Lacan Unary Trait PDF
Lacan Unary Trait PDF
Lacan Unary Trait PDF
1-2, 2006
Abstract: While a significant amount of research has recently been carried out that investigates
the similarities and differences between Alain Badiou and Jacques Lacans theories of the subject,
less attention has been paid to the direct relationship between the latter and Badious set-theoret-
ical ontology. This article applies some of the most important conceptual propositions advanced
in the first two parts of Being and Event to the key psychoanalytic issue of the identification of the
conscious and unconscious subject as expounded by Lacan in his ninth Seminar, Lidentification.
More specifically, this article aims to show how Badious notions of the count-as-one and the
forming-into-one can profitably be put to work in order better to understand Lacans notions of
the unary trait and the S1, the master-signifier. What is at stake in both cases is the relation-
ship between structure and metastructure, presentation and representation. Furthermore, this
article provides an outline for a set-theoretical formalization of the relation between conscious-
ness and the unconscious as developed by Lacan in Lidentification. Lacans breaking of the solidar-
ity between unity and totality allows him to work with parts: from the inexistence of totality as
a one follows the possibility of thinking the part as partial system. Lacan identifies this system
with the unconscious. Applying a number of set-theoretical axioms, this article argues that the
existence of the unconscious as partial system ultimately relies on the in-existence of the void, or,
more specifically, the existence of the void as part that in-exists as element.
Keywords: Badiou; Lacan; Ontology; Psychoanalysis; Set-theory; Subject; Identification;
Number
Let us give Lacan his due: he was the first to make a systematic use
of numericality
Alain Badiou
Introduction
According to Alain Badiou, psychoanalysis thinks the amorous procedure, one of
the four procedures for the sake of which the abstract categories of his Being and Event
www.cosmosandhistory.org 68
Lorenzo Chiesa 69
. I would like to thank Ana Alvarez Velasco, a true non-working mathematician, for her invaluable advice.
I am also grateful to Alberto Toscano for his Badiouian comments on an early draft of this article.
. Alain Badiou, Ltre et lvnement, Paris, Seuil, 1988, p. 10. The English translation, which is otherwise
excellent, curiously omits this reference to psychoanalysis, replacing it with a reference to artwhich does
not appear in the original, Alain Badiou, Being and Event, trans. Oliver Feltham, London, Continuum, 2005,
p. 4 (henceforth BE).
. Lesson of 29/11/61 from Jacques Lacan, Seminar IX (1961-1962): Lidentification, unpublished (henceforth
Seminar IX).
. Alain Badiou, Infinite Thought: Truth and the Return to Philosophy, ed. and trans. Justin Clemens and Oliver
Feltham, London, Continuum, 2003, p. 6.
. See, for instance, Slavoj iek, The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology, New York, Verso,
2000, pp. 127-70.; Slavoj iek, Foreword to the Second Edition: Enjoyment within the Limits of Reason
Alone, For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political Factor, 2nd, London, Verso, 2002, pp. lxxxi-
lxxxviii. See also Bruno Bosteels, Alain Badious Theory of the Subject: The Recommencement of Dialec-
tical Materialism? (Part I), Pli: Warwick Journal of Philosophy, no. 12, 2001, pp. 200-29, pp, 220-9. and Bruno
Bosteels, Alain Badious Theory of the Subject: The Recommencement of Dialectical Materialism? (Part
II), Pli: Warwick Journal of Philosophy, no. 13, 2002, pp. 173-208, pp. 197-208.; Ed Pluth and Dominiek Hoens,
70 COSMOS AND HISTORY
latter and Badious set-theoretical ontology. Badious ontology of the One and the Mul-
tiplethe a priori conditions of any possible ontologyrelies on the law that the one
is not (BE 23, 28). By Badious own admission on page 1 of Meditation One of Being and
Event, this law is closely associated to Lacans pathbreaking principle according to which
there is [symbolic] Oneness (BE 23)or better, there is only symbolic Oneness. What
Badiou fails to emphasize in this context is that this principle is, for Lacan, confined to
a theory of the subject: in spite of proposing important hypotheses about being, Lacan
never really developed any ontology independently of his notion of subjectivity.
My considerations should therefore always be measured against the threat of a short
circuit in Badious magnum opus, which I do not intend to investigate any further in this
occasion. On the one hand, Badious theory of the subject-event in Being and Event may
rightly be labelled as beyond Lacanas the title of Part VIII of the book suggests
due to his rigorous philosophical appropriation of Paul Cohens mathematical notion
of forcing. On the other hand, in spite of its reliance on the radical thesis according to
which ontology [] is nothing other than mathematics itself (BE xiii), Badious solid
ontological edifice is itself amply anticipated by Lacans own theory of the subject. The
latter is indeed based on the principle that there is only symbolic Onenessor, adopt-
ing a formula closer to Badious own terminology, there is no One except in math-
ematicsalbeit in an often hesitant and imprecise manner. Thus, the least we can say
is that, in practising the ontological categories made available by Being and Event across
Lacanian psychoanalytic notions, we will not be surprised to discover a high degree of
compatibility between them. The ideal result of such a practice would be nothing less
than an accurate set-theoretical formalization of the relation between consciousness and
the unconscious, succeeding there where Lacans courageous attempts to demonstrate
that mathematical topology is structureand meta-structurefailed.
What if the Other Is Stupid? Badiou and Lacan on Logical Time, in Peter Hallward (ed.), Think Again:
Alain Badiou and the Future of Philosophy, London, Continuum Books, 2004, pp. 182-90.
. For a discussion of Lacans ethics as an ontological ethics, see Lorenzo Chiesa and Alberto Toscano,
Ethics and Capital, Ex Nihilo, Umbr(a): A Journal of the Unconscious,, no. 1, 2005, pp. 9-25. And Chapter 5 of
Lorenzo Chiesa, Lacan and Subjectivity: A Philosophical Introduction, Cambridge, MIT Press, 2007.
. Lesson of 17/5/1972 from Jacques Lacan, Seminar XIX (1971-1972), Ou pire, unpublished.
. Topology is not made to lead us to structure. Topology is this structure (Jacques Lacan, Ltourdit,
Autres crits, Paris, Seuil, 2001, p. 483.).
Lorenzo Chiesa 71
having necessarily been structured by means of the count-as-one. As Badiou puts it, the
count-as-one (the structure) installs the universal pertinence of the one/multiple couple
for any situation (BE 24). This amounts to saying that, with regard to presentation, the
one is also an operational result (BE 24, my emphasis). A concomitant splitting occurs
on the side of the multiple: inconsistent multiplicities, multiples that are retroactively
understood as non-one as soon as being-one is a result, are to be distinguished from
consistent multiplicities, multiple[s] as several-ones counted by the action of struc-
ture (BE 25). We can thus conclude that the law that the one is not is at the same time
the law that the one is a law of the multiple (BE 25).
It is vital to stress that, according to Badiou, what is normally presented in any
situation is the fact that the one is: all that is presented in a situation is counted-as-one,
which is to say that the principle the one is not cannot be presented in it. At this level,
inconsistent multiplicity is solely the presupposition that prior to the count the one is
not (BE 52). Having said this, we should also keep in mind that the one is an operational
result, and that for this reason, there must be something of the multiple [that] does
not absolutely coincide with the result (BE 53). In other words, in situations, which are
as such always structured, a remainder exceeds the one of consistent multiplicities, and
this can be nothing other than the very operation, the law of the count-as-one, from
which the one results. With regard to a given situation, inconsistent multiplicities, the
pure multiple, are therefore included as an exclusion: adopting a quasi-psychoanalytic
terminology whose Lacanian affinities, as we shall later see, are remarkable, Badiou
suggests that this inclusive exclusion is what causes the structured presentation to waver
towards the phantom of inconsistency (BE 53, my emphasis). This phantom, a retroactive
by-product of the count-as-one, cannot itself be presented, yet it is included in the situa-
tion in the name of what would be the presentation itself, the presentation in-itself ,
if what the law does not authorize to think was thinkable: that the one is not (BE 53).
Put differently, from the structured situational standpoint for which the law is the one
is a law of the multiple, the phantom of inconsistency amounts to the excluded law that
the one is not.
More specifically, the pure multiple, unpresentable insofar as it is excluded by the
law the one is a law of the multiple, is nothing from the standpoint of the situation. As
Badiou observes, being-nothing is different from non-being: There is a being of noth-
ing, as form of the unpresentable. The nothing is what names the unperceivable gap
[] between [] the one as result and the one as operation (BE 54, my emphasis). But
being-nothing is not, just as the one is not: the there is of being-nothing does not instigate
any search for the nothing, and thus avoids falling back into an ontology of presence:
The nothing is neither a place nor a term of the situation. For if the nothing were a
term that could only mean one thing: that it had been counted as one (BE 54). Rather,
the nothing is the non-one of any count-as-one; or, the phantom of inconsistency is the
name nothing, which is not a-nothing [un-rien]. At this stage, it is important to empha-
size that, for Badiou, the nothing is both the pure unpresentable multiple, the name of
unpresentation in presentation, and the operation of the count, that which exceeds the
72 COSMOS AND HISTORY
. The law of the count as condition for existence, which renders presentation possible by precluding the
presentation of inconsistent multiplicity (i.e. being itself), is ultimately indiscernible from the ontological
inconsistency whose presentation it forecloses, Ray Brassier, Presentation as Anti-Phenomenon in Alain
Badious Being and Event, Continental Philosophy Review, 2006, [available on-line at: http://www.springer-
link.com/content/k3r6782060171279/?p=1661625d348044a1b73f87e8d0c3fd49&pi=4]
Lorenzo Chiesa 73
to themselves that the others are Others (BE 33). A multiple is Other than any other
multiple only due to its unicity. Or, the Other [] cannot designate the gap between
the one and the others-than-one [autres-que-lun], because the one is not (BE 33 trans.
modified). Put simply, the Other is coextensive to the unicity of the others, not the one.
Finally, there is a fourth meaning of the signifier one, which Badiou designates as
forming-into-one [mise-en-un]. This is basically a second count, a count of the count
(BE 83-4 my emphasis), which should be understood in two inextricable ways according
to the two sides of the couple one-result/one-multiple installed by the first count, the
count-as-one. Indeed, the forming-into-one indicates the concomitant possibility of both
count[ing] as one an already counted one-multiple and apply[ing] the count to the
one-result of the count (BE 90). Such an operation is possible insofar as, after the first
count, the one is not really distinguishable from the multiple: given that the one is the
result of the structuring count that makes the multiple consist, it remains immanent to
presentation, which, as such, can present only multiples. Differently put, the one-multiple
results from the count-as-one, and for this very reason the one-result can only itself be a
multiple.
If we now consider that the count-as-one is, as we have already remarked, a law that
produces a namethe proper name of each multiple as uniqueit also follows that
the forming-into-one will be nothing other than submitting to the law the names that it
produces (BE 90). It is important to emphasize that the resulting multiple of names (BE
91), the product of the forming-into-one, is itself a multiple: even after the second count
has taken place, the one is solely a retroactive fiction, albeit a more elaborate one, since
it now transcends presentation into representation. At this level, the one as representa-
tion can be distinguished from presentation as multiple, yet it remains a re-presentation
of a multiple and thus a fiction. On the other hand, notice that retroactive representa-
tion will necessarily have a retroactive effect on retroactive presentation: it is also in this
sense that I understand Badious suggestion according to which forming-into-one is not
really distinct from the count-as-one (BE 91).
The relation between the two counts, the counting-as-one of presentation and the
forming-into-one of representation, is to be conceived of in terms of a relation between
structure and metastructure, situation and the state of the situation. Although Badiou
insists on differentiating the two countsthey are absolutely distinct (BE 83)he also
affirms that the reduplication of the count is necessaryevery structure call[s] upon
a metastructure (BE 84)and consequently structure and metastructure, situation and
its state, are not really distinct. The reason for this necessity is countering the danger
of the void, warding it off from structured presentation (BE 84): all situations are thus
defined by an inevitable anxiety of the void [angoisse du vide] (BE 93). As we have seen,
the unpresentable and unlocalizable character of the void as the name of a situations
(inconsistent) being is what guarantees the consistency of this very situation, the emer-
gence of consistent multiplicity. That is to say, it is only insofar as a structured presenta-
tion does not encounter its own void that the situational one is not ruined. However, we
have also seen that, within presentation, something exceeds the count: the very opera-
74 COSMOS AND HISTORY
tion of the structural count-as-one qua nothing. This means that the errant void could fix
itself in the guise of structure: It is [] possible that, subtracted from the count, and by
consequence a-structured, the structure itself be the point where the void is given (BE
93). In order to counter the danger of the void, it is therefore necessary to structure the
structure or that the there is Oneness be valid for the count-as-one (BE 93).
Significantly, according to Badiou, this redoubling, the second count, should be
understood as an imaginarization of the first: if the count-as-one as a (symbolic) opera-
tion retroactively produces a fictional (imaginary) one-result, the counts undergoing,
in turn, the operation of a count is equivalent to the fictionalizing of the count via the
imaginary being conferred upon it (BE 95). Put simply, while the first count symboli-
cally produces the one, the second count, the count of the count, imaginarily is one.
of establishing collections.17 In other words, the count-as-one of the unary trait is what
produces the one, many ones, as strokes ///; however, at this stage, there is no second
count, or addition, that can count the strokes as 1s, or put differently, that can count the
operation of the first count as an operation. As Lacan observes, the unary trait []
supports [] one plus one and one again, the plus being meant there only to mark well
[a] difference, where the problem begins is precisely that one can add them together,
in other words that two, that three have a meaning.18 In order to stress how / + / +
/ is not the same as 1 + 1 + 1, Lacan goes as far as suggesting that a child may well be
able to count up to two and three without being able to operate with numbers: two and
three are in this case nothing but a repetition of the / produced by the unary trait, and
should be distinguished from the number 2 and 3 understood as 1 + 1 and 1 + 1 + 1.
This early counting is ineffective when dealing with numbers higher than 3: we should
therefore not be surprised when we are told that certain so-called primitive tribes along
the mouth of the Amazon were only recently able to discover the virtue of the number
four, and raised altars to it.19 What is at stake in the gap that separates these two counts
is nothing less than the birth of the subjects identification as modern Cartesian subject
split between consciousness and the unconscious.20
In what precise sense does the + of the / + / + / mark a difference between the
strokes produced by the count-as-one of the unary trait? This question certainly has to
do with the fact that, throughout Seminar IX, Lacan indiscriminately alternates the
phrases trait unaire and trait unique: put simply, a unary trait is a single trait. If the unary
trait, as instrumental operation, is the most simple structural trait in the sense that it
presents no variations,21 its sole property will be its unicity. That is to say, the + separat-
ing / from / denotes the singleness of the trait as such, the absence of any qualitative
difference in it,22 and thus works as an indicator of signifying difference, difference in
the pure state.23 Or, every count, every / is absolutely different from any other / without
its ever being a question of counting the trait as a qualitatively differentiated 1: as we
have just seen, the unary trait precedes number stricto sensu.24
Two crucial specifications should be made. Firstly, the unary trait marks difference
as such,25 which does not mean it is difference as such. This is a straightforward way to
distinguish the unary trait from the full-fledged signifier which it supports. While the
unary trait is a stroke, and, significantly enough, it is as letter that it can be differenti-
ated from all other strokes,26 the signifier is the one as difference, that is, following Saus-
sure, simply being what the others are not.27 Thus, unlike the unary trait, the signifier
implies [the] function of the unit [] qua pure difference.28 According to Lacan, the
one as difference, the emergence of the one [which] as such is the Other,29 that is the
fictional big Other, necessitates the second count.
Secondly and most importantly, at its first appearance, the one manifestly desig-
nates actual multiplicity [multiplicit actuelle].30 The count-as-one of the unary trait as trait
unique produces nothing other than consistent, that is actual, multiplicity: Lacan also
refers to it as a distinctive unity [unit distinctive].31 In order to illustrate this last point, he
evokes a scene of everyday pre-historic life:
I am a hunter [] I kill [an animal], it is an adventure, I kill another of them, it
is a second adventure which I can distinguish by certain traits characteristic of the
first, but which resembles it essentially by being marked with the same general
line. At the fourth, there may be some confusion: what distinguishes it from the
second, for example? At the twentieth, how will I know where I am?32
Like a child who counts without numbers, our primitive man can initially distinguish
the second adventure from the first by certain imaginaryintuitively qualitativetraits
that are then symbolically presented as a stroke / on an animal rib-bone. Yet, as soon as
this occurs, his two adventures are marked by the same general line, the same kind of
stroke which leads to signifying sameness, //. Although qualitative difference is never
eliminated completely, the fact that each adventure is, for a limited time, intuitively
experienced as new proves to be all the more secondary inasmuch as quality is precisely
what is overshadowed by the signifying in-difference of the traits //.33 From a slightly
different perspective, all this amounts to saying that the distinctive unity of the unary
trait is still immanent to the situation it counts, and thus runs the risk of becoming indis-
tinguishable from the non-situation of a primitive man who is still lacking any method
of location.34 Thus, marking signifying difference as such results in nothing other than
signifying sameness, in-difference, if the count is not itself counted, if the actual multi-
plicity /, the one-multiple that presents the hunters adventure, is not itself represented
as 1. We can then understand why Lacan pays so much attention to the later appearance
in pre-history of a series of strokes carved on an animal rib-boneFirst two, then a lit-
tle interval and afterwards five, and then it recommences.35 It is only at this level, that
of the count of the count, where 1 + 1 retroactively replaces //, that the properly human
symbolic dimension begins: this is the subjects own identification with the signifier.
Finally, it is quite remarkable that, in this context, Lacan himself draws a compari-
son between the use of the / made by the primitive hunter and the notion of the one
with which set theory operates. Against what we are taught at schoolYou cannot add
up oranges and apples, pears with carrots and so on36the primitive hunter counts as
one a multiple adventure made by irreconcilable objects and things. In the same
way, in set theory, you can very well add up what you want.37 More technically, Lacan
acknowledges that in what one calls the elements of sets, it is not a matter of objects, or
of things, it is rather a question of the multiples of a multiple. In other words, at the level
of presentation, the set is a one-multiple, what Lacan refers to as actual multiplicity: the
count-as-one of the unary trait presents a multiple-of-multiples, or to put with Badiou, a
multiple as several ones (BE 25).
In order to appreciate better the proximity between Badious consistent multiplic-
ity and Lacans distinctive unity we should not lose sight of the following convergence.
Badious consistent multiplicity, the one-multiple, is initially determined solely by its
unicity, in all cases; unicity is the property of consistent multiplicity qua counted-as-one,
independently of any other possible property of a situation (or set). What matters at the
level of presentation without representation is the proper name alpha, a letter that seals the
multiple, rather than the extension of what is being presentedthe terms or elements
of the situation. Indeed, extension is not properly defined before the second count takes
place and the state of the situation is established retroactively: only at that stage, the
one-multiple will have been counted as a situation (or, ontologically, all the parts of a
set will have formed the elements of a set as the powerset). A situation is not identical to
what is being presented in it. Following Ray Brassier, another way to put this would be
to say that presentation as such, presentation without representationthe prehistoric
hunters adventureis an anti-phenomenon.38
utterance and something which in its radical nature is of the order of the letter.43
Most importantly, the proper names relation to the letter as unary trait is itself
dependent on the logic of the written mark. Lacan plainly points out that the charac-
teristic of the proper name is always [] linked to [] writing.44 As Aaron Schuster
remarks in his elegant commentary on the fourth lesson of Seminar IX:
The crucial point for Lacan is that writing emerges first as the isolation of the
signifying trait (unary trait) which then becomesagain, retroactivelythe basic
support for the phoneticization of language, i.e. the treasury of signifiers proper.
Far from being simply the translation of a more original speech, it is speech itself
that ultimately finds its basis in the exteriority of the written mark. What results
from this, Lacan adds, is that the proper name qua brand [] ought to be linked
not with sound la Gardiner, but with writing. The proof of this is found in the
decipherment of unknown languages: one always begins by looking for proper
names since they remain the same across all languages []. In the proper name,
one thus rediscovers within the synchronic order of language a signifier in its pure state, a state
represented in diachronic (pre-)history by the primitive hunters notched bone.45
Let us dwell on these issues. It is doubtless the case that mans vocal utterings preced-
ed writing, chronologically speaking; however, language stricto sensu as determined by
the function of the signifier is, for Lacan, ultimately retroactively dependent on writing.
Conversely, the letter as writing potential was waiting to be phoneticized: this is what
we have at a first stage in prehistory, the simple traits, or strokes, of primitive bone etch-
ings. Lacan is careful in specifying that, as we have already seen, the letter as unary trait
always involves an initial imaginary dimensionsomething figurativethat is soon
effaced:46 this is valid both for the simple stroke / carved on an animals ribwhich
originally marked the image of an adventureand, even more so, the more sophisti-
cated traits used in ideographic notationthe schematic representation of the head * of
the animal I killed during my adventure still functions as a unary trait.
At a second stage, the writing of the traitthat designates something imaginaryis
accompanied by the utterance of a phoneme; but, for the time being, the utterance m
is not as yet detached from the image represented by the trait *. Put differently, phoneti-
cization here depends on the designation of an object via the marking of the trait. In a
third and final stage, which determines the retroactive passage from prehistory to his-
tory, we witness the reversal of this relation: now the marking of the trait depends solely
on phoneticization. This is writing proper: the letter is retroactively transformed into a
signifier and, being an element in a differential structure of other signifiers, acquires a
life that is completely independent of the object it used to designate.
From a slightly different perspective, we can say that writing properand language
stricto sensu with itonly really begins when the marking of the trait * is phoneticized
as trait, that is, named as such. At that point, * becomes the support of the phoneme m
which was previously the mere sound of the object designated by *the mooing head
of the animal I killed. We retroactively move from theultimately animalicsound m
to thehumanphonematic signifier m only when m can even be regarded as a proper
name M. As Lacan has it, It is a fact that letters have names, a is named alpha.47 We
should pay particular attention to this apparently trivial remark which, in its expanded
form, reads as follows: it is only insofar as a has a name, insofar as A is a proper name,
that the letter a can be said to be a, that a is identical to itself (albeit as part of a dif-
ferential sonant structure). The idiotic character48 of the proper nameits meaning-
lessness, the fact that, as already noted by John Stuart Mill, it is not the meaning of the
object that it brings with it49is nothing less than the precondition of identification:
Lacan is Lacan only if Lacan is a proper name.
More specifically, the proper name [] specifies as such [] the rooting of the sub-
ject precisely insofar as it is more specially linked than any other, not to phonematiciza-
tion as such, the structure of language, but to what in language is already ready [] to
receive this informing by the trait.50 The proper name is closer to the letter than to the
symbolic proper: it approaches the unary trait by redoubling its operation, the idiotic
in-difference of its count, and in this way guarantees the consistency of the structure of
language, the differentially phonematic chain of signifiers. In other words, the proper
name make[s] us question ourselves about what is at stake at this radical, archaic point
that we must necessarily suppose to be at the origin of the unconscious, that is, primary
repression.51 And this in two complementary ways: the proper name as the redoubling
of the letter, the unary trait, raises the issue of the attachment of language to the real,52
as well as that of negation as directly involved in the genesis of language in the guise of
an existential relationship.53 If the letter as unary trait is that which retroactively makes
the real object exist as negated (be it the killed animal or the mothers breast), the proper
name is that which, operating retroactively on the letter, allows the subjects own iden-
tification by naming this very negation.
taken as a whole.58
To cut a long story short, according to Lacan, what is being counted by the unary
trait is the possibility of the real (its affirmation) through the preservation of the rights
of the nothing.59 In opposition to the false axiom for which anything real is possible, one
should always start with the axiom for which the real takes its place only from the not
possible: the possibility of affirming that something exists always relies on a law that
safe-guards the nothing. But if the real, or better reality, only originates in the not pos-
sible, this not possible, presented as such by negation, is the real. Here, Lacan uses the
term real in two ways: a) as the possible that follows the not possible; b) as the not pos-
sible that originates the possible. But it is in fact possible to think these two acceptations
together: the real qua reality takes its place only from the possibility of the not possible,
the possibility of the real as such. Indeed, this real exists, Lacan says, as exception or
exclusion.60 In other words, there is not only the not possible at the origin of any enun-
ciating, but also the possibility of the not possible: the origin of any enunciating is the
enunciation of the nothing,61 the affirmation of negation accomplished by the unary trait.
Badious philosophy thinks meta-ontologically a set theoretical ontology which relies
on the very same axiom, the axiom of the empty set, which formalizes existence at its
most basic level. As he writes in Being and Event, the axiom of the empty set states, in sub-
stance, that there exists a negation (BE 86 my emphasis); it is necessary that the absolutely
initial existence be that of a negation, the existence of an inexistent (BE 67). What nega-
tion as the absolutely initial existence negates is belonging: no elements belong to the
void-set, not even the void. If, for Badious set theoretical ontology, the void presents the
unpresentable as that which alone in-exists (BE 69), for Lacans theory of the subject,
the possibility of the not possible affirms the real that ex-sists as exclusion. If for Badiou,
the in-existent void subtractively sutures a situation to its being (inconsistent multiplic-
ity), for Lacan the ex-sistent, or ex-timate, realthe real-of-the-symbolicretroactively
reminds a subject of the undead (an inconsistent real which was and will be not-one,
barred in itself, before and after the presence of the symbolic).62 If, finally, for Badiou,
the void as set is absolutely in-different in the sense that nothing differentiates it, its
unicity is not based on a difference that can be attested (BE 68), for Lacan, the real-
of-the-symbolic is the other side of a distinctive unity whose unicity precisely resolves
itself, as we have seen, into in-difference. (It is important to bear in mind that the count
Set theory sheds light on the fecund frontier between the whole/parts relation
and the one/multiple relation; because, at base, it suppresses both of them. The
multiple [] for a post-Cantorian is neither supported by the existence of the one
nor unfolded as an organic totality. The multiple consists from being without-one
(BE 81).
Interestingly enough, in this context, it is Badiou himself who bends his fundamen-
tal ontological thesis according to which the one is not towards a formulation, being
without-one [sans-un], that is reminiscent of Lacans -1, the one-less. Unity and totality,
the particular and the universalor better their semblancescan only be conceived of
if one begins from the multiple, which initially un-presents itself in the void-set as being
without-one. The fact that both elements and sets are multiples-of-multiples and thus
become indistinguishable collapses the traditional distinction between unity as an ele-
ment of a totality and totality as a set of unities. Using natural language paradoxically,
we could suggest that a particular unity is always already a one-multiple whilst being
an element of a universal totality which is never as yet a one-multiple. Thus, there is
only one possible relation between sets and elements, belonging, which indicates that a
multiple is counted as element in the presentation of another multiple (BE 81). Besides
this, all we can do is count the multiple according to its parts. This is the relation of inclu-
sion, which indicates that a multiple is a sub-multiple [or part] of another multiple (BE
81). Such a relation is dealt with by the axiom of the powerset, the set of subsets, among
others: this affirms that between belonging and inclusion there is at least the correlation
that all the multiples included in a supposedly existing alpha [the initial set] belong to a beta
[its powerset]; that is, they form a set, a multiple counted-as-one (BE 82 my emphasis). Let us
dwell on this last point, which is crucial for Badiou. According to axiomatic set-theory,
the following can be stated:
1. inclusion is derived from belonging as the sole primitive relation between sets
and elements, yet belonging and inclusion are distinct;
. the fact that inclusion and belonging are distinct entails that there is an excess
of inclusion over belonging, the powerset over the set; this excess is an excess in
belonging: there is always at least one element of the powerset which does not
belong to the initial set;
as an element, a 1. In this way the powerset of the void operates against what Badiou calls
the errancy of the void, the fact that, after the first count, the void is included in all sets
without belonging to them. As a consequence of this, it is inevitable that we consider the
second count as an operation which, by turning the -1 into an element, representing the
name of the void, somehow preserves the semblance of the distinction between unity as an
element of a totality and totality as a set of unities, even though what is being counted
are multiples-of-multiples.
This in no way means that, after the second count has taken place, the void does not
continue to err on the level of the first count; after all, the state of a situation can be said
to be separate (or transcendent) with regard to the situation. While the retroactive
effect of the forming-into-one on the count-as-one definitely makes the void take place
in a part [that] receives the seal of the one (BE 97), its errancy is far from being inter-
rupted within this circumscribed partial place. Here, it would certainly be reductive, if
not misleading, to regard the situation as a mere part of the state of the situation, since,
in a sense, the state is attached (or immanent) to its structure (the powerset is still a
set); rather, we should acknowledge the following: the situation as situation character-
ized by the errancy of the void takes place in a part of the situation as state of the situa-
tion. From a slightly different perspective, we can propose that both the initial counting
of the multiple in the set and the second counting, that of the parts of the set as elements
of the powerset, both structured presentation and metastructured representation, ulti-
mately rely on the void-setthe initial multiple as absolutely initial point of being (BE
48)which should always remain errant. As a matter of fact, what should be avoided at
all costs as the catastrophe of presentation, is a fixation of the void, the presentations
encounter with its own void (BE 93-94).
It should be stressed that Badiou himself seems implicitly to distinguish the errancy
of the void in a situation as such, the pure errancy of the void (BE 96 my emphasis) from
the errancy of the void at the level of the situation after the state of the situation has been
established: this second, impure errancy is nothing other than what he refers to as the
unconscious of the void. Given Badious deliberate choice to employ psychoanalytic
terms to describe the basics of his meta-ontological edifice, I do not think I am forc-
ing his argument in finally suggesting that the unconscious of the void amounts to the
unconscious status of the situation under state control, or put simply, the states uncon-
scious. The unconscious of the void, or, significantly enough, the phantom of inconsistency, is the
name retroactively imposed on the name void, the letter , by state repression. Having said this, it
must be observed that Badiou fails to emphasize the following: as long as the state of a
situation (consciousness) remains both separate from the situation (the unconscious) and
attached to it, repetition is the movement that prevents the taking place of the void in the
phantom of inconsistency from degenerating into a fixation of the void.66
66. Badious failure to account for the function of repetition in the phantom of inconsistency gives rise to
terminological ambiguity when he describes the difference between the taking place of the voidwhich
wards it offand its fixationthat is, the ruin of the One (BE 93): how does the fixation of the void,
its becom[ing] localizable (BE 56), differ from its taking place if one does not specify that the latter still
86 COSMOS AND HISTORY
entails (repetitive, circular) movement? In Saint Paul, Badiou seems to suggest that repetition should rather
be associated with fixation, a fixation of the subjects desire which is, however, a fixation of the law (and not
aimed against it): The law is required in order to unleash the automatic life of desire, the automatism of
repetition. For only the law fixes the object of desire [], Alain Badiou, Saint Paul: The Foundation of Univer-
salism, trans. Ray Brassier, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 2003, p. 79. Beyond terminological confu-
sion, should we not identify such a repetitive fixation of the law with what Being and Event defines as the
taking place of the void?
For a recent critique of Badious unsatisfactory notion of repetition with regards to the political subject, see
Slavoj iek, Badiou: Notes From an Ongoing Debate, International Journal of iek Studies, vol. 1, no. 2,
2006, http://ics.leeds.ac.uk/zizek/article.cfm?id=21&issue=3 [available on-line at http://ics.leeds.ac.uk/
zizek/article.cfm?id=21&issue=3].
67. Seminar IX, lesson of 24/1/62.
Lorenzo Chiesa 87
In this way, a fundamental un-presentation functions as the radical support for any
relationship of inclusion. More precisely, Lacan explains how we can formulate a defini-
tion of the traditional category of classif you really want to guarantee it its universal
status68only by means of the un-presentation of the -1: the mammalian class can only
be postulated on the basis of the absence of the mamma.
There is first of all the absence of the mamma and [then] one says: it cannot be
that the mamma is missing, here is what constitutes the mammalian class. [] The
zoologist, if you allow me to go this far, does not carve out the mammalian class
in the assumed totality of the maternal mamma; it is only because he detaches the
mamma that he can identify the absence of the mamma.69
The in-existence of the un-presented mamma which nevertheless exists as void-part de-
termines both the particular existence of the mamma and the representation of the pos-
sible absence of the mamma with regard to the mammalian class taken as a whole. How-
ever, Lacan immediately specifies that, if the construction of the whole relies on the
un-presentation of the -1, then it is the product of an error of counting, and consequently
universality can be regarded only as a semblance; in order to obtain the universal, the
enunciation of the nothing, the void-set as -1, must necessarily be primally repressed.
More precisely, Lacan believes that it is the subject who necessarily makes an error
of counting: there is a constituting necessity [that] the subject should make an error in
the count.70 This count is a second count for the subject since, on an initial level, he is
nothing other than what dis-counts itself by means of the unary trait, the very un-pres-
entation of the -1. Put differently, initially, the subject as such is minus one71 insofar as
he identifies with the absent object, first and foremost the mammaIn the [first form
of the] identification relationship [] what the subject assimilates [] is him in his
frustration.72 It is only at a second stage, which works retroactively on the first and car-
ries out identification proper, the splitting between the unconscious and consciousness,
that we are going to rediscover the subject [as] first of all established as minus one []
as [himself] verworfen, primally repressed.73 Identification proper is then the subjects
retroactive counting of himself, a - 1, as a 1. More specifically, the second count con-
comitantly brings about in a retroactive way the conscious subjects primal repression of
himself as the un-conscious un-presented -1 and his unconscious seeking (or, desiring)
himself as that very same un-conscious un-presented -1, that is, the enunciation of the
nothing, the void-set. (Strictly speaking, what precedes the second count is not uncon-
scious: the unconscious, just like consciousness, is a retroactive effect of the second count
on structure qua count of the unary-trait).
Lacan clearly states that, with regard to the subject, the fact that should most inter-
est philosophers and psychoanalysts is that his inaugural mistake is what allows him to
express, or name, himself as a subject. Thus, it will not be a matter of simply rectifying
the means of knowing in order to avoid the mistake: what is ultimately involved in it
is the subjects conscious access to reality (the re-presentation of structure) and, at the
same time, his endless unconscious search for the real qua not possible74since, as we
have seen, the real is precisely what in-exists as enunciation of the nothing. The second
count has therefore a retroactive effect on the original counting of the un-conscious
unary-trait ///; more specifically, the latter should now be understood in terms of un-
conscious repetition, in the precise sense of a compulsion to repeat something which is
as such unrepeatable.75 Consequently, repetition is characterized by unicity, the unicity
as such of [each] circuit of repetition, just like the counting of the un-conscious unary
trait ///.76 As Lacan puts it, repetition in the unconscious is absolutely distinguished
from any natural cycle, in the sense that what is accentuated is not its return, the same-
ness of the cycle; what is accentuated is rather the original unary trait /the initial
enunciation of the nothing as the real qua not possiblewhich has marked the subject
as -1.77 Each circuit of repetition is unique since repetition, the making of / always anew,
amounts to the impossibility of repeating the signifying uniquity of the first /, the un-
presentation of the part-object.
The subjects conscious access to reality, his knowledge [connaissance], presupposes
a mistake, an error of counting, about which he knows nothing, and which moreover
forces him into an endless unconscious search for what preceded it. It is important to
remark that this mistake, bluntly put, the turning of -1 into 1, originates at the very mo-
ment the initial enunciation of the nothing, the void-set, is turned into the absence of the
part-object, the void as part. In Being and Event, Badiou clarifies precisely this point when
he discusses the operation from which the property the void is a subset of any set is
obtained, the fact that the void is omnipresent in all structured presentation, its errancy.
As Badiou has it, this fundamental ontological theorem is deduced as a particular case
of the logical principle ex falso sequitur quodlibet: if a statement A is false (if I have non-
A) and if I affirm the latter (if I posit A), then it follows that anything (any statement B
whatsoever) is true (BE 86-87). The void as part which is universally included in all sets
supposed given follows from a falso; it relies on the negation of the true negative state-
ment advanced by the axiom of the empty set, that is, there is a negation, or nothing
belongs to the void, not even the void itself. The void as included part tacitly presumes
the existence of an element that belongs to the void.
This kind of negation of negation is precisely the error, or falso, on which Lacans
symbolic structured like a fiction, the big Other qua one as difference, is based. As we
have seen, for Lacan, initially we have non-A, which is why taking A is A as the basis
of identification is so problematic; the A of lAutre is barred and tautology is possible only
at the price of making a mistake. More specifically, in Lacans theory of the subject, the
void as part of all sets supposed givenwhose existence as formed-into-one is itself af-
firmed only starting from the in-existence of this part as universally includedshould
be located on the level of what he calls the symbolic object. During the dialectic of
frustration between the mother and the child at the beginning of the Oedipus com-
plexthe time of the un-conscious counting of the unary trait ///, of structure without
metastructurethe symbolic object is the object which the child demands beyond the
object of need, the object as grasped in what it lacks. Remarkably enough, Lacan also
specifies that the symbolic object is not nothing since it has the property of being there
symbolically;78 the part-object as there is the nothing as part, the void-part, results
from the falsity of the negation of the initial true enunciation of the nothing, the void-
set. The mistaken falsification of truth as the real qua not possible is what allows any af-
firmation whatever to be symbolically true, first of all that which proclaims the existence
of the void as part. This error will then be aggravated retroactively by the second count,
an operation (a metaphor) which Lacan refers to as the Name-of-the-Father; through
the Name-of-the-Father, the part-object as the errant, and thus potentially dangerous,
void-part itself receives the seal of the one, taking its place as a part in the phantasy -
a. The Name-of-the-Father operates on the extimate part-object in which the subject
identifies himself as vanishing in the same way as the forming-into-one operates on the
in-existent part of a situation that initially does not belong to it.
78. Jacques Lacan, Le sminaire livre IV. La relation dobjet, 1956-1957, Paris, Seuil, 1994, p. 155 (my emphasis).
90 COSMOS AND HISTORY
amounts to a resumption of the unary trait at another level. Put differently, the un-con-
scious unary trait as structure will have been the S1, the structural, that is unconscious,
side of the metastructure. It would also be correct to suggest that the S1 is the unary trait
as repressed. Lacan himself stresses the similarity between the unary trait and the S1
when, in Seminar XI, the first seminar to introduce the notion of the master-signifier, he
openly refers the S1 to the notch made by primitive hunters on sticks in order to signify
the killing of an animal.79
Let us conclude with the following remarks:
1. Initially, the subject in-exists as -1, it is what dis-counts itself by means of the
original unary trait as enunciation of the nothing; more precisely, at this
level, the subject should be regarded as the gap, or cut, between the structured
presentation of signifiers, or more precisely letters, which signify the subjects in-
existence, and their inextricable void, the symbolic object. After the operation
of the Name-of-the-Father, the second count, has taken place, the subject as -1
counts himself as 1; this 1 should rather be understood as a new gap between
the structured presentation of letters, now turned into the signifiers of the
unconscious, and metastructured representation, that is, conscious discourse.80
. The first gap, between structure and its void, which causes the latters errancy,
designates the metonymic dimension of demand, the unstoppable sliding of the
symbolic object (the object of love) beneath the objects of need. On the other
hand, the second gap, between structure and metastructure, designates the
metaphoric dimension of desire. In order to pass from the gap of demand to the
gap of desire the subject must carry out a positivizing organization of the void:
the void must take place within the phantasy -a by means of the metaphor of
the Name-of-the-Father.
. The subject that counts himself as 1 is equivalent to the subject as the gap of
desire who is represented in the unconscious phantasmatic object a as enunciation
of the nothing; that is, the subject is 1 in the unconscious insofar as he appears
there as not-one, -1.81 More precisely, the subject continues to make 1 in the
unconscious phantasy precisely because, as enunciation of the nothing, he is
not-one. Differently put, the subject can name himself I in consciousness
and thus value himself [se compter]only because he repeats the act of counting
himself [se compter] as not-one in the phantasythere where in fact the object a
79. Jacques Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, London, Vintage, 1998, p. 141.
80. The gap between a (which counts-as-one the belongings, or elements) and (a) (which counts-as-one
the inclusions, or subsets) is [] the point in which the impasse of being resides. [] I said that a and (a)
were distinct. In what measure? With what effects? This point, apparently technical, will lead us all the way
to the Subject and to truth (BE 83-84, my emphasis).
81. See especially lesson of 3/6/1959 from Jacques Lacan, Seminar VI (1958-1959), Le dsir et son interpretation,
unpublished.
Lorenzo Chiesa 91
Lorenzo Chiesa
School of European Culture and Languages,
University of Kent, UK
REFERENCES
Badiou, Alain, Un, Deux, Trois, Quatre, et aussi Zro, unpublished.
Badiou, Alain, Ltre et lvnement, Paris, Seuil, 1988.
Badiou, Alain, Infinite Thought: Truth and the Return to Philosophy, ed. and trans. Justin
Clemens and Oliver Feltham, London, Continuum, 2003.
Badiou, Alain, Saint Paul: The Foundation of Universalism, trans. Ray Brassier, Stanford,
Stanford University Press, 2003.
Badiou, Alain, Being and Event, trans. Oliver Feltham, London, Continuum, 2005.
Bosteels, Bruno, Alain Badious Theory of the Subject: The Recommencement of
Dialectical Materialism? (Part I), Pli: Warwick Journal of Philosophy, no. 12, 2001,
pp. 200-29.
Bosteels, Bruno, Alain Badious Theory of the Subject: The Recommencement of
Dialectical Materialism? (Part II), Pli: Warwick Journal of Philosophy, no. 13, 2002,
pp. 173-208.
Brassier, Ray, Presentation as Anti-Phenomenon in Alain Badious Being and Event,
Continental Philosophy Review, 2006.
Chiesa, Lorenzo, Lacan and Subjectivity: A Philosophical Introduction, Cambridge, MIT Press,
2007.
Chiesa, Lorenzo and Alberto Toscano, Ethics and Capital, Ex Nihilo, Umbr(a): A Journal
of the Unconscious, no. 1, 2005, pp. 9-25.
Freud, Sigmund, Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego, The Standard Edition of
the Complete Psychological Work of Sigmund Freud, vol. XVIII, London, The Hogarth
Press and the Institute of Psychoanalysis, 2001.
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar IX (1961-1962): Lidentification, unpublished.
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar VI (1958-1959), Le dsir et son interpretation, unpublished.
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar XIX (1971-1972), Ou pire, unpublished.
Lacan, Jacques, The Seminar of Jacques Lacan. Book I, Freuds Papers on Technique, 1953-1954,
Jacques-Alain Miller (ed.), trans. John Forrester, 1st American ed., New York,
W.W. Norton, 1988.
Lacan, Jacques, Le sminaire livre IV. La relation dobjet, 1956-1957, Paris, Seuil, 1994.
Lacan, Jacques, Le sminaire livre V. Les formations de linconscient, 1957-1958, Paris, Seuil,
1998.
Lacan, Jacques, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, London, Vintage, 1998.
Lacan, Jacques, Ltourdit, Autres crits, Paris, Seuil, 2001.
Lacan, Jacques, Le sminaire livre X. Langoisse, 1962-1963, Paris, Seuil, 2004.
Pluth, Ed and Dominiek Hoens, What if the Other Is Stupid? Badiou and Lacan on
Logical Time, in Peter Hallward (ed.), Think Again: Alain Badiou and the Future of
Philosophy, London, Continuum Books, 2004, pp. 182-90.
Lorenzo Chiesa 93
Safouan, M., Lacaniana: Les sminaires de Jacques Lacan * 1953-1963, Paris, Seuil, 2001.
Schuster, A., Commentary on Lacan Seminar IX LIdentification, 20 December 1961,
unpublished.
iek, Slavoj, The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology, New York, Verso,
2000.
iek, Slavoj, Foreword to the Second Edition: Enjoyment within the Limits of Reason
Alone, For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political Factor, 2nd ed.,
London, Verso, 2002, pp. xi-cvii.
iek, Slavoj, Badiou: Notes From an Ongoing Debate, International Journal of iek Studies,
vol. 1, no. 2, 2006, http://ics.leeds.ac.uk/zizek/article.cfm?id=21&issue=3