. (2002). Teaching students to recognize structural similarities
Rips, L. (1983). Cognitive processes in propositional reasoning. Psychological Review, 90, 38-
71.
Rips, L. (1994). The psychology of proof: Deductive reasoning in human thinking. Cambridge,
Roberts, M. J. (1993). Human reasoning: Deduction rules or mental models, or both? Quarterly
Roberts, R. D., & Stankov, L. (1999). Individual differences in speed of mental processing and
Zornetzer, J. L. Davis & C. Lau (Eds.), An introduction to neural and electronic networks
(Ed.), Cognitive skills and their acquisition (pp. 335-359). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Cognitive Development 67
Salovey, P., & Mayer, J. D. (1990). Emotional intelligence. Imagination, Cognition, and
Personality, 9, 185-211.
Sattler, J. M. (1992). Assessment of children: Revised and updated third edition. San Diego:
Schroyens, W., Schaeken, W., & d'Ydewalle, G. (1999). Error and bias in meta-propositional
reasoning: A case of the mental model theory. Thinking and Reasoning, 5, 29-65.
Schunn, C. D., & Reder, L. M. (2001). Another source of individual differences: Strategy
130, 59-76.
Shafto, P., & Coley, J. D. (2003). Development of categorization and reasoning in the natural
Siegler, R. S., & Chen, Z. (2002). Development of rules and strategies: Balancing the old and the
Simon, T., & Halford, G. S. (Eds.). (1995). Developing cognitive competence: New approaches
Singer, D. G., & Singer, J. L. (1990). The house of make-believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Cognitive Development 68
Slater, A., Rose, D., & Morrison, V. (1984). Newborn infants' perception of similarities and
Sloman, S. A. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin,
2, 287-294.
& R. Gelman (Eds.), The epigenesis of mind: Essays in biology and cognition (pp. 133-
Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., & Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge.
Stankov, L. (2000). The theory of fluid and crystallized intelligence: New findings and recent
27, 11-20.
365.
Cognitive Development 69
Press.
Sternberg, R. J. (2004). Four alternative futures for education in the United States: It's our
Sternberg, R. J. (2007). A systems model of leadership: WICS. American Psychologist, 62, 34-
42.
Sternberg, R. J. (Ed.). (1999b). Handbook of creativity. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg, R. J. (Ed.). (2000). Handbook of intelligence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg, R. J., & Detterman, D. K. (1986). What is intelligence? Norwood, NJ: Ablex
Publishing Corporation.
Sternberg, R. J., Forsythe, G. B., Hedlund, J., Horvath, J., Snook, S., Williams, W. M., et al.
(2000). Practical intelligence in everyday life. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg, R. J., & Grigorenko, E. L. (Eds.). (2002). The general factor of intelligence: How
Sternberg, R. J., & Powell, J. S. (1983). The development of intelligence. In J. Flavell & E.
Markman (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology (3 ed., Vol. 3, pp. 341-419). New York:
Wiley.
Cognitive Development 70
Sternberg, R. J., & Smith, C. (1985). Social intelligence and decoding skills in nonverbal
Sternberg, R. J., Torff, B., & Grigorenko, E. L. (1998). Teaching triarchically improves school
Sternberg, R. J., & Williams, W. M. (1986). How to develop student creativity. Alexandria, VA:
Tanner, J. M., & Inhelder, B. (Eds.). (1956). Discussions on child development (Vol. 1). London:
Tavistock.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition
Turner, G., & Thomas, H. (2002). Bridging the gap between theory and model: A reflection in
the balance scale task. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 81, 466-481.
Unsworth, N., & Engle, R. W. (2007). On the division of short-term and working memory: An
examination of simple and complex span and their relation to higher order abilities.
Vygotsky, L. (1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (Original work
published 1934).
Waltz, J. A., Knowlton, B. J., Holyoak, K. J., Boone, K. B., Mishkin, F. S., de Menezes Santos,
M., et al. (1999). A system for relational reasoning in human prefrontal cortex.
Williams, W. M., Blythe, T., White, N., Li, J., Gardner, H., & Sternberg, R. J. (2002). Practical
Woltz, D. J., Gardner, M. K., & Gyll, S. P. (2000). The role of attention processes in near
Hershberger (Eds.), The new rules of measurement: What every psychologist and
educator should know. (pp. 65-104). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Yang, S., & Sternberg, R. J. (1997a). Conceptions of intelligence in ancient Chinese philosophy.
Yang, S., & Sternberg, R. J. (1997b). Taiwanese Chinese people's conceptions of intelligence.