Lecture Notes On Immanuel Kant
Lecture Notes On Immanuel Kant
Lecture Notes On Immanuel Kant
Preface
Immanuel Kants Critique of Pure Reason introduces his critical philosophy.
His philosophical approach is critical in the sense that he is making a critical
analysis of the power and limits of our mind and our ability to understand the
world we find ourselves in. As such, Kant is the founder of a philosophical
tradition of critical analysis that has included many other important
philosophers since, such as Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein.
I found Peter Rickmans lecture series, delivered in 1995 at the City University
in London UK, on the Critique of Pure Reason of immense value in trying to
understand Kants work. It is my view that Kants work is so subtle and
revolutionary that one needs the guidance of a good teacher to properly
appreciate it and to avoid the common misunderstandings. Since I had these
notes in electronic form, I thought they may be of benefit to others so I have
published them here. I thank Peter Rickman for his permission to make the
notes available and for his helpful comments and suggestions. I hope they
may help others who are trying to understand Kants great work and answer
some of the riddles of philosophy.
These are my notes of the lectures, so I should make it clear that any flaws
and errors in them are mine. If you spot any, I can be contacted at the email
address below.
Tony Bellotti, January 2006
[email protected]
Page 1 of 31
Contents
Preface
Lecture 1: INTRODUCTION
The Text
Historical Background
Key Concepts
Lecture 3: LOGIC
Logical methods
The Synthesis of Concepts
The Categories
Stages of Understanding
Method for Deducing the Categories
Transcendental Synthesis of Apperception
Introduction
The Refutation of Idealism
Lecture 9: NOUMENA
Bibliography
Page 2 of 31
Lecture 1: INTRODUCTION
The Text
In these lecture notes, we shall examine the ideas in Immanuel Kants
groundbreaking philosophical work, the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant
published this work as a first edition in 1781, but followed it up in 1787 with a
substantially revised second edition. Norman Kemp Smith's translation (1929)
is the recommended text for English readers. It contains the full text from
both editions and includes a standard indexing of the works using A and B
page numbers for the first and second edition respectively.
This course will deal mostly with that part of the work called the Transcendental
Analytic. This section is considered to be the most important part of the book.
However, it should be noted that it is far from the only important part.
There is some difficulty in translating from the original old eighteenth century
German that Kant used. Additionally, Kant's particular writing style can be
awkward and difficult to understand. He tends to be very exact and to
carefully qualify his statements. This can lead to problems when reading the
Critique.
Kant uses some words in a very specialized and technical sense. For
example, the words form, intuition and synthesis all have a special
meaning. The reader should bear this in mind when reading the Critique.
Kant worked on the contents of the Critique of Pure Reason over a period of
ten years, gathering dispersed notes and papers across that time. After these
ten years Kant seemed to be concerned that he was getting old and that he
may not complete his philosophical work before he died. Thus he spent just a
single year putting all his notes and thoughts together in the Critique of Pure
Reason. Some have considered the overall work to be a little divergent.
Also, the quality of Kant's writing seems to have suffered because he felt
rushed.
Even though Kant's writing style may be difficult, it is generally accepted that
the concepts and ideas behind his words are full of clarity. Goethe is quoted
as having said of Kant's work that reading it was like "walking into a lighted
Page 3 of 31
room". Many critics have found flaws with the Critique of Pure Reason, yet it
remains a watershed in the history of philosophy.
Historical Background
It should be remembered that the work of a philosopher is both personal and
a product of and response to the age within which he or she lives.
Kant was born in 1724 in East Prussia during a time of war, the son of a poor
saddler. His family were of protestant Scottish descent. Because of his low
background, Kant struggled his way into his position at the University of
Knigsberg. He first joined the university in 1740 as a student, from 1746 he
was a private tutor, became an assistant lecturer in 1755 and in 1770 a
professor. He died in 1804. He spent his whole life in Knigsberg.
He lived most of his life whilst
Frederick the Great reigned as
King of Prussia. Frederick the Great was considered an enlightened autocrat,
encouraging free-thought and philosophical speculation.
Kant was described by others as a happy and witty man throughout his life.
His lectures were entertaining and very popular. On the other hand, Kant was
a bachelor who lived a mechanical life and required punctuality in all his
engagements. He was also very health-conscious.
Kant wrote many essays on natural philosophy prior to the Critique, but it was
the Critique that made his reputation as a great philosopher. The first edition
of the Critique of
Pure Reason was published in 1781. After this date, Kant wrote several other
important books including the Critique of Practical Reason.
When Kant was writing the Critique of Pure Reason he was very much aware
of the works of philosophers before him. Much of the book is addressed to the
works of Hume, Berkeley and Locke, delivering a refutation of their empirical
philosophies. In particular, the second edition offers a refutation of idealism.
Kant's main goal in this work was to demonstrate that empiricism and
rationalism - i.e. the sense and the reason - both necessarily complement
each other.
Page 4 of 31
Key Concepts
1. The Aesthetics and Intuition
The first part of the Critique contains an analysis of the Aesthetics. This word,
as commonly used, has only an approximate meaning to that intended by
Kant. Although we usually use it to mean an appreciation of beauty and love
of the arts, Kant never intended this particular meaning. In the Critique of
Pure Reason, aesthetics simply refers to the study of the senses as directly
given through perception.
Kant divides the aesthetic into two parts: an intuitive aspect and a conceptual
aspect. That is, any sense perception is given as raw sense data, but
organised and understood through conceptualization.
The word intuition does not have the meaning we usually attach to it as
instinctive knowledge. In Kants technical sense, intuition means the
reception of raw sense data of an experience, prior to the application of any
concept. Intuition is the accepted English translation of the German
Anschauung which gives a much better sense of Kants usage as a view or
a looking at.
Intuition is intended to refer to that which is just given: the state of just
observing something, without any conceptualization of the data. There is no
other intended meaning behind the use of this word.
2. Kant's Copernican Revolution
One of the key consequences of
Kant's philosophy is his Copernican Revolution. This is mentioned in the
preface to the second edition (although nowhere else).
Copernicus was a sixteenth century astronomer who suggested replacing the
old Ptolemaic astronomic model, where the Sun and all the heavenly bodies
are viewed as orbiting about the Earth, with the new model where the planets,
including Earth, are viewed as orbiting the Sun. This new model turns out to
be the far simpler and more accurate model and eventually overturned the
Ptolemaic model in science. Although, in its day, it was a revolutionary theory
and Copernicus was much condemned by the Church in Rome.
Page 5 of 31
Kant's parallel theory was to view the human mind not as a passive vessel
that experiences events, but rather as active in cognition. So, instead of
viewing the mind as the passive centre of observation, Kant viewed the mind
as an active participator in observation. More radically, the consequence of
this theory was that the mind creates and shapes its experiences. The world
that we know is very much a product of the organizing effort of the mind. How
Kant arrived at these conclusions will be explored in this series of lectures.
3. The Nature of Knowledge
Another word which is given only an approximate English translation is
Understanding from the German Verstand. Kant intended this word to refer
simply to the use of reason and concepts in knowledge.
Kant's approach to the analysis of knowledge is based very much on common
sense. He did not believe there was any value in doubting our observations.
If we see a tree, then we see a tree. There is no doubting it. Thus Kant
believed that to postulate sceptical theories, such as there is really no
external world, was a bottomless pit that discredits philosophy.
Kant argued that we cannot seriously doubt our knowledge. The real task is
to explore what is involved in having knowledge. Kant looked to discover the
conditions that must be fulfilled for us to have knowledge. He saw this as an
analytic problem that could be solved by reason.
Kant asks if any of our knowledge has a privileged position. For example, our
notion of causality between events in the universe seems to be presupposed.
That is, it is a notion about the universe, yet it does not need to be shown to
be true by empirical evidence. According to Kant, it seems to be necessarily
true that every event must have a cause.
Kant categorized our knowledge as follows:
Page 6 of 31
A statement is true a
posteriori if its truth follows after experience. That is, its truth can only
be determined with reference to empirical evidence.
All analytic statements are a priori on the grounds that they are logical truths
that are true regardless of our experience. They do not require empirical
evidence to be proved.
All a posteriori statements are synthetic, as they provide added information
from experience, which was not there prior to the experience. So, for
example, if I observe a particular chair is red then this is synthetic as the
predicate 'is red' is not in the notion of the subject 'chair'.
The question remains, however, whether there are any synthetic statements
that are a priori. Kant argued that there are and gives the idea of causality as
an example of this.
4. Synthetic A Priori Statements
Kant argued that philosophy was at its most interesting when dealing with
synthetic a priori statements.
In fact, philosophy must be synthetic a priori.
This was counter to the views of many empiricists of the time. Hume denied
that synthetic a priori statements were possible. However, Kant challenged
this by arguing that ironically Hume's denial is itself synthetic a priori (this
argument anticipated the similar argument used against the logical positivist
Verification Principle later this century: how do you verify the Verification
Principle?).
Kant argued that the synthetic a priori was essential because it was a part of
our cognitive equipment. Synthetic a priori truths are those essential truths
that are necessary conditions for knowledge to be possible at all.
Page 7 of 31
This is where Kant's Copernican Revolution comes in. The mind is active in
knowledge, and the synthetic a priori is how we have that active role.
5. Phenomena and Noumena
The phenomenal world refers to the world as it appears to each of us from our
own personal perspective. For Kant, the real world is just this phenomenal
world that we perceive and conceptualize.
We can broaden our perspective to the general human point of view, and it is
from this position that we have an appreciation for the notion of objectivity.
The objective world is constructed from our human and cultural consensus
and shared knowledge. Yet ultimately, we cannot break out of our own
individual perspective. We always perceive our world from our own individual
point of view.
The phenomenal world is in contrast to what Kant calls the noumenal world
consisting of things-in-themselves that exist for themselves independently of
our perceiving them. The thing-in-itself is the thing beyond our experience,
yet it is what our phenomenal knowledge is about.
Kant argues that we can never know this noumenal world. It is forever out of
our reach because we cannot step out of our perspective on the world.
A consequence of Kant's theory of phenomena and noumena is that the world
we know and live in is the phenomenal world that our own minds organize
and synthesize from the multiplicity of data. If I see a tree, then that tree
exists because it can be seen (and touched, etc.). It is essentially
phenomenal, not noumenal. Kant supposes a thing-in-itself, beyond our
experience, which gives rise to the phenomenon of the tree, but we cannot
call this a tree-in-itself since the application of concepts such as tree is
limited to phenomena. Beyond our own experience, their application makes
no sense. There can be no tree-in-itself.
Thus the limits of the world are only as limited as my ability to actively
conceptualize and understand the world. This is reminiscent of the line "I
never had the blues until I knew the words".
We have only touched the surface of this topic. More will be said about the
noumenal world in later lectures.
Page 8 of 31
Only if A then B,
(2)
(3)
A.
Page 9 of 31
Page 10 of 31
Kant argues that space and time are empirically real, but by using our
method of transcendental examination - characterized by Kant's Copernican
Revolution - we also understand that space and time do not represent
properties of things-in-themselves. Rather, they are part of the way that we
perceive the world. This is an example of the distinction that Kant draws
between empirical objectivity and transcendental subjectivity. It also
demonstrates the unity of these two notions.
Space and time have transcendental subjectivity since they are forms
through which the mind understands the world.
Page 12 of 31
Lecture 3: LOGIC
Logical Methods
The understanding is our faculty to think about intuitions and so to form
concepts. Kant states that understanding is essential since knowledge must
always involve the two components: intuition and concept. "Thoughts without
content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind" (A51/B75).
Kant presents Logic as the science of the laws of understanding. He divides
it into three categories: General Logic, Particular Logic, and Transcendental
Logic.
general. This is not the proper study of philosophy. Kant means to analyse
only those concepts that are necessarily in the nature of reason and
knowledge. Thus philosophical analysis should only be about the pure
concepts of the understanding, free from the empirical conditions attached to
them.
In answer to the question "What is truth?", Kant asserts that some questions
are just absurd since any answer to them would be nonsensical. This is one
of them. It is part of the art of philosophy to distinguish the proper questions
from the meaningless questions. Kant gives a simple definition of truth as
the "accordance of the cognition with its object", and suggests that the
question "What is truth?" is absurd (if it is not simply that definition) because
its answer would require a universal criterion of truth that would contradict this
definition which tells us that the truth of a cognition can only be ascertained
with respect to its particular object, not by universal criteria. Note however
that Kant does state that such a universal criterion is possible for the case of
pure cognitions.
Page 15 of 31
Synopsis
2.
Imagination
3.
Recognition
these views. He says that the categories are a means by which we know
things about the world. He used the transcendental deduction to establish
them.
Kant was critical of the empiricists
Locke and Hume. He writes that Locke is "extravagant" in his attempt to
show that pure concepts (ie categories) could be derived empirically. He
writes of Hume that, though he realized correctly that they could not be
derived so, he remained "sceptical" since he was unable to see that pure
concepts could be deduced.
The transcendental deduction of categories is a subjective task, yet the
deduction provides for the categories an objective validity.
Transcendental Synthesis of Apperception
Kant uses the term apperception to denote experience coming together in the
transcendental unity of self-consciousness. He argues that this
transcendental unity of experience must hold, since without it we would not be
able to have any synthesis of intuitions. That is, for a manifold of separate
intuitions to come together to form a single concept, there must be a unified
cognitive self to perceive and bring together the disparate intuitions.
For example, when seeing an elephant, one may see four legs, a trunk, two
ears, a body, a tail, and so on; that is, a disparate set of components. To see
them all as a whole elephant requires that there be a single unified observer:
the transcendental self. If the self were not unified it would be several distinct
consciousnesses, each perceiving just one part of the presented phenomena
and the concept of the whole elephant would never arise.
Note that this argument for the transcendental unity is achieved through the
transcendental deduction. That is:
(1) Only if there is transcendental unity can synthesis of concepts be
achieved,
(2) I experience the synthesis of concepts (e.g. the concept of the elephant) in
the world, therefore,
(3) There is transcendental unity.
Page 17 of 31
Kant's notion of the transcendental unity is the same as the 'I' we refer to that
perceives and understands the world around it. Many have found this
transcendental 'I' difficult to comprehend because it does not seem to relate to
the bodily self that we are familiar with. It seems a ghostly, disembodied
representation of the self. Indeed Kant considered the transcendental 'I' to be
distinct from the bodily or the psychological person. We shall look at this
more closely in the next lecture.
Substance and causality are two of the twelve categories derived by Kant. In
these lectures we will focus on these two in particular, as these two concepts
were of importance to the rationalist philosophers. It will be useful to compare
Kant's approach to theirs.
Substance and causality are ways that we organize the data we receive
through intuitions. They are only necessary for understanding. We can
imagine the world of intuitions without them. However, Kant says that if we
did not have and use these categories the world would appear to us as a
rhapsody of experience, "something less than a dream".
Categories are rules which provide a relation between predicate and subject
in a statement. For example, in the statement "All bodies are divisible" it is
difficult to determine which is the predicate and which is the subject, for the
statement could equally be written as "There exists a divisible thing which is a
body, for all bodies." Which is the subject: "divisible thing" or "body"? By
merely using logic we cannot tell. Only by using the categories can we
decide, for the categories provide the proper relations between
representations. So, with this example, based on the category of substance,
we determine that "body" must be the subject, since it is substance, and
"divisible" is thus the predicate.
Page 18 of 31
Objects
Objects are conceived through the faculty of understanding using the
categories. It is by holding our experience in terms of objects that prevents
our knowledge being haphazard and arbitrary. We receive intuitions and we
synthesize these intuitions, through the categories, into concepts of objects.
The categories are necessary a priori rules that impose the way that the
intuitions must come together as objects in space. This act of synthesis is
spontaneous.
As intuitions are compelled to be viewed in particular relations as objects by
the categories, it follows that the categories are the intellectual form of all
such knowledge about objects.
Events can be conceived in a similar way, except in relation to time, rather
than space. We are compelled to conceptualize events in a certain way
because of the rules of the categories in our faculty of understanding.
Thus objects are just a question of experience. Their sensuality is presented
in the manifold of intuitions, yet their relational conception is given by the
understanding.
Page 20 of 31
Laws of nature about our world of objects and events are also formulated as
the aggregate of experience, and this aggregation is achieved in the
understanding. Thus, the laws of nature are not out there in the things-inthemselves, but only within the context of our understanding of the world.
The categories provide the possibility of synthesis of the laws of nature.
Thus, we derive the laws of nature from the manifold of intuitions in
understanding. Thus, if laws of nature have any objectivity then it is only by
consensus to agree to the truth of laws. Again, this is an example of
objectivity through intersubjectivity (being the interaction by communication of
disparate individuals).
This analysis of object shows that the unity of apperception arising from the
concept of objects is an objective unity.
Page 21 of 31
Page 22 of 31
Page 23 of 31
argues that the pure form of time is the schema that mediates the
subsumption of objects under concepts.
A consequence of this result is that it is only through time that we can
understand and perceive the world, and so all our experience must by
necessity be temporal.
This then is the first transcendental deduction, in two steps:
(1a)
Only if we have the form of time, can we subsume objects under
concepts;
(1b)
Only if we can subsume objects under concepts, can we
experience the world;
(2) We experience the world; therefore
(3) We must have the form of time.
Kant goes on to define the categories of substance and causality as further
schemas in relation to time as follows.
It is only with respect to permanence that change can occur, for we know that
changes must always occur in relation to a something which remains
permanent. For example, if someone, say Fred, has a haircut, it is usual to
say that Fred is something that is permanent, and the haircut is a change that
has occurred to him. It makes no sense to say that since the haircut he is a
different something from the Fred before the haircut. Nor does it make sense
to refer to the haircut in the abstract without relation to Fred. That is, the
haircut is essentially a process happening to Fred. Consequently substance,
as defined as permanence of object, is a necessary condition of the
experience of change.
Causality is this succession of changes in time. Without succession, it would
be impossible to perceive time, for time is simply the form by which
successive events are presented. This gives us the second transcendental
deduction:
Page 24 of 31
(1)
Only if we have the categories of substance (as permanence) and
causality (as succession of events), can we experience time;
(2)
We have the form of time (from the first deduction); therefore
(3)
The schemata of the pure concepts (i.e. categories) are the only grounds for
understanding. They are the necessary organising principles and it is only
through schemata that we represent experience with concepts, in general,
and not just as a collection of impressions.
Page 25 of 31
Page 26 of 31
Page 27 of 31
In other words you could not know the truth of, I seem to see a table in front
of me where previously there was no table and other similar propositions.
The I need not be self-conscious in the full sense that it involves
recognizing others, as Strawson suggests. Arguably it neednt even have a
body, although Kant never considers this possibility. It is not even necessary
for the I to trace a single path in space and time. All that is necessary is the
idea of limitation implied by a subjective view. The limitation implies a wider
world within which we are limited.
Whatever the form of limitation, there will be a story to tell about how things
seem to the subject at different times which coheres with an empirical theory
about the places actually visited by the subject at those times. That theory in
turn presupposes a theory about how things are both in the vicinity of the
subject and elsewhere: a theory of the world as objects distributed in space.
(I am grateful to Dr. Geoffrey Klempner for these additional notes).
The Refutation of Idealism is one of the more important passages in the
Critique. The proof is only half a page long (B275) but this brevity hides its
underlying difficulty. It would seem that Kant himself was not totally satisfied
with his account, since he added two pages of additional notes on the proof
along with a long footnote in the
Preface (Bxl) about the refutation.
Page 28 of 31
Lecture 9: NOUMENA
Noumena
Our knowledge is ultimately limited by our faculty of understanding through
the categories. This culmination of Kant's philosophy distinguished it from the
previous schools of empiricism and rationalism which conceived of no such
limits. This limited knowledge is the everyday knowledge of our phenomenal
world.
The phenomenal world is the limit of our knowledge. We cannot go beyond it
to have knowledge of that which gives rise to phenomena: that is, the thingsin-themselves. In the Critique of Pure Reason, there is an inconsistency in
the use of the term 'noumena', but usually the term 'thing-in-itself' is meant to
denote an object whilst 'noumena' is the thought of the thing-in-itself.
Thus the noumena stands as an intellectual marker of that which we cannot
know, but stands beyond phenomena.
Many thinkers were unhappy with Kant's notion of the unknowable things-inthemselves. If we do not know anything about them, how do we know they
are there at all? And, how do noumena relate to the phenomena? Since
causality is a category applicable only in the world of experience, it means
that causality cannot be proposed as the relation between the two. Unable to
find satisfactory answers to these questions, some followers of Kant revised
his notion of noumena.
The German idealist Hegel removed noumena altogether and took
phenomena as the only reality within an Absolute spirit.
Others have taken noumena to be the objects of modern physics. However,
this is not convincing, as ultimately evidence of the objects of physics, e.g.
atoms, can still be given phenomenally, and we conceive concepts within the
atomic realm. These properties were necessarily excluded from what Kant
termed noumena. Kant's notion of the noumena was a negative one:
noumena is the thinking about that ultimate reality that we can never know. It
is the thought of the limitation of understanding.
Page 29 of 31
Page 30 of 31
Bibliography
This is a brief list of books I have found useful in understanding the Critique
of Pure Reason.
Page 31 of 31