Schauer. On Open Texture of Law
Schauer. On Open Texture of Law
Schauer. On Open Texture of Law
Fredrick Schauer
University of Virginia School of Law
September 2011
Frederick Schauer
University of Virginia
Summary
H.L.A. Hart and others have argued that law is open-textured. It is in the nature of law, they
say, that it necessarily possesses an open texture going beyond the open texture of the
language in which legal rules are written. But when we examine the question of open texture
in light of Harts claim that the open texture of law entails the necessary defeasibility of legal
rules, we discover that Hart and his followers are mistaken. Both the alleged open texture of
law qua law and the defeasibility of legal rules are contingent features of certain legal rules in
certain legal regimes, but neither are necessary components of the nature of law or the nature
of rules.
1. Introduction
In The Concept of Law, H.L.A. Hart famously claimed that the law is open-textured (Hart
1994, 123, 128-36). Hart borrowed the term from his Oxford colleague Friedrich Waismann
as well as language is open-textured. But is Harts claim correct? Waismann argued that
least going beyond, the open-texture of the language in which legal rules are written? Hart
seemed to believe so, but it is not at all clear that Hart was right in so believing. Nor is it
apparent that Hart and others are correct in maintaining that laws open texture produces the
necessary defeasibility of legal rules. For even if law is open-textured, it does not follow for
law, as it may follow for language, that the uncertainty generated by an instance of open
texture is necessarily an occasion for revising an existing legal rule. Indeed, resistance to
precisely such revision may well be what characterizes rules. If that is so, then Harts insistence
I begin with a prcis of Waismanns basic idea. Arguing against the logical positivist
credo that meaning was a function of verifiability (Ayer, 1946), Waismann observed that even
the most precise and carefully delimited empirical terms might nevertheless produce
uncertainty in the face of unforeseen and virtually unimaginable instances. Because language
cannot anticipate all possible occurrences in all possible worlds, he argued, there persists the
dimensions can break down in the face of unforeseen and unforeseeable events. To illustrate
the phenomenon, Waismann observed that if we attempted to verify the statement, There is a
cat next door, no amount of seeing, touching, or patting the cat to verify that it was indeed a
2
cat could foreclose the logical possibility that the creature we thought was a cat according to all
of the existing criteria of catness might then grow to gigantic size, or die and then come back
from the dead. Were such eventualities to occur, Waismann argued, the existing criteria for
application of the term would collapse. An uncertainty that had not previously existed would
arise precisely because of the appearance of the unexpected, and it is central to Waismanns
idea of open texture that the possibility of the unexpected, at least for material object
At about the same time that Waismann was writing about open texture, J.L. Austin
captured the identical idea even more vividly. Austin asked us to imagine a creature that
but which then proceeded to explode, or quote Virginia Woolf (Austin 1946, 160). Under such
circumstances, he says, we dont know what to say. It is precisely the lack of knowing what to
say (or do) in the face of the unforeseen and unforeseeable that Waismann originally called, in
German, Die Porositt der Griffe (the porosity of concepts), and then, at the suggestion of
W.B. Kneale (Waismann 1945, 121), relabeled in English as open texture. Thus, as Stewart
Shapiro puts it in summarizing Waismanns idea, P exhibits open-texture if there are possible
objects p such that nothing in the established use of P, or the non-linguistic facts, determines
that P holds of p or that P fails to hold of p. In effect, Pp is left open by the use of language, to
(Waismann 1945, 122). Some terms are indeed vague in that they are indeterminate with
3
respect to known (existing or currently imaginable) applications. It takes no great foresight to
understand that some collections of things may or may not be heaps, that certain kinds of
behavior may or may not be kind, or that a car traveling at 90km/hour on a particular stretch of
highway may or may not be traveling quickly. In such cases, we perceive now that some
applications of the term are indeterminate. But open texture is different. It is the possibility of
vagueness the potential vagueness of even those terms that appear to have no
uncertainties with respect to known or imagined applications. We could list all of the existing
criteria for something being a goldfinch, and thus the term goldfinch would not be vague for
any of the known existing goldfinches and non-goldfinches in the world. But because such a
precise and non-vague definition of goldfinch would not likely contain the criteria of does
not explode or does not quote Virginia Woolf, the occurrence of the previously unimagined
would render the hitherto non-vague term newly vague with respect to that application. And
because such a possibility could never entirely be eliminated for empirical concepts, Waismann
maintained, attempting to define the meaning of such concepts in terms of verifiability was
destined to failure.
In analyzing the operation of legal rules, Hart purported to adopt Waismanns idea and
adapt it to law. Hart claimed that rules necessarily possess a fringe of vagueness or open
texture (Hart, 1994, 123), and he attributed the idea to Waismann (Hart, 1994, 297). But it is
not obvious that Hart and Waismann were talking about the same thing. One problem is that
Harts language is ambiguous as between the view that vagueness and open texture are
4
distinct, as Waismann argued, and the view that open texture is for Hart simply a synonym
for vagueness. Perhaps he is merely following the common practice of using the x or y
locution to say that y is an alternative and possibly better way of saying x, as when I describe
is that Hart did see vagueness and open texture as different, but not in the same way as
Waismann. After introducing the term open texture, Hart defines it as the fringe area of a
term with clear and unclear core and fringe (or core and penumbra) applications. Thus, a
man who is two meters in height is clearly tall, and a man who is one and one half meters is
clearly not tall, and so a man who is in the area of uncertainty 1.85 meters, say exists in the
fringe of the term tall. And the same applies to terms less pervasively vague than tall that
is, to terms which, unlike tall, are determinate for most of their known applications. Take
wine, for example. Its extension is quite precise, such that the vast majority of substances,
and even the vast majority of potable liquids, are easily classified as wine or not wine. But
whether non-alcoholic wine is wine at all is not so clear. Consequently, we can say that non-
alcoholic wine is located in the relatively small fringe of a term with a large core of settled
That open texture was to Hart the label not for potential vagueness but for the actual
even more plain when we examine his introduction of the now-famous example of a rule
prohibiting vehicles in the park (Hart 1994, 129; Schauer 2008). For most of the paradigm,
5
clear cases, the application of the term is straightforward, and Hart offers motor-cars, buses,
and motor-cycles as examples of such clear cases. But with respect to an electrically propelled
toy motor-car, he says, the application of the term vehicle is no longer straightforward.
Accordingly, with respect to the question whether the no-vehicles-in-the-park rule applies to
the electrically propelled toy motor-car, Hart continues, the law can be seen to have exhibited
its open texture. He then goes on to say that in such cases we confront the issues at stake and
[] then settle the question by choosing between the competing interests in the way that best
satisfies us. In doing so we shall have rendered more determinate our initial aim, and shall
incidentally have settled a question as to the meaning, for purposes of this rule, of a general
word. (Hart 1994, 129). The open texture of the law means that there are, indeed, areas of
conduct which must be left to be developed by courts or officials striking a balance, in the light
of circumstances, between competing interests which vary in weight from case to case. (Hart
1994, 135).
but Hart may be less explaining or using Waismanns idea than he is modifying it. Of course
many terms do have cores of settled meaning and fringes of now-debatable applications. What
Hart said about the term vehicle in a legal rule holds also for most terms. And it holds even
when those terms are not components of prescriptive rules. In numerous contexts, there are
core and fringe applications of bus, run, blue, and dead, for example, and so the core
and fringe feature of most of the words in any language will be part of the language of legal
6
rules as well. Waismanns point, however, is different. It is that even terms with no currently
known fringes may still develop such fringes in the face of currently unforeseeable applications,
and that this possibility can never completely be eliminated. The claim of languages open
texture is thus a claim about (empirical) languages inevitable potential uncertainty, and it is
In one respect Hart is plainly correct. Law is inevitably potentially uncertain just
because language is inevitably potentially uncertain. Legal rules are ordinarily canonically
written in language, and are typically (or perhaps necessarily) understood in language even
when, as is often the case in common law systems, they may have no single formal canonical
are thus language-dependent, the properties of language in general are present with respect to
legal rules expressed in language. More particularly, the phenomenon of open texture, as
identified by Waismann, must be a feature of all legal rules.1 To illustrate, imagine a legal rule
pertaining to goldfinches say, a rule declaring the goldfinch to be an endangered species and
thus protected against hunting, capturing, and the like. The rule would specify what could or
could not be done with or to goldfinches, and, because goldfinch is a term with no special
legal meaning, might then implicitly or explicitly incorporate the ordinary meaning of
goldfinch then present in the language. But if someone were charged with violating the law
by, say, capturing an exploding goldfinch, the very uncertainty of whether such a creature was a
goldfinch at all would make the legal consequences of the capture pro tanto uncertain as well.
1
For purposes of this article, I assume that Waismann is basically correct. My question is not
whether Waismann is, ultimately, right, but what, if Waismann is right, this says about law.
7
If Waismanns idea is sound, then open texture is indeed an ineliminable feature of law,
written and understood in language, then the characteristics of language infuse law as well.
Law is thus open-textured, and necessarily so, just because of the ineliminable open texture of
language, but this conclusion does not yet suggest that legal open texture is any more than, or
any less than, the open texture of the terms in which the law is written and understood.
5. Is the Open Texture of Law More than the Open Texture of its Language?
The open texture of language thus produces open texture in law, but this conclusion is
that any use of language is pro tanto open-textured. Law is thus open-textured, but so too are
novels, theatrical productions, everyday conversations, restaurant menus, and the instructions I
give to the automobile mechanic. If Waismann is right, then the phenomenon of open-texture
pervades language use, and Austins exploding goldfinch can appear and make the immanent
open texture of language present and problematic in any use of language, including but by no
Hart, however, seems to make a broader claim, as his examples demonstrate. The
important difference for our purposes between Austins exploding goldfinch and Harts
electrically propelled toy motor-car is that we can not only imagine the latter, but can also
describe it with existing linguistic tools. A toy electric motor-car does not exemplify the open
texture of language, and so for it to be an example of the open texture of law, Hart must have
had in mind a feature of law distinct from the open texture of language.
8
That there is something about law, or more precisely about legal rules, that seems to
Hart analogous to the open texture of language, but which is not simply the open texture of
is a straightforward example of a rule. Many rules, including this one, are presently both under-
and over-inclusive with respect to their background justifications (Alexander & Sherwin, 2001;
Schauer 1991). Consider the typical highway speed limit. The speed limit is a rule, designed to
serve the background justification of fostering highway safety. But we know now that a
designated speed limit aimed at ensuring safe driving will excessively limit some experienced
and safe drivers under ideal conditions who are in fact driving safely, albeit above the speed
limit. And by reaching some instances of safe driving, the rule reaches beyond its background
driving just below the limit in snow and ice, for example, or an inexperienced drivers driving
right at a high motorway limit are not covered by the speed limit rule. The rule is thus under-
inclusive to the extent that some behaviors covered by the rules background justification of
ensuring safety are not covered by the rule itself. But neither such over- nor under-inclusion
confrontation with what was previously unexpected or undecided. For all of the reasons of
predictability and consistency, among others, that we use rules, the speed limit rule is
knowingly adopted with full-knowledge of its under- and over-inclusion, and with, ideally, full
appreciation of the fact that achieving the virtues of rule-based decision-making involves
9
In other instances, however, the tokens of under- or over-inclusiveness may not be
imagined by the rule-makers at the time a rule is made, and thus not anticipated in selecting
the language of the rule. Such instances are presumably what Hart had in mind when he used
the example of the toy electric motor-car (Bix 1993, 17-35). He considered it an example of
legal open-texture because a particular application of a rule was not settled by the language of
the rule, as it would have been had the rule-maker specified that the prohibited vehicles were
passengers. But in Harts example, the extension of the rule is not so limited, extending to
anything that is a vehicle. And because we do not know whether the toy electric motor-car is
The mere fact that a new occurrence is not covered by a rule, however, need not
produce the same we dont know what to say response that the exploding goldfinch
occasions with respect to the previous criteria for proper use of the word goldfinch. The rule
could have carefully defined vehicle in all then-known directions, and could also have said
that anything not a vehicle according to that definition would not be covered by the rule. And
the rule could accomplish this goal with then-existing linguistic resources. Were the rule to be
formulated in this way, and if, say, the rule defined a vehicle in a way that limited vehicles for
the purpose of the rule as being of a certain size, or having the capacity to hold a certain
number of human passengers, then the toy electric motor-car would simply not have been
covered by the rule, even though this particular application was not imagined at the time the
rule was written and enacted. But if the rule, as in Harts example, is specified simply in terms
of vehicles, then the presence of the toy electric motor-car might well be an example of the
10
limited foresight or imagination of the particular drafters of a particular rule, but little more
than that. If the term vehicle, standing alone, is indeterminate with respect to toy electric
motor-cars, then we have an example of the open texture of language as manifested in a legal
rule, but not an example of a feature of law going beyond the open texture of language. And if
the term vehicle, standing alone, is determinate with respect to toy electric motor-cars
(assuming that toy electric motor-cars are vehicles), then this is like the speed limit an
application lying within the scope of the rule but not serving the rules background justification.
This, to repeat, is a familiar (and often intentional) feature of rules, but does not generate the
As noted above, rules may contain closure provisions, excluding (or, in theory, including)
all applications not plainly encompassed by the rule. And as Hart observed (Hart 1994, 272),
Jeremy Bentham imagined and discussed just this kind of rule, one with its own specified
closure. For Bentham, who notoriously abhorred the idea of judicial legislation, a gap in the law
was not the occasion for judicial gap- filling, but for legislative action, albeit legislative action
prompted by the a proposal from the judge. Bentham, with his penchant for neologisms, called
this the suspensive power or sistitive function, whereby a judge would suspend execution
of the law pending legislative revision (Postema 1986, 434-439). For present purposes,
however, the issue is not principally about the strategy to be followed when a legal rule does
not plainly cover some occurrence in the world. Rather, Bentham shows that a set of rules can
in theory provide a closure or default rule specifying what is to happen in all events not plainly
11
covered by the existing rules (Gardner 2001, 212). Consider the implicit closure rule of the
Anglo-American criminal law, according to which all behavior not clearly prohibited by an
enacted legal prohibition is permitted. Or consider a hypothetical rule of private law, pursuant
to which claimants could recover against defendants only if an explicit rule authorized such
recovery, and only if the claimants actual claim clearly fell within such an explicit rule. In all
other cases, the claim would fail. This might well be a bad rule, neglecting to account for the
compensation where there is no injury or wrong. But the justice or injustice of the rule is a side
issue. What is important is simply that a closure or default rule is entirely possible.
Any closure rule would, of course, remain subject to the open texture of the language of
the closure rule itself. But if the closure rules language were determinate, then there is no
reason why law would necessarily be compelled to face a situation in which the law simply runs
out, in the way that language runs out when confronted with the exploding goldfinch. Indeed,
form of closure rule -- as an alternative to judicial discretion, Hart implicitly concedes that there
are systemic options for law other than judicial discretion or judicial law-making. In so
conceding, however, Hart sets himself at odds with what he, earlier in The Concept of Law,
appears himself to have maintained, and sets himself at odds with what others have said about
12
With the foregoing analysis in mind, consider Harts claim that a rule with an unless
clause can still be a rule (Hart 1994, 136). This itself seems uncontroversial. A rule that is
specified in If A, then , unless B form is merely a different way of formulating a rule with
multiple conditions for its application, as in If A and not-B, then (Schauer 1991, Stone 1985,
reason-providing but still non-absolute rule. In American constitutional law, for example, a
governmental classification by race is unconstitutional unless the government can justify such a
mere rational basis typically needed to justify ordinary legislative classifications (Loving v.
Virginia 1967). But neither using an unless clause to formulate a rule with multiple conditions
for its application nor using one to express a non-absolute rule genuinely implicate the idea of
open texture. The latter is, to be sure, a way of accommodating for the possibility that the
details of all potential overrides cannot fully be anticipated in advance, but still differs from the
case in which specific law confronts the genuinely unexpected. Making rules defeasible and
using a vague standard for defeat is a way of managing the uncertainty of the future, but is
different from the case in which a non-vague rule confronts the genuinely unexpected.
straightforward, Hart makes a stronger and more problematic claim when he maintains not
only that a rule with an unless clause is still a rule, but also that the list of unlesses cannot
2
I put aside burden-of-proof considerations, which may make the two formulations more
different than they would be absent such considerations (Chapman 1998; Finkelstein, 1999).
13
be exhaustively specified in advance. (Hart 1994, 136; MacCormick, 1974, 117). In this he
marks a position now quite common in the legal literature. Richard Posner, for example, insists
that courts always (the word is crucial) retain the power to append ad hoc exceptions at the
moment of application even to existing, precise, and exceptionless rules (Posner 1988, 834-
835). Similarly, Richard Tur argues that courts necessarily have the power to set aside the
indications of rules in the service of equity or justice when applying the rule would produce an
unjust result or a one at odds with the rules background justification (Tur 2001), Ronald
Dworkin has described the list of legal principles as numberless, (Dworkin 1977: 43-44), and
Neil MacCormick has offered a slightly more qualified version (MacCormick 1995) of the same
claim. And although Ronald Dworkins later insistence that there is a real rule existing behind
the formal words of a written rule is mysterious (Bix 1993, 34-35), the heart of his argument is
the view, related to those just set out, that written rules are necessarily defeasible in the
Thus a new argument is now before us -- that laws open texture is not merely the open
texture of laws language, and not simply the conventional claim that legal rules, like all rules,
can be treated as defeasible,3 but that legal rules are necessarily defeasible. The claim is not
that treating legal rules as defeasible is desirable, useful, or common, but that it is in the nature
of rules or the nature of law that legal rules are necessarily and thus invariably defeasible.
3
Indeed, there is a vast literature exploring the logic of legal defeasibility (Hage 2005; Prakken
1997; Sartor 1995; Stelmach & Broek 2006), but that literature attempts to model and analyze
defeasibility when chosen by a legal system, rather than addressing the question whether such
defeasibility itself is a legal or logical necessity.
14
To be distinct from the defeasibility occasioned by the open texture of language, legal
defeasibility must exist within the area of linguistic determinacy. Were it otherwise, we would
simply be rehearsing in legal context the issues of linguistic open texture and consequent
linguistic indeterminacy. Thus the claims of Dworkin, MacCormick, Posner, and Tur, among
others, and suggested by Hart in asserting the impossibility of listing in advance all of the
possible unlesses, are best understood as claims positing defeasibility even in the face of
linguistic determinacy. Consider, to take the obvious example, the case featured by Ronald
Dworkin, the 1889 decision of the New York Court of Appeals in Riggs v, Palmer. In Riggs,
Elmer Palmers grandfather had named Elmer is his will, but was contemplating changing the
will, to Elmers disadvantage. In order to accelerate his inheritance, Elmer killed his grandfather
with poison. He was eventually caught, charged with murder, tried, convicted, and imprisoned.
But Elmer argued that he was still entitled to inherit his grandfathers estate, relying on the
New York Statute of Wills, which provided, to oversimplify, that anyone named as a beneficiary
in a will would inherit upon the death of the testator. Importantly, the Statute provided no
relevant exceptions to that rule, and the judges who thought Elmer should inherit and even
those who thought he should not agreed that the rule as written was clear and did not contain
The judges who thought that Elmer should lose were in the majority, relying on the no
man should profit from his own wrong principle to produce that outcome. But it is important
that there was agreement among all the judges that a literal application of the rule would allow
Elmer to inherit. This was not, therefore, a case of linguistic vagueness, ambiguity, or open
texture in Waismanns sense. The language was clear. It is just that the clear language
15
happened to produce an unfortunate and seemingly unfair result. But is such a result an
indication of the open texture of law qua law? Is it an example of the necessary defeasibility of
legal rules?
Riggs illustrates the distinction between a rule that gives no answer and a rule that gives
a bad answer, and precisely this distinction undercuts the claim of necessary defeasibility. The
rule in Riggs did not contain an unless clause, and thus we might conclude, or Hart might
have concluded, that Riggs presents a situation not envisaged when the rule was drafted. And
we might also conclude that the situation presented by Riggs is one in which a previously
unimagined situation shows how a hitherto unneeded and unanticipated unless clause might
have been a good idea. Yet even if that is so, the rule without the unless clause is still capable
of generating a clear outcome, albeit a morally (in this case) unpalatable one. Consequently,
the existence of hypothetical unless clauses whose addition would have prevented an
unfortunate outcome is insufficient to make the case that legal rules are necessarily defeasible.
If there is such a case to be made, essentially a claim that all of the rules in a system should
have open-ended unless clauses, it must be a moral or policy claim rather than a logical or
linguistic one. A rule that ill serves its background justification in a particular case is still a rule
capable of producing an outcome, and whether such an outcome should be tolerated when it is
unsound as a moral or policy matter is different from whether such an outcome presents an
16
When the New York court concluded in Riggs that Elmer could not inherit because of
the no man shall profit from his own wrong principle, it treated the most directly applicable
legal rule as defeasible in the service of justice. The no man may profit from his own wrong
principle is narrower than the full domain of justice, but few dimensions of justice probably
no dimensions of justice -- are not instantiated by some common law principle. Thus, the court
avoided the unjust outcome by implicitly concluding that all legal rules are defeasible in the
service of justice. And a similar situation arises when the rule-generated outcome result is
unreasonable or ridiculous, even if not unjust. In United States v. Kirby, for example, a
Kentucky law enforcement officer had been convicted under a federal law making it a crime to
interfere with the delivery of the mail. And that is exactly what Kirby had done. He had
unquestionably interfered with the delivery of the mail, but did so in the process of boarding a
steamboat to arrest a mail carrier named Farris who had been validly charged with murder by
Kentucky court. The case reached the Supreme Court, where the Court treated the statute as
defeasible, rejecting its literally dictated outcome where that outcome was inconsistent with
the purpose of the statute, inconsistent with commonsense, and inconsistent with justice.
If we depart the realm of the real and enter that of the hypothetical, we see the same
example (Fuller 1958, responding to Hart 1958). Fuller imagined a group of patriots who
installed a fully functional military truck in the park as a war memorial. This would clearly be a
vehicle, Fuller argued, but it would just as clearly be absurd to exclude it from the park on the
17
Had this been an empirical debate, Fuller may well have won. If Hart is understood to
claim that the plain meaning of the terms of a rule provides a conclusive answer in most real
cases in real legal systems, and if Fuller is understood as responding that the plain meaning
answer was typically defeasible and rarely conclusive in well-functioning legal systems, then
Fuller is closer than Hart to the reality in many modern legal systems (Schauer 2008).
But Fuller made a broader claim. For him (and Dworkin, MacCormick, Posner, and Tur),
it is not merely a contingent empirical fact that legal rules are typically (and, to Fuller,
preferably) defeasible in common law legal systems, but also that the defeasibility of legal rules
is an essential feature of legality itself, on a par with those other desiderata of legality that for
Fuller came close to defining law itself (Fuller 1969). For Fuller, failing to treat a rule like the
no-vehicles-in-the-park rule as defeasible was simply to abandon reason, and for him it was of
the essence of law that it be reasonable. A system that did not allow purpose-based or
equitable override of the plain indication of a legal rule when necessary to achieve a reasonable
outcome was for that reason just so much less of a legal system, and perhaps not even a legal
system at all. Indeed, we can understand Fullers claim in the best light, and without saddling
him with the view that nondefeasible law is not law at all, by interpreting him as maintaining
that non-defeasible law is necessarily defective as law, even if the defective law is still law. Just
as any boat that leaks is defective as a boat even as it remains a boat, so Fuller is best
understood as insisting that any legal system is necessarily defective as a legal system, and as
18
The course of action that Fuller rejects, however, is conceptually possible, often
adopted, and often far from unjustifiable. The New York Court of Appeals could have said that
Palmer would inherit despite the wrong he committed, just as the United States Supreme Court
could have concluded that Kirby violated federal law even though he did it for good reason, and
even though punishing Kirby was inconsistent with the purpose of the law he literally violated.
And some hypothetical judge could conclude that a war memorial made from a functioning
military truck was nevertheless a vehicle, and thus to be excluded from the park by virtue of the
even more pejoratively in some legal circles, formalistic, but they are neither conceptually nor
core, and as long the meaning of a word is not entirely a function of the particular context in
which it is used on a particular occasion (Bix, 1993, 21-22), then rules which are written in
words can indeed generate poor outcomes, and judges can embody those poor outcomes in
their rulings.
Indeed, not only can this happen, but it does frequently. The result in Riggs is more
exceptional than normal, even in the anti-formal American judicial system. There are other
cases in which the outcomes do resemble those in Riggs, but in many others beneficiaries who
were culpably responsible for the death of the testator were allowed to inherit. (Schauer 2004).
Tennessee Valley Authority v. Hill, in which a literal application of the Endangered Species Act
mandated the preservation of the habitat of a small, unattractive, and ecologically unimportant
fish called the snail darter, even at great cost to the aggregate public welfare by virtue of
19
blocking of an important public works project. And in United States v. Locke, a statute setting a
filing deadline of prior to December 31 was upheld even when its literal application resulted
in the arguably unfair exclusion of a claim filed on December 31 by someone who assumed, not
unreasonably, that the statute really meant to say on or prior to December 31.
There are numerous other examples, in the United States and elsewhere, and it would
rules as defeasible, frequently they do not. Often they treat the literal language of a rule
formulation as conclusive, and refrain from adding exceptions at the moment of application,
overriding the indications of rules in the service of justice or equity or efficiency, or modifying
rules at the moment of application. Such non-defeasibility may not be wise, but it is both
possible (Baker 1977, 38) and widespread. Rule-formulations have meanings distinct from the
background justifications lying behind the rules and distinct from what the best (or even a
good) rule-free outcome in some particular instance would be. Although treating rules as
defeasible is widespread in many legal systems, examples like those just offered show that rules
are often applied as written treated as non-defeasible even when what seem to be valid
defeating conditions are present. As a descriptive matter, it is hard to defend the position that
a legal system without widespread and legitimate defeasibility is for that reason no legal system
at all.
Moreover, non-defeasibility is hardly without justification. The arguments for rules are
familiar, and most of the arguments for rules in general are arguments for treating rules as non-
20
defeasible. When the designers of some decision-making environment are distrustful of judges
and other legal decision-makers who might be biased, corrupt, incompetent, ill-equipped for
the job, or just very rushed, then the designers might want to constrain those decision-makers
by rules rather than granting wide discretion. Indeed, when distrust is at its acme, decision-
makers may not be granted the authority to decide when some application of a rule is
ridiculous or absurd, let alone unfair, inequitable, unjust, or inefficient. It is easy to see that it
would be absurd to exclude the truck used as a war memorial from the park, but the real
question is whether and when some class of officials should be empowered to decide which
applications are absurd and which are not. Moreover, rules also serve to allocate decision-
making responsibility. To treat a rule as non-defeasible is often simply to decide that some but
not other officials will have the power to cancel, override, amend, or modify an existing rule.
And insofar as rules also bring the advantages of certainty, predictability, settlement, and
stability for stabilitys sake, treating the rules as defeasible comes at the sacrifice of each of
these values, even though of course it brings the potential advantages of fairness, equity, and,
It now becomes apparent that the traditional defenses of the necessary defeasibility of
legal rules whether Harts, or Posners, or MacCormicks, or Turs mostly rest on a certain
view about the powers and abilities of judges. Few people would maintain that police officers
or ordinary bureaucrats, for example, should have the power to revise the rules that constrain
them when those rules appear to indicate a poor outcome in a particular case. And if that is so,
21
then the view that defeasibility in the hands of judges is required by the Rule of Law while
defeasibility in hands of others is not turns out to be a view about the capacities of judges
within particular legal systems. So long as we can imagine something properly called a legal
system in which the power of rule revision and rule override is not entrusted to judges, then we
can imagine something properly called a legal system in which defeasibility is somewhat or
Defeasibility is thus not a property of rules at all, but rather a characteristic of how some
decision-making system will choose to treat its rules. The Wittgensteinian maxim that rules do
not determine their own applications reminds us that how a rule will be treated is not
something inherent in the rule itself. If the plain or literal (but not necessarily the ordinary
language) meaning of a rule can indicate an outcome, it is a function not of the rule but of how
the rule will be treated whether that indicated outcome is to be taken as conclusive,
presumptive, or even, at the extreme, as having no weight in itself, being but a totally
heuristic or rule of thumb. The question of defeasibility is not a question about what is in a
rule, but is rather a question about how what is in a rule, or about how what a rule says, is to be
treated, and this is not, and can never be, something that can be determined by the rule itself.
The question of defeasibility is this exposed as descriptive and prescriptive, but neither
logical nor conceptual. It is logically and conceptually possible for rules to be interpreted,
understood, applied, and enforced according to the literal meaning of the component language
of their formulations. Whether in this or that legal system they are in fact so treated is a
22
descriptive question, and it turns out, as the examples above illustrate, that as a descriptive
matter defeasibility is less universal in actual legal systems than we might have thought, even in
With respect to the prescriptive question, whether the literal meaning of a rule-
formulation will be treated as what the rule indicates, and whether what the rule indicates will
be treated as conclusive, are questions that cannot be answered by reference to the moral
goals of particularized justice. Those goals exist, to be sure, as Plato, Aristotle, and countless
successors have argued. But so too do the Rule of Law goals that might be thought of as the
goals of generalized justice, or aggregate justice, or systemic justice. And as long as those non-
particularistic goals have a place in our moral and prescriptive reasoning, then we cannot
conclude, the actual practices of some parts of some legal common law legal systems
notwithstanding, that the defeasibility of legal rules is a necessary part of all legal systems, or
that the defeasibility of rules in general is a necessary part of all decision-making environments.
Defeasibility may well be a desirable component of some parts of some legal systems at some
times, but it is far from being an essential property of law. And if law is not necessarily
defeasible, then law is not open-textured in Waismanns sense. Insofar as language is open-
textured, then so too, necessarily is law. But the open texture if laws language exhausts the
open texture of law, and thus when laws language does not exhibit languages open texture,
23
Bibliography:
Alexander, Larry, & Emily Sherwin 2001: The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of
Ayer, Alfred Jules 1946: Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollancz, Ltd., 2d. ed.
Austin, J.L. 1946: Other Minds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp.) 20, 148-187.
Baker, G.P. 1977: Defeasibility and Meaning. In: P.M.S. Hacker & J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality,
and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 26-57.
Bix, Brian 1993: Law, Language, and Legal Determinacy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Chapman, Bruce 1998: Law Games: Defeasible Rules and Revisable Rationality. Law and
Dworkin, Ronald M. 1986: Laws Empire. Cambridge, Mass.; Harvard University Press.
Finkelstein, Claire Oakes 1999: When the Rule Swallows the Exception. In Linda Meyer (ed.),
Rules and Reasoning: Essays in Honour of Fred Schauer. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 147-175.
Fuller, Lon L. 1958: Positivism and Fidelity to Law A Reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law
Fuller, Lon L. 1969: The Morality of Law (revised edition). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
24
Gardner, John 2001: Legal Positivism: 5 Myths. American Journal of Jurisprudence, 46, 199-
227.
Hart, H.L.A. 1958: Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard Law Review, 71,
593-629.
Hart, H.L.A. 1994: The Concept of Law, 2d ed., Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz (eds.). Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
MacCormick, Neil 1974: Law as Institutional Fact. Law Quarterly Review 90, 102-129.
MacCormick, Neil 1995: Defeasibility in Law and Logic. In Zenon Bankowski, Ian White, &
Ulrike Hahn, eds., Informatics and the Foundations of Legal Reasoning. Dordrecht,
Posner, Richard A. 1988: The Jurisprudence of Skepticism. Michigan Law Review 86, 827-
858.
Postema, Gerald J. 1986: Bentham and the Common Law Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Prakken, Henry 1997: Logical Tools for Modelling Legal Argument: A Study in Defeasible
25
Sartor, Giovanni 1995: Defeasibility in Legal Reasoning. In Zenon Bankowski, Ian White, &
Ulrike Hahn, Informatics and the Foundations of Legal Reasoning. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Kluwer, 119-158.
Schauer, Frederick 1991: Exceptions. University of Chicago Law Review, 58, 871-904.
Schauer, Frederick 2004: The Limited Domain of the Law. Virginia Law Review, 90, 1909-
1956.
Schauer, Frederick 2008: A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park. New York University Law
Stelmach, Jerzy, and Bartosz Broek 2006: Methods of Legal Reasoning. Dordrecht,
Netherlands: Springer.
Tur, Richard 2001: Defeasibilism. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 21, 355-368.
26
Waismann, Friedrich 1945: Verifiability. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp.) 19,
119-47, and in A.G.N. Flew (ed.), Logic and Language (First Series). Oxford: Basil Blackwell
(1951), 117-44.
27