Moses Hess 1843 The Philosophy of The Act
Moses Hess 1843 The Philosophy of The Act
Moses Hess 1843 The Philosophy of The Act
into blackness and seeing only what is not real is seeing, that
is, the difference between the thinking and the thought about,
between the subject and the object, and is not seeing their
identity. The simple I, the thinking in distinction from the
thought-about, is empty, has no content; there are no rational
grounds for this saying of I; it is hollow, not at all a moi
raisonn, a something thought about, but only a something
believed. Only the I think amounts to anything, that is, the
likeness to itself of the one in the other. What the I"-sayer
believes, the I, the identity, here becomes the imminent
content of the act against which the mathematical point, the
black nothingness that calls itself Being, manifests itself in the
middle of the activity as the fixed and frozen act of selfconsciousness. The act thus becomes only half-realized, the
thinking becomes arrested in the process of differentiation from
the thought-about, which is really itself, so that the spirit runs
its head against the wall, against the barrier that it has created
and not broken through; it runs itself into a dead end. The act
becomes frozen. The bridge, the steep passageway from the
thinking to the thought-about, is broken away, the artery that
carries life itself is choked off. Living Becoming is turned into
dead Being, and self-consciousness into theological
consciousness, which now must lie its way out of black
nothingness into pallid Being.
The reign of shadows begins. All of the thought-about
remains a mere shadow, which shrivels up into a dark point
beyond the realm of the thinking. Now that the thinking and the
thought-about have been torn asunder, real life, the living I,
the self-conscious identity, makes its appearance outside of
both; it is the unperceived, though believed or guessed at. This
life that has been placed at a remove is an empty reflection of
the empty I, the shadow of a shadow, the theological God, the
Eternal Being, the Absolute Spirit, and so on.
The self-conscious I, from which all philosophy must
proceed, because the I think, which has been elevated above
all proof and is impossible to prove (in this case, even doubting
is an act of thinking), this moi raisonn of Descartes, is thus in
no way a proof of abstract Being, but only a proof of thinking, of
the act of the spirit. The I think has presented itself to us as
the act, which is comprised of three moments that together
constitute the I; but even this latter is not Being, and is
neither the thinking nor the thought-about, but is rather the
realization of an act: the movement of life imposing itself upon
itself as another, or distinguishing itself from itself, but in either
case perceiving its likeness to itself.
The I within is not something that stands still or is
quiescent, as the I"-sayer thinks it is, but is rather something
that is changing, is in constant motion, just as life, before it has
been awakened to self-consciousness, is likewise constantly
changing. Man is just like the worlds body, like everything
that we see growing and moving, and this is true not only of the
sensible part of his experience, but also of the spiritual part, his
self-consciousness, which is constantly changing, is engaged in
a constant activity of altering itself. The only thing that remains
constant is this activity itself, or life. This constant altering of
the I is necessary, because there is an I only so long as it
goes on becoming another, in other words, only so long as it
defines itself, limits itself, and perceives, in this act of the self
becoming another, or limiting itself, its likeness to itself or free
self-determination. Without this act there is no real I, no
identity, but rather either its act is unconscious (innocent,
natural life), or it has split itself in two, and is a broken thread
of life, a disrupted line, a black nothingness.
Reflection is like the Fates, cutting through the
continuous thread of life with the shears of the understanding,
disrupting all movement and choking off the breath. The I is
an act of the spirit, an idea, which can comprehend itself only in
change. The only thing that stands above change is the law that
is involved in movement itself. The spirit perceives this law
through the perception of its own life. In perceiving itself and its
own activity, it is perceiving all activity, all life, with the same
certainty. Life is activity. But activity is the recovery of an
identity through the establishment and transcendence of its
opposite, the producing of its likeness, its likeness to itself,
through the breaking of the barrier within which the I is notI. Activity is, in a word, self-creation, the law of which is
perceived by the spirit through its own act of self-creation.
Change, the differentiating of life, cannot be taken to be a
change of the law of activity, an objective differentiating of life,
but can be considered only a differentiating of selfconsciousness. Reflection, which remains entirely within the
head, turns things upside down and says: Objective life is
differentiated, but the I remains constant. It seizes upon what
is really the change of the I, of self-consciousness, and views it
as a change in the other, in the representation made by the I
(which is really itself). All its representations are looked upon as
objective life, which is seen, naturally, as differentiating itself, as
becoming something else at every moment, because the I itself
is becoming something else at every moment, because the selfconsciousness is a continuous chain of representations, because
the idea, the one act of the spirit, is not fixed, but is movement,
excitation, a constant rising and falling between the lowest form
of self-consciousness (not in the usual meaning of this word)
and its highest and most lucid form. The different states or
excitations of the self-consciousness, which manifest themselves
through time as different moments, stages, phases, and
episodes, and in space as different examples or settings, are
really the product of one and the same activity, which the selfconsciousness recognizes in the end as its own. But reflection,
the activity that can never arrive at likeness to itself, sees the
opposite of reality everywhere. Objective life therefore seems to
it to be differentiated, and the I (about which
it knows nothing, but only believes) seems to be the constant,
the immortal!
the slumber, rather than the truth, is the part that properly
belongs to religion and politics. If truth were to awaken from its
slumber, it would stop appearing in the form of the dualism of
religion and politics.
Religion
and
politics
are
passageways
from
unconsciousness to the self-consciousness of the spirit. The
religious dualism, the heavenly politics, is a product of
reflection, of dichotomy, of misfortune as is the political
dualism, the earthly religion. Although reflection has no idea
that it is the pons asinorum of the spirit, it nevertheless divines
this fact, and this divination manifests itself in the form of
reveries about a lost Golden Age, and later on in the form of
prophecies about a better era to come, in which all fighting,
antagonism and sin will come to an end. The Bible itself, this
venerable document of the origin of our religion and politics
that guides us with the most extreme navet into a theological
dead end, allows Adam to hear the voice of a higher essence
outside himself only after the fall. In its last section it
prophesies a time of realization, in which all creatures will come
together, no longer divided from one another and from their
God. Christ is simply an anticipation of this time of realization.
It is precisely for this reason that His role comes to an end at the
moment when prophecy is no longer valid, because it has been
fulfilled.
The state, like the Church, is the anticipation of the unity
of social life. It is precisely because religion and politics hint at a
future condition that they would never concede this condition to
be in the present, because they would then do away with
themselves. Yes, they must constantly postpone the presence of
this future, because their role consists in hinting at a condition
which, if realized, would bring this role to an end. In order that
their lies not be browbeaten or denied by the truth, they must
deny truth itself and turn it into falsehood. That is the greatest
advantage won by religion and politics, although this is not their
entire essence.
the peoples and individuals had not yet begun to strive for
morality or self-realization, they had to be satisfied with
allowing themselves to be treated like the good old cow; as long
as they did not know how to govern themselves, they were
governed by powers outside of themselves. That is clear. But it
is also clear that religion and politics are the products of a
situation appropriate only for cows, and that they themselves or
their representatives are only the other side of the materialism
that is dominating individuals and peoples. The priests and
rulers cannot use the excuse that the peoples had made them
necessary, any more than the individuals and peoples can
somehow excuse their condition of slavery by pointing to their
priests and rulers. Slavery and tyranny, abstract materialism
and spiritualism, make their peace with one another, and the
only deplorable people are those who do not perceive that there
is no way out of this closed circle of servitude except a radical
break with the past. This break the French and Germans have
now achieved, the former by calling forth anarchy in politics,
the latter by bringing about the same anarchy in religion. The
main task now is to find the common ground from which this
power of negation emerged on both sides. Without this common
ground, all efforts are merely fragmentary and run themselves
into their own opposition, as has actually been the case up until
now in Germany and France.
Slavery has its own enclosed system; it has set up a wellordered structure of lies that works as a block upon the still
unborn freedom, a theoretical and practical block that is
effective so long as freedom does not rise up and oppose it with
the consequences of truth. Freedom becomes the surrounded
phalanx of slavery, against which it will always be at a
disadvantage so long as it does not carry out its own principles
to their furthest consequences, as slavery had done with its
principles. As long as dualism has not been overcome
everywhere, in the spirit as in social life, freedom has not yet
been victorious. The dualistic world-view necessarily bad to
come forth in history. But lies are none the less lies because of
this. All of our history until now has been a necessary lie, so to
speak. The Christ, in order to become a reality, had to appear as
an individual among others, and thus above all in opposition to
himself. The spirit evolves in opposition to itself.
History, which is nothing but this evolution of the spirit,
could also not possibly have been anything in itself but the
appearance of this opposition, and it should therefore not be
surprising that, until now, only this opposition, the struggle of
the individual with himself and with the universal, has come to
the fore. The true individual the self-conscious spirit, the free
man, the true universal had not taken shape as yet. The
universal did not yet have any inner reality, since it is not real
outside the individual. The individual appeared, in opposition to
its essence, the universal, as the particular; the universal
appeared, in opposition to reality, as abstraction God,
Priesthood, Pope, Church, State, Monarch, etc. And so a
dichotomy came upon us, with the abstract universal on one
side, and the material individual in opposition to it on the other,
a dichotomy that is in itself nothing but an illusion created by
falsehood, since the universal has no life without reality, and the
particular has no spirit without truth. This dichotomy of the
spirit has manifested itself, as I have said, in all history up until
now. It achieved its highest peak in Christianity, the most fully
realized religion, and in monarchy, the highest form of
realization of the state. This is quite correct to say: Christianity
is the true religion, and monarchy is the summit of all the forms
of the state. In other words, the absolute religion and the
absolute state are themselves nothing but the absolutism of the
heavenly and earthly tyrants over slaves.
Domination and its opposite, subordination, are the
essence of religion and politics, and the degree of perfection
with which this essence manifests itself is the degree of
perfection of religion and politics. In absolute religion and
politics, the Lord is a lord of all. Universality manifests itself
here as the negation of all individuality. All separate existences
vanish before God and the monarch. God and the monarch are
not themselves real individuals; they are exalted above all
reality, are sacred persons, which is to say that they are not
persons at all. The monarch, like God, is unthinkable majesty.
Do not think about it, do not ask just fall upon your knees!
Abstraction can be pushed no further, and dualism, brought to
these heights, can no longer maintain itself. It capsizes, and
revolution and criticism begin.
The abstract universal must give way to the abstract
individual; this, however, is no longer the natural individual, as
was the case at the beginning of history, but the spiritual
subject. From now on, not individual free will, but subjective
freedom comes to the fore, not natural equality or the equal
rights of individuals struggling in immediate opposition with
one another, but the abstract rights of man or the equal right of
the abstract personality, the reflected I, the mathematical
point. The majesty and sovereignty of the one has transformed
itself into the majesty and sovereignty of everyone. Whereas
previously the abstract universal ruled in the form of the one
over the particular, and oppressed the individual, now the
abstract individual rules in the form of the many over the
universal, and oppresses the unity. In place of hierarchy and
class structure, in place of fettered individuals, representation
and the competition of individuals come forth.
Through the medium of this revolution an essentially new
history emerges. The individual again begins with himself,
history again begins at the Year One, and surges forward in fits
and starts, in pendulum-swings of the spirit, along the path that
leads from the anarchy of abstract freedom through slavery to
the final point, where the striving for real freedom begins, as the
law of negation begins to take shape along with the common
ground from which this power of negation arose, to manifest
itself on the one side as the subjective, and on the other as the
objective, act of the spirit.
the free act distinguish itself from unfree work; for, in the
condition of slavery, the very act of creation enchains what is
created, whereas, in the condition of freedom, every limitation
of which the spirit divests itself is not turned into determined
nature, but is overcome, and thus turned into selfdetermination.
It is now the task of the philosophy of the spirit to become
the philosophy of the act. Not only thought, but all human
activity, must be brought to the point at which all oppositions
fade away. The heavenly egoism, that is, the theological
consciousness, against which German philosophy is now so
zealously crusading, has thus far hindered us from stepping
forth into the act. In this respect, Fichte went much further than
our latest philosophy has gone. The young Hegelians,
paradoxical as it may sound, continue to be enmeshed in the
theological consciousness; for, although they have renounced
the Hegelian Absolute Spirit, which is a reproduction of the
Christian God, although they have given up the Hegelian
politics of Restoration and juste-milieu, and although they have
finally negated the religious dualism, they nevertheless continue
to set up the universal, or State, against the individual, and
they arrive at best at the anarchy of liberalism, that is to say, at
the condition of limitlessness, from which they nevertheless fall
back into the theological State, because they have never really
stepped forth into self-determination or self-limitation, but
rather have remained in the self-centeredness of reflection.
With them, social life has never overcome the attitude of
reflection, the stage of self-centeredness. In this stage, the
object of activity still appears to be really another, and the
subject, in order to strive for the gratification of its selfhood, of
its life, of its activity, must hold on to this object that has been
torn from it as its property, because it is otherwise threatened
with the loss of its selfhood. It is in the form of material
property that the notion of itself being active no, of itself
having been active for its own sake, first occurs to the
consciousness of the subject, which is still in the stage of
Germany between the radicals and the Pietists against the old
rationalism. But now as they organize themselves to pursue
practical goals, the irony fades into the background, and they
show a stern mask to the world. To any but the most superficial
observer, this alliance appears only all the more comical as a
result. But because of this ironical alliance, the people allow
themselves to be led out of the light, that is, back to religion,
which here in Germany serves, by tacit agreement, as a common
meeting-ground for both the radicals and the reactionaries. Just
as it is the State that is exploited here in Germany, in the
name of their opposing aims and by very different means, of
course, by the philosophers and the Pietists (the one group
using the material power of the State, the other employing the
abstract Idea), so it is the Church, religion, that is exploited in
France.
The free act of the spirit is the common ground from
which all the aspirations of the present time originate, and to
which they return. It is therefore necessary to inquire into the
very law of its structure and of its consequences. The basis of
the free act is the Ethics of Spinoza, and the forthcoming
philosophy of the act can be only a further development of this
work. Fichte laid the groundwork for this further development,
but German philosophy cannot break out of idealism on its own.
In order for Germany to be able to attain socialism, it must have
a Kant for the old social organism, just as it had for the old
structure of thought. Without revolution, no new history can
begin. As strong as was the approval of the French Revolution in
Germany, its essence, which consisted in nothing less than
tearing down the pillars upon which the old social life had
stood, was just as strongly misunderstood everywhere. The
value of negation was perceived in Germany in the realm of
thought, but not in the realm of action. The value of anarchy
consists in the fact that the individual must once again rely
upon himself, and proceed from himself.
spiritual and social revolution cleared away the rubble that was
weighing down the buds of the modern era. Suddenly there
appeared two little shoots, whose roots no one had perceived.
Atheism and communism were taught, to the horror of the
Philistines, by Fichte and Babeuf, in the two chief cities on
either side of the Rhine, Berlin and Paris, and young people
streamed to these places, seeking the inspiration of the new
teachings. Atheism and communism! Let us examine this
sapling.
The thing about it that most frightens people is its
apparent lack of roots in any solid earth. Anarchy, upon which
both atheism and communism are based, the negation of all
domination in both spiritual and social life, seems at first to be
the absolute annihilation of all definition, and thus of all reality.
But it is only the process of the act becoming fixed by something
outside itself, the domination of one thing over another, that
anarchy strips away. So far is self-determination from being
negated here, that it is rather the negation of it (brought about
by the process of determination from the outside) that is being
transcended. The anarchy created through the spirit is only a
negation of limitation, not of freedom. It is not the limits that
the spirit establishes for itself that anarchy clears away, for the
limits that the spirit establishes for itself form the content of its
free activity. Thus this establishing for itself, this determining of
self, this limiting of self, is not something that can be negated by
the free spirit; it can be negated only by the setting of limits
from the outside.
When I believe in a power that is above or outside of my
I, I am thus limited from without. When I think in opposition
to the object, and self-consciously create in accordance with the
law of my spirit, I limit myself, without my being limited from
without. In this way, I can determine myself in social life, and
can be active in this or that determined way, without
acknowledging a limit imposed from the outside on my activity
without having another to allow me my rights, or to limit me.
acting but not to create itself as material and fix itself in that
state in which the free act would become an objective fact that
limits it, in which the spiritual being-for-itself would become
material property that throws away its likeness to itself, its
morality, negates its freedom, freezes and confines the flow of
its life, its movement.
Material property is the being-for-itself of the spirit
transformed into a fixed idea. Because the spirit does not itself
spiritually conceive its work, its working-out or working-away,
as a free act, as its own life, but rather creates this work as a
material other, it must therefore fix this other to itself, so as not
to lose itself in infinity, so as to arrive at its being-for-itself. But
property comes to an end and turns into spirit, which is what it
should be (that is, into being-for-itself), when it realizes not the
forms of the act but the result, the creation itself, as the beingfor-itself of the spirit, when it realizes the phantom, the
representation of the spirit, to be its own idea in short, when
it realizes its otherness as its being-for-itself, and holds firmly
on to this. It is the very quest for being, that is, the quest to
endure as determined individuality, as a delimited I, as
unending essence, that leads to greed. It is, once again, the
negation of all determination, the abstract I and abstract
communism, the outcome of the empty thing-in-itself of
Kantian criticism and of the revolution, of the unsatisfied sense
of duty, that led to being and having. This is howauxiliary verbs
became transformed into substantives. This is how all verbs
become substantives, and how everything that belongs to the
changing periphery is made into the permanent core; yes, this is
how the world was stood upon its head!
Freedom is morality; it is above all the fulfillment of the
law of life, of spiritual activity, as much in the narrow sense, by
which the act is called idea, as in the broader sense, by which
the idea is called act, with clear consciousness of this law. Thus
it is fulfillment, not as natural necessity or as determination by
nature, as was the case for all living creatures until now, but as