F. Neumann Behemoth
F. Neumann Behemoth
F. Neumann Behemoth
Duncan Kelly2
Abstract: Because of its characterization of National Socialism as a form of totalitarian monopoly capitalism, many critics of Franz Neumanns pioneering book of
1942, Behemoth, have rejected what they see as a crude Marxist analysis of the subject.
This not only does little justice to the richness of Neumanns book, it also distorts its
central focus. By contrast, this paper suggests that a proper appreciation of the impact
of Max Weber in general, and Carl Schmitt in particular, on the development of
Neumanns thought permits a more detailed assessment of both the merits and the
shortcomings of his most famous analysis.
Franz Neumann is best known as the author of what remains a standard work
on the subject of National Socialism.4 His Behemoth, first published in 1942,
is acknowledged today by one of the foremost experts on the subject as a
masterly attempt to analyse the National Socialist state.5 Indeed, recent
works that have attempted to fuse state theory with a historical understanding
of the period typically begin with Neumanns analysis.6 It has, however, been
a long time since Franz Neumann was discussed in any detail in a major
English-language journal concerned with the history of political thought.
Because of Neumanns association with the SPD, the Institut fr
Sozialforschung, and because of his characterization of National Socialism as
My thanks to Andrew Gamble, Mike Kenny and Keith Tribe for their comments on
earlier versions of this paper, and to Iain Hampsher-Monk, Gail Prosser and an anonymous reviewer of the journal for further help. I would also like to acknowledge the assistance of The British Academy.
2 Department of Politics, University of Sheffield, Northumberland Road, Sheffield,
S10 2TU. Email: [email protected]
3 Franz Neumann, Letter to Carl Schmitt, 7 September 1932, Reform und Resignation: Gesprche ber Franz Neumann, ed. Rainer Erd (Frankfurt am Main, 1985),
pp. 79 f.
4 Franz L. Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National Socialism,
19331944 (New York and Evanston (1942), 1966).
5 Ian Kershaw, The Nazi Dictatorship (London, 1993), p. 20.
6 Jane Caplan, National Socialism and the Theory of the State, in Re-evaluating the
Third Reich, ed. T. Childers and J. Caplan (New York, 1993), pp. 101 f; Jane Caplan,
Government Without Administration (Oxford, 1990), pp. 3218.
1
459
460
D. KELLY
Leipzig and Rostock during the winter and summer semesters. It was, however, his move in 1919 to the new University of Frankfurt am Main, where he
would take his first legal exams in 1921, that provided the catalyst for his
move towards the SPD and highlighted his capacity for practical action.13
Here, for example, he established the first socialist student group with Leo
Lwenthal and Ernst Fraenkel. Although Neumann fought on the side of the
soldiers and workers councils of 1918 and 1919, his revolutionary political
impetus ended there. From this point onwards, as Intelmann observes, he had
made the decisive move towards the SPD as the body best placed to instigate
meaningful political change a partnership that continued formally until
1933, and then in exile.14 By 1923 he had also recorded what would remain his
general assessment (Haltung) of Marxism.15 In his doctoral dissertation of
that year, Rechtsphilosophische Einleitung zu einer Abhandlung ber das
Verhltnis von Staat und Strafe, he suggested that historical materialism is a
prize theoretical method (eine Methode der Erkenntnis), but that it cannot
offer an adequate guide to political action.16
After completing his studies, he worked for three years as an assistant to
Hugo Sinzheimer, passing his Assessorexamen in 1927. He immediately set
up in private practice with Fraenkel a partnership that would last until his
emigration and they quickly built up a large caseload. During this period,
Neumann wrote much more than is typically acknowledged often on legal
and trade union issues and lectured alongside Hermann Heller and Carl
Schmitt at the Hochschule fr Politik in Berlin. He also worked closely with
the SPD, soon becoming its legal adviser.17 His desire to fuse practice with a
corresponding interest in legal theory, however, was already clear from the
first dissertation, and in this regard there are two main points to observe. First,
Neumann adduced a positive-legal (positivrechtliche), rational relationship
between state, punishment (Strafe) and democracy.18 Second, the dissertation
laid the preparatory legal foundations (Grundlagen) with which he could later
investigate such relationships (principally those pertaining to the state and
democracy) sociologically. Despite Jays accusation of infidelity towards the
autonomy of politics, Neumann was certainly not a crude determinist.19
13 Rolf Wiggerhaus, The Frankfurt School, trans. Michael Robertson (Oxford
(1986), 1995), p. 224.
14 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, p. 15.
15 Ibid. Cf. Neumann, Behemoth, pp. 1112; Peter Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann:
Chancen und Dilemma des politischen Reformismus (Baden-Baden, 1996), p. 93.
16 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, p. 19. Cf. Franz Neumann,
Economics and Politics in the Twentieth Century (1951), DAS, p. 263.
17 See Tribe, Capitalism, pp. 172 f.; Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L.
Neumann, p. 21; Wiggerhaus, Frankfurt School, p. 224.
18 Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann, p. 85.
19 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, p. 15. See also Franz
Neumann, The Rule of Law (Leamington Spa, 1986), p. 16. This is a publication of
461
For these foundations, as was also the case with Schmitts thought, particularly during the Weimar Republic, the method of analysis owed much to
both Max Weber and Hans Kelsen.20 But whereas Schmitt denied that the
sociological-political and legal elements of law are in fact distinct, an
opposition to Kelsen in particular and legal positivism in general that developed strongly after the First World War,21 Neumann found Kelsens famous
separation of legal science from practical questions helpful.22 He reiterated
this point some thirteen years later in his second dissertation, suggesting that
in this separation of the categories of essence and existence, of ethical norm
and legal norm, lies the merit of Kelsens pure theory of law.23 This was a
continuation of the neo-Kantian themes pursued in the first dissertation,
possibly showing the influence of his supervisor, Max Ernst Mayer.24
Neumann utilized the separation in a significant way, though: distinguishing
between ideal-type conceptual discussion, and sociological investigation of
culturally significant (deutend) developments is typically Weberian, and
Neumann, as Weber had before him, wrote that the state is not simply
pace Kelsen synonymous with law, or more specifically, with the legal
order (Rechtsordnung).25
According to Weber, the state is not only the most important and powerful
political association; it is also a means to an end. For Weber, the central purpose of the modern state should be to fulfil the objective cultural tasks of the
Neumanns second doctoral dissertation, written under Harold Laski and Karl
Mannheim, The Governance of the Rule of Law. An Investigation into the practical theories, the legal system and the social background of the contemporary society, London
School of Economics (1936).
20 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, pp. 16, 18. Cf. Reinhard
Mehring, Carl Schmitts Lehre von der Auflsung des Liberalismus: Das Sinngefge der
Verfassungslehre als historisches Urteil, Zeitschrift fr Politik, 38 (1991),
pp. 20016, pp. 213 ff. A detailed defence of my position regarding Schmitts proximity
to Weber, which cannot be dealt with here, is provided in a forthcoming book, D. Kelly,
The State of the Political. Conceptions of Politics and the State in the Thought of Max
Weber, Carl Schmitt and Franz Neumann.
21 Carl Schmitt, Political Theology (1934 edition), trans. G. Schwab (Cambridge,
MA (1922), 1985), pp. 10, 15. Cf. Peter Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty and the Crisis of
German Constitutional Law (Durham and New York, 1997), pp. 1012.
22 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, p. 18. Cf. Neumann, The Rule
of Law, p. 237. Kelsen suggested that with his master concept of the reconstructed legal
norm (Rechtssatz), the origin of every legal norm could be traced, until the highest level
of norms in the legal system is reached, [that is] the level of the constitution. The validity
of positive law norms beyond the constitution can then simply be assumed. See Stanley
Paulson, The Neo-Kantian Dimension of Kelsens Legal Theory, Oxford Journal of
Legal Studies, 12 (1992), pp. 31132, pp. 3256.
23 Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 13.
24 Cf. Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann, p. 93, n. 45.
25 Intelmann, Zur Biographie von Franz L. Neumann, p. 18; Weyma Lbbe,
Legitimitt kraft Legalitt (Tbingen, 1990), esp. pp. 2633.
462
D. KELLY
463
that law is to some extent a function of society, also represents a foundational assumption of Neumanns writings.
When these general considerations are borne in mind, therefore,
Neumanns proximity to both Weber and Schmitt, and hence his proper place
within the particularly strong German traditions of both Allgemeine
Staatslehre and Staatsrechtslehre, is clear in the following summary of his
position written in 1936:
I call every sociologically sovereign institution a state. Therefore the state
cannot, according to this definition, be a legal order (Hans Kelsen): neither
can it be a fiction, nor an abstraction. For in all these three cases we could
not speak of state sovereignty but only of the sovereignty of organs of the
state. In this definition it is further evident that state and society are both
quite distinct phenomena. The specific relationship existing between state
and society is, formally speaking, that the acts of the sovereign state relate
to the society and that these are at the same time caused by the social factors
operating in that society.32
He continues:
We have defined the state as a sovereign institution. Sovereignty contains
as a legal moment the original right of the sovereign to issue general norms
and individual norms (commands, decisions). In consequence of this dualism of the right of issuing general and individual norms there exists the possibility of an antagonism between the then existing series of general norms
and the then issued individual norms . . . Where the state in case of such a
conflict has the right in the interests of its self-maintenance to break
through partially the series of norms by means of individual norms, or even
to suspend the whole series, a situation arises which we do not intend to discuss here [surely an allusion to Schmitts Die Diktatur]. Alone important
for us here is that [the] state has done this thing, and is continually doing it.
In [such] cases the exercise of sovereignty is a power decision in the sense
of Carl Schmitt.33
As Weber had suggested, the modern bureaucratic state possesses the monopoly of legitimate violence within a given territory and functions, separate
from society, sine ira et studio. In this it is clearly sociologically sovereign
in Neumanns terms, and the highest form of political association. However,
although the modern state is the sole source of legitimate law, and hence of
(rational-legal) legitimate authority in general, as already implied, it cannot
be seen as being based on some ideal conception of the legal order.34 Specifically, the state can properly be understood only in terms of its empirical
Gesammelte Aufstze zur Wissenschaftslehre, ed. Johannes Winckelmann (Tbingen,
1973), pp. 200 f.
32 Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 23. Emphasis added.
33 Ibid., pp. 23 f. Cf. p. 26.
34 Max Weber, Economy and Society, trans. C. Wittich and G. Roth (2 vols., Berkeley, 1978), Vol. 2, p. 666.
464
D. KELLY
465
constituent power of the people, for the constitution was formed in the wake
of the 1918 revolution. The constitution, qua state, represents the political
unity of the people. However, the concept that best unlocks these interrelated
ideas is that of sovereignty. Schmitts argument in this respect, as outlined
most famously and clearly in Political Theology, suggests that the sovereign
entity is defined by its ability to decide upon the state of exception.41
Underpinning this is the related assumption that for a legal order to make
sense, a normal situation must exist, and he is sovereign who definitively
decides whether this normal situation actually exists.42 The sovereign figure,
therefore, by deciding on the exceptional situation, gives meaning to the
argument that the exceptional situation produces the order of the norm.
Under the Weimar constitution, however, the whole issue of sovereignty
was confused. Article 48, for example, gave the Reichsprsident sovereign
emergency powers to abrogate the constitution if need be, that is, to act as a
dictator. Simultaneously in Article 76 it was claimed, for example, that the
constitution could be amended by legislation. Given Schmitts highly specific
understanding of the constitution, he thought these attempts to legislate in
procedural terms for decisions that by their very nature cannot be legislated
for confused the question of sovereignty, rendered dictatorship . . . subordinate to the sovereign constitution, and actually threatened the legitimacy of
the constitution itself.43 Furthermore, although Schmitts focus on the existential basis of the constitution and state put forward a powerful critique of legal
positivism, as was common in legal discussions under Weimar, his argument
also formed a more general attack on liberalism.44 For Schmitt, liberal belief
in procedural neutrality and the rule of law treats the political sphere (i.e. the
state) as if it were just another association among many to be regulated and
controlled. Against this, in a pointed critique of contemporary pluralist social
theory, he suggested that the specificity of the political, and hence the state,
can actually be found in the particular degree of intensity it involves, which is
altogether alien to other spheres. This intensity stems, as he had earlier argued,
from the states central role in distinguishing between friends and enemies, and in gauging levels of antagonism between them.45 The two major
threats to the unity of the contemporary state were therefore pluralism and liberalism, and his broad criticisms of the Weimar constitution as just outlined
provide a necessary initial context within which to locate Franz Neumanns
41 For the rapid development and impact of Schmitts arguments regarding sovereignty and emergency constitutional powers, see John P. McCormick, Carl Schmitts
Critique of Liberalism (Cambridge, 1997), esp. pp. 14153.
42 Schmitt, Political Theology, p. 13.
43 Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty, p. 107.
44 Ibid., pp. 82 f.
45 Carl Schmitt, Staatsethik und pluralistischer Staat, Kant-Studien, 35 (1930),
pp. 2842, esp. pp. 367; Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (1932 edition), trans.
George Schwab (Chicago (1927), 1996), esp. pp. 19, 43, 44.
466
D. KELLY
467
constitution as decisionless, he is not only referring to the problematic relationship between what he terms the old classical and the new social rights,
he is also questioning the source of sovereignty within the constitution,
though in such a way that will nevertheless lead him to challenge the import of
Schmitts fears about constitutional change based on an opposition between
constitutional legitimacy (unified, original political will) and legality (procedural neutrality). To recall, Schmitt argues that:
the distinction between the written and unwritten constitution is in truth
the opposition of the constitution (in its positive sense) and the constitutional law which is based on it [zugrunde lag].52
The central problem for Neumann is that there is a tension between the
essence of the Weimar constitution and how it has come to be interpreted and
implemented. In this respect, another side of his argument is particularly
52 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, p. 386. Ernst-Rudolf Huber, Verfassung und
Verfassungswirklichkeit bei Carl Schmitt, in E.-R. Huber, Bewahrung und Wandlung
(Berlin, 1972), p. 19, characterizes this as the central problem (Kernproblem) of every
constitutional theory.
53 Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty, p. 227, n. 109.
54 Franz L. Neumann, The Social Significance of the Basic Laws in the Weimar
Constitution (1930), in Social Democracy and the Rule of Law: Otto Kirchheimer and
Franz L. Neumann, ed. Keith Tribe, trans. K. Tribe and L. Tanner (London, 1987) (hereafter SD), pp. 29 f. Emphasis added. Cf. Jrgen Bast, Totalitrer Pluralismus: Zu Franz
L. Neumanns Analysen der politischen und rechtlichen Struktur der NS-Herrschaft
(Tbingen, 1999), p. 77, n. 102, who also extraordinarily calls this a polemic
against Schmitt.
468
D. KELLY
469
470
D. KELLY
theory of action. He argues that a precondition of the social democracy he supports is material equality and that such equality can be properly brought about
and maintained through the actions of the state, in some form of post-capitalist
society.68 It is this idea of using the state as a means to an end that provides a
crucial link back to Weber, though as Neumann (borrowing largely from
Schmitt) would point out, under contemporary conditions it was not at all
clear that the state was up to this task. Nevertheless, given that Neumann
understood equality under Weimar to be negative equality, it is worthwhile
examining the similarities once again between Neumann and Schmitt concerning the nature of the Rechtsstaat.
For Schmitt, the development of the Rechtsstaat corresponds to the rise of a
modern, bourgeois and individualist political order.69 Its ambivalence centres
on the question of whether the individual rights it purports to protect are to be
created or presupposed, in much the same way as liberal constitutionalism, for
Schmitt, confuses the question of how a constitution is itself constituted.70
Nevertheless, Neumann keenly observes the positive propaganda that
accrued to the bourgeoisie by only calling its state a Rechtsstaat.71 Thus,
writing in 1934 under a pseudonym, he lamented the fact that both his and
Hermann Hellers attempts to promote the ideals of a social Rechtsstaat
based on the old ideals of 1789 had failed under criticism from both socialist (Otto Kirchheimer) and bourgeois (Carl Schmitt, Albert Hensel) camps.72
His understanding of the Rechtsstaat suggests that it only develops clearly if
it is considered in the context of the economic, political and philosophical system of liberalism. Therefore, general law and the division of powers
which for Neumann represents not only a differentiation of powers as
Montesquieu had elaborated, but also a distribution of powers between social
groups within the Rechtsstaat have the sole and exclusive aim of securing
freedom and property.73 A truly progressive development of the generality of
law, therefore, would be to complete the process of legal rationalization
begun under the Rechtsstaat in order to achieve the positive notion of equality
he supports. Otherwise, as he makes clear in discussing competitive
capitalism:
See Chris Thornhill, Political Theory in Modern Germany (Oxford, 2000), p. 96.
Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, esp. pp. 12533, 13857. Cf. Ernst Wolfgang-Bckenfrde,
The Origin and Development of the Concept of the Rechtsstaat, in E. WolfgangBckenfrde, State, Society and Liberty, trans. J.A. Underwood (Leamington Spa, 1991),
esp. pp. 58 ff., 6170.
70 Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty, pp. 85 f., 105.
71 Neumann, Rechtsstaat, SD, p. 67. Cf. Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 293.
72 Cf. Neumann, Rechtstaat, SD, p. 68; Bast, Totalitrer Pluralismus, p. 77;
Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann, p. 94.
73 Neumann, Rechtsstaat, SD, pp. 68 f.
68
69
471
If one does not draw . . . distinctions, and sees in the generality of the law,
nothing but a requirement of capitalist economy, then of course, one must
infer with Carl Schmitt that the general law, the independence of judges,
and the separation of powers, must be abolished when capitalism dies.74
472
D. KELLY
sovereignty of Parliament. By this the generality of the law took the place of
a natural law. It was in fact nothing but a hidden natural law.79
Neumanns central claim, then, was that the democratic elements of the
Weimar constitution could be upheld and promoted only through the intervention of a strong, sovereign state. Indeed, the fact that the social equality he
desires can be brought about only through the activities of such a strong interventionist state offers a very particular development and modification of
Schmitts position.80 Both thought that the contemporary state was weak and
that Parliament was no longer able to provide adequate political leadership.
For Schmitt, however, this is the logical conclusion of the rechtsstaatlich elements of the constitution, which stand opposed to its properly political foundations and tend simply to relativize state power.81 Democracy and
liberalism have now to be disentangled. Neumann, on the other hand, suggested that the ideals of liberty under the Rechtsstaat were not only compatible with a competitive market society and a minimal state, but that the
non-interventionist state of liberalism was certainly negative but it was never
weak. It was, rather, just as strong as its economic and social structure made
necessary;82 and the force which integrated that society, based upon personal, political, and economic freedom, into a State, was the conception of the
nation (the irrational basis of society).83 He wished, therefore, to radicalize
the Rechtsstaat rather than renounce it, and to complete the process of legal
rationalization begun under it, for this would allow the sovereign state to
defend a positive principle of equality. This is, in fact, precisely the challenge
he had earlier laid down for a socialist political theory of the state to develop and concretely present the positive social content of the second part of
the Weimar Constitution.84
This can be further explained by listing in more detail the major discrepancies
Neumann perceives between contemporary constitutional norms and reality.85
79 Ibid., p. 276. See also Otto Kahn-Freund, Das soziale Ideal des Reichsarbeitsgerichts
(1931), quoted in Tim Mason, The Origins of the Law on the Organization of National
Labour of 20 January 1934. An Investigation into the Relationship Between Archaic
and Modern Elements in Recent German History (1974), in Nazism, Fascism and the
Working Class, ed. Jane Caplan (Cambridge, 1995), p. 97. Cf. Alfons Sllner, Franz
Neumann, Telos, 50 (1980), pp. 1719, pp. 172 f.
80 Volker Neumann, Kompromiss, p. 68: the position [Stellung] of the state marks
the difference between the political theory of Schmitt and Neumann.
81 Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty, p. 102.
82 Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 198.
83 Ibid., pp. 186, 205.
84 Franz L. Neumann, The Social Significance of the Basic Laws in the Weimar
Constitution (1930), SD, p. 43; Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann, pp. 97, 123.
85 The six points quoted in this paragraph are drawn from Franz Neumann, On the
Preconditions and the Legal Concept of an Economic Constitution (1931), SD,
pp. 4951.
473
474
D. KELLY
475
476
D. KELLY
477
478
D. KELLY
economic change, but also notes that law and economy are mutually constituting. Therefore, and this is the aspect of Renners account of most importance to Neumanns analysis:
to decide the function of the law in general, we have to study inductively all
social orders as they appear in the course of history, from the most primitive
to the most highly developed. By this method we obtain the general categories of the social order and at the same time the general functions of the
law.119
479
both Schmitt and Neumann, Weber questioned how individual freedom was
to be maintained under modern, bureaucratized conditions.124 Equally, in earlier reflections on the historical triumphs of liberalism that are included within
his essays on the 1905 Russian Revolution, Weber wrote that:
it is vital that liberalism continue to see its vocation as fighting against both
bureaucratic and Jacobin centralism and working at the permeation of the
masses with the old individualistic basic idea of the inalienable rights of
man, which have become as boring to us Western Europeans as black
bread is for the person who has enough to eat.125
Moreover, he asked, how can such ideals as liberty and democracy exist at all
for any length of time under the domination of capitalism? In fact (Weber
continues) they are only possible where they are backed up by the determined
will of a nation not to be ruled like a flock of sheep. Therefore, we individualists and supporters of democratic institutions must swim against the
tide of material constellations.126
The questions and sentiments are exactly the same as Neumanns.
Neumann, however, subdivided the rights of man, and offered a distinction
between liberalism and democracy again reminiscent of Schmitt, in order to
separate inalienable liberties, which can only be removed by the legislature
in the process of constitutional amendment, from those that can be removed
by the simple legislative process. Apart from such positive constitutional
law distinctions, Neumann further compartmentalized these rights according to their subject matter economic or social rights to freedom, for
instance.127 The point of this was to show that from political rights the rights
of the status activus must be divorced.128 That is, Neumann is here reinforcing the distinction between liberal and democratic rights, because liberalindividual rights as currently understood would appear to have little use in the
kind of post-capitalist society based on material and social equality that he is
keen to promote.129 Moreover, given that he has already defined democracy
once again in Schmitts terms, it is clear that his work continues to remain
very much within the latters frame of reference.130
124 Max Weber, Parliament and Government in Germany under a New Political
Order (191718), Political Writings, p. 159.
125 Max Weber, Bourgeois Democracy in Russia (1906), in The Russian Revolutions, ed. and trans. P. Baehr and G.C. Wells (Oxford, 1995), p. 108. My emphasis.
126 Ibid., p. 109.
127 Neumann, The Rule of Law, pp. 367.
128 Ibid.
129 Cf. Franz Neumann, On the Concept of Political Freedom, Columbia Law
Review, 53 (1951), pp. 90135, pp. 934 f.; Scheuerman, Norm and Exception, p. 57.
130 See Neumann, Rechtsstaat, SD, p. 73: Democracy rests upon equality. Popular
sovereignty means identity of the rulers and the ruled.
480
D. KELLY
481
482
D. KELLY
Neumann vents his spleen at so-called decisionistic legal thought in a passage worth quoting fully:
Decisionistic legal thought has, in fact, nothing to do with law. In this kind
of legal thinking, law is nothing but a technique for transforming the political will into legal form. In decisionism law is nothing but an arcanum for
the maintenance of power. It is an arcanum dominationis, and it is characteristic that in political theory the doctrine of the arcana arose at the time
when theology lost its dominating influence.142
Neumanns authority for the historical clause at the end of this quotation is
none other than Carl Schmitt.143 The irony of this (surely purposeful) reference is that the very type of thought that Neumann decries is in fact that which
he (now, in 1936) views Schmitt as practising.144 As is well known, in Behemoth Schmitt was presented as the leading ideologist of National Socialism, a
non-state in which there is no longer any such thing as the rule of law.
Indeed, the impassioned paragraph that ends The Rule of Law had already outlined the position of law in contemporary Germany:
We therefore sum up: That law does not exist in Germany, because law is
now exclusively a technique of transforming the political will of the Leader
into constitutional reality. Law is nothing but an arcanum dominationis.145
The implication of his argument, which suggests that for law to exist there
must be a state, nevertheless corresponds with Schmitts Weimar writings.
Indeed, the rapid call for the transcendence of the state by such National
Socialist party hacks as Otto Kllreutter, was a direct challenge to Schmitts
ideas and played at least a bit part in his ousting from the heights of the Nazi
legal establishment.146 For example, Neumann quotes from Schmitt to the
effect that the people under the totalitarian, National Socialist state are
treated as essentially unpolitical, and located mainly within the private
sphere. The unified constituent will of the people, which stood at the root of
the democratic state, is now forgotten, for the people here exist simply to be
483
484
D. KELLY
This clearly builds on Webers discussion of modern law as rational formalism. Weber suggested that although the validity of law under conditions of
modernity is logically derived from abstract norms, it is dependent upon
either textual considerations legal propositions which accord with logical
correctness or empirical validity, which has as its basis the probabilistic
assumption that people will, in fact, obey.155 Here too law is reason and will.
Neumanns combined critique of decisionistic thinking and contemporary
monopoly capitalism therefore culminates in what Scheuerman terms a
neo-Marxist reworking of Webers concept of legal rationalization, because
Neumann wants both radical (and explicitly anti-capitalist) social and economic reforms and all of the virtues of liberal general legal norms. He therefore tries to show not only that social and economic equality and classically
liberal legal modes are compatible but that they need each other. Thus, the
real elective affinity is between social democracy and formal law.156 For
Scheuerman, Neumann is attempting to prove that:
modern politics still needs state organs holding a monopoly on the instruments of coercion (and law, unlike morality, must still be backed up by the
possibility of state-based force), yet he hopes that this monopoly can take a
significantly more acceptable form than it has in the past, and that the state
should no longer need to act in a manner incompatible with general legal
norms or above and against a system of neatly codified formal law.157
Reforming Rationalization
The implication of this reading is that Neumanns history of occidental legal
thought tells the story of a long attempt to extinguish its inherent decisionist
or normless elements. Because of this, it also represents a curious mirror
image of Schmitts own generalizations about political history since the six153
154
p. 45.
155
156
157
485
Yet, as Scheuerman has further pointed out, there are perhaps two general
points worth reminding ourselves of here. One is, simply, that Neumann
wishes to defend something akin to a Weberian account of the state against
what he sees as Schmitts decisionism. The other, subtler, undertaking is his
re-working of Webers account of legal rationalization. Indeed, taking
Webers remarks about the potential fate of the working classes under
deformalized law very seriously, Neumann suggests that a focus on
deformalized law is actually the epitome of an irrationality, but this is an irrationality that actually serves to bolster the ruling class. These irrational
trends come from above and not below, and they benefit the most secure
core sector of the capitalist economy. It is therefore in the interests of this secure sector to hinder the completion of those processes of rationalization that
would fulfil the necessary preconditions for the implementation of general
law. Neumann suggests, alongside Weber, that the decline of liberal
parliamentarism is due to the rise in strength of the working class, whose
incorporation via political parties into Parliament makes it a potential agent of
social change, although it has weakened Parliament at the same time. It is this
potential strength that has led to the renewed focus on deformalized law.
Moreover, although right to identify regulatory laws immediate roots in the
158
159
Cf. Neumann, The Rule of Law, Part II; Schmitt, Age of Neutralizations, p. 141.
Scheuerman, Norm and Exception, pp. 107 f. Cf. Neumann, The Rule of Law,
p. 28.
160 Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 137. Cf. Andrew Levine, The End of the State (London, 1987); Thornhill, Political Theory, pp. 967; Neumann, Rechtsstaat, SD, p. 71.
161 See Neumann, Decay of German Democracy, pp. 530 f.
162 Scheuerman, Norm and Exception, p. 117.
486
D. KELLY
487
488
D. KELLY
monopoly capitalism was clearly at odds with Friedrich Pollocks predominant account of National Socialism as a form of Staatskapitalismus.175
That National Socialism was a new arrangement was crucial to Pollocks
argument; it constituted a break with previous history. Neumann saw no such
temporal caesura. Rather, for him there was a clear continuity between competitive and monopoly capitalism.176 To Pollock, of course, it was the new
coordinating role of the state that was truly dramatic it had taken over the
previous functions of the market. As a corollary of this, he described a fusion
between state bureaucracy and capital from which the cadres of political leadership under a totalitarian variant of the more general trend towards state capitalism were formed. This totalitarian variant was National Socialism.177 Both
Neumann and Pollock nevertheless agreed that a Marxist analysis of the concentration and centralization of capital could explain the inherent trend
towards monopolization,178 and equally both agreed that capitalist crises had
in no way been ameliorated or evaporated. Correlatively, state intervention
had increased to an unprecedented degree.179 Pollock suggested that private
capitalism had been superseded, as the state now assumed important functions
of the private capitalist, and that although capitalist institutions continued to
play a significant role, this new state form was not socialist.180
Whereas Neumann saw National Socialism as a totalitarian form of monopoly capitalism, Pollock thought it had, by transforming quantity into quality, mutated into a state capitalism with the attendant central features of vast
state planning buttressed by an all-powerful bureaucracy.181 Crucially,
though, everybody who does not belong to this group is a mere object of
175 See esp. Intelmann, Franz L. Neumann, pp. 24551; Intelmann, Zur Biographie
von Franz L. Neumann, p. 42; David Held, An Introduction to Critical Theory (Oxford
(1980), 1990), p. 365; Jay, Dialectical Imagination, pp. 161 f.
176 Bast, Totalitrer Pluralismus, Ch. 2, part III.
177 Friedrich Pollock, Is National Socialism a New Order?, Studies in Philosophy
and Social Science, 9 (1941), pp. 44055.
178 See Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 266.
179 Pollock, Is National Socialism a New Order?, p. 454. See also Held, Critical
Theory, p. 57. Cf. James, German Slump, p. 123.
180 Pollock, Is National Socialism a New Order?, p. 450, also quoted in Held, Critical Theory, p. 58.
181 Neumanns point that total integration did not exist has been developed by many
subsequent historians. See Mason, Social Policy, pp. 44, 71, 242 f., 273; Tim Mason,
The Workers Opposition in Nazi Germany, History Workshop Journal, 11 (1981),
pp. 12037; Ian Kershaw, Popular Opinion and Political Dissent in the Third Reich
(Oxford (1983), 1991), esp. pp. 329 f.; cf. Ulrich Herbert, Labour and Extermination:
Economic Interest and the Primacy of Weltanschauung in National Socialism (1987),
Past and Present, 138 (1993), pp. 14495; Ulrich Herbert, The Real Mystery in Germany: The German Working Class During the Nazi Dictatorship, in Confronting the
Nazi Past, ed. Michael Burleigh (London, 1996), pp. 2336.
489
490
D. KELLY
491
fying figure of the leader.196 Yet legally, neither element party or state
controls the other. Because the party is not an organ of the state . . . its position cannot be defined in terms of our traditional jurisprudence.197 The nub of
the argument, explicitly directed against Schmitt (among others), is that little
light is shed by the formula that party and state are different but not separate,
combined but not merged.198 Here is the crucial analytical claim:
Our task will be to show that this is not quite true, that there is a definite pattern of political and constitutional theory, although this pattern does not fit
the rational categories of political thought as we know it, whether liberal,
absolutist, democratic or autocratic.199
492
D. KELLY
493
Thus, German constitutional life is characterised by its utter shapelessness . . . [and] it follows that from our point of view it is doubtful whether Germany can be called a state.209 Neumann clearly thinks the regime is rife with
contradictions, between the Fhrer and the high-level bureaucratic
machines in fact between the four principal political powers he has identified and also, importantly, between rulers and ruled. He sees therefore the
necessity of the destruction of Behemoth, but also recognizes the possibility
for conscious political action of the oppressed masses, which . . . [could] utilise the breaks in the system.210 Nevertheless, while there is a fairly clear
presentation of the problem linked to a detailed analysis of the present, there is
no clear picture of what the fully realised picture of the new social form
might look like. Indeed, whilst Neumann posits the problem of order or integration as a crucial feature of modern democracies, his own account of
National Socialism remains somewhat incomplete. This is not simply due to
the enormity of the subject matter. By tying sovereignty and state so closely
together, he actually remains incapable of theorizing anything that does not
conform to his pre-established norms of social and political theory. He
remains tied, in other words, to his understanding that the state is the highest
form of sovereignty, and that sovereignty contains elements of both might and
right. The new social form that Neumann sees coming into existence in Germany clearly is not a state in this sense, and whilst it possesses all the coercive
power of such a body, it is neither sovereign nor legitimate in the terms that
Neumann understands.211 Therefore, if National Socialism was a chaotic
non-state, could he do anything other than provide a detailed contextual
description of it?
Ibid., pp. 469 f. Emphasis added. The Schmitt reference refers to his Der
Reichsbegriff im Vlkerrecht, Deutsches Recht (1939), pp. 3414. Cf. Peter Stirk, Carl
Schmitts Vlkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung, History of Political Thought, XX
(1999), pp. 35774, pp. 367 f.
209 Neumann, Behemoth, p. 522. On the new power of retroactive legislation,
Neumann cites Constant approvingly: retroaction is the most evil assault which the law
can permit . . . a retroactive law is no law at all. See Neumann, The Rule of Law, p. 222;
and also Neumann, The Change in the Function of Law in Modern Society, DAS, p. 36.
210 Neumann, Behemoth, p. 476.
211 Ibid., p. 470.
208
494
D. KELLY
Many present-day accounts of the NS-Zeit have also illustrated the importance of bureaucratic efficiency and technical procedures for economic
restructuring. Indeed, some of the most provocative and controversial recent
German work has outlined the often eager complicity of various academics
and influential political decision-makers in particular in adapting their scientific procedures to fit the new economic order.212 This kind of research
could actually square the circle, so to speak, of Neumanns account. The overall ascription of rationality to, in particular, the planning elite, nevertheless
runs against the grain of his basic understanding.213 There is no space here to
go into detail about the relationship between Neumanns writings and discussions about the Third Reich and modernization.214 It will have to suffice to
observe that for contemporary research, the problems of systemic order and
the rational reproduction of an irrational regime remain paramount.
Certainly, though, one of the most basic and highly provocative argument[s] within Behemoth is that some version of an identifiably modern
state apparatus controlling the exercise of coercion remains a civilizational
achievement worth defending.215 It is precisely the universal fulfilment of the
rule of law, as opposed to its curtailing, that is to say, the completion of legal
rationalization as a basis for meaningful social change, which Neumann has
attempted to argue for in a complex mixture of sources. Such a mixture has led
Thornhill to characterize Neumann as an anti-Schmittian Schmittian . . .
[and] simultaneously . . . an anti-Marxist Marxist.216 He is perhaps right. Perhaps the fact that Neumann had trouble explaining Nazism through the use of
his categories should not be that surprising. However, if what is modern
about National Socialism is the deliberate reconstruction of a social and political order by the application of the modern instrumentaria of power and domination,217 then Neumann did at the very least ask the right questions. He
obviously also went a long way towards providing us with answers, indeed
answers on which we still rely. The problems faced by Neumann are the same
as those facing researchers today who, as they delve deeper into the structures
of the Third Reich, confront those modern aspects of the regime, and
Gotz ly, The Planning Intelligentsia and the Final Solution , in Confronting
the Nazi Past, ed. Burleigh, p. 153. Cf. Norbert Frei, Wie modern war der Nationalsozialismus?, Geschichte und Gesellschaft, 19 (1993), pp. 36787, esp. pp. 385 ff.;
Michael Burleigh, A Political Economy of the Final Solution? Reflections on Modernity, Historians and the Holocaust, in M. Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination (Cambridge, 1997), pp. 1709.
213 See Herbert, Labour and Extermination, pp. 173 ff.
214 See Tribe, Capitalism, passim.
215 Scheuerman, Norm and Exception, p. 196.
216 Thornhill, Political Theory, p. 115. Cf. Neumann, The Change in the Function of
Law in Modern Society, DAS, pp. 40 f.; Caplan, Government Without Administration,
p. 199.
217 Tribe, Capitalism, p. 199.
212
495
particularly now ask awkward questions about the impact of the NS-Zeit
on post-war German economy and society.218
Re-Reading Behemoth
That Neumanns thought during the period under consideration in this paper
owes so much to Schmitts categories casts the well-known portrait of
Schmitt in Behemoth as the clearest representative of Nazi ideology in a different light. The key point for Neumann is that under National Socialism the
state per se has ceased to exist, and without the state there is simply a
decisionistic, situation-specific, deformalized or dematerialized law that
owes little, if anything, to the general rule of law he seeks to defend. As a representative of such decisionistic thought, Schmitt has become not simply
authoritarian, but also irrational, and he can therefore legitimately be viewed
as a Nazi ideologue. Whether there was indeed a break in Schmitts thought
in 1933 is itself a vexed question, and depends on whether one views his
Weimar writings as a quantifiable progression towards an overtly fascist politics. Neumanns observations in both the quoted letter that forms the epigraph
to this paper, and most of the work referred to here, suggests that he did not
take such a view. This is clearly a difficult question. This is no reason to
ignore it, however, and ignored it often has been.
By reconstructing Franz Neumanns route to Behemoth, I hope to have
shown that it is much too simple just to suggest that his political writings, at
least before the end of the war, are determined by the dictates of a clearly
defined social-democratic reformism. Although there is, of course, an element of truth in such a broad general characterization, this neat ideological
label not only hides important differences within social-democratic politics
itself, but also in this case ignores a, perhaps the, major protagonist in
Neumanns political writings before the end of the war.219 Equally, there is
also a wider point to be made here. In their related concerns about the nature
of the modern state and questions of political-legal rationality and legitimacy,
the works of Weber, Schmitt and Neumann clearly touch on themes that go
beyond the confines of Weimar democracy and National Socialist
218 For one recent overview, Martin Urban, Die Hintermnner der Mrder,
Sddeutsche Zeitung, 24 October 2000, p. V2/13.
219 Neumanns views on Schmitt obviously changed. His last, unfinished work contains an important reference. See Franz Neumann, Notes on the Theory of Dictatorship
(1954), DAS, pp. 23356: Strange as it may seem, we do not possess any systematic
study of dictatorship, ibid., p. 233. His note, p. 254, n. 1, states that Schmitts work Die
Diktatur is the most significant exception, but his analysis is not acceptable. Emphasis
added. Neumann tragically died in a car crash in 1954 before he could develop a more
acceptable account. On the post-war relations between Neumann and Schmitt, see
Michael Salter, Neo-Fascist Legal Theory on Trial: An Interpretation of Carl Schmitts
Defence at Nuremberg from the Perspective of Franz Neumanns Critical Theory of
Law, Res Publica, 5 (1999), pp. 16194.
496
D. KELLY
UNIVERSITY OF SHEFFIELD
David Runciman, History of Political Thought: The State of the Discipline, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 3 (2001), pp. 84104, pp. 97, 100.
221 See Francis Oakley, Anxieties of Influence: Skinner, Figgis, Conciliarism and
Early-Modern Constitutionalism, Past and Present, 151 (1996), pp. 60110, for an elegant defence of the utility of the concept of influence in the history of political thought.
220