The Relation of Logic To Ontology in Hegel: Paul Redding
The Relation of Logic To Ontology in Hegel: Paul Redding
The Relation of Logic To Ontology in Hegel: Paul Redding
Even among those philosophers who hold particular aspects of Hegels philosophy in
high regard, there have been few since the nineteenth century who have found Hegels
metaphysics plausible, and just as few who are not skeptical about the coherency of the
logical project on which it is meant to be based. Indeed, against the type of work characteristic of the late nineteenth-century logical revolution that issued in modern analytic philosophy, it is often difficult to see exactly how Hegels logical writings can be
read as a contribution to logic at all. Furthermore, any tendency toward skepticism
here can only have been reinforced by the well-known views of Bertrand Russell about
the logical inadequacy of the Hegelian approach of his predecessors.
Russell had regarded his own embrace of the emerging modern logic around the turn
of the twentieth century as part of a reversal of his own youthful Hegelian views, and in
various places he provided synoptic accounts of how he had come to see that Hegelian
metaphysics was irretrievably damaged by its naive logical assumptions.1 As he tells it, it
was his work on Leibniz that had led him to the topic of relations, and there he had
discovered a thesisthe axiom of internal relationsat the heart not only of Leibnizs
metaphysics but also of the systems of Spinoza, Hegel and Bradley. This thesis held that
every relation is grounded in the natures of the related terms,2 and it was an ontological
thesis that was ultimately based in Leibnizs assumption that every proposition attributes a predicate to a subject and (what seemed to him almost the same thing) that every
fact consists of a substance having a property.3 Elsewhere he expanded:
Now the traditional logic holds that every proposition ascribes a predicate to a subject, and from this it easily follows that there can be only one subject, the Absolute,
1
2
3
145
for if there were two, the proposition that there were two would not ascribe a predicate to either. Thus Hegels doctrine, that philosophical propositions must be of the
form, the Absolute is such-and-such, depends upon the traditional belief in the
universality of the subject-predicate form. This belief, being traditional, scarcely
self-conscious, and not supposed to be important, operates underground, and is
assumed in arguments which, like the refutation of relations, appear at first such as
to establish its truth. This is the most important respect in which Hegel uncritically
assumes the traditional logic.4
On this reading, Hegels philosophical system was just a late remnant of premodern
thought, the elimination of which had been under way in the sciences since the sixteenth century.
Not all logically astute readers have been so dismissive. Graham Priest, for example, sees Hegel as an innovatory dialethic logician, who, above all philosophers,
understood the dialethic limits of thought,5 while Robert Brandom claims Hegel as
the initiator of his own inferentialist approach to semantics based on analytic
thinkers such as Wittgenstein and Wilfrid Sellars, who helped free modern philosophy from the myth of the given.6 And while, among logicians, Priest and Brandom are unusual in this regard, their unconventional assessments of Hegel find
lateral support from a number of more general recent reassessments of the idealist
traditionreassessments that suggest that it is perhaps time to reexamine the issue
of Hegels logic. Among analytic philosophers Kant has always been held in higher
regard than Hegel, and among the stream of positive readings of Kants work, a
number of studies have stressed Kants positive relevance for the development of
modern logic.7 Meanwhile, innovative recent interpretations of Hegel have stressed
the continuity of his thought with just those aspects of Kants taken as responsible
for its generally modern character.8
In the claim that Hegels metaphysical inadequacies are consequent upon problems
in the logic from which he starts, Russells view at least concurs on one issue with
Hegels sympathetic post-Kantian interpreters: it acknowledges the degree to which
Hegels metaphysics is meant to be somehow grounded in logic, and as such suggests a
distinctly Kantian dimension to Hegels approach. Kant, it might be said, had effectively
reversed the relation of logic to ontology found in Aristotles account of the categories.
While Aristotle attempts to explain the categories used in talking and thinking about
the world in terms of the basic structures of being, Kants Copernican strategy gives
explanatory priority to the structures of our judgments about the world, and then
derives the corresponding categorical structures from the way we talk and think
about it.9 But Kants reversal was carried out on the assumption that what was explained
in terms of the judgment-derived categories was a subject-relative appearance, behind
which stood the unknowable thing-in-itself.10 However, is not the idea of a conceivable
world-in-itself just as problematic from the Kantian orientation as the conception of it
as knowable? Such a combination seems to take away our capacity for an aperspectival
Gods-eye view with one hand only to give it back with the other. Much of Hegels work
can be read as an attempt to show how while we are each fundamentally limited and
conditioned in our cognitive capacities, we are nevertheless capable of somehow going
beyond those limits in virtue of a socially based capacity for conceptual reason, an idea
he thought was expressed in theological imagistic form in the Christian myth of an
incarnated God, who after his death continued to live in the spirit of a certain kind of
human community.
In the spirit of the post-Kantian interpretation, one can see Hegel as having
attempted to extend the scope of Kants reversal of explanatory direction to the metaphysical assumption that limited Kants own attempt to go beyond Aristotles category
theory. This gives to Hegels approach the seemingly paradoxical result that features
of Aristotles logic and ontology are reintroduced, it being a characteristic of Hegels
approach to negation (Aufhebung) that what is so negated is in some way retained
within the superseding account. For Hegel, then, the categories do not simply reveal
the form of thought that is able to be conceived apart from and opposed to the world;
they reveal the structure of the world itself, and so in this way the extension of Kants
critical approach is meant to restore substantive content to philosophy by undermining the residual dogmatically metaphysical assumptions responsible for Kants denial
of it. But of course the type of ontology restored could not be that original type susceptible to Kants critiqueit must be a new, post-critical form.
Such a post-Kantian reading at least has the advantage of fitting with Hegels claim
that logic is the basis of philosophy and the starting point of his system, but what of
Russells diagnosis of the fundamental inadequacy of Hegels logical starting point?
In this reversal of the direction of explanation, Kants position might be likened to that
expressed in Wittgensteins claim that grammar tells us what kind of an object anything is (1953,
373).
10
Or at least that was how Kant was understood by Hegel, as he has been by many others. Such
a two-worlds interpretation of Kant is, however, now commonly disputed. See, for example,
Allison 2004.
In the following section I sketch some of the progressive features of Kants approach
to logic against which any assessment of Hegels logical thought needs to be situated. While Hegels criticisms of Kant have often been taken as symptomatic of a
slide back into the type of pre-scientific and dogmatic metaphysics that Kant
attempted to overturn, I will suggest a different reading in which Hegel attempts to
make explicit Kants seemingly ambiguous attitude to the way thought achieves a
representational content.
11
15
Arguments are singular terms regarded as standing for individual objects within some domain,
and functions are incomplete expressions that take arguments and assign values as outputs for
those arguments. For example, in the case of arithmetic, the relation ... + ... will be considered
as a function that yields numerical outputs for numerical arguments: the output 7 for the arguments 5 and 2, for instance.
16
Furthermore, in association with modern set theory, this seemed to square logic with a modern
natural-scientific conception of the world.
17
Critique of Pure Reason, A51/B75.
18
Ibid., A68/B93.
19
Kant 1999.
20
Lenzen 1990.
21
Leibniz 1998b.
22
In fact, the relations between Aristotle, Leibniz, Kant, and Hegel here are more
complex than the story suggests when told in this way. Furthermore, the resources of
Aristotelian term logic, on which Hegel (and Kant) drew, cannot be simply equated
with the predicate-in-subject principle (the logical doctrine expressed in the metaphysically holist doctrine of internal relations), nor can Hegels rejection of the intuition-concept distinction, despite his idealism, be simply equated with a blanket
rejection of the idea that determinate thought involves a relation of concepts to something non-conceptual or worldly. As in other contexts, on issues of logic Hegel seems
to have had an acute, albeit general, idea of what distinguished modern reflective
thought from ancient thought, and he was far from being some simple nostalgic critic
of all things modern. What he was typically critical of was what he perceived as a
one-sided affirmation of modern as against ancient thought, and he sought to effect
some type of mediation between them.
25
This is one of the basic considerations behind his idea that space and time must be considered
transcendentally ideal, and hence his conception of his own position as transcendental idealism.
period, and hence prior to his making of the concept-intuition distinction, Kant
employed conceptual oppositions to make similar points concerning the determination of spatial representations. Specifically, in an essay from 1763, Attempt to Introduce
the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy,26 he employs a distinction between
what he calls real and logical negation to describe the structure of spatial relations
that he later deals with in terms of the idea of pure intuition.27
Logical negation, he says, is just that which holds between contradictory statements,
the simultaneous affirmation and denial of some property of a thing: one statement
thus affirms that A is F and the other says that it is not the case that A is F, or to put it
otherwise, it predicates of A the contradictory predicate not F. In contrast, real negation occurs where two predicates of a thing are opposed to each other [entgegengesetzt], but not through the law of contradiction.28 Such oppositions hold between
opposed and reciprocally cancelling determinations, Kants favored example being that
between mechanically opposed forces. As with this example, a number of others given
also involve opposed spatial directions,29 but Kant also identifies as real oppositions
those holding between credits and debits of money, and between amounts of pleasure
and displeasure, good and evil, love and hate, and desire and aversion.
In fact, Kants distinction between real and logical negations repeats a distinction
within Aristotles term logic. Unlike modern propositional logics, in which negation is
an operation applying externally to a proposition (p) to give its contradictory (~p),
traditional term logics have two forms of negation: one can negate either of the two
terms (subject or predicate terms) making up the sentence, or one can deny rather
than affirm the predicate of the subject of the sentence.30 Term negation produces the
contrary of the term negatedfor example, negating the predicate term beautiful
would produce a term having the meaning non-beautiful, effectively the term ugly.
26
31
See, for example, Kants distinction (in the discussion of the transcendental ideal) between the
merely logical principle of determinability and what he calls the principle of thoroughgoing determination [Grundsatze der durchgngigen Bestimmung], according to which, among all possible
predicates of things [Dinge], insofar as they are compared with their opposites [Gegenteilen], one
must apply to it (Critique of Pure Reason, A57172/B599600). See also the discussion of this in
Tiles 2004, 11114.
32
The concept as such Hegel describes in the Encyclopaedia Logic (161) as containing the moments of universality, particularity, and singularity, which in the Lectures on the Philosophy of
Religion (362) are identified with the kingdoms of the Father, Son, and Spirit, respectively. Even
in discussing these conceptual determinations logically, Hegels vocabulary is redolent with theological terminology. See, for example, his description of the universal as free power which
takes its other within its embrace, but without doing violence to it or as free love, and boundless
blessedness, for it bears itself towards its other as towards its own self (Science of Logic, 603).
For Aristotle, the singular and particular judgment forms are importantly different.
Thus, in his threefold distinction of judgment forms in chapter 7 of De Interpretatione, the first group is described as containing judgments about individuals (singular judgments) while the second and third groups contain judgments about
universals.33 Judgments of the second group, he says, are about universalssay, about
the species man, rather than about individual men such as Socratesand they
express truths about those universals by being made universally about its members.
In contrast, those of the third group, while also judgments about universals, are made
non-universallyas in man (as such) is mortal. While Aristotle does not explicitly
refer to particular judgments here, it has been convincingly shown that they, along
with judgments about universals made universally, properly belong to the second
group.34 Particular judgments, it would seem, rather than being judgment about individuals per se, are judgments about universals, but made in a non-universal way.
Particular judgments are made partially about a universal or species, by way of reference to some rather than all of its members (literally, individuals are referred to as
part of the universal).35
Strictly speaking, there is no role in syllogisms for the singular judgments of group
one: the syllogism provides no way of reasoning about individuals as such. Rather,
syllogistic reasoning maps relations among universals. The particular judgment
form can appear in syllogisms precisely because it is a form of judgment about universals. Traditional logicians had, of course, been aware of the problem posed by
singular judgments for syllogisms, and the standard solution had been to treat singular terms as universals on the grounds of certain common logical properties
shared between their respective (universal and singular) judgment forms.36 In recent
times, this move has effectively been revived by Quine.37 Leibniz too had followed
this practice, but he had also used the Aristotelian particular judgment form as way
of referring to individuals alongside the standard scholastic treatment of singular
33
Aristotle, On Interpretation.
Whitaker 1996, 8489.
35
Judgments partially made is Whitakers apt term (1996, 86). Preserving the etymological link
between particular and part, for Aristotle a particular affirmative judgment affirms the predicate of part only of that totality of members of the universal for which the predicate is affirmed
when it is affirmed universally, and so, like the concept part, it depends for its sense on the idea
of the judgments being made universally.
36
For example, both universally affirmative judgments and affirmative singular judgments can be
considered alike inasmuch as they are both exceptionless. Kant alludes to this treatment of singular judgments in the Critique of Pure Reason, A71/B96.
37
Quine (1960, 181) links his construing names as general terms with the attitude of logicians in
past centuries who commonly treated a name such as Socrates rather on a par logically with
mortal and man, and as differing from these latter just in being true of fewer objects, viz. one.
34
38
This is remarked upon by Sommers (1982, 15): Leibniz has an interesting variant of the traditional doctrine that singular terms are syntactically general. According to Leibniz, Socrates is
mortal is a particular proposition whose proper form is Some Socrates is mortal. But Some
Socrates is mortal entails Every Socrates is mortal so we are free to choose either way of representing the sentence. Leibniz thus views the singular proposition as equivalent to the particular
proposition that entails a universal one.
39
For Kant the subject term of a properly cognitive judgment contains a (necessarily general)
concept. (The only properly singular judgment in Kant is an aesthetic judgment, which is not
genuinely cognitive.) When one takes into account the role of intuitions, this gives to the judgment a different underlying logical structure. See the perspicuous discussion of this in Longuenesse 1999, 90, 90 n. 20.
40
Thus Kant describes a concept as resting on a function, by which is understood the unity of
the action of ordering different representations under a common one and as hence grounded
on the spontaneity of thinking (Critique of Pure Reason, A68/B93). Judgments are described as
functions of unity among our representations, since instead of an immediate representation a
higher one, which comprehends this and other representations under itself, is used for the cognition of the object, and many possible cognitions are thereby drawn together into one (ibid.,
A69/B94).
42
These various shapes of consciousness had been differentiated by their respective assumptions
regarding the fundamental characteristics of that independent in-itself.
43
Phenomenology of Spirit, 91.
44
Ibid., 114.
45
Ibid., 120.
46
Ibid., 115. The idea is that if, say, the world were monochromatically colored red, then from the
point of view of perception, it could not even be thought to be red. Being (determinately) red
requires the existence of other, non-red things.
structure of such perceivable objects, and is ultimately, with the transition to the
Understanding, replaced by something like nomologically interacting forcesthe distinction between Perception and the Understanding roughly enacting the distinction
between the everyday commonsensical and modern scientific views of the world.47
The logic of the purely conceptual relations existing among these thought determinations, but now abstracted from the concrete form in which they are presented to a
consciousness in the Phenomenology and thus free of any empirical determination, is
charted in Hegels Science of Logic. Of course, the lack of empirical determination does
not exclude such logic from having a content, and the apparent ontology in which the
Science of Logic appears to terminate in Book 3 represents Hegels equivalent to the
transcendental content of Kants logic. The first two books of this work can be considered as Hegels category theory, which, like Kants, is meant to be objective in the sense
that its thought determinations are considered to be equally determinations constituting the transcendental structure of the things that thought is about, but unlike
Kants in that no longer are they to be considered the mere appearances behind which
unknowable things-in-themselves stand.48 Moreover, while Kants synthesis of ancient
and modern positions in logic might be described as in some sense ad hoc and unconscious, Hegels is clearly very conscious. Here as elsewhere, Hegels position was that of
the self-conscious mediation of what he understood as the immediate characteristics
of ancient thought (in this case, the mediation of the term logic reflected in the opposed
categories of Book 1, the logic of being) with the mediation characteristic of modern
thought (here the modern propositionally based approaches to logic reflected in the
structures of Book 2, the logic of essence).
It must be remembered that Hegel refuses the modern reflective starting point in
which all things mindly (concepts, knowledge, etc.) and all things worldly (objects, facts,
etc.) are conceived as radically separate and yet determinate, and their relations then
inquired into. Nevertheless, the content generated from logic itself will need to be such
that we can understand how the world can be known, conceived, reflected upon, and so
forth from somewhere within it. It is not surprising, then, that Hegels logical categories
will fit a more or less organic worldview within which we might think of mind as somehow immanent. More particularly, however, Hegels way forward here will be essentially
to ground cognitive processes in something like the pragmatics of socially based and
rule-governed language games that is central to his notion of objective spirit.49 In this
47
regard, the role of what Hegel describes as the recognition holding between finite
embodied and socially located subjects is crucial for understanding his approach to the
human capacity for reflection and thought. There will thus be a sense in which a life of
the mind is immanent within or emergent from his somewhat organic conception of the
world. This has led some interpreters to think of Hegels starting point as a type of metaphysical philosophy of nature, and to consider his approach to thought itself, and hence
to logic, as somehow derived from this organic metaphysics.50 On the opposed postKantian approach, however, this is to reverse the relation between Hegels logic and his
metaphysics. Hegels task is to, in some sense, derive what is taken to be his organic
metaphysics from the immanent development of a content for logic. While it is clear that
the feature central to this logical derivation, Hegels notorious use of contradiction, is
clearly thought of as a type of organic feature of thought, for the post-Kantian reading
this must not rely on any independently conceived organicist metaphysics, but rather
must have a properly logical origin. Again, it would seem, his attempt to combine determinations of term and proposition logics and their differing accounts of negation is
crucial here.
50
Something like this position is represented in current debates by Frederick Beiser. See, for example, Beiser 2005.
51
For example, Hegel accounts for the lifeless, dull, and spiritless content of the modern
reflective version of logic, in that its determinations are accepted in their unmoved fixity and
are brought only into an external relation with each other. In judgments and syllogisms the
operations are in the main reduced to and founded on the quantitative aspect of the determinations; consequently everything rests on an external difference, on mere comparison and
becomes a completely analytical procedure and mechanical [begriffloses] calculation (Science of
Logic, 52).
52
Contradiction is the root of all movement and vitality it is only in so far as something has a
contradiction within it that it moves, has an urge and activity (ibid., 439).
53
Ibid.
While most defenders of Hegel claim that he does not deny the law of noncontradiction,54 for Priest it is his dialethist denial of this law that marks the advanced
nature of his logical thought.55 However, it is far from clear that Hegel means by contradiction what modern logicians typically mean (the conjunction of contradictory
propositions), as Hegel does not assume propositional logic as fundamental. Rather, he
attempts to integrate structures of term and propositional logics, each with their differing senses of negation.
Aristotle sometimes seems to invoke the modern idea of contradiction, but this is
misleading, as he did not have the modern notion of negation as an external operation
applied to a propositional content and so could not consider sentences of the type p
and ~p. Where he apparently refers to a contradictory pair of propositions,56 he typically means statements that result from simultaneously affirming a predicate of a subject and denying that predicate of that subject.57 As Laurence Horn points out, We
should be aware that any translation of the term logic operation of predicate denial
into the one-place truth-functional connective of propositional (or sentence) negation
cannot faithfully render Aristotles vision.58 Since, as I have argued, Hegels fundamental logical idea, the idea of determinate negation, is derived from Aristotles alternative
to modern propositional negation, it would seem unlikely that Hegel too could mean
by contradiction exactly what modern logicians typically mean by the term. But what
then does he mean by it?
Hegel expresses the law of contradiction in terms that seem primarily ontological
rather than logical, concerning as it does the contradictoriness of all things rather than of
judgments or propositions. However, as has been stressed, here we can read Hegels
ontology as expressing his logic: the things that are contradictory are things as articulated
within the evolving set of thought determinations traced throughout the Science of
Logic. We might understand this by considering the fate of an object that is first grasped
as a perceptual object and then thought and reasoned about. If what we have seen of the
term-logical determinations of perceptual objects and the more propositional determinations of objects reasoned about is correct, then there is a very real sense in which such
objects must change despite being the samemust be, in Hegels sense, contradictory.
54
According to Brandom, for example, rather than deny the law of not-contradiction, Hegel
places it at the very center of his thought (Brandom 2002, 179).
55
Of course paraconsistent logics do not accept p and ~p for all sentences p. Specifically, paraconsistent logics are posited as ways of dealing with such logical paradoxes of the form This
sentence is false (a version of the liar paradox).
56
As, for example, in Aristotle, On Interpretation, 17a30.
57
We mean by affirmation a statement affirming one thing of another; we mean by negation a
statement denying one thing of another (ibid., 17a27).
58
Horn 1989, 21. It is commonly argued that the Stoics invented propositional logic.
59
This is brought out most clearly in Hegels discussion of the evaluative judgment of the concept in Science of Logic. See note 64 below.
60
See, for example, Freges discussion of the question Is the Sun bigger than the Moon? in his
classic paper Negation (1997, 34748).
61
Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1011b2425.
62
This A is neither +A nor A, and is equally well +A as A (Science of Logic, 43839).
being judged true or false. It is this conception of the content of a judgment that is
the heir to Kants contextualization of judgments within the transcendental unity of
apperception.
Such a signless content of a belief fits with the content in relation to which the
rational asserter must come to stand under conditions of dialectical contestation.
Faced with a counterasserted denial, the asserter is thereby confronted with the
two opposed beliefs that stand as contradictories, p and ~p, and must deal with the
dilemma that both cannot be believed at the same time. The subject is forced into
reflection to judge which of the two propositions, p or ~p, is correct, and this
change of stance requires a complete modification of its conception of the nature of
that original object of knowledge. Originally it had been conceived as unproblematic and as immediately available to the subject: one simply had to observe how the
thing was in order to know its properties. It was simply F and not non-F. Now,
however, the object is grasped as that which is possibly F or possibly not F. If it is F,
it will have to be understood as that which was responsible for its appearing to the
other to be not F; if it is not F, it must be understood as that which was responsible
for its originally appearing to be F.63 The known object will develop through many
further categorial transformations beyond these, but at least this transition allows
us to understand the contradictory nature of such objects for Hegel. From the
modern model-theoretic perspective, for example, thinking of the object first in
terms of its particularity and then in terms of its singularity will appear to conflate
a class that has a single member with that member.
63
Clearly, the object is now being treated as the subject of a reflective judgment whose inner nonapparent properties are manifested in terms of the effects the thing has on other things, namely,
human perceivers.
That this criticism rests on a mistake, however, can be appreciated by again invoking
the singular-particular distinction. If we pose this question from the reflective point of
view that we moderns seem to adopt instinctively, then Hegel is surely in agreement
with the idea that in judgments, concepts are ultimately applied to something external
to thought, for here concept and thought are meant in the subjective sense. The
concepts applied to objects or the thoughts entertained about them are the concepts
and thoughts of particular, finite subjects, and the correctability of these testifies to the
independence of that which they are about.
In his account of the forms of judgment in Book III of The Science of Logic, the final,
most developed form of judgment is the explicitly evaluative judgment in which predicates such as good, bad, true, beautiful, correct, and so on are applied to objects.64
What distinguishes this form of judgment from the immediately preceding judgment is
the moment of singularity in the subject term. The preceding judgment form, the disjunctive judgment, specifies the array of mutually limiting particulars into which a kind
or species is differentiated: colour is either violet, indigo, blue, green, yellow, orange or
red.65 Such a necessary judgment is neither empirical nor analytic, but rather something like a Kantian synthetic a priori judgment.66 Hegel says of this judgment form that
its moments do not confront one another in determinate self-subsistence and that
although objective universality has completed itself in its particularization, the unity of
the judgment has not yet determined itself to the third moment, that of singularity
[Einzelheit].67 In contrast, in the assertoric judgment form, which is the immediate
form of the judgment of the concept, the content is posited as a determinate relation
between the moments of a subject as an immediate singularity [ein unmittelbar
Einzelnes] and a predicate.68
Hegel portrays the initial manifestations of these judgments of the concept as
subjective and problematic because each will be based only on some bare assurance
(Versicherung) that is able to be confronted with equal right by its opposite [die
entgegengesetzte]. When one is assured that this action is good, then the opposite
assurance, this action is bad, has equal justification [hat ... gleiche Berechtigung].69
Such judgments will be initially based on some contestable, immediately felt assurance
64
Science of Logic, 65758. Such judgments express that the thing is measured against its universal concept ... and is or is not, in agreement with it. Ibid.
65
Ibid., 656.
66
The disjunctive judgment is a subtype of the judgment of necessity, of which the initial, more
analytic form is the categorical judgment (The rose is a plant).
67
Science of Logic, 658.
68
Ibid., 659.
69
Ibid., 660. Miller has here contradictory for entgegengesetzte despite the fact that good [gut]
and bad [schlect] are a typical pair of polar contraries, not contradictories.
as to their rightness, and as such, they can be met by their contraries offered in
judgments by others who can have opposed assurances that they feel to be equally
justified. Here it is the singularity of the object judged in its abstraction from any
concept that is associated with the merely subjective element in the assertion,
some external third factor that makes the connection between the object and the
universal applied to it externally posited.70
The clear suggestion here is that the concrete thing in its singular determination has
an effect on the judgment, but it is not efficacious in the sense of playing the role of an
intuitive given that secures a truth about the object that is known with certainty. It
produces certainty merely in the sense of a subjective assurance that will bring the
judge into conflict with other similarly assured judges with different certainties. But
this is just the dialectical situation that, as we have seen, forces reflection and the search
for justifications that can initiate self-correction. Hence it is essential that a concept
applied by any particular finite judge is brought into contact with the world considered
as external to his or her concept. But in another sense, of course, the singular object
judged and the world to which it belongs are not beyond the sphere of conceptuality,
precisely because in predicating the concept of the concrete thing in its singularity, the
judge becomes aware of (posits) that thing in the determination of singularity, and
therefore as external. As Hegel puts it in the discussion of Sense-certainty in the Phenomenology of Spirit: An actual Sense-certainty is not merely this pure immediacy, but
an instance (or example [Beispiel]) of it.71 Anything present to us as bare this is nevertheless present as an instance of the determination of singularity, an exemplification
of thisness in general. But is there any reason to demand some further, stronger sense
of the externality of the world? A Hegelian answer here would be that anything stronger indicates the metaphysically skeptical picture of an unbridgeable gap between concept and a world-in-itself. But if we have formed the concept of a gap here, then it is
clearly not unbridgeable.
REFERENCES
Allison, Henry E. 2004. Kants Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense. Rev. ed.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Aristotle. 1938. On Interpretation. Trans. H. P. Cooke. In The Loeb Classical Library: Aristotle 1.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
. 1960. Metaphysics. Trans. Hugh Tredennick. In The Loeb Classical Library: Aristotle
XVIIXVIII. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
70
Ibid., 659.
71