Location Through Consciousness

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 2

The Location of Consciousness

http://www.princeton.edu/~freshman/science/crick/location.html

That different areas of the visual cortex respond to different stimuli and are arranged in a
somewhat heirarchical manner has already been established. Neurons in the lower region of
the cortex react most to simple pieces of a scene, with only some attention given to the
broader context. Higher regions respond most to more complicated objects (hands, faces, etc.)
with less attention given to where these objects appear in your sight. There is no current
evidence for an area which is responsible for the global aspect of vision.
The challenge, then, is to determine which region of the brain controls the area of sight of
which we are aware at any one moment. Theories exist that this section is located in either the
high or middle region of the visual hierarchy. Philip Johnson-Laird's theory that this area is
on the high end of the hierarchy contends that the determining region is responsible only for
dealing with the processed information which it is given. In contrast, Ray Jackendoff
contends that consciousness lies somewhere in the intermediate levels and results from
population dynamics.
At first, these two theories may seem only subtly different and irrelevant as far as
determining the actual location of consciousness. They, however, provide profoundly
different ways of addressing the problem and, hence, of attempting to solve it. To illustrate,
consider the mind as a an idealized courtroom. The lawyers are responsible for sorting and
identifying all the evidence and then presenting it to the jury. The jury then must meet and
discuss together the evidence which they have seen. They must decide which evidence to give
the most weight and which to ignore. Based on the decision of the group as a whole, they
present one verdict. The judge then decides the sentence, without having had any say in the
verdict itself. Johnson-Laird asserts that consciousness lies in the judge, whereas Jackendoff
thinks that it lies in the jury. The differences, as we shall see, are profound.
Johnson-Laird's judge determines the perceived area based on the information presented to it
alone; it has no dealings with the processing which occured at the lower levels in the
identification of objects. Other analogies for this theory include a conductor of an orchestra,
unaware of the exact technique and posture of each individual member yet aware of the
sound they produce, and the operating system of a computer, which allows communication
between different programs and devices without itself being involved in the creation of the
data.
Crick finds some fault in this theory since consciousness is hardly likely to be that exactly
defined. Not only would consciousness more likely be spread out between different regions
of the brain, but also, within the regions themselves, the decision would be spread out
between various neurons.
Crick leans more towards Ray Jackendoff's theory which has much to do with David Marr's
2D sketch. Jackendoff contends that conscious lies in the 2 1/2-D sketch and not in the 3D
model, which would correspond to a higher level in the heirarchy. Like most of our thoughts,
the 3D model remains outside of our consciousness yet influences heavily the final product of

which we are conscious. Furthermore, Jackendoff claims that the processing of the 2 1/2-D
sketch is determined by selection from a population of possible thoughts.
Despite making strong statements on where consciousness is most likely to be in an abstract
sense, these theories remain almost purely psychological and do not address the actual
characteristics of neurons which determine consciousness. In fact, no one actually knows
where these consciousness determining neurons are located or what distinguishes them from
other neurons.
These theories may provide some clues to aid in determining the identity of these neurons,
though. Consciousness stems from awareness, so we should examine the behavior of neurons
associated with objects of which we are aware. Furthermore, awareness arises from short
term-memory, so we should try to better understand short-term memory. Difficulty arises
when we consider that we are able to be aware of multiple objects at a time. The processes
which determine our consciousness are anything but understood and seem to consist of some
sort of temporary binding similar to that involved in the recognition of objects.
Mike Akins '99
Return to the Architectonic
May 25, 1996.

You might also like