The Scientific Nature of Post Processulism
The Scientific Nature of Post Processulism
The Scientific Nature of Post Processulism
Tlie coniptrtibilify of processunl trrzd postprvcesszrnl nrchrreology has been heavily debnrecl. This discrrssio~lis freqrreritly
debate" is based
phrased in terms of scientific vs. nonscienfific/lzunznrzi.c.tictrrchaeology. We suggest thrrr the "posr~~rocessurrl
or1 N mischrrrtrcterizntion of science rhnr ispervnsive in nrchneology, and is largely Lrnrzecessars, whet1 n more rensonnble view
of the rlrrrure of science is considered. To demonstrate this point, rve begin our discussion by identrhing sever01 conirnorzrrlitrpproaches to provide tr jburldnriorl for our disc~lssion.We then corzsider the rnlo clnssic crities within most post~~rocess~lnl
terin used to differentiate science nricl nonscience, Bncorzinn inductivism nnd fnlsificntion, rmd clenzonstrnte nlhy these views
lend ro nri incomplete and irznccurnte unclerstnnding of science. We next exnmirle seven nttribures thrrr ore conzrnorlly rrccepred
as chnrncteristics of science in order to provide n more accurnte view of tlze nnture rrncl ~vorkirlgsof science. Bnsed on tlzis
discus.rion, we argue thrrf nzuch posrprocessurrl research is in fact scientific, nrld we rtltirnc~telycor7cl~rdethnt post1~rocessunl
rrpproc~chestrs currently rrpplied can contribure to tr scientific understariclirzg of the nrchneologicnl record.
Lo conzpntibiliclrrd del procescmlismo y postproceslmlisnzo se hrr disc~lticloe.xtensivniiiente. Con fieczrericin este debnre s ~ r ~ ~ o r i e
unrr oposicidn ,fundnnzenml entre In nrqueologirr cieritijicrr y lrr nryueologi'rr hurnnnistictr. Sugerenios qrre el clebnte procesunlconl~irieri In rrrqueologi'cr, y qLre
postprocesunl se derivrr de un erzterldirizierzto fnlso del rrze'todo cient$co, desgrncindnnzente ri~~ry
es posible tomnr urin perspectivn nzds bnlrmceadrr. Pnrrr clesnrr.ollnr r~~restrsls
iderrs, comerz:rrrnos corl identijicnr rrspecros
conzunes de Itr rnrryorin de Ins posiciones teore'tictrs del postprocesunlis~izo.Corisiderrrmos 10s dos crirerios tipicnnzerzte usnrlos
p n m distiriguir lo cientl$co de lo no cientij?co, el rn:onnmierzto irzductivo de Bncon y In,frrls(ficrrcidn, y derizostrtrmos que estrrs
perspectivas rzos dnrz urz erztendinzienfo inconzpleto y disforsionndo de In ciencitr. Iderztjficarrzos siete czmlidndes de In ciericirr
i~~s
conzLmn?rzerztenceptrrdns porn mejor erifender cdmo fitrzciorzn el n~e'toclocientijico. En base N estrr discusidn, ~ r o p o n e ~qrie
pzrede contribuir nl erlterldirniento
muchos estudi0.r posrprocesutrles merecen llnmrrrse cienfrjScos, y que el post~~rocesntrlisnlo
cienrijico de 10s restos arqueoldgicos.
34
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
not reflect the variation among the individual postprocessual approaches and refer readers interested
in the nuances of these approaches to any of the
excellent overviews available (e.g., Hodder et al.
1995; Preucel 1995; Trigger 1989a; Wylie 1992a).
We do suggest, however, that few postprocessualists will find our discussion at odds with the general
principles underlying most postprocessual theories.
The second section discusses the nature and
demarcations (i.e., identifying characteristics) of
science, and illustrates why much of postprocessual archaeology is, in reality, scientific. The suggestion that much of the recent postprocessual
research is scientific is not unique to us. For example, Pruecel ( 199 1x287, 1995) suggests that there
are different types of science, which includes types
that are co~llpatible with postprocessual and
processual research. However, what has been missing from the discussion, and what this article is
intended to provide, is an explicit identification of
what it is about a portion of postprocessual research
that makes it scientific. We will accomplish this
task by identifying the requirements for a scholarly
pursuit to qualify as science, and then deinonstrating that much of the recent postprocessual research
meets these requirements.
Specifically, we will address the "classic"
denlascation criteria proposed by Heinpel (1965)
and Popper (1980) and will argue that neither of
their criteria are acceptable. Instead, we present
seven characteristics typifying science, and argue
that Inany postprocessual approaches process these
characteristics. Our ultinlate goal is not to change
postprocessual research. Instead, we wish to
denlollstrate that the conflict between the practitioners of the various perspectives is unnecessary,
and that postprocessual and processual approaches
are conlpatible and can contribute in conju~lction
with one another to a rigorous understanding of the
archaeological record.
While processual and postprocessual research
lnay entail different intellectual approaches to the
archaeological record, the diversity in approaches
can be beneficial, in so far that they each force the
other to examine their underlying assumptions.
Additionally, the diversity in research questions
and analytical approaches may produce a more
conlplete understanding of the past. However, these
potential benefits of diversity are only possible if
the underlying sinlilarities and differences are
35
Postprocessual Archaeology
Postprocessual archaeology is a manifestation of
the growing influence of postmodern thought in the
social sciences (Bintliff 199 1; Duke 1995:211 ;
Knapp 1996; Watson 1990:675). Postmodei~lisrn
shares inany elements with critical theory, feminist
theory, hermeneutics, neo-Marxism, Western
Marxism, and poststructuralis~n (Rosenau
1992: 13). As a general movement, postinodernis~n
is a reaction against modernism, i.e., the
Enlightenment. It is largely based on the beliefs
that science is not objective, not based on absolute
and true laws, and in practice has not improved
humanity (Bintliff 1991; Rosenau 1992). In fact,
some postrnodernists (and postprocessualists)
argue that adherence to rigid positivist science has
dehumanized disciplines such as archaeology by
removed the spiritual nature from the human experience by saying non-empirical entities don't exist
(Fields 1995; see Leone 1986:431-432; Shanks
1992; Shanks and Tilley 1987, 1992)'. Extreme
postrnodernisln questions episte~nological and
ontological assumptions, refutes methodology,
resists knowledge claims, obscures all versions of
truth, challenges beliefs about reality, and discards
policy recomlnendations based on any political,
religious, or social knowledge systems (Fields
1995; Rosenau 1992:3).
In co~llparisonto other social sciences such as
psychology and sociology, archaeology has been
slow to incorporate elements of postrnodernist
thought (Bintliff 1991:275; Rosenau 1992). In fact,
just as the postrnodein movernent was gaining
rnornentum in philosophy during the 1960s,
archaeologists were beginning to apply the frainework of logical positivism. It was alrnost two
decades before postmodernisin's influence was felt
in archaeology through the works of Ian Hodder in
the early 1980s (Bintliff 1991; Hodder 1982). This
brand of postmodern thought is commonly called
postprocessualism because it was viewed as a reaction to perceived weaknesses of the processual
school. Preucel(1995) has noted, though, that postprocessualis~nis no longer just a critique of the
36
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
Many scholars in the 1970s were growing increasingly pessimistic with processual archaeology as
presented by Binford (1968), Fritz and Plog (1970)
and Watson et al. (1971). Their criticisms were
threefold. First and foreinost, postprocessualists
(and many processualists) argued that there are no
(or at the least only a very limited number of) universal generalities, laws, or absolute truths of
human behavior to be found by archaeologists
(Hodder 1986, 1992; Leone 1986; Shanks and
Hodder 1995; Shanks and Tilley 1987; Trigger
1993; see also Clarke 1979; Flannery 1986;
Renfrew 1989). They further argued that archaeological knowledge is subjective, not objective
(Hodder 1986; Shanks and Hodder 1995; Shanks
and Tilley 1987, 1992). Postprocessualists discarded the natural science model of archaeology
underlying the positivist approach (Hodder 199 1a).
They also rejected generalizing theory and replaced
it with a paiticularist view of culture; by knowing
the specific history of the culture, the postprocessual archaeologists argued they could provide
understandings of certain aspects of society (e.g.,
syrnbolisrn and ideology) that could never be
obtained using a strict positivistic framework.
Thus, postprocessual archaeologists believed that
archaeology should be and is a humanistic field of
inquiry, rather than a natural science (Bawden
1996; Hodder et al. 1995; Shanks 1992; Shanks
and Tilley 1987, 1992; Vinsrygg 1988).
Another philosophical disagreement between
the postprocessual and processual approaches is
that the postprocessual archaeologists believe that
society is not composed of a set of patterns that
accurately and absolutely produce behavior.
Postprocessual archaeologists criticized the processualists for asking questions that only pertain to the
collective group (i.e., Why societies change?, How
did societies iinpact one another?, and so on)
(Cowgill 1993; Shanks 1992; Shanks and Tilley
1987; Wylie 1992a). The postprocessualists
37
Fundamental Concepts in
Postprocessual Approaches
38
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
39
40
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
41
42
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
43
observed, they are reflected in artifacts and features, according to the majority of postprocessual
archaeologists. Therefore, by their own argument,
it can be demonstrated that the subject matter of
most postprocessual archaeologists is as empirical
as much as the subject matter of physics.
Furthernlore, logically similar arguments are
advanced to justify the empiricalness of the subjects of other social sciences such as sociology,
psychology, and econonlics.
The second criterion is that scientific knowledge
is based on theoretical structures. It must be more
than isolated facts gathered by people who call
themselves scientists. Scientific knowledge is a
systematic body of knowledge based on a body of
theory organizing all of the facts and variables into
a coherent system. Non-empirical or abstract ideas
are not necessarily theoretical, and a theoretical
structure is much more than the agglomeration of
~niscellaneous hypotheses, propositions, or ideas
created using analogy or experience (Kuhn 1970;
Lakatos 1970; Lauden 1977). As Kuhn (1970)
observes, theoretical structures are coherent bodies
of thought that link important variables together in
specific ways such that their interaction can be
understood. Thus, the statement, "water freezes at 0
degrees Centigrade at sea level under normal
atlnospheric pressure," is not a theoretical statement, but an understanding of ~noleculartheory,
which explains why water freezes, is theoretical.
A related criterion is that a scientific theory
must, or at least ideally should, be non-contradictory. While the view of the world presented by a
scientific theory need not be Plre in an absolute
sense, it must at least be possible. Scientific theories are not always held to this ideal, but extreme
contradictions will make a theory nonscientific
according to most authors (e.g., Lauden 1977;
Popper 1980:39; Thagard 1978).
While Marxist archaeologists contend that they
do have a coherent theoretical structure (e.g., Saitta
1992), other postprocessual archaeologists might
argue that they do not have a coherent or systematic
body of theory, and therefore are not scientific.
According to such arguments, postprocessual
archaeological interpretations are based on whatever the particular aschaeologists wishes it to be.
Such a scattered theoretical structure would appear
to contradict the noncontradictory theory criterion
of science, as well as deny the presence of a theo-
44
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
45
46
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
47
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
48
Conclusion
A realistic view of the nature of science is necessuy
for any discipline that wishes to employ scientific
approaches. We suggest that science is more inclusive
than most archaeologists believe. Most discussions of
science in archaeology have been, and continue to be,
based on the "Legendary View of Science" (Kitcher
1992), a view that has been discredited. We have
attempted to provide a more complete discussion of
the nature of science, and have demonstrated why
much of the postprocessual research is scientific, in
spite of claims to the contruy.
Clearly, hyperrelativists and extreme positivistic
scientists do not share compatible worldviews.
Some scientists, particularly those influenced by
the writings of Hempel, will only accept the "legendary" view of science. They will never accede to
postprocessual study as science. For these individuals, postprocessual archaeology, psychology, history, economics, and even evolutionary biology are
inherently nonscientific, because their subject matter cannot be addressed using a nomological
approach. Likewise, hyperrelativists who argue that
there is not a "real" world beyond the mind will
never meet the accepted criteria of science.
References Cited
Arnold, B.
1990 The Past as Propaganda: Totalitarian Archaeology in
Nazi Germany. Antiquity 64:464-478.
Bapty, I.
1990 Nietzche, Denida, and Foucault: Re-excavating the
Duhern, P.
1962 The Air77 crr~rlSrrucrutie qf Physic01 Theory. Atheneum,
New York.
Duke, P.
1995 Working through Theoretical Tension in Contelnporary
Archaeology: A Practical Attempt from Southwestern
Colorado. J o ~ i n ~ aqfl Archrreologicrrl Merhorl ar~dTlzeoiy
2:201-229.
Dunnell, R. C.
1978 Style and Function: A Fundamental Dichotomy.
Anzerican Ar~tiq~iity
43: 192-202.
1980 Evolutiona~yTheory and Archaeology. In Arl~aiicesin
Archneologicnl Methodarid Theor?., vol. 3, edited by M. B.
Schiffer, pp. 35-99. Academic Press, New York.
1982 Science, Social Science and Common Sense: The
Agonizing Dilemma of Modem Archaeology. Jo~trrinlof
A17rhrol,ologicalResearch 38:l-25.
1989 Aspects of the Application of Evolutionaly Theory in
Archaeology. In Archaeologicnl Tl~ollghr irz Aii~ericn,
edited by C. C. Lamberg-Kwlovsky, pp. 3 5 4 9 . Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Earle, T.K.
1991 Toward a Behavioral Archaeology. In Process~rala i ~ d
Postprocess~~nl
Archoeologies: Multiple Ways qf Ktiowirzg
the Past, edited by R.W. Preucel, pp. 17- 29. Occasional
Paper No. 10. Center for Archaeological Investigations,
Southern Illinois University, Carbondale.
Earle, T., and R. Preucel
1987 Processual Archaeology and the Radical Critique.
C~trreiirAnthropology 28:501-527.
Engelstad, E.
1991 Images of Power and Contradiction: Feminist Theory
and Post-processual Archaeology. Ar~tiquir).65:502-5 14.
Feyerabend, P.
1975 Agczinst Method: O~itlirzeqf 017 Aiirrrchistic Tlieor:~of
Krzorvleclge. New Left Books, London.
Fields, D.M.
1995 Postmodernism. Prenzise 2(8):5-14.
Flannery, K.V.
1973 Archeology with a Capital S. I11 Resetrr.ch and Tlzeoiy
irz Cltrirrit Archtreolog?: edited by C.L. Redman, pp.
47-58. John Wiley and Sons, New York.
1986 Guild Naquiti: Archaic Foragirig a i d Early
Agric~ilt~ire
iri On.unca, ~Vex-ico.
Academic Press, Orlando.
Flax. J.
1990 Thirzkirig Frngmeizts: Psychoarzalysi.~,Feniiiii.srii, arzcl
Postnzotlersieisr?i in the Conter?zpornr:y West. University of
California Press, Berkeley.
Fotiadis, M.
1994 What is Archaeology's "Mitigated Objectivism"
Mitigated By? Com~nentson Wylie. Amer,icari Ailtiquit)!
59545-555.
Foucault, M.
1970 The Order of Things: Ari Aritliology of the H ~ i n ~ n n
Scierices. Vintage Books, New York.
Fried, M.
1967 E,:ol~ctioriof Politicnl Society. Random House. New
York.
Fritz, J.M. and F.T. Plog
1970 The Nature of Archaeological Explanation. An~ericnn
Aiztiq~riv35:405412.
Gero, J. M.
1983 Gender Bias in Archaeology: A Cross-Cultural
Perspective. In Alinlyzirig Gender, edited by J. M. Gero, D.
Lacy. and M. L. Blakey. pp. 51-57. University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.
1991 Gender Divisions of Labor in the Construction of
50
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
Knapp, A.B.
1996 Archaeology without Gravity: Postlnodernisln and the
Past. Journnl of Archoeologiral iMer11oil and Tlzeory
3:127-158.
Kohl. P.
1993 Limits to a Post Processual Archaeology. In
Arclzneologicnl Tlieory: bV11o Set.$ tlze Agerzdir? edited by
N . Yoffee and A. Sheratt. pp. 13-20.
Kosso, P.
1991 Method in Archaeology: Middle-Range Theory as
Hermeneutics. Aniericcrn Aiitiqlrity 56621-627.
Kroeber, A. L.
1952 Tlle Ntrflor of C~tltrlrc..University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Kuhn, T.
1970 The Structure of Scientitic Revolutions. University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
1957 Tile Coljerrlicnrl Reiwlrrtiorz: Plrrrleta~.~,
A.srrorionzy in
of M/('\tenl TIio~tgkt.Harvard University
tile De~~eloprnent
Press, Cambridge.
Laltatos, I.
1970 Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific
Research Programmes. In Criticisin nnil the Gron,tlz of
Knowledge, edited by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave.
Calnbridge University Press. Cambridge.
Lamberg-Karlovsky, C. C. (editor)
1989 Archneologicnl Tlzo~rghr irl Anler.rcn. Cambridge
University Press. Cambridge.
Lauden, L.
1977 Progress arid its Pr.oh1eril.s: TO1virri1,s a Tlieov of
Scient$c Gror~:th.University of California Press, Berkeley.
Leonard, R. D.. and G. T. Jones
1987 Elelnellts of an Inclusive Evolutiollary Model for
Archaeology. .lorti.nnl of Anrhropologicrrl Archaeology
54:491-503.
Leone, M. P.
1986 Symbolic. Structural, atid Critical Archaeology. In
Ainericirr~ Archtreolog~ Pir.ct irritl Future, edited by D.J.
Meltzer, D.D. Fowler, and J.A. Sabloff. pp. 415438.
Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, D.C.
1991 Material Theory and the Formation of Questions in
Archaeology. In Proce.s.sntr1 irriil Po.st~>roces,s~rnl
Arcl~ireoIogie.\:Mnltil~leIl/nj,s o f Knor\,ing the Pir.st, edlted
by R.W. Preucel. Occasional Papers No. 10:235-241.
Center for Archaeological Investipations. Southern Illinois
University, Carbondale.
Leone. M. P.. P. B. Potter Jr., and P. A. Shackel
1987 Toward a Critical Archaeology. Cni.i.erit Antlzropology
28:283-302.
Leone. M. P.. and R. W. Preucel
1992 Archaeology in a Democratic Society: A Critical
Theory Perspective. In Qrtnnrklrie.~rrrzil Qltest.~:Vision of
Archneology'.~Future. edited by LuAnn Wandsnider, pp.
115-135. Occasional Paper No. 20, Center for
Archaeolopical Investigations,
Southern Illinois
University, Carbontlale.
Little, B. J.
1994 Consider the Hermaphroditic Mind: Columents on
"The Intelplay of Evidential Constraints and Political
Interests: Recent Archaeological Research on Gender."
Ainer.icrrn Anrlquiry 59539-544,
Macquairrie. J.. and E. Robinson.
1962 Translation of Heidegger. M. Being niid Tirne.
Blackwell, Oxford.
Maschner, H. D. G. (editor)
1996 Drrrn,ir~itrirArc11rreologie.s.Plenum Press. New York.
Maxwell. G.
I964 The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities. In
Miiiriesota Stzirlies iii the Pliilosopliy of Scierlce, Vol. 111,
editetl by H. Feigl and G. Maxwell, pp. 3-14. University of
Minnesota Press. Minneapolis.
Mayr, E.
E~:olzttiori,
1982 Tlie Gro~.tliojRiologicri1 Tliozight: Dii3er:sif>:
cirirl Irilier.itrirtcc. Halvard University Press. Cambridge.
1997 Tliir is Riologv: Tlie Scierlce o f tlie Livirig World.
Harvartl University Press. Cambridge.
McGuire. R. H.. and R. Paynter (eds.)
1991 Tlir Ai.cIineology o f Ii~eq~inlity.Basil Blackwell.
Oxfortl.
Miller, D.. autl C. Tilley (eds.)
I984 Irlrolofiy. Poi~~ei:errid Prehi.stoi~. Canibridge
Univel-sity Press. Cambridge.
Morpan. C.
1973 Arcliaeology autl Explanation. World Arclltreology
4:259-276.
1974 Explanation and Scieutific Archaeology. World
Ai.c~l~rii,olog\6 :135-1 37.
Mueller-Vollmer, K.
1994 Tlir Ki~i~iiierieritic.~
Rrotler: Continuum, New York.
Nagel, E.
1979 T l ~ eSti.ricrrria of' Sciertce: Piubleni~irl tlie Logic o f
Scierltific Evplortntiorl. Hackett Publishing Company,
Intlianapolis.
O'Sliea. J.
I992 Review of Ian Hodtler's Tllr Donlesticotiorl of Errrol~e.
Aiiiericrirl Aiitl~ropologi,st94:752-753.
Patterson. T.C.
1989 History and Postprocessual Archaeology. Mnrl
24:555-566.
1990 Some Theoretical Tensions Within and Between the
Processual and Postprocessual Archaeologies. Joz~riiiil of
Aiitlii~o~~olo,qicril
Arclicirology 9: 189-200.
Pinsky. V.. and A. Wylie (editors)
1989 Ci.itic.rr1 Tinditioils it1 Corltrii~por~crr~
Arcllcieology:
Es.sci\~.s iii rllr Pliilo.vol~h!; History nrld Socio-Politics of
Ai.chneolo,yy. University of New Mexico Press,
Albuquerilue.
Popper. K. R.
1961 Tlii, Po~,i,rt~
of'Historici.siii. Routledge, New York.
r
Row, New
1962 Coi[jec,tirres cirid Refittririoits. H a ~ l ~ eand
York.
1980 Tllr Logic of Sci~~ittificDi.scoi,ei>,. Routledge. New
York.
Preucel. R.W.
1991a Comments to Richard Watson's W l ~ a tflie Neu'
Ai.choc,olog) Hris Accoii?~~li.shi~tl.
Cztr.rriit Aiitliro~iology
32287-288.
199 1 b Tlie Philosophy of Arcliaeology. In Plocessztal erild
W(i!;.sof Krion,iilg
Postl~,nces.szinlArclineologies: ~Mctlri/~le
tlir Ptist, edited by R.W. Preucel. Occasional Papers No.
10: 17-29. Center for Archaeological Investigations,
Southern Illinois University, Carbondale.
1995 Tlie Postprocessual Condition. Jotri.rznl of
Airl~cirologiccilReseciir.11 3: 147-175.
Preucel. R. W. (etlitor)
1991 Pi.oce.\.szteil orid Po.stpivci~.ssireil Archoeologies:
~Moiii/~le
Wiys of Kiion,iiig tlie Post. Occasiolial Paper No.
10. Center for Arcliaeolopical Investigations, Southern
Illinois University, Carbondale.
Preucel, R. W., and I. Hodder (editors)
I996 Coriteriiporciry Ar~hcreo/ogy iri Tlieor:\': A Reorlei..
Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
51
Quine. W.V.O.
1961 Froiii ci Logical Poiiit of Viett,. Ha~perand Row, New
York.
Redman, C. L.
1991 Distinguished Lecture in Archaeology: In Defense of
Ari~ericcrrtAiithropologi.st 93:295-307.
Renfrew, C.
1989 Co~nmentson Archaeology into the 1990s. iVor.r~,egiciii
Arclzaeological Revieu, 22: 33-41.
1973 Tl7e Erl~lri~iatiorlof Crtlr~ir~tilChtrrige: jMotlels iri
Pi.eiiisror:v. Duckworth, London.
Rosenau, P M.
1992 Posti~~odei~i~i~sn~
arld tlie Socicil Scieilces: Iiisights.
Irirocitls, crrzd Iritrzi.siori.s. Princeton University Press.
Princeton.
Sackett. J. R.
1982 Approaches to Style in Lithic Archaeology. J O L ( ~ IofI N /
Archtreology 1 :59-1 12.
Aiitl~ro~~ological
1985 Style and Ethnicity in the Kalahari: A Reply to
Weissner. Aiilericnrl Aiitiqciity 50: 154-159.
Saitta, D.J.
1992 Radical Archaeology and Middle-Range Theory
Methodology. Ailtiqili~66:886-897.
Salmon, M. H.
1982a Phiio.rol~hyiiizrl A~licieology.Academic Press, New
York.
1982b Models of Explanation: Two Views. In Tiieories crrld
Esplerniitiorl iri Archcieology: Tlle Sozttliciriy~tori
Cor!ference, edited by C. Renfrew. pp. 3 5 4 4 . Academic
Press, New York.
Salmon, W.
1984 Scierztific E.xplciriritior~cirltl rile Ctiziscil Strrtctcrru of tile
1Vorld. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Schiffer, M.B.
1988 The Structure of Archaeological Theory. AI~IR).~(.NII
Arltiquih 53:461-485.
1991 Tile PortcrBle Rerdio iri Arilei~icrirlLqe. University of
Arizona Press, Tucson.
1995 Bel~ervioralArcliiieology, First Pririciples. University
of Utah Press, Salt Lake City.
1996 Some Relationships between Behavioral and
Evolutiollary Archaeologies. Ainer,iciiil Ailtiq~tih
61:643-662.
Shanks, M.
1992 Es~ierieiiciizg Tlir Pti.st: 011 tlie Clierrcicter of
Archaeology Routledge, New York.
Shanks, M. and I. Hodder
1995 Processual. Postprocessual and
Interpretive
New York.
Stanford.
52
AMERICAN ANTIQUITY
Notes
I The antagonism between the adherents of the two perspectives is generally more subtle, but the hostility is particularly
noticeable in statements such as "well, fellow archaeologists.
if you do feel tempted to respond to the frantic signals of
[postniodernism's] local practioners, the Postprocessualists-be advised that. in the words of that poignant poem
'
'
53