Stefan Bolea - What Is Existentialism-Libre
Stefan Bolea - What Is Existentialism-Libre
Stefan Bolea - What Is Existentialism-Libre
and the existential subject. Before that we explore other historical definitions of
existentialism. We were mainly interested in the relation between existentialism and nihilism,
the focus of existential philosophy on the individual and the situation of the studied
philosophical trend on the 1950's zeitgeist. The definition of existentialism as a form of transrationalism and its capacity to become a practical alternative to contemporary academic
philosophy were also emphasized.
Keywords
existentialism,
nihilism,
postmodernism,
practical
philosophy,
literature,
Introduction
We would like to take into consideration some of the most important definitions of
existentialism (before providing a personal definition, which analyzes the relations between
the studied philosophical trend, nihilism and postmodernism) in order to understand its
position in the history of philosophy. The first phase of existentialism is represented by Sren
Kierkegaard, who publishes his most influential works in the 1840's Denmark. Its second
chapter is mainly German and refers to the activity of thinkers like Friedrich Nietzsche,
Edmund Husserl, Karl Jaspers and Martin Heidegger, who conceived their works between
1880 and 1940. Its third phase and its most recognizable one is the French version of
existentialism that became the dominant philosophical trend between 1930 and 1970. Albert
Camus, Gabriel Marcel, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and especially JeanPaul Sartre are the most visible French existentialists.1
vague and palpable in its everyday connotation, we must refer to a classical quote from
Samuel Coleridge, which directs our existential sensibility in a splendid way. The Romantic
poet observed in an essay from The Friend:
Hast thou ever raised thy mind to the consideration of EXISTENCE, in and by itself, as the
mere act of existing? Hast thou ever said to thyself, thoughtfully, IT IS! heedless in that moment
whether it were a man before thee, or a flower, or a grain of sand? ... The very words, There is
nothing! or, There was a time, when there was nothing! are self-contradictory ... Not TO BE ...
is impossible: to BE, incomprehensible. If thou hast mastered this intuition of absolute
existence, thou wilt have learnt likewise, that it was this, and no other, which in the earlier ages
seized the nobler minds, the elect among men, with a sort of sacred horror.2
the distinction between essence and being (discussed mainly by Heidegger and Sartre),
represents a sort of originary existentialism (one could also call it Urexistenzialismus), which
considers that intuition and the pre-understanding of existence are a source of both
zeitgeist that precedes the activity of the principal forerunner of existentialism (i.e.
Kierkegaard), writes about the impossibility of non-existence and the incomprehensibility of
For more on this chronology, see for instance Denis Huisman, Histoire de l existentialisme, Editions Nathan,
Paris, 1997, pp. 7, 122.
2
Samuel Coleridge, The Friend, Chauncey Goodrich, Burlington, 1831, pp. 450-451.
existence, starting from the poetical revelation of the totality and actuality of the almost
inaccessible being.
existentialism, in its whole. Hans Jonas (1952) asserted in his book The Gnostic Religion the
similarity between existentialism and nihilism (maybe as a consequence of the 1950's
zeitgeist, which did not provide a working definition of existentialism): "More than two
generations ago, Nietzsche said that nihilism, 'this weirdest of all guests,' 'stands before the
door.' Meanwhile the guest has entered and is no longer a guest, and, as far as philosophy is
concerned, existentialism is trying to live with him. Living in such company is living in a
crisis."3
live with" nihilism, is captivating. In order to do co-exist with it, existentialism must "hijack"
the purpose of nihilism, inventing a meaning where nihilism presents only meaninglessness.
This more than 60 years old definition provided by Jonas makes us think of the effective task
of existentialism that had to bring over meaninglessness and to create value and meaning in a
specific moment in which those had to be reconstructed. The aforementioned definition has a
strong historical connotation: the world after Auschwitz and Hiroshima seemed to have
reached the "climax" of nihilism. Existentialism becomes the soul doctor of a "nihilisminfected" world and has to find solutions where the chaotic dimension of the society proves
explosive.
Gary Cox (2009) re-thinks this relation between existentialism and nihilism:
"Existentialists are nihilists because they recognize that life is ultimately absurd and full of
terrible, inescapable truths. They are anti-nihilists because they recognize that life does in fact
have a meaning: the meaning each person chooses to give his or her own existence." 4
Existentialism emphasizes the inherent creativity of the human subjects, who must find their
"personal truths" and have to invent meaning, even though they are living in a world where
absurdity is unavoidable. To observe the difference between the two philosophical trends, one
must only refer to their conceptions regarding death:
Hans Jonas, The Gnostic Religion, Beacon Press, Boston, 2001, p. 322.
Gary Cox, How to Be an Existentialist or How to Get real, Get a Grip and Stop Making Excuses, Continuum,
London, New York, 2009, p. 15.
a) For existentialism, death is viewed from the perspective of life. This conception
intends to stimulate the individual to realize his destiny, to achieve his life. One must
construct a meaning, despite finitude. To live without the quest of a personal truth is to refuse
self-awareness; more exactly, it is to refuse to live at all.
b) For nihilism, life is viewed from the perspective of death, life is an useless
finitude. Our effort amounts to nothing because our achievements do not accompany us
beyond death's door. From the reductive perspective of nihilism, which presupposes the
appeal to a brutal lucidity, our resourcefulness and creativity are, to put it plainly, lies. Our
beings are crushed and leveled by a death that acknowledges no merit.
Existentialism could reply to nihilism that the human being could prosper on the
brink of abyss, could live with death, even though finitude is unavoidable. With death pressed
against his heart, the individual can find a desire to go beyond himself and to build something
amazing from his life. Therefore, existentialism opposes an affective truth ("I love this finite
and unique life") to a mental truth ("the fact that death ends us is the background of our lives:
compared to nothingness, our being is mainly appearance"). The mental truth requires a
heroic lucidity; however, it could encourage the evasion of responsibility towards the "low"
(i.e. passive) zones of nihilism, where truth and paralysis are identical.
Walter Kaufmann (1960) noted that "the existentialists have tried to bring philosophy
down to earth again like Socrates" 5 , and Wartenberg (2008) added that "existentialism is
arguably the only contemporary form of philosophy that remains true to the conception of
philosophy first articulated over two and a half millennia ago in Ancient Greece. For the
Greeks, philosophy was
mind-body dualism (the Cartesian reminiscence) is abandoned in favor of the quest for a
practical philosophy, which tends to alter existence and reform it according to personal
commandments (existentialism is akin to stoicism in this practical aspect).
The fact that existentialism expressed itself so fluently in literature (from Camus to
Beckett, from Kafka to Sartre) is one of its advantages. The literary existentialism could
convince even a philosophically unspecialized audience, with a philosophical preunderstanding through direct access to everyday life. The distance between the academic
5
Walter Kaufmann, Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, Meridian Books, New York, 1960, p. 51.
Thomas E. Wartenberg, Existentialism, Oneworld, Oxford, 2008, pp. 4-5.
philosophy and the great affective problems of the contemporary human being (anxiety,
a different approach: more personal and more direct. Existentialism should be studied, as we
have mentioned, as an introduction to contemporary philosophy (along postmodernism we
have a pre-understanding of postmodernism while being immersed in contemporary society ),
having an increased efficiency as a recovery after the essentialist mind games of the academic
philosophy, which has lost contact with unmediated existence.
Towards A Historical Definition of Existentialism
William Barrett (1962) reveals an important piece of the existentialist discourse: the
central subject of the existential philosophers is "the unique experience of the single one, the
individual"7. The focus on the individual is emphasized not only by Macquarrie 8 (1972) but
also by contemporary authors like Earnshaw 9 (2006) and Flynn 10 (2006). We have thus a
philosophy of the individual extracted from the serial mass, but not a new solipsism: the way
the individual interacts with others or how he is immersed in social life, his effort to build an
authentic existence, interest us greatly. However, existentialism begins with Kierkegaard's
reaction to the Hegelian "absolutist" and "totalitarian" system, which tries to obliterate
individual attributions. Texts like Kierkegaard's jeblikket, in which the subject needs to fight
against conformism in his effort to establish an authentic society or Nietzsche's Beyond Good
And Evil, in which the modern European must extract himself from the huge leveling process
of history and civilization to become an exceptional individual, are constitutive for the
existential individual ethos. The individual needs to go beyond the leveling and the
conformism of the social life to find his true measure.
One should note that this existentialist focus on individual was under severe scrutiny.
For example, Guido de Ruggiero (1947), found the existentialist exploitation of the theme of
the individual highly disharmonious:
William Barrett, Irrational Man. A Study in Existential Philosophy, Anchor Books, New York, 1962, p. 13.
"For the existentialist the subject is the existent in the whole range of his existing." (John Macquarrie,
Existentialism. An Introduction, Guide and Assessment, Penguin Books, London, 1972, pp. 14-15).
9
"Existentialism is a philosophy that takes as its starting point the individual s existence." (Steven Earnshaw,
Existentialism. A Guide for the Perplexed, Continuum, London New York, 2006, p. 1.)
10
"It is commonly acknowledged that existentialism is a philosophy about the concrete individual. This is both
its glory and its shame." (Thomas R. Flynn, Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, New York, 2006, p. X.)
The existentialist philosophy ... gives a pathological development to the individual and
contingent element of existence by lifting it to a ruling position and making it the measure of all
values. The suffering of the individual, his preoccupation, his anguish, his defeat, his jump into
nothing or into life beyond, have become absolute criteria of judgment, without any
consideration being given to what the individual actually accomplishes in his passing through
life.11
objectivity, recording the very anti-essentialism of existentialism and that is exactly the author
blames "contingency". One could answer the Italian philosopher that anxiety, suffering,
nothing are concepts that belong to the philosophical existential heritage, active not only in
postmodern philosophy but also in existential psychotherapy. To quote only Appignanesi
(2001): "Could it be that the residue popularity of Existentialism today continues from a
legacy of words that still have a power to scandalize? Anguish, despair, anxiety, the absurd,
authenticity, nothingness, and so on, are literary features that have almost have the status of
genuine 'categories'."12
Barrett gives two definitions of existentialism that exploit its historical dimension:
a) "Existential philosophy
dissolution."
is
'The following pages deal with the sentiment of absurdity which prevails in our world.' This
opening sentence of Albert Camus' Le Mythe de Sisyphe conveys the climate in which
Existentialism originates. Camus does not belong to the existentialist school, but the basic
experience which permeates his thought is also at the root of Existentialism. The time is that of
the totalitarian terror: the Nazi regime is at the height of its power; France is occupied by the
German armies, the values and standards of western civilization are coordinated and superseded
by the reality of the fascist system.14
Terry Eagleton's version (2009) of the zeitgeist argument appeals to the same
Guido De Ruggiero, Existentialism: Disintegration of Man s Soul, Kessinger Publishing, NewYork, 2004, p.
13.
12
Richard Appignanesi, Oscar Zarate, Introducing Existentialism, Totem Books, New York, 2001, p. 14.
13
William Barrett, op.cit., pp. 34, 65.
14
Herbert Marcuse, "Remarks on Jean-Paul Sartre s L tre et le Nant", in Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, Vol. 8, No. 3, March 1948, International Phenomenological Society, p. 309.
11
It is surely not irrelevant to the arguments of Heidegger s Being and Time that the book was
written in just such a period of historical tumult, appearing as it did in the wake of the First
World War. Jean-Paul Sartre s Being and Nothingness, which also explores such momentous
issues, was published in the midst of the Second World War ... Maybe all men and women
ponder the meaning of life; but some, for good historical reasons, are driven to ponder it more
urgently than others.15
(1999), who observed that "is quite wrong, first, to regard existentialism as the expression of
should be noted, were written before the war began or before it ended" 16 . The British
philosopher makes two valuable points: both Being and Time (1927) and Being and
Nothingness (1943) were published before 1945; because of this fact existentialism (at least in
its lab phase) should be regarded as an interwar philosophical trend. Moreover, its extended
is revealed through the fact that choice is primordial in our lives, moreover, that we live in a
culture of choice).
studying the 1940's and the 1950's. Our starting point was Hans Jonas' ambiguous definition,
which inferred the similitude between existentialism and nihilism. The determined zeitgeist
makes us better understand the critics of existentialism, Guido de Ruggiero, Herbert Marcuse
and even Pope Pius XII, who wrote in the Humani Generis encyclical (1950): "Such fictitious
tenets of evolution which repudiate all that is absolute, firm and immutable, have paved the
way for the new erroneous philosophy which, rivaling idealism, immanentism and
pragmatism, has assumed the name of existentialism, since it concerns itself only with
existence of individual things and neglects all consideration of their immutable essences." 18
Terry Eagleton, The Meaning of Life: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York,
2008, p. 18
16
David E. Cooper, Existentialism. A Reconstruction, Blackwell Publishing, Malden, Oxford, 1999, p. 13.
17
"To describe existentialism as an expression of an age ... is to suggest that its claims could be only temporarily
and locally valid." (David E. Cooper, op.cit., id.)
18
Pius XII, Humani Generis, http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/pius_xii/encyclicals/documents/hf_pxii_enc_12081950_humani-generis_en.html (consulted on 17.03.2014).
15
Another trait of the existential philosophy often revealed by its exegetes is its
things in the world are in accordance with rationalist, unambiguous principles, that the world
is rational ...; the existentialist claims that ... there are no unambiguous principles constituting
that world
19
of existentialism, taking into account the German cultural space and including (besides
mechanism which seemed to destroy individual freedom, personal decision and organic
community; an analytic rationalism which saps the vital forced of life and transforms
everything, including man himself, into an object of calculation and control; a secularized
humanism which cuts man and the world off from the creative Source and the ultimate mystery
of existence.20
We must note that the existential philosopher refers mostly to the German brand of
existentialism (or Existenzphilosophie), because the works of the French existentialists were
"vehicles of understanding" 21 and not as the residues of a clear and cold mind. Kierkegaard
and Heidegger show that anxiety is a fundamental and ontological affect which reveals the
world in its entirety. We find that the "intelligence of emotions" (the expression belongs to
Robert Solomon) is one of the essential discoveries of existentialism, a discovery that does
not veer towards irrationalism and that aims to understand the human life in its entirety.
20
b) Kierkegaard, Shestov, Camus but also Cioran, Ionesco and Kafka meet with the
problem of the absurd, understood as a limit of the human rationality. Their apparent
irrationalism is at the same time a struggle against meaninglessness and an effort to generate
alternative meanings and reasons. We should describe their thought as a deeper and larger
(also more subversive) trans-rationalism.
narrow Hegelian rationality (the so called identity between reality and reason), analyzing
despair, anxiety, the possibility of the suspension of ethics, on one hand, the will to power, the
death of God, the destruction of the morals, on the other. But their discourse, undermining the
Western rationality is technically built through the methodology of the same rationality:
synthesizing, their irrationalism (or what we better named trans-rationalism) creates a new
thought territory, a new philosophical field, which widens and completes the heritage of
Western rationalism. Moreover, this accusation is tempered in the writings of Cooper 22 and
Solomon23, who, discussing existential phenomenology, observe the coherence and even the
systematization of the philosophical trend, which in this way becomes a harmonious part of
"Existentialism
is not a mood or a vocabulary, but a relatively systematic philosophy." (David E. Cooper,
op.cit., p. 9)
23
"The dramatic ethical and literary masterpieces of the existentialists are first the products of a serious and
technical development within traditional Western epistemology and Husserl's phenomenology." (Robert C.
Solomon (Ed.), Phenomenology and Existentialism, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, 2001, p. 38.)
22
Conclusion
Summarizing, the traits of existential philosophy are:
(Cooper, 1999);
argued
we have
Considering that there are at least five ways of accessing the problem of
existentialism, we believe that the most important traits are the recuperation and
transformation of nihilism, the focus on the individual and the fact that existential philosophy
expresses par excellence the postwar zeitgeist. Our personal definition of existentialism
follows: existentialism is the alternative to the reductive manner of nihilism and to the
fragmentary method of postmodernism, endorsing the existent individual in its entirety, an
individual immersed in a universe, which offers mostly meaninglessness and discontinuity.
pursuing authenticity and recuperation of death. The attitude of the existentialist towards
choice, decision and responsibility is exemplary. The existentialist knows the founding value
of the choice, which has an open horizon and must be kept in pure potentiality. The decision
that follows after choice, although narrowing the horizon of the existential subject, must be
respected and brought in the field of continuity. Immersed in a culture of irresponsibility (in
which the society, fate, God, the genes are always to blame), the existentialist will
comprehend that the assignment of guilt, with all its seductive appearance, is ineffective,
covering up the truth.
10
Cited Works
Richard Appignanesi, Oscar Zarate, Introducing Existentialism, Totem Books, New York,
2001.
William Barrett, Irrational Man. A Study in Existential Philosophy, Anchor Books, New
York, 1962.
Gary Cox, How to Be an Existentialist or How to Get real, Get a Grip and Stop Making
Terry Eagleton, The Meaning of Life: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press,
Steven Earnshaw, Existentialism. A Guide for the Perplexed, Continuum, London New York,
2006.
Walter Kaufmann, Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, Meridian Books, New York,
1960.
London, 1972.
Lanham, 2001.
Paul Tillich, "Existential Philosophy", in Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 5, No. 1, Jan.
1944, University of Pennsylvania Press.