Assessing Good Governance' New Zealand
Assessing Good Governance' New Zealand
Assessing Good Governance' New Zealand
Robert Gregory
Year 2013
1
INSTITUTE FOR GOVERNANCE
AND POLICY STUDIES
WORKING PAPER
13/03
2
Assessing Good Governance and Corruption in New Zealand:
Scientific Measurement, Political Discourse, and Historical
Narrative
Robert Gregory
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
School of Government
Victoria University of Wellington
New Zealand
Abstract
New Zealand is ranked highly on the Worldwide Governance Indicators (WGI), which assess
performance on six dimensions of governance: voice and accountability, political stability
and absence of violence, government effectiveness, regulatory quality, rule of law, and
control of corruption. In addition, New Zealand has long been rated by Transparency
Internationals Corruption Perceptions Index (CPI) as having the very lowest rates of
corruption. It was rated as first, or first equal (that is, perceived as the least corrupt or equally
least corrupt country in the world), in 2006, 2007, 2008, 2009 and 2010, and sat alone atop
the rankings in 2009 and 2011. In 2012 it was ranked first equal again. This paper gives some
attention to methodological and related arguments about the general validity of both the WGI
and the CPI, and is based on the premise that these international rankings are not only widely
accepted as valid statements of relative fact, but also can divert attention away from pertinent
issues of good government within particular countries. It may be claimed on the basis of these
indicators that relative to the performance of most other countries New Zealanders have little
to be worried about regarding the quality of their governing institutions and processes. Yet
good governance, including low levels of corruption, needs to be assessed against the
countrys own standards over time, and informed by historical understanding. International
league tables, using precise indexes and indicators have their uses. However, they should not
be reified or allowed to dominate or supplant valid social criticism in the form of political
discourse and historical narrative, which are essential in assessing any countrys quality of
governance.
Acknowledgement: The author thanks Jonathan Boston and Michael Macaulay, of the
School of Government, VUW, for helpful comments on two drafts of this paper. The usual
disclaimer applies.
The publicity of the government, the press, and a host of private organisations
constantly assures the public that New Zealand leads the world in this, that, and the other. So
often is the point repeated and asserted about so many features of the Dominions life that it
is now earnestly believed by the majority. It is held as a faith which few call in
questionUnder its worst forms it can degenerate into smugness and complacency, the
national delusion of the self-satisfied.
Leslie Lipson (1948) The Politics of Equality: New Zealands Adventures in
Democracy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 459-460.
3
What is good governance?
The main idea of governanceas distinct from governmenthas become intellectually
fashionable in academic circles over the past decade or so, constituting a new conceptual
paradigm that embodies ideas about the dispersal and fragmentation of formerly centralised
state authority, the increasing involvement of civil society in the delivery of public goods and
services, and the networked collaboration of a wide range of governmental and non-
governmental bodies in the pursuit of public purposes and the public interest (Bevir, 2009;
Bovaird and Lffler, 2003; Kjaer, 2004; OECD, 2001, 2005; Osborne, 2010; Pierre, 2000;
Pierre and Peters, 2000, 2005; Srensen and Torfing, 2007; Rhodes, 1996, 1997, 2007;
Stivers, 2008). According to Rhodes (2007: 1247), for example, with particular reference to
Britain, the model of Westminster hierarchical government is no longer acceptable,
requiring a different story of the shift from Government with its narrative of the strong
executive to governance through networks. This paradigm shiftwhich Marsh (2008: 735)
has critically described as the new orthodoxyhas been strongly contested by other
scholars who are also less convinced about the scope of actual change in governing relations
(Bell and Hindmoor, 2009; Frederickson, 2005; Hill and Lynn, 2005; Grix and Phillpots,
2011; Lynn, 2010, 2011; Marsh, 2008; Olsen, 2006; Robichau, 2011).
While government can be understood as an entity, embodying such components as the
machinery of government, governance is better understood as a process. Good
governance, therefore, refers to processes that work well or badly according to certain
criteria. Just what these criteria are or should be is a matter of political choice. As Holmberg
et al (2008) point out, because good governance is such a broad concept and
encompasses a range of issues, empirical analyses hinge on the definition of the term.
However, it must also be true that the assessments as to whether governance is good or bad,
or better or worse, must depend to some extent on the outcomes that they give rise to,
support, facilitate or enhance. It is possible to conceive, theoretically at least, of a country
which displays good governance but repeatedly produces disastrous policy and
governmental outcomes, and a situation in which the converse is true. (Even if such
possibilities seem to offend common sense, this in itself is an insufficient reason for
academics to desist from conceiving them.) Thus, there is an on-going relationship between
means and ends, process and result, and so on. And while this involves interaction between
two clearly separable components at a conceptual level, in practice they are always in an
iterative, mutually constitutive, relationship. As Friedrich (1940: 6) famously observed,
4
Public policy is being formed as it is being executed, and it is likewise being executed as it is
being formed.
Good governance is probably best defined experientially: for example, people living in
what have come to be known as failed states probably share a sense of living in a society
that is chaotic, unpredictable and largely indifferent to their welfare, individually and
collectively. Diamond (2007: 119) does not paint a glittering picture:
There is a specter haunting democracy in the world today. It is bad governance
governance that serves only the interests of a ruling elite. Governance that is drenched
in corruption, patronage, favouritism, and abuse of power. Governance that is not
responding to the massive and long-deferred social agenda of reducing inequality and
unemployment and fighting against dehumanizing poverty. Governance that is not
delivering broad improvements in peoples lives because it is stealing, squandering, or
skewing the available resources. The Philippines, Bangladesh and Nigeria lie at
different points along the path of democratic decay, but they reflect a common problem.
Where power confers virtually unchecked opportunities for personal, factional, and
party enrichment, it is difficult if not impossible to sustain democratic rules of the
game. The democratic spirit of elections drowns in vote-buying, rigging, violence, or
all three.
In reversing, in summary form, Diamonds dimensions of bad governance it follows that its
opposite good governance occurs in a democratic polity in which officialdom (political
and administrative) serves the interests of all, is non-corrupt, not given to the abuse of power,
seeks effectively to reduce inequality, unemployment and poverty, uses public resources in
the pursuit of collective purposes, operates according to the rule of law, and maintains fair
and open electoral processes.
We might assume that, if they were asked, most New Zealand citizens, for example, would
say that they prefer to be subjected to good governance than to bad governance,
notwithstanding the likelihood that some people will see any form of government as bad
government. But good governance and bad governance are rhetorical categories, rather
than scientific ones. One persons good governance is anothers bad governance, in the
same way that, One persons red tape may be anothers treasured procedural safeguard
(Kaufman, 1977: 4).
Such evaluations are obviously political rather than scientific. Citizens of virtually all of the
worlds developed nations are likely to believe that their countries are more or less well
governed, with their positive or negative judgements being based on a myriad of often
conflicting assessments, impressions, experiences, and biases. Good governance is
5
experienced by people in a wider community of shared interest, a politywhich may be
another way of saying that good governance is a process which effectively promotes and
secures some albeit elusive notion of the public interest. As Rothstein (2013: 12) says,
Trying to define good governance while ignoring the normative issue of what should
constitute good defies logic. He cites Offes (2009) argument that the concept is empty of
agency: There is no verb form of the word like there is for government. Members of the
government can govern but what it is [is it sic] that members of a network of governance
are doing? In reality, the concept tends to capture all forms of collective social co-ordination,
outside pure market relations or the family (Rothstein, 2013: 8). For his part, Offe (2009:
553) claims that the use value of the concept of governance for the social sciences is
jeopardized by a tendency of over aggregating the phenomena it refers toIt is not
surprising that the concept has not been introduced by an authority in social theory, but by the
World Bank, which suggested it in 1989with rapid and obviously lasting success.
Nor, as Rothstein (2013) argues, should elements which need explanation, in and of
themselves, be included in any definition of good governance, if the quality of how the state
manages to govern society is considered to be a truer measure of good governance than how
access to power is organised in a representative democracy. In this regard, Rothstein cites Sen
(2011), who claims that on most standard measures of human well-being, the Peoples
Republic of China now clearly outperforms democratically governed India. For their part,
Holmberg and Rothstein (2011) find weak, sometimes negative and sometimes no
correlations between standard measures of human well-being (including child deprivation)
and the level of representative democracy. They cite a study by Hallerd et al (2013), using
data from 68 low and middle income countries, measuring seven aspects of child poverty, and
showing no positive effect of democracy on levels of child deprivation for any of the
indicators access to safe water, food, sanitation, shelter, education, health care and
information. Rothsteins (2013: 4) conclusion is that, Representative democracy is not a safe
cure against severe poverty, child deprivation, economic inequality, illiteracy, being unhappy
or not satisfied with ones life, infant mortality, short life-expectancy, maternal mortality,
access to safe water or sanitation, gender inequality, low school attendance for girls, low
interpersonal trust or low trust in Parliament. Presumably, given the experiences of countries
like Britain, the United States and New Zealand over the past couple of decades or so, he
might have added high levels of income inequality to this list.
6
Apart from the idea of governance that grew out of the critique in western democracies of
what has been seen as the growing inefficiency and rigidity of traditional Weberian public
administration, Rothstein (2013) identifies two other emergent conceptualisations of
governance. The first is the idea of participatory governance, which focuses on means of
overcoming a democratic deficit by involving citizens in broad based and open systems for
collective deliberation in public decision making either as a complement or an alternative to
the system of representative democracy (Rothstein, 2013: 9). The second is what Rothstein
calls the political economy approach to governance. This idea has not emerged from any
dissatisfaction with public administration and policy in mature Western democracies, but
from cross-national research on development and economic growth in so-called third world
countries. Here, good governancecentral to which is the effective fight against
corruptionis seen to be essential in achieving social and economic development.
This approach has been central to the work of international donor organisations, and is
exemplified in the World Governance Indicators (WGI) developed in recent years under the
imprimatur of the World Bank, covering more than 200 countries since 1996, and updated
annually (Kaufmann, Kraay and Mastruzzi, 2008, 2010).1 The WGI are widely publicised and
draw upon data from many sources in ranking countries on six aggregate measures of
governance: voice and accountability, political stability and absence of violence, government
effectiveness, regulatory quality, rule of law, and control of corruption. The first two
dimensions address the process by which governments are selected, monitored and replaced;
the second and third ones are intended to cover the capacity of the government to effectively
formulate and implement sound policies; and the latter two deal with the respect of citizens
and the state for the institutions that govern economic and social interactions among them
(Kaufmann, Kraay and Mastruzzi, 2010: 4).
Because of the ambiguity of the idea of governance, and because complex definitions are
too difficult to operationalize for comparative purposes, Rothstein (2013) prefers a
parsimonious conceptualisation of the quality of government. This is built on the Rawlsian
normative understanding of what should be seen as a just political order, and the
Machiavellian strategy of practical implementation in enhancing human well-being, social
trust, life satisfaction, peace and political legitimacy. Discarding the six dimensions of the
1
See: http://info.worldbank.org/governance/wgi/index.asp
7
WGI, Rothstein instead argues that the sine qua non of quality government is impartiality in
the exercise of political power. Rothstein is aware of the objections that can be raised against
such a parsimonious procedural conceptualisation. 2 The main point is to contrast such a
conceptualisation of good government, one that can be operationalised for meaningful
comparative purposes, on the one hand, with the WGI attempt to operationalise for cross-
country comparisons six dimensions of governance, all of which in themselves embody
complex relationships between input and output sides of government.
It may be, after all, that good governance is something of an indefinable abstraction. Of
course, in practical terms the notion speaks to a communitys collective capacity to ensure
that the haunting spectre of which Diamond speaks is not allowed to visit its calumnies on
that particular polity. But which factors most enhance or diminish the risk of any of these
tragic outcomes? What actions are necessary to ensure that any of these tragedies are
avoided? What theoretical knowledge is available to inform such action, providing governors
and people with some useful understanding of the relationships among a range of variables?
These are challenging questions for public policymakers.
2
For example, a procedural definition of political processes cannot preclude morally bad decisions,
which might violate the rights of minorities and individuals. Rothstein (2013: 15) argues that, the
strategy suggested by John Rawls is the right one. His central idea is that if a society structures its
systems for making and enforcing collective decisions in a fair way, this will increase the likelihood
that the outcomes are normatively just.
8
What has emerged in recent years, however, and which by implication seeks to supplant
political ways of judging governmental quality, is the attempt to generate comparative
measures of good governance, as if such quantitative evaluations can be based on detached,
better informed, rational, and scientific calculation, even assuming that we know what good
governance actually is. Apart from the WGI, there has been an explosion of indexes and
indicators, as various international organisations develop measures to rank comparatively the
performances of different countries, both globally and regionally. Among the most widely
cited of other indexes to have emerged within the past 20 years, Transparency Internationals
Corruptions Perceptions Index (CPI), established in 1995, ranks countries according to the
degree of corruption experienced across all areas of society. Others include the Asia
Foundations Economic Governance Index, the OECD Better Life Index, the UNDPs
Human Development Index, the Fund for Peace Failed States Index, the Economist
Intelligence Units Democracy Index, the World Justice Project Rule of Law Index, the Open
Budget Index, the Freedom House Index of Press Freedom, the UN Industrial Development
Organisations Competitive Industrial Performance Index, and the Reporters Without
Borders Press Freedom Index. Then there is Hofstedes (2001) heroic attempt to rank
countries on a set of six indexes which purport to measure, respectively, power distance
(PDI), uncertainty avoidance (UAI), masculinity versus femininity (MAS), individualism
versus collectivism (IDV), long-term versus short-term orientation (LTO), and indulgence
versus restraint (IVR). And so it goes, seemingly without end.
One inevitable by-product of the emergence of such indexes has been a burgeoning of
academic criticism of the methodologies adopted in formulating them. While it is not the
purpose of this paper to canvass and try to assess the relative merits of all such criticisms, it is
worthwhile mentioning some of those pertaining to the WGI, to at least gain a sense of how
problematic are the foundations of such indexes in general.
9
cited critics of the WGIs, emphasise this point in their critiques. While a single composite
number is seductive, and enables quick comparisons to be made among countries, the
problem is that for comparative purposes these numbers are virtually meaningless, since they
are based on sources and information which vary greatly between countries, and even within
countries, over time (Anderson, 2009). As Pollitt (2008: 19) argues, the concept of
governance itself is so vague, abstract, value-laden and multi-faceted as to present an
insurmountable challenge for expert measurers and lay decisionmakers alikethe idea of
reducing governance to six composite indicatorslet alone one, as some indices attempt
seems just too Olympian.
10
The indicators are also ahistorical, in that they tend to represent their key dimensions as
central to a liberal democratic end of history apotheosis. They say almost nothing about the
complex historical, cultural and political forces which have shaped the present day
representation of a state in the form of a series of index numbers. They say nothing, therefore,
about how those historical factors can shape the future of governance in those states.
Do the six WGI dimensions simply say roughly the same thing, but with different words in
each case? If there is indeed some substantive relationship between economic development
and good governance, then is it a causal oneand if so, in what direction?or is it a
spurious correlation more explicable by other independent variables? For example, do low
levels of governmental and/or business corruption foster good governance, or does good
governance keep the lid on governmental and/or business corruption? Is it possible to have
simultaneously both good governance and high levels of corruption, and low levels of
corruption together with not-so-good or bad governance? These are theoretical possibilities at
least, but the WGI do not recognise them as such, since low corruption is taken a priori to be
one of the six dimensions of good governance. The situation is clouded by the fact that low
and high corruption, on the one hand, and good or bad governance, on the other, are relative
not absolute concepts. Countries like the United States, Britain and Australia, for example,
score relatively well on both good governance indicators and on the CPI, but not as well as a
11
number of other countries, including New Zealand, on either indexes. It is not at all clear how
the WGI can help to explain, as distinct from demonstrating, such differences (Andrews,
2008).
As Oman and Arndt (2010) see it, the WGI suffer from a transparency paradox, in that while
the construction of the indexes is itself not transparent, they are nevertheless used by
international aid agencies as a means of enhancing the transparency and objectivity of their
aid-allocation decisions. The lack of transparency results in the main from the absence of any
coherent theory or analytical framework of governance to guide their scoring systems. They
simply produce scores according to aggregated subjective perceptions relating to each
indicator. They do not say anything explicitly about the priorities that governments might be
encouraged to attend to, or the sequencing of reforms and developments that might arguably
be needed to lift a countrys WGI scores. Are there social, political or economic tipping
points, for example, which can have a major impact, for better or for worse (depending on
the specific criteria by which better and worse are evaluated)?
Misuse
Not only do the WGI tend to oversimplify complex realities, but the indexes themselves tend to
become reified, that is, they become accepted as precise and objective measurements, as largely
indisputable facts.3 They therefore diminish rather than enhance the capacity for more insightful
analysis and judgements about the countries themselves. Because they lack any coherent
theoretical foundations, they say nothing about how individual countries can develop better
governance (assuming that it is possible to know in what specific ways better governance
differs from good governance, or not so good governance).
Worse than this, however, to the extent that the WGI (and the CPI) become used as decision tools
for international agencies, the WGI can actually impede what might be considered by many to be
desirable forms of development, simply because the indicators do not necessarily provide valid
and meaningful comparisons among different countries.
3
See Oman and Arndt (2010: 15-16) for a critique of the over-estimation of the accuracy of
countries point scores for cross-country comparisons and the identification of change (or the lack of
it) in the quality of governance over time.
12
The problem lies with composite indexes, like the WGI, rather than with indexes per se. Pollitt
(2008: 18) argues that, WGIsare highly attractive to elite groups yet almost useless, if not
actively misleading, for lay decisionmakersBy contrast PISA [OECDs Programme for
International Student Assessment] measures are attractive and useful, though with some
significant pitfalls concerning what the tests do and do not mean, and with a considerable gap
between the results and the drawing of policy conclusions.
In other words, indexes are useful and valid to the extent that they measure what can sensibly and
reasonably accurately be measured, rather than trying or purporting to measure accurately what
they cannot so measure. In this regard, the Serendipity Prayer may be recast: Grant me the
ability to measure those things than can sensibly be measured; the intelligence to understand
those that cannot be measured; and the wisdom to know the difference.
However, there has emerged a growing scepticism about these sorts of assumptions, one
which rejects the idea that one size fits all when it comes to development, and is much more
open-minded about the relationships between such factors as economic development and the
progressive establishment of the institutions believed to be central to good governance. For
example, in his comparative study of public financial management in a selection of OECD
and non-OECD countries, Andrews (2010) found that there was no single best way, no best
practice model, in achieving sustained sound practice, and that good public financial
management means different things in different countries.
13
In similar vein, Sundaram and Chowdhury (2012), in their edited volume entitled Is Good
Governance Good for Development?, strongly question any received wisdom that economic
development is dependent upon action that would substantially raise countries scores on the
six WGI dimensions. The rapid rates of economic development displayed over the past two
or three decades by countries like China and Vietnam are obvious cases in point. In Vietnam
the regime has deliberately eschewed the progressive development of Western institutions
like the rule of law, in the apparent belief that economic growth is the main priority and any
real concern over good governance if it is a concern at all can be left till later (Painter,
2012). (The same can also be said of China, of course.) Painter (2006) has mounted a similar
argument in regard to Vietnams apparent adoption of some of the principles of Western
New Public Management (NPM) before securing the rule of law and an administrative
system based solidly on the principles of Weberian legal-rational authority. He is not
convinced that some of the key ideas embodied in NPM cannot be successfully adopted in
developing countries where legal-rational foundations have not been consolidateda view
that runs counter to the widely cited argument made by Schick (1998).
That there are indeed many different ways to achieve economic development, rather than a
single technocratic template based on the sort of dimensions embodied in the WGI, is
reflected in the pragmatic programmes of marketization displayed in post-Mao China,
according to the idea of crossing the river by feeling the stones (Gabriel, 1998). More
generally, Grindle (2004: 541-542) argues that the path to good governance as a means of
effectively tackling poverty in developing countries is fraught with ambiguities, challenges,
and the potential for failure and less-than-anticipated results. She suggests that the best that
can be hoped for, at least in the shorter-term, is good enough governance.
Response
The authors of the WGIs have offered detailed and sometimes quite persuasive refutations of
these and other criticisms (Kaufmann, Kraay and Mastruzzi, 2007, 2010). In response to
Thomas (2010), who queries what the WGI actually measure, they argue that the absence of
definitional consensus regarding governance would paralyze any effort to measure
governance using any means (2007: 24).4 Similarly, Endlessly waiting for the articulation of
a complete, coherent and consistent theory of governance before proceeding to measurement
and action (of course with due regard to limitations), while perhaps intellectually satisfying to
4
They were responding to an earlier (2006) draft of Thomas (2010).
14
a few, would be impractical to the point of irresponsibility (2007: 26). They are particularly
careful to offer caveats regarding the interpretation and use of the WGI, cautioning users that,
aggregate indicators such as the six WGI measures are often a blunt tool for policy advice
at the country level, and that Userscan usefully complement their analysis with an in-
depth examination of the detailed disaggregated data sources underlying the WGI, together
with a wealth of possible [sic] more detailed and nuanced sources of country-level data and
diagnostics on governance issues (2010: 21).
Regarding ideological biases, they point out that they found no substantial difference between
the views offered by business people and those household surveys that they did use, nor any
apparent bias in the ways rating agencies assessed the performances of governments of the
political left or right. At least in regard to perceptions of corruption, this argument may be
supported by Rothstein (2013: 22-23), who cites a large survey of ordinary people in
various EU countries, which produced results surprisingly similar to expert-based measures
(see Charron et al, 2013).
However, much of their response focuses on narrower methodological points, without really
offering a convincing refutation of the argument that (a) governance is too elusive a concept
in the first place to be operationalized with the precision that the WGI purport to offer; and
(b) that their own assumptions as to what constitutes good governance do not really demand
critical scrutiny. Moreover, their pleas for caution in the interpretation and use of the WGI
our estimation of, and emphasis onmargins of error is intended to enable users to make
more sophisticated use of imperfect informationwhile valid in itself, overlooks the reality
that most (especially non-academic) users of the WGI are likely to have neither the time,
expertise nor inclination to act on such warnings. As Pollitt (2008: 20) asks, what
percentage of the users of WGIs access the technical documentation [that supports them]?
15
and sharing the top position again with Denmark and Finland in 2012. Since the CPI was
established in 1995, New Zealand has never ranked below fourth, with absolute scores
ranging between 9.3 and 9.6 out of 10.
There are other international indexes on which New Zealand scores highly. Included among
these are the World Justice Project Rule of Law Index, which in 2011 ranked New Zealand in
second place in open government and third on regulatory enforcement, among a total of
66 countries; the Open Budget Index, ranking New Zealand first out of 100 countries in 2012
with a score of 93/100 (18 OECD countries averaged a score of 72); and the Freedom House
Index of Press Freedom, which ranked New Zealand in 16th equal place in 2012, among a
total of 197 countries.
While the growing use of such objective measures in making international comparisons has
proved useful for research purposes of various kinds, it also raises questions. Some criticisms,
although addressing primarily methodological issues, do not challenge the inherent validity of
using such indexes as tools for assessing countries performances in both absolute and
relative terms.
The CPI, for example, is based on a series of cross-national surveys of business peoples
views on their own countrys economic performance. Each survey includes several questions
on corruption. Responses to these questions are processed by way of a complex algorithm
that also incorporates the views of groups of academics. This algorithm determines an
international ranking of countries, from least corrupt to most corrupt. The CPI was designed
so that there would be stability and consistency in rankings over time, and it is very unusual
for a country to move up or down the rankings significantly in a one or even two-year period.
(Iceland after 2008 became the major exception in this regard.)
16
General should design an indicator measuring the incidence of corruption in New Zealands
public sector (though they did not specify how this might be done).
Perceptions are real in their effects, and New Zealands consistently high scores and positions
on the CPI are valued for instrumental purposes, such as maintaining a national image which
helps the countrys cause in international trade and foreign investment, and so on. Other
countries that are ranked lowly, however, can be caught in a corruption trap, whereby
development aid, essential in fighting corruption, is cut off or reduced because little
progress is apparent on the CPI (Andersson and Heywood, 2009). The World Bank can
easily be seen as an institutionalised embodiment of powerful political interests, so the
widespread use of its indicators may not be neutral in its effects on developing countries
(Arndt 2008). For his part, one of the founders of the CPI has argued that the index should be
discontinued in its present form because it tends to undermine the efforts of reformers
(Galtung, 2006). This is a particular take on the Matthew Principle: For he who has shall
more be given, and from he who hath not shall more be taken away or the rich get richer
and the poor get poorer.
The main problem with measuring perceptions of corruption lies not in the measurement but
in the perceptions. That is, believing is seeing, rather than seeing is believing. Donchev and
Ujhelyi (2009) argue that there is substantial evidence indicating that the use of corruption
perception indexes as a measure of corruption experience may be more problematic than is
commonly believed. They argue that better measures of the levels of actual corruption are
needed. Arguably, without them the CPI can be self-fulfilling, both positively and negatively.
It is positively so to the extent that those whose opinion and expertise is canvassed
themselves have some interest in not seeing or acknowledging it, when it exists, and
negatively so to the extent that corruption is seen even when it does not exist. The former,
analogous to Horatio Nelson putting his telescope to his blind eye, is more likely to apply in
New Zealands case, for a number of possible reasons (Gregory, 2002). One of these might
simply be the absence of a dedicated anti-corruption agency; another may be official interests
in promoting a strongly positive image of Brand New Zealand; another may be the lack of
real incentives for the leaders of public organisations to seek out corrupt practices within their
own agencies. In this latter regard, it is worth noting that in New Zealand since the
introduction of the State Sector Act 1988 there has been no central record kept of criminal
offences committed by state servants. Nor is there in New Zealand any common law covering
17
misconduct in public office, as there is in Britain and Hong Kong, for example. 5
Conversely, negative perceptions may be generated and exacerbated from excessive news
media attention paid to what are in fact infrequent and atypical cases of corruption, or what is
presented as such.
As with the WGI, so too with corruption: the definitional issue is crucial. The World Bank
has defined governmental corruption as the abuse of public office for private gain, and
Transparency International refers to it as the abuse of entrusted power or private gain.
These generic definitions are widely accepted, with relatively minor variations. But more
encompassing definitions can be invokedfor example, the abuse of public interest and the
undermining of public confidence in the integrity of rules, systems, and institutions that
promote the public interest (Baker, Christensen and Shaxson, 2008). This definition
suggests that corruption can involve much more than those practices which are commonly
understood to be hard core forms of corruption, like active or passive bribery and the
seeking and granting of secret commissions. Definitions of corruption must include activity
that occurs in society at large, in business and not-for-profit organisations, and not just in the
public sector.
Cultural and historical factors shape the meaning of corruption in different countriesfor
example, a gift in Vietnam may be a bribe in New Zealandbut it can be argued that in all
countries what is considered to be corruption is a function of legality and legitimacy. An act
may be illegal but not widely considered to be socially illegitimate; or it may be socially
legitimate but formally illegal; both illegal and illegitimate, and both legal and legitimate
(Gregory, 2002).6
5
In Hong Kong, public officials can be prosecuted for serious forms of corruption under the
Prevention of Bribery Ordinance, and for other offences they can be charged with misconduct in
public office, in cases where they are alleged to have received unwarranted personal advantage. For
example, in the late 1990s/early 2000s, the chief property manager of the Government Property
Agency was found guilty of misconduct in public office after exerting improper influence in the
award of large management contracts to a company in which the brothers of his sister-in-law had a
financial interest. He was sentenced to nine months in prison, later increased on appeal by the
prosecution to 30 months. Apart from being dismissed from the public service, he also lost his
pension rights, then totalling HKD six million.
6
For example, the huge remuneration paid to top executives in the financial sector in the United
States, and elsewhere, even after the global financial crisis, was not illegal but many considered it
highly illegitimate, and a form of corruption. At the other end of the income scale, the pilfering of
18
Clearly, behaviour which is both legal and legitimate is the desirable norm, the antithesis of
that which is both illegal and illegitimatein other words, hard core corruption. All crime is
by definition illegal, but not all crimes are corruption; not all forms of what can be considered
to be corruption are illegal, in that they may not be socially abhorred.
So while such definitional issues are challenging and important, especially for comparative
analytical purposes, in general terms it may be best to accept that, corrupt behavior is
behavior that is considered wrong immoral and condemned as such (Reder, 1975: 607).
Definitional issues aside, indexes such as the WGI and the CPI establish the firm impression
that New Zealand is doing very well, that its quality of governance is among the very best in
the world, and that corruption is virtually non-existent in Aotearoa. This sanguine view is
problematic for several main reasons.
First, marginal differences in scores among countries mean that proximate rankings are a
product of the methodology rather than a true depiction of relative levels of corruption, year
by year, even putting aside the fact that the country sources of CPI data can and do change
year by year. In regard to the incidence of corruption, what can reasonably be inferred from
the fact that the CPI ranked New Zealand first in 2011 and fourth in 1998? Obviously, it
suggests that New Zealands performance has improved since 1998, but what accounts for
any such marginal improvements, even assuming they are not a function of the measuring
methodology rather than of the performance itself? And, of course, it could also mean that
New Zealands shift in the rankings is a reflection of performance in other countries rather
than within New Zealand itself.
Secondly, while the CPIs real value may lie in ranking countries according to broad
categories, such a least corrupt, most corrupt, and relatively corrupt, such judgements can
also readily be made, and always have been made, through well-informed observation.
Marginal differences among countries which lie within the same general category are usually
considered to be more interesting than major variations between countries which are in
different groupings. New Zealanders and Australians, for example, are likely to display what
Sigmund Freud called the narcissism of small differences in focusing their attention on
workplace material for private use is illegal, but has often been widely accepted as a legitimate perk
of employment, especially for lower paid workers.
19
those differing elements, which through the eyes of someone from a markedly different
cultural background might seem to be trivial.
Thirdly, such observation is arguably of most value when it provides insight not into why
some countries are most different, but into why they are most similar, but stillperhaps
marginallydifferent.
Finally, it may simply be more productive to consider issues of good governance and non-
corruptibility according to the circumstances, conditions, norms and values within any
particular country rather than in comparison with others. In drawing up its 2013 National
Integrity System Assessment Report, Transparency International (New Zealand) rightly
examines circumstances and changes within New Zealand, and against local standards, rather
than evaluating these in the light of what may be occurring in other countries.
The first issue speaks for itself. Turning to the second one, it can be asked whether or not
explanations of the quality of governance in any country are impeded by the absence of such
indicators. In other words, to what extent, if at all, has the comparatively recent emergence of
these data bases enhanced the assessment of the quality of governance in individual countries,
in ways which were not possible in their absence? Beyond that, it can be asked whether the
emergence of such league tables has in fact impeded rather than enhanced the generation of
valid knowledge about the quality of governance in different countries. These are matters
worthy of serious consideration, the sort of consideration that can too easily be pushed aside
on the grounds that any advancement in social scientific inquiry, such as the emergence of
what purport to be valid measures of complex social and political phenomena, isipso
factodesirable.
In this context, therefore, the age-old epistemological question reasserts itself: what
constitutes valid knowledge? Is the knowledge generated by indexes like the WGIs and the
CPI more reliablescientific and rational, for examplebecause it is distilled into a single
number, than that body of usually disparate, verbalised, contested, and subjectively shaped
knowledge which can be found in any political community?
Such arguments were well canvassed, for example, by Lindblom and Cohen (1979) in their
examination of the differences and relative utilities of what they called professional social
inquiry, on the one hand, and ordinary knowledge, on the other. Their arguments, later
20
extended by Lindblom (1990), challenged any assumptions that the use of formal social
science methodologies had generated knowledge which provided an undeniably
indispensable contribution to governments capacities to grapple effectively with what are
tendentiously called social problems. In particular, the distinction made by Lindblom and
Cohen (1979) between political authoritativeness and scientific conclusiveness, and the
relationship between the two, speaks to the same issue: scientific conclusiveness, even when
it can be achieved, does not in and of itself generate political authoritativeness, in the sense
that science can pre-empt political and policy decision-making. If this were the case, then the
strong consensus reached by scientists on anthropogenic climate change would long since
have been enough to secure collectively effective political action, notwithstanding the
recalcitrant power exercised by strong vested interests.
To illustrate the third issuethe relative utility of examining marginal rather than radical
differences among countriesit may be asked, for example, why Somalia has much more
corruption than Denmark. Any half-plausible explanation would refer to historical and
cultural circumstances and differences rather than to the relative effectiveness of
governmental institutions, and the like, in each country. Conversely, historical and cultural
factors are likely to be much less important than institutional approaches in explaining why
two countries, say Denmark and New Zealand, are consistently ranked on the CPI as being
largely corruption-free. In comparisons of similar cases like these, cultural and historical
factors seem less important than the fact that both countries are highly rated on five of the six
dimensions comprising the WGI (obviously, reference to corruption levels on the WGI would
be tautological). Historical and cultural differences have less explanatory force than do
institutional similarities.
What about, say, Australia and New Zealandtwo countries with similar cultures and
heritages, and both Westminster-styled parliamentary democracies, but which have continued
to display consistently different rankings on the CPI? New Zealand has always ranked
significantly higher than Australia. In the 13 years from 2000 to 2012, New Zealands lowest
position on the CPI was third or joint third position, while from 2006 to 2012 it was either
first or joint first position. On the other hand, Australias lowest ranking was 13 th position in
2000, and its highest ranking was joint seventh position in 2012. New Zealands average CPI
score during this period was 9.42, while Australias was 8.65 a substantial difference in
21
perceived levels of corruption within these two countries with such similar backgrounds.
How can these differences best be explained?
Some factors immediately spring to mind, as possibilities: for example, early European
Australia was to a large extent a penal colony, whereas New Zealand was a British settler
society; and Australian political culture never embraced egalitarian ideals, as did New
Zealands. Australia, perhaps because of resentment of the English, developed its self-image
along individualist and competitive American lines. By contrast, New Zealanders generally
looked fondly on Britain as home and were one of the first countries to develop a welfare
state, with Australia lagging well behind for a long time, in that respect. Moreover, as a
federal system, Australia experienced political corruption reminiscent of American
Tammany Hall politics, especially in New South Wales and Victoria in the earlier half of
the 20th century (see Griffin, 2004). This form of politics was much less apparent in New
Zealand.
Such explanations are clearly contestable. For example, while it might seem plausible to
suggest that Australias 19th century history as a British penal colony gave rise to non-
compliance norms and values (presumably because a higher propensity for unlawful
behaviour has been somehow passed down through Australian generations), it would be
drawing a very long bow to conclude that this helps to explain why New Zealand has always
been markedly higher on the CPI than Australia. After all, the central figure in New
Zealands early colonisationthe Director of the New Zealand Company, Edward Gibbon
Wakefieldhad in 1827 himself been sentenced to three years in Londons Newgate prison
on abduction charges (Temple, 2002). It is more likely that the relatively small but
significant differences between New Zealand and Australia on the CPI result from the well
grounded perceptions among those whose views help to shape the scores that organised
crime has a much stronger presence in Australia than in New Zealand, and that police
corruption too is more widespread in some Australian states than it is in New Zealand,
notwithstanding the much publicised formal inquiries in Queensland and New South Wales
in the 1980s and 1990s. In fact, the very existence of dedicated anti-corruption agencies in
these two states, and now in Victoria, can reinforce the popular perception that if such
agencies exist then corruption must be a significant if not serious problem.
22
The final issueassessing any country against its own standards rather than in comparison
with other jurisdictionsis readily illustrated by the New Zealand case. An approach based
on an historical narrative is required if corruption levels are to be explained in any particular
country, regardless of how that country may rank on a league table such as the CPI. Most
New Zealanders are probably little interested in the fact that, according to the CPI, New
Zealand has far less corruption than does China, the Philippines, and South Africa, for
example, and significantly less than Australia. However, they are likely to be much more
interested in any evidence indicating that in their own country corruption in its various forms
is becoming more prevalent. In short, comparisons with other countries may be interesting,
especially to academics, but they will seldom ignite political controversy or public policy
challenges in the way that evidence of corruption at home can do.
Apart from this, there is also the possibility that New Zealands consistently high ranking on
the CPI and the WGI reinforces political and social complacency, as if such indicators
confirm that all is well. Such an effect will be greater to the extent that such indicators, and
the means of their construction, are accepted uncritically. In the case of the CPI, there is
likely to be a self-fulfilling effect at work: not only does the algorithm work against any rapid
shifts in a countrys ranking, but also the perceptions of those whose views and opinions
determine a countrys score are likely to be influenced by their knowledge of the countrys
previous ranking. Reputations, good and bad, are sometimes difficult to shakegiving a dog
a good name might, in such cases, have the same effect as giving a dog a bad one.
Supposing, however, that New Zealands performances, as gauged by both the WGI and the
CPI, dropped significantly during a relatively short space of time, leading to mounting public
demand that something be done about it. What body of knowledge, formally theoretical
and/or experientially practical, would inform any such action? In this high modernist era of
big data (Cukier and Mayer-Schoenberger, 2013), there is available a growing body of
information on corruption and its relationships to a range of variables, includingbut not
limited toGDP growth, income inequality, universally state-provided education, fair and
progressive taxation, the rule of law, and so on (see, in particular the research carried out by
the Quality of Government Institute, at the University of Gothenburg:
http://www.qog.pol.gu.se/).
23
However, Cukier and Mayer-Schoenberger (2013) argue that the advent of big data shifts
attention from trying to understand the deeper reasons behind how the world works to
simply learning about an association among phenomena and using that to get things done, a
supplanting of causations by correlations. They see real benefits in this, especially in areas
like medical research, even when the underlying causes remain obscure. Nevertheless, such
underlying causes in social behaviour are even more difficult to identify and understand, if
they can be identified and understood at all. To this end, insightful social inquiry and
criticism will probably be more productive than formal social scientific research. Any real
understanding of why one country ranks much higher than another on the WGI or on the CPI
must be substantiallymainly?dependent on knowledge of the history and culture of that
particular country, rather than on correlations in data across countries in general. Such
knowledge and insight is also essential, especially in public policymaking, to help ensure that
big data correlations are not interpreted as spurious correlations engendered by confounding
variables. For example, it has been an article of faith among monetarist economists that in
western countries high levels of central bank political independence are essential in keeping
down inflation (that is, in causing financial stability). However, it has also been argued that
the relationship between the two is spurious, since both conditions are the product of a third
variablethe political power of financial markets (Dillow, 2007; Posen, 1998). In this
connection, Stiglitz (2006: 279) sees a depoliticization of the decision-making process:
No economic issue affects people more than the macroeconomic performance of the
economy. Increasing the unemployment rate makes workers worse off, but the resulting
lower inflation makes bondholders happy. Balancing these interests is a quintessentially
political activity, but there has been an attempt by those in financial markets to
depoliticize the decision, to turn it over to technocrats, with a mandate to pursue the
policies that are in the interests of financial markets.7
(The reified concept of financial markets, as if they were some tangible apolitical entity,
was dramatically exposed by the global financial crisis of 2008-2009, yet the inordinate
political power of those who are the main players in international finance, the very wealthy,
seemed to be scarcely weakened as a result.)
24
answer to the first question requires more than a tautological referral to the six dimensions of
the WGI. It would also need to acknowledge that New Zealands journey along the pathway
of liberal-democratic development has not been as smooth as many might at first believe, and
remains very much a work in progress, in which little if anything should be taken for granted.
Beyond the betrayal by the Crown of the Treaty of Waitangi for so long, other institutional
and behavioural factors have studded this development with controversy.
Any historical analysis would need to reflect on changing standards of political acceptability
over time and not judge what can be seen as anti-democratic occurrences by the standards of
today. It would focus on constitutional legislation such as the New Zealand Constitution Act
1852, the Constitution Act 1986, the Bill of Rights Act 1986, and the Electoral Act 1993, and
alsoperhaps more importantlyon the evolution of constitutional conventions. It would
examine events such as: the abolition of the provinces in 1876; Masseys Cossacks of 1913;
the passage of the Public Service Act 1912; the political riots during the Great Depression;
the case of the deliberate radio jamming undertaken by the government in 1935 before the
election; the monopoly on radio news by the state broadcaster under the governments
direction; the abolition of the second chamber in 1950; industrial conflict of 1951 and the
state of emergency with its draconian regulations; the advent of the first independent public
broadcasting news services in 1962; the introduction of the Ombudsman in 1962; the
Fitzgerald v Muldoon case of 1976; the introduction of the Official Information Act 1982;
the 1984 post-election constitutional crisis; the Maori renaissance of the 1970s and the
advent of the Treaty settlements process, the 1987 judgement of Justice Sir Robin Cooke on
the Treaty and State owned enterprises; the history of local government reform; the politics of
the move to MMP in the early and mid-1990s, and the consequences; the passage of the
Protected Disclosures Act 2000; the changing character and status of the foundational
Westminster doctrine of ministerial responsibility, especially relationships between ministers
and public service chief executives; and the funding of political parties. There are, of course,
many other developments, events and episodes which could be included in any such analysis.
Then there is the counterpoint, lest it be assumed that New Zealands political development
has been on a track leading inexorably and progressively to some sort of social and political
utopia. Any such temptation should be tempered by an interrogation of the countrys suicide
and imprisonment rates, youth unemployment, child poverty, violence against children, the
gap in reading performance between New Zealand students from different socio-economic
25
backgrounds (the widest among all OECD countries), housing affordabilityespecially for
young people, and the fact that a political poll found that more than half of the respondents
thought New Zealand was a better place to live ten years ago than it is today (Fairfax Media-
IPSOS Political Poll, reported in The Dominion Post, 25 February 2013). And all this is to
say nothing of the leaky homes disaster of the past 20 years, nor the progressively declining
standards of occupational health and safety.
However, such data cannot substitute for the sort of insightful social commentary that is
embodied in classic studies like those of de Tocqueville on America (de Tocqueville, 1994),
or either Siegfried (2014) or Lipson (1948, 2011) on New Zealand. Nor could it sensibly
ignore historical narratives, such as those offered by Sinclair (2000) or King (2003), to name
but two. Historical narratives such these offer the insights needed to explain how a country or
a political system came to be as it is, and also to assist in establishing how different
traditions in politics and governmentor in governancecame to be established and
maintained over time, albeit subject to various influences, endogenous and exogenous, that
may have transformed or may transform those traditions (Painter and Peters, 2010). Indeed,
before its (still contested) transformation into a behavioural science, the study of politics was
8
They conceive of unitarism as a political system where the national government is sovereign
relative to its territorial units (if any), and as a continuum that varies along two dimensions(a) the
degree of independence between national and subnational units, and (b) if any separation at all, then
the relative power of the two, with more central power equating to more unitarism. Parliamentarism
refers to a system of government in which the governmental executive (the prime minister and
cabinet) is chosen by, and responsible to, the legislature, thus creating a single locus of sovereignty at
the national level.
26
itself almost totally an historical research enterprise, in which narrative was the dominant
methodology (Bevir, 2000, 2006). In Bevirs (2006: 16) words:
For their part, Bevir and Rhodes (2008, 2010) have sought to reinterpret, by means of
historical narrative, the idea of state governance as the differentiated polity, and to outline
what they believe promises to be a new and productive research agenda.
Turning attention to New Zealands long-standing reputation as a country with little
corruption, a historical analysis is necessary to help to understand why this has been so
(assuming, of course that the perception largely matches the reality). Arguably, a key factor
in this has been the strong egalitarian ethos that underwrote one of the worlds first welfare
states (King, 2003; Lipson, 2011; Sutch, 1969). As Boston (2013) shows, there are different
kinds of equality, including equality before the law, equality of opportunity, equality of
(certain specified) outcomes, and social equality. In his words, Achieving greater specific
egalitarianismis a noble objective and should be one of the foremost goals of any society
which treasures the pursuit of justice (Boston, 2013: 86. Emphasis in original). Throughout
most of its post-European history New Zealanders have generally valued all these forms of
egalitarianism, perhaps in different mixes in different periods. As Fischer (2012) has
demonstrated in his comprehensive historical comparison between New Zealand and the
United States, New Zealanders have traditionally been far more committed to fairness rather
than freedom, while in America the converse has generally been true. New Zealands
egalitarian ethos has been described as a society of fair shares (Roberts, 1978: 73).
However, over several years from the late 1980s New Zealand experienced the most dramatic
increase in income inequality among all OECD countries, which was sustained until the Gini
co-efficient levelled out in the 2000s (see Figure 1). This resulted largely from factors such
as the Labour governments programme of economic deregulation in the 1980s, poor
economic performance, and the reform of the welfare state carried out by the National
government of 1990-1993. Although income inequality in New Zealand has been depicted as
a national crisis (Rashbrooke, 2013), it is not clear that most New Zealanders share such a
27
view. Income inequality per se has not become a major election issue since the rise in the
Gini coefficient, and some periodic surveys of public opinion have produced mixed results
regarding New Zealanders attitudes to wealth distribution (see, for example, Massey
University, 2010; Carroll et al, 2011; Humpage, 2011). It cannot be argued with any certainty
that the rise in income inequality in New Zealand, or any accompanying decline in social
equality, will be associated with rising levels of corruption, in government and/or in society
at large. Nevertheless, it is at least plausible to argue, on the face of it, that this will occur,
especially in light of the fact that corruption levels tend to be higher in countries where
income inequality is higher rather than lower.
Figure 1: New Zealands Gini co-efficient, 1982 2011. Source: Perry (2012), derived from
Statistics New Zealand Household Economic Surveys (HES), 1982 2011.
On the other hand, relatively low levels of government corruption are also seen in some
jurisdictions, like Singapore and Hong Kong, which are by no means egalitarian. Conversely,
Denmark, Norway and Sweden, all at or near the top of the CPI, are countries with
historically strong egalitarian cultures, and all today have Gini co-efficient scores much
lower than New Zealands, as has Australia. All these countries (including Hong Kong and
Singapore) score well on the WGI, however, confirming that lower levels of corruption are a
function of factors other than just egalitarianism, which places a relatively low emphasis on
28
acquisitive and competitive values, especially those which define social status
overwhelmingly as a function of wealth. Included among other factors which probably help
to explain New Zealands historically low levels of corruption are the strong Calvinist
culture that the countrys British settlers brought with them, especially from Scotland 9;; and
a unified and merit-based, professional, civil service, with a strong ethos of ethical probity,
reinforced by effective controls, and with remuneration levels closely comparable to those in
the private sector.10
Other factors include high levels of social capital, and a long-standing reluctance to flaunt
wealth in the faces of those less well endowed; and peoples wariness of behaving in ways
that could result in a loss of individual or family reputation, were it publicly exposed. All in
all, New Zealand was a country of relative innocence, straight-laced, rather nave and
unsophisticated, and with virtually no organised crime built around prostitution, gambling, or
boot-legging. Even low-level tipping was generally not socially acceptable.
The New Zealand Police was itself almost entirely devoid of corruption. New Zealand was
also a full-fledged member of the Old Commonwealth along with Britain, Canada, and
Australia, countries not generally known for having significant levels of governmental
corruption. New Zealand was also the first country to adopt the Danish institution of the
Ombudsman, in 1962, as a further means of mediating executive authority (Hill, 1976;
Gilling, 1998). It also opened up official information to the public in the early 1980s, well
before the abolition of the Official Secrets Act in Britain (Gregory, 1984). As Lipson (1948:
9
Individual Scots, well educated and inheriting a Calvinist concern to improve society, made
important contributions to New Zealands public life. Besides individual achievements, the egalitarian
spirit of Scottish culture helped make New Zealand a nation of rough equality, compared with the
class system of England. The strong Scottish traditions of the Presbyterian Church in New Zealand
help explain the prominence of Scots in public life. It was a church in which liberals were divided
against fundamentalists, but the two groups shared a passionate concern, derived from their common
heritage, for justice in society (Te Ara, the Encyclopedia of New Zealand. Accessed 10 August 2013 -
http://www.teara.govt.nz/en/scots/page-10).
10
As Polaschek (1958: 283) wrote: There seems to be common in New Zealand a notion that the
responsibilities and moral obligations of public servants are somehow substantially greater than those of other
citizens. If his standard of conduct is more scrupulousand, in some respects it isthe reason is to be
found largely in the self-interest of the public servant. He is subject to more extensive controls than most
private citizens: he is more likely to be caught if he commits an indiscretion: his career may suffer even if there
is only suspicion of unsatisfactory conduct. Similarly, as Lipson (1948: 479) argued in his a seminal
commentary on New Zealands egalitarianism, there is a commendable absence of graft and a strict code of
honesty, attributable in his view to job security, strict accounting and audit requirements, and also to an inner
check reflecting public servants professional commitment to the ideal of the public interest.
29
481-82) argued, the state in New Zealand was not some external force in the continental
European traditionit was rather the people themselves in action, nation-building in
pragmatic rather than ideological ways. Public employment was not seen as having ones
snout in the public trough, and although New Zealand never developed an institutionalised
administrative elite like that in Britain, its public service ethos similarly embodied values
like honour, duty, decency and a strong sense of the public interest.
The strong normative ethos was greatly reinforced during the years of World War II by the
serendipitous convergence into top leadership positions in the New Zealand public service of
a group of several highly capable men. It has been suggested that the period 1940 to 1951
was the age of mandarins in New Zealand government (Martin, 2010). They were fully
committed to the tacit Schafferian Bargain which shaped the relationship between the
political executive and the top levels of the public service (Hood and Lodge, 2006).
Characterising one of these men, as if describing them all, Duff (1941: 95) observed that,
He is a public servant. With his energy, ability and bold imagination, he could have had a
half a dozen careers and made half a dozen reputations. But he entered the public service. He
remained in the public service. He is the public service.
However, the whole picture was far from being entirely rosy. Mori were victims of unjust
and greedy practices perpetrated by the Crown and its agents mainly in the 19 th century,
notwithstanding the fact that the early colonial administration in New Zealand had been at
pains to deal fairly and honestly with land acquisition and settlement issues. If corruption as
a governmental phenomenon has to be gauged largely by perceptions of its incidence, as with
the CPI, then it certainly matters as to who is doing the perceiving.
30
whose job it is to devise the means of combating such a decline, need to know what is
happening and why. Theoretical knowledge can assist greatly in this endeavour, but indexes
such as the WGI and the CPI (or most others of this kind, for that matter) do not provide
much of it, in any formal quasi-scientific sense. In practice, policymakers who have to act in
the short term rather than waiting till social science generates any such knowledge, if it ever
does, will have to draw from informal theoretical knowledge, derived from other sources, in
many forms. This will be the theoretical knowledge provided by, among other things,
historical insight, social commentary and criticism, social and political disputation, and
policymaking and administrative judgment, experience and wisdom.
In this regard, even before the global financial crisis of 2008-2009, fraud had become
glaringly apparent among New Zealand finance companies. A former chief executive of the
Serious Fraud Office (SFO), Adam Feeley, publicly admonished corporate directors for
doing too little about financial crime and corruption in their organisations, in the light of a
series of high profile convictions of finance company executives following a spate of
institutional collapses linked to the international financial crisis, and involving the loss to
31
investors of hundreds of millions of dollars. Feeley argued that New Zealand is today
socially, ethnically and financiallyin terms of rich and poor in our societya very
different country than we were a few years ago and, particularly since the global financial
crisis (quoted in Birchfield, 2012). The former director dismissed the value of the CPIs
rating of New Zealand: in his view, company directors and legislators were sweeping the
countrys growing crime and corruption problem under the board table.
Miles Lawwhere you stand depends on where you sitmay partly explain the level of
concern expressed by the former chief executive of the SFO, but the results of an SFO public
survey suggest that a majority of New Zealanders do not share the CPIs view of corruption
in their country: only 37 percent of respondents believed that the country was largely free
of serious fraud and corruption. Nevertheless, this may simply mean that people regard
financial fraud as being different from corruption per se. It may also reflect the fact that over
the past 20 years there has been a dramatic increase in the New Zealand news medias
coverage of corruption and allegations of corruption (see Figure 2).
This in turn is fully consistent with the huge increase in international academic and news
media attention, greatly aided and facilitated by the internet, that has been given to
corruption (including the establishment of the CPI itself) since the former president of the
32
World Bank, James Wolfensohn, identified it in 1996 as a cancer that had to be dealt with,
especially by international donor organisations.
It seems highly inconsistent that the marked increase in the attention given to corruption in
the New Zealand news media has not been reflected in growing perceptions of corruption
among those whose views are used to compile the CPI. Might this suggest that the opinions
of this select group are out of kilter with the views of a much wider segment of the
population? After all, a Price Waterhouse Cooper/Office of the Auditor-General (2011)
survey of fraud and corruption in New Zealand organisations of various sizes found that such
events in the previous two years, with a cost of more than NZ$100,000, were reported by up
to eight percent of respondents. Fraud and/or corruption events in the previous two years,
with a cost of between NZ$10,000 and NZ$100,000, were reported by up to 9.5 percent of
those surveyed. A KPMG survey in 2012 of fraud, bribery and corruption in Australia and
New Zealand, while not providing separate data on each country, found that almost three-
quarters of respondents reported that their organisation has experienced behaviors that are
defined as bribery or corruption (KPMG, 2013: 34). Moreover, while perpetrators of fraud
were more likely to be non-management employees, a real concern was that fraud
committed by senior executives and company directors had doubled since 2006 (KPMG,
2013: 9). The study also found that more than half of the respondents indicated that their
organisations did not perform active monitoring of bribery and corruption payments. A
Deloitte Bribery and Corruption Survey (2012) found that one in five of about 200 New
Zealand organisations had encountered corruption, mainly in the previous 12 months.
It is clear that while some activities, like bribery, are almost universally accepted as being
corrupt, there are many others that may or may not be seen to be corrupt. 11 But like social
problems in general, they are ultimately defined politically rather than scientifically. If the
old canard that sunlight is the best disinfectant is valid, then transparent political processes
and public debate are essential, not just to help combat corruption, butjust as
11
In New Zealands Crimes Act 1961 (sections 99-106), [bribery and] corruption is defined in what
might be called the hard core sensethat is, the offering or acceptance of bribes to public officials.
The Secret Commissions Act 1910 relates to other specifically dishonest activities involving
principal-agent relationships. (The penalties for conviction under the latter act are currently under
consideration by Parliament to bring them more into line with those applying to bribery under the
Crimes Act.)
33
importantlyto define what it actually is. Moreover, corruption will be understood in
various ways in different countries, and within different countries, over time.
Since the Enlightenment, knowledge has been viewed through the metaphor of light.
More knowledge has been taken to mean a stronger human ability to see and thus an
enhanced capability for action or, to be precise, for controlThat more knowledge
could cause problems, that light might prove another tyranny, that knowledge might
bring suffering, were not thoughts the philosophers of the Enlightenment were prepared
to entertain (Tsoukas, 1997: 839).
He identifies three paradoxes of the modern age: there is more information, but less
understanding; more information but less trust; and more social engineering and more
problems. Such contradictions suggest that a type of Greshams Law in economics (that is,
bad money drives out good money) applies to the extent that, in the comparative assessment
of good governance, quantitative data tends to drive out qualitative assessment, a process
hugely enhanced by the increasing sophistication and capacity of information technology.
Experimental knowledge derived from spurious calculation that is overly abstracted from
lived realities can tend to supplant insightful reflection on social and political experience. 12
A good example is provided by Gerring and Thacker (2004), discussed above. Their data
enables them to calculate precisely that a country which swaps its federal, presidential system
12
As Bevir (2006: 592) argues: If natural scientists and economists played the fullest role in directing the
expansion of state activity after the Second World War, other social scientists also contributed, and a positivist
concept of social science helped to legitimate their contributions at a time of optimism about technocratic
reform. With state funding for social science favouring scientism and policy relevance, social scientists who
defined themselves as delivering such goods were simply more likely to find stable employment. The positivist
concept of science also appealed to some social scientists as a way of taking control of the mass of data then
being generated. The new techniques and concerns of modernist empiricism had led, in this view, to hyper-
factualism; social scientists were being overwhelmed by quantitative and qualitative data in the absence of a
theoretical framework with which to make sense of it all
34
for a unitary, parliamentary one can reduce its level of perceived political corruption by
somewhere between 0.335 to 0.860, or by 0.586 on average (Gerring and Thacker, 2004:
326). Admittedly, they qualify their calculation with ceteris paribus, but of course when it
comes to such a radical transformation of a political system all other things are most unlikely
to be equal or to remain the same. While they themselves are not unmindful of this, the
prospect of serious obstacles to such a change does not deter them:
Again, New Zealand could find itself touted as a model for reform, just as it was during the
heyday of NPM in the late 1980s and early 90s. According to the WGI and CPI, respectively,
it is one of the best governed countries, with very little corruptionand it is a unitary and
parliamentary system, to boot. However, lest New Zealand should once again become the
destination for hordes of academics, politicians and governmental officials from other
countries, hell bent on discovering the Holy Grail of good governance, they might first
pause to ask what New Zealands scores on the WGI between 1995 and 2011see Figure
3actually mean, in their own terms, as distinct from comparing them with those of other
countries, in relative terms. (And for their part, New Zealanders might ponder this articles
epigraph, from Lipson.)
Are they not largely meaningless? Or worse, are they not misleading? The scores indicate
that things have not changed much over the best part of two decades, except
paradoxicallyfor Political Stability/No Violence, which seems to have suddenly spiked
around 2004, before dropping below normal levels around 2008-2009. How can one
sensibly explain these numerical changes? Does the drop around 2004 represent the
widespread protest movement against the proposed foreshore and seabed legislation? Was
this movement a manifestation of increased political instability and violence, or do both the
spike and the drop reflect the political predispositions of those whose opinions shaped the
35
scores? It would not be difficult to mount an argument to that effect, but no doubt other
arguments could readily be made in refutation.
Similar ambiguity surrounds the scores for the other five dimensions. What does the graph
tell us about the on-going effects of the welfare reforms of 1990-93, described as the most
radical social policy changes in 60 years (Boston, 1999: 4)? Probably nothing. In short,
anyone looking at this graph for valid information about changes over time within New
Zealand society and politics would probably be left imposing meaning on the graph, rather
than inferring meaning from it.
2.55
2.35
2.15
1.95
1.75
1.55
1.35
1.15
0.95
0.75
1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 2009 2010 2011
Control of corruption Rule of law
Regulatory Quality Government effectiveness
Political stability/no violence Voice and accountability
Figure 3: New Zealand on WGI, 1995 2011. From Zirker, Scrimgeour and Gregory (2013,
forthcoming).
This is not just a problem of social inquiry, whether formally scientific or socially critical,
per se, but is also, and paradoxically, an incipient threat to the democratic values which are
supposed to be central to at least a Western notion of good governance. It can be argued
that indexes such as the WGI and the CPI make it easier rather than harder for lay people to
consider good governance because they have available to them a neat figure and a set of
rankings that they can readily understand, useful reference points to guide their own
36
assessments. This may be so, but the question arises as to whether or not it is actually better
to have no such indexes if such numbers disguise a whole host of methodological problems
which by their nature tend to undermine the validity of the index itself; and secondly,
whether the existence of what can easily become a reified index actually tends to
disenfranchise lay people from what should be a much more inclusive debate. Most people
do not display the mentality of Charles Dickens typically Victorian schoolmaster in Hard
Times, Thomas Gradgrind: A man of realities. A man of facts and calculations (Dickens,
1961: 2).13
Today, in the era of what Pollitt (2008: 18) calls the politics of quantification, numbers
embody in themselves a claim to science and objectivity, purporting to place them above
political disputation. In this sense, the facts always speak for themselves, a position not
dissimilar to the argument invoked in New Zealand and elsewhere during the neo-liberal
heyday that, there is no alternative. Tsoukas (1997) argues, in ways that are also analogous
to the New Zealand experience of those times, that this claim to higher levels of scientific
sophistication tends to alienate lay audiences, who see instead the machinations of a
technological elite like the World Bank.
13
A man who proceeds upon the principle that two and two are four, and nothing over, and who is
not to be talked into allowing for anything overWith a rule and a pair of scales, and the
multiplication table always in his pocket, Sir, ready to weigh and measure any parcel of human nature,
and tell you exactly what it comes to. It is a mere question of figures, a case of simple arithmetic
(Dickens, 1961: 2).
37
What is more desirable in attempts to understand what constitutes good governance
largely spurious objectivity or inevitably manifest subjectivity? And is it better to try to be
roughly right than to strive to be precisely wrong? While formal social science, as
exemplified in the burgeoning of indicators such as the WGI and the CPI, can usefully
contribute to public debates on the extent to which any country displays good governance,
it should not be allowed to displace such debate. As Bevir (2006: 601) puts it, a challenge is
to effectively to engage social scientists, most of whom still favour typologies, correlations
and models, rather than skeptical narratives. Many social scientists are aware that their modes
of knowledge create distortions and simplifications. They just regard these problems as
necessary consequences of crafting generalizations that are capable of guiding action in the
world. Social science should be mediated by such open and usually informal inquiry and
commentary, as diagramatically represented in Figure 4, where the shaping of a better
informed understanding of what shapes and maintains good governance in general, and low
levels of corruption, in particular, emerges around the nexus point of an on-going, mutually
constitutive, relationship.
Social Social
Science Criticism
Rationality
The irony is that seeking after scientific measure of good governance (including levels of
corruption), tends in itself to diminish the democratic essence which is so often thought to be
central to good government. Democratic virtue is thereby thrice reduced, in the hubristic
pursuit of a scientific objectivity which by its flawed nature can only be spurious at best, and
politically self-serving at worst. Valid cross-national comparisons of factors in different
countries which can be argued to diminish or enhance the quality of both government and
governance are instead increasingly displaced by reified illusions.
38
Out of touch or in touch?
The American political commentator, Jonathan Alter, in his critique of the graduate
programmes run by Harvards Kennedy School of Government, argued in 1983 that, Some
day the public sector could be so professionalized that it will lose touch altogether with the
people it is supposed to representAny movement in that directionmust be viewed as
frighteningly anti-democratic (Alter, 1983: 38). Alter was especially critical of what he saw
as the excessive emphasis placed on quantitative techniques in the schools Master in Public
Policy programme, seeing professionalisation as the schooling of more and more top public
officials in predominantly technocratic approaches to government (and by later extension,
one presumes, governance). Alters critique was a forerunner to the later arguments made by
Tsoukas, and supported by Pollitt, as discussed above, regarding the development and use of
highly reductionist indexes in not only the study but also in the pursuit of good governance.
However, professionalisation could also mean that governmental officials, elected and
appointed, use more sophisticated tools to keep in touch with public attitudes and opinion,
including public surveys, notwithstanding the fact that (mere) public opinion is not the
same thing as (substantive) public judgment (Yankelovich, 1991). To this end, the surveys
of public attitudes now conducted by the State Services Commission (SSC) should be
considered an important tool. In 2007, the SSC instituted New Zealands first-ever all-of-
government longitudinal survey of New Zealanders experiences and perceptions of public
services (State Services Commission, 2008). In addition, the SSC has developed a Common
Measurements Tool to help agencies to measure and understand client satisfaction, in order
to make effective improvements in service delivery. Such tools are essential if the current
governments commitment to Better Public Services is to be adequately fulfilled. Despite
the general belief shared by many commentators that the New Zealand governmental system
is more efficient and more accountable than it was before the radical changes of the 1980s
and 90s, such a belief must remain a belief since no rigorous or quasi-scientific assessments
have been done; and would be extremely difficult if not impossible to carry out (Boston,
2000; Gregory, 2000).
In the inevitable absence of any formal evaluation using leading-edge techniques and
measurements, assessments of the quality of New Zealands public services must be largely
informal, contested, and based on conflicting perceptions and experiences. This, however,
39
does not render them invalid. On the contrary, in a society which espouses liberal-democratic
values, such general and contestable assessments are more worthy of respect than are league
table measures of good governance, which purport to be precise and objective but which
may not withstand closer scrutiny.
All social criticism is a kind of political commentary, explicitly or implicitly. And unlike the
endeavours of the social scientist per se, the social critics do not purport to be in any sense
objective, though they may often strive to be detached. This does not mean, however, that
social critics cannot contribute to a debate on what constitutes good governance. Those who
might believe that they cannot must by extension assume that good governance is a function
of some general law.
Returning briefly to the New Zealand experience, therefore, one social critic may be
impressed, for example, by the strong tradition of political stability, a professional public
service, little governmental corruption, the rule of law, strong judicial independence,
relatively high standards of living and of environmental protection, and generally harmonious
race relations. Another may be far less impressed, preferring to highlight low levels of public
trust in politicians, growing evidence of political sleaze (a term commonly applied to a
series of political scandals in Britain in the 1980s and 90s), a lack of political accountability,
poor public sector management and leadership, mounting allegations of corruption in the
police, an electoral system which faithfully translates popular votes into Parliamentary seats
but which leaves far too much power in the hands of the politicians in the post-election
process of government formation, an erosion of the public service ethos, declining social
egalitarianism, government failure to grapple effectively with a range of social problems
including child poverty and abusea fraught public health system, and emerging racial
tensions. There would be no shortage of evidence to support the perspectives offered by such
social critics.
The general principle guiding the scope of perspectives in any assessment of the quality of
governance in New Zealand, including the incidence of whatever is widely considered to be
corruption, should be: the broader and deeper the better.14 As far as corruption in particular is
14
Lindblom (1990: 233) in his extensive examination of the impairments that distort thinking and
perceptions in government, politics and policymaking, and extending his earlier work on partisan
mutual adjustment, advances the concept of multiplism. In his words: probing of social
problems requires the participation of vast numbers of people, most of whom bring significant though
40
concerned, systematic research is overdue into how corruption in its various forms is
assessed across the broad spectrum of New Zealand society. Any complacent parroting of the
countrys high position on the CPI, while it may assist in promoting the countrys mythical
clean and green image and Brand New Zealand internationally, will ultimately be self-
defeating. Swift and dramatic changes are occurring in the composition, class structure, and
ethnic mix of New Zealand society (Rashbrooke, 2013; Spoonley and Bedford, 2012). These
will demand that the foundations of good governanceincluding those which are required
to counter any growing risks of enhanced corruptionare continually appraised and
developed (see Transparency International New Zealand, National Integrity System Report,
forthcoming 2013). This requirement invites the development of an analytical framework
within which to conduct an investigation into what New Zealanders perceive corruption to be
in their own country.
Conclusion
Indexes and indicators such as those embodied in the WGI and the CPI have a valid role to
play in social science research into the means of promoting, establishing and sustaining
government or governance which is getting better, good or even outstanding, depending
on the criteria by which such categorisations are made. Those who generate these
measurements, as upholders of Tsoukas tyranny of light, are not about to turn their ivory
towers into tents and steal quietly into the dark night. However, in promoting the sharp
illumination that they believe measurement provides they should not at the same time be
allowed to extinguish the more diffuse, yet more authentic, glow of understanding that is
emitted by democratic discourse on what these criteria should be in the first place.
All public institutionsincluding the Institute of Governance and Policy Studiesand all
components of civil society have to be committed to fostering, developing and sustaining an
intelligent and balanced relationship between social science and social criticism. In the quest
for good governance the real challenge is to ensure that while we have ever burgeoning
stores of data and information, we also have more knowledge of what this data and
information actually means, andabove all elsemore wisdom in applying it.
greatly limited competence to their inquiries, and many of whom bring educated and experienced
competences to the task. Call such a state of affairs multiplism. Multiplism requires pervasive
sustained inquiry at many levels of competence broadly distributed in the society. Because formal
organisationsinterest groups and business enterprises, especiallytend to crowd individual
participants out of activism in the political system, multiplism not only becomes essential but in fact
needs a revival.
41
References
Alter, J. (1983) Harvard vs. Democracy, The Washington Monthly, March, pp. 32-38.
Anderson, J. (2009) A Review of Governance and Anti-Corruption Indicators in East Asia
and Pacific, draft working paper, June, Washington DC: World Bank.
Andersson, S. and Heywood, P. (2009) The Politics of Perception: Use and Abuse of
Transparency Internationals Approach to Measuring Corruption, Political Studies,
57(December): 746-767.
Andrews, M. (2008) The Good Governance Agenda: Beyond Indicators Without Theory,
Oxford Development Studies, 36(4): 379-407.
Arndt, C. and Oman, C. (2006) Uses and Abuses of Governance Indicators, Paris: OECD
Development Centre.
Arndt, C. and Oman, C. (2010) Measuring Governance, Policy Brief No. 39, Paris: OECD
Development Centre.
Baker, R., Christensen, J. and Shaxson, N. (2008) Catching Up With Corruption, The
American Interest, September/October. Online at: http://www.the-american-
interest.com/article.cfm?piece=466
Bell, S. and Hindmoor, A. (2009) Rethinking Governance: The Centrality of the State in
Modern Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bevir, M. (2006) Political Studies as Narrative and Science, 1880-2000, Political Studies,
54(3): 583-606.
Bevir, M. and Rhodes, R. (2008) The Differentiated Polity as Narrative, British Journal of
Politics & International Relations, 10(4): 729-734.
Bevir, M. and Rhodes, R. (2010) The State as Cultural Practice, New York: Oxford
University Press.
Birchfield, R. (2012) Cover Story: Boards Blas About Management, New Zealand
Management, September.
42
Boston, J. (1999) New Zealands Welfare State in Transition, in J. Boston, P. Dalziel and S.
St. John (eds) Redesigning the Welfare State in New Zealand: Problems, Policies, Prospects,
Auckland: Auckland University Press.
Boston, J. (2000) The Challenge of Evaluating Systemic Change: The Case of Public
Management Reform, International Public Management Journal, 3: 23-46.
Boston, J. (2013) What Kind of Equality Matters? in M. Rashbrooke (ed) Inequality: A New
Zealand Crisis, Wellington: Bridget Williams Books.
Bovaird, T. and Lffler, E. (2003) Evaluating the Quality of Public Governance: Indicators,
Models and Methodologies, International Review of Administrative Sciences, 69(3): 313
328.
Carroll, P., Casswell, S., Huakau, J., Howden-Chapman, P. and Perry, P. (2011) The
Widening Gap: Perceptions of Poverty and Income Inequalities for Health and Social
Outcomes, Social Policy Journal of New Zealand, 37.
Charron, N., Lapuente, V., and Rothstein, B. (2013) Quality of Government and Corruption
from a European Perspective: A Comparative Study of Good Government in EU Regions,
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Cukier, K. and Mayer-Schoenberger, V. (2013) The Rise of Big Data: How Its Changing the
Way We Think About the World, Foreign Affairs, May/June. Online at:
http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/139104/kenneth-neil-cukier-and-viktor-mayer-
schoenberger/the-rise-of-big-data
Deloitte Bribery and Corruption Survey (2012) Australia and New Zealand: Storm on the
Horizon? http://www.deloitte.com/view/en_NZ/nz/services/forensics/insurance-
claims/6c1fdcf2d93b9310VgnVCM1000001a56f00aRCRD.htm
Fischer, D. (2012) Fairness and Freedom: A History of Two Open Societies: New Zealand
and the United States, New York: Oxford University Press.
43
Flinders, M. and Buller, J. (2006) Depoliticization, Democracy and Arena Shifting, in T.
Christensen and P. Laegreid (eds) Autonomy and Regulation: Coping With Agencies in the
Modern State, London: Edward Elgar.
Friedrich, C. (1940) Public Policy and the Nature of Administrative Responsibility, Public
Policy, 1(3): 3-24.
Gerring, J. and Thacker, S. (2004) Political Institutions and Corruption: The Role of
Unitarism and Parliamentarism, British Journal of Political Science, 34(April): 295-330.
Gregory, R. (ed) (1984) The Official Information Act: A Beginning, Wellington: New
Zealand Institute of Public Administration.
Gregory, R. (2000) Getting Better But Feeling Worse? Public Sector Reform in New
Zealand, International Public Management Journal, 3: 107-123.
Gregory, R. (2006) Governmental Corruption and Social Change in New Zealand: Using
Scenarios, 1950-2020, Asian Journal of Political Science, 14(2): 117-139.
Gregory, R., Zirker, D. and Scrimgeour, F. (2012) A Kiwi Halo? Defining and Assessing
Corruption in a Non-Corrupt System, Asia Pacific Journal of Public Administration, 34(1):
1-29.
Grindle, M. (2004) Good Enough Governance: Poverty Reduction and Reform in Developing
Countries, Governance, 17(4): 525-548.
44
Hallerd, B., Rothstein, B., Daoud, A. and Nandy, S. (2013) Bad Governance and Poor
Children: A Comparative Analysis of Government Efficiency and Severe Child Deprivation
in 68 Low- and Middle-Income Countries, World Development, 48: 19-31.
Holmberg, S. and Rothstein, B. (2011) Correlates of Democracy, QoG Working Paper Series
2011: 10, The Quality of Government Institute, Gothenburg.
Hood, C. and Lodge, M. (2006) The Politics of Public Service Bargains: Reward,
Competency, Loyalty-and Blame, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ignite Consultants and Transparency International New Zealand (2011) New Zealand and the
Corruption Perceptions Index: How is New Zealands Rating Compiled and What Can and
Cannot be Inferred From It, Dunedin: University of Otago.
Kaufman, H. (1977) Red Tape: Its Origins, Uses and Abuses, Washington DC: Brookings
Institution.
Kaufmann, D., Kraay, A. and Mastruzzi, M. (2007) The Worldwide Governance Indicators
Project: Answering the Critics, World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 4149.
Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=965077
Kaufmann, D., Kraay, A. and Mastruzzi, M. (2008) Governance Matters VII: Aggregate and
Individual Governance Indicators 1996 2007, Washington DC: World Bank.
Kaufmann, D., Kraay, A. and Mastruzzi, M. (2010) The Worldwide Governance Indicators:
Methodology and Analytical Issues, World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 5430.
Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1682130
King, M (2003) The Penguin History of New Zealand, Auckland: Penguin Books.
KPMG (2013) A Survey of Fraud, Bribery and Corruption in Australia and New Zealand
2012. Retrieved from:
45
http://www.kpmg.com/au/en/issuesandinsights/articlespublications/fraud-survey/pages/fraud-
bribery-corruption-survey-2012.aspx?chan=story1
Langbein, L. and Knack, S. (2008) The Worldwide Governance Indicators and Tautology:
Causally Related Separable Concepts, Indicators of a Common Cause, or Both? Policy
Research Working Paper No. 4669, Washington DC: World Bank.
Lindblom, C. (1990) Inquiry and Change: The Troubled Attempt to Understand and Shape
Society, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Lindblom, C and Cohen, D. (1979) Usable Knowledge: Social Science and Social Problem
Solving, New Haven, Yale University Press.
Lynn, L. (2010) Has Governance Eclipsed Government? In R. Durant (ed) The Oxford
Handbook of American Bureaucracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lynn, L. (2011) The Persistence of Hierarchy, in M. Bevir (ed) The Sage Handbook of
Governance, Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Marsh, D (2008) What is at Stake? A Response to Bevir and Rhodes, British Journal of
Politics and International Relations, 10(4): 735-739.
Martin, J. (2010) The Age of the Mandarins? Government in New Zealand 1940-51, paper
presented to a conference, The Seven Dwarfs and the Age of the Mandarins: Australian
Government Administration 1940s to 60s, 3 November, Canberra: Australian National
University.
Massey University (2010) Social Inequality in New Zealand: International Social Survey
Programme, School of Communications, Journalism and Marketing.
Oman, C. and Arndt, C. (2010) Measuring Governance, Policy Brief No. 39, Paris: OECD.
46
Osborne, S. (ed) (2010) The New Public Governance? Emerging Perspectives on the Theory
and Practice of Public Governance, London: Routledge.
Painter, M. and Peters B. G. (eds) (2010) Tradition and Public Administration, Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Perry, B. (2012) Household Incomes in New Zealand: Trends in Indicators of Inequality and
Hardship 1982 2011, Wellington: Ministry of Social Development.
Pierre, J. and Peters, B. G. (2000) Governance, Politics and the State, New York: St.
Martins Press.
Pierre, J. and Peters, B. G (2005) Governing Complex Societies: Trajectories and Scenarios,
Basingstooke: Palgrave Macmillan.
47
Reder, M. (1975) Comment [on E C Banfields article], Journal of Law and Economics,
18(3): 607-609.
Rhodes, R. (1996) The New Governance: Governing Without Government, Political Studies,
44(4): 652-667.
Rhodes, R. (2007) Understanding Governance: Ten Years On, Organization Studies, 28(8):
1243-1264.
Roberts, J. (1978) Society and its Politics, in I. Wards (ed), Thirteen Facets: The Silver
Jubilee Essays Surveying the New Elizabethan Age, a Period of Unprecedented Change,
Wellington: Government Printer.
Schick, A. (1998) Why Most Developing Countries Should Not Try New Zealands
Reforms, World Bank Research Observer, 13(1): 123-131.
Sen, A. (2011) Quality of Life: India vs. China, New York Review of Books LVIII: 44-47.
Spoonley, P. and Bedford, R. (2012) Welcome to Our World? Immigration and the
Reshaping of New Zealand, Auckland: Dunmore Publishing.
State Services Commission (2008) Public Satisfaction with Service Quality 2007: The Kiwis
Count Survey, Wellington: State Services Commission.
Stiglitz, J (2006) Making Globalization Work: The Next Steps to Social Justice, New York:
Penguin.
Stivers, C. (2008) Governance in Dark Times: Practical Philosophy for Public Service,
Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.
48
Sundaram, J. and Chowdhury, A. (eds) (2012) Is Good Governance Good for Development?
The United Nations Series on Development, London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Sutch, W (1969) Poverty and Progress in New Zealand: A Reassessment, Wellington: Reed.
Tsoukas, H. (1997) The Tyranny of Light: The Temptations and the Paradoxes of the
Information Society, Futures, 29(9): 827-843.
Zirker, D., Scrimgeour, F. and Gregory, R. (2013, forthcoming) Iceland and New Zealand:
Comparative Perceptions of Corruption in a Global Economic Downturn, Public
Administration and Policy.
_________________________________________________________________
49