Boghossian Eprulesproofs Libre
Boghossian Eprulesproofs Libre
Boghossian Eprulesproofs Libre
EPISTEMIC RULES*
We have some sort of inductive rule linking beliefs about the observed
to beliefs about the unobserved, an example of which might be:
(Induction) For appropriate Fs and Gs, if you have observed n (for some
sufficiently large n) Fs and they have all been Gs, then you are prima
facie rationally permitted to believe that all Fs are Gs.
These rules, and others like them, constitute what me may call our
epistemic system. They represent our conception of how it would be
most rational for a thinker to form beliefs under different epistemic circumstances.
Let us call this the rule-following picture of rational belief. It is a very
familiar picture and has tempted many. As I shall try to explain later,
its roots run very deep.3
Because we accept this picture, we take seriously a number of questions that it seems to entrain.
For example, we recognize that, in addition to the rules that we actually use, there are other rules, different from and incompatible with
ours, which we might have used instead. And this seems to raise the
question: Are our rules the right ones? Are they the ones that deliver
genuinely justified belief?
These questions in turn raise a more fundamental one: In what
sense could there be a fact of the matter as to what the right epistemic
rules are? And if there is such a fact of the matter, how do we find out
what it is? And what, in any case, entitles us to operate with the rules
that we actually operate with?
None of these familiar and compelling questions would make
much sense in the absence of the rule-following picture of rational
belief. Each of them presupposes that we rely on rules in forming rational beliefs.
I find the rule-following picture, along with the questions that it
entrains, as natural and as compelling as the next person. However,
I have also come to worry about its ultimate intelligibility, a worry that
I find myself unable to lay to rest. In this paper, I aim to explain the
considerations that give rise to this worry.
I have been talking about the rule-governed picture of rational
belief. But rational belief is hardly the only domain in which rulefollowing has been thought to play a prominent role. The sort of generalist picture I have been sketching for epistemology has of course
always loomed large in ethics. We find it very natural to think that,
in our moral judgments, we are guided by a set of general moral principles that tell us what we have most reason to do under various practical conditions.
3
For explicit endorsements of the view, see, among many others, John Pollock and
Joseph Cruz, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,
1999), chapter 5; Christopher Peacocke, The Realm of Reason (New York: Oxford, 2004);
Ralph Wedgwood, Internalism Explained, and Hartry Field, Apriority as an Evaluative Notion, in Boghossian and Peacocke, eds., New Essays on the A Priori (New York:
Oxford, 2000), pp. ?????? and pp. ??????.
epistemic rules
See, for example, Jonathan Dancy, Ethics without Principles (New York: Oxford, 2006).
See Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Cambridge, UK: Blackwell, 1953);
Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge: Harvard, 1982).
5
epistemic rules
Now, I take it that suspending judgment about h is not simply: not believing h. If it were, then the imperative at (5) would amount to saying:
If e, then either believe h or do not believe h!
which does not say much of anything. Suspending judgment, then, requires something activeconsidering whether h and then rejecting
taking a view on the matter.
If that is right, though, (5) now seems to call for you to do things
that go well beyond what (4) says. According to (4), if a certain kind
of evidence is available, then, if you believed h on its basis, that belief
would be justified. (4) does not say that you should believe h; it does
not say that you should consider whether h; it does not say that you
should do anything.
In other words, (5) is most naturally seen not as the imperatival
counterpart of the norm of permission formulated in (4) but as the
imperatival counterpart of the norm of requirement formulated in
(6) If for some e, f(e, h), then you are required either to believe h (on the
basis of e) or to suspend judgment on h.
Would we do better with something more along the lines of (7) rather
than (5)?
(7) If for some e, f(e, h), then either belief h (on the basis of e) or do not
do anything (on the basis of e)!
But this does not seem right, either. Even without going into the details
of what it might mean for someone to not do something on the basis
of e, I hope it is clear that, whatever exactly it means, if, in response to
e, I scratched my nose on the basis of e, I would not have done anything
that is in violation of the norm of permission issued by (4).
There are, no doubt, many other proposals that could be considered, but I hope it is clear that there really is a problem capturing a
norm of permission in imperatival terms. An imperative, however disjunctive its consequent, will require you to do something, or to refrain
from doing something; but a norm of permission does not say anything about anyones doing anything, or refraining from doing anything. It just says that, under the appropriate conditions, if one were
to do something, doing that thing would be alright.9
9
There are a number of other proposals that we could consider, but I cannot go into
them more here. Probably the most promising is the one employed by Allan Gibbard:
think of accepting a rule of permission as consisting in the rejection of a rule of requirement. So accepting the permissibility of castling under C would consist in rejecting the
rule: If C, dont castle! But we are now owed an account of what it is to reject an imperative. See Gibbard, Thinking How to Live (Cambridge: Harvard, 2003).
epistemic rules
Arguments for the Imperatival Construal. These, then, are some of the
considerations that push one in favor of a propositional view of rules.
On the other hand, there is the following argument that pushes one
in the opposite direction.
Recall that the picture we are working with says that it is necessary
and sufficient for a belief to be rational that it be held in accordance
with the correct epistemic rules. In other words, we are working with:
(RuleRatBel) Ss belief that p is rationally permitted if and only if S arrived at the belief that p by following the correct rule N.
(EpNorm*) If C, then if S were to believe that p on the basis of this very norm, he
would be rationally permitted to believe that p.
Second, this problem of false rules would not arise on the imperatival picture of epistemic rules, on which the rules are of the form:
If C, believe that p!
This suggestion is worth exploring, although, for obvious reasons, I am always leery of
self-referential devices and am not sure I understand them.
11
Limitations of space prevent me from considering various ways of responding to
this difficulty for the propositional construal. For further discussion, see my Rules and
Intentionality in Nature (in preparation).
epistemic rules
The suggestion seems to be that rule-following and normative constraint come to much the same thing. Or, if not quite that, that
rule-following on Ss part is necessary for Ss behavior to be subject
to normative assessment.
But this seems wrong. Intuitively, and without the help of controversial assumptions, it looks as though there are many thoughts that
S can have, and many activities that he can engage in, that are subject
to assessment in terms of rule R even if there is no intuitive sense in
which they involve Ss following rule R.
Consider Nora playing roulette. She has a hunch that the next
number will be 36 and she goes with it: she bets all her money on
12
10
it. We need not suppose that, in going with her hunch, she was following any ruleperhaps this was just a one-time event. Still, it looks
as though we can normatively criticize her belief as irrational since it
was based on no good evidence.
Or consider Peter who has just tossed the UNICEF envelope in the
trash without opening it. Once more, we need not suppose that Peter
has a standing policy of tossing out charity envelopes without opening
them and considering their merits. However, even if no rule was involved it can still be true that Peters behavior was subject to normative assessment, that there are norms covering his behavior.
In both of these cases, then, norms or rules apply to some thought
or behavior even though there is no intuitive sense in which the agent
in question was attempting to observe those norms or follow those
rules himself.
Of course, some philosopherslike Kripkes Wittgensteinthink
that wherever there is intentional content there must be rule-following,
since meaning itself is a matter of following rules. But that is not a
suitably pre-theoretic fact about rule-following; and what we are after
at the moment is just some intuitive characterization of the phenomenon. We will come back to the question whether meaning is a matter
of following rules.
When we say that S is following a rule R in doing A, we mean
neither that S conforms to R nor simply that R may be used to assess
Ss behavior, ruling it correct if he conforms and incorrect if he does
not. What, then, do we mean?
Let us take a clear case. Suppose I receive an email and that I answer it immediately. When would we say that this behavior was a case
of following the:
(Email Rule) Answer any email that calls for an answer immediately
upon receipt!
epistemic rules
11
Equally clearly, the because here is not any old causal relation: if a
malicious scientist (or an enterprising colleague) had programmed my
brain to answer any email upon receipt (in some zombie-like way) because he accepted the rule that I should answer any email upon receipt,
that would not count as my following the Email Rule. (It might count as
my brain following the rule.) Rather, for me to be following the rule,
the because must be that of rational action explanation: I follow the
Email Rule when my acceptance of that rule serves as my reason for
replying immediately, when that rule rationalizes my behavior.
However exactly the notion of acceptance or internalization is understood, what is important is that, in any given case of rule-following,
we have something with the following structure: a state that can play
the role of rule acceptance; and some nondeviant casual chain leading from that state to a piece of behavior that would allow us to say
that the accepted rule explains and rationalizes the behavior.
Occasionally, I will also describe the matter in terms of the language
of commitment: In rule-following there is, on the one hand, a commitment, on the part of the thinker to uphold a certain pattern in his
thought or behavior; and, on the other, some behavior that expresses
that commitment, that is explained and rationalized by it.
It will be up to the reader to discern whether I have loaded these
notions in a way that is illicit. For the moment, let me just note that
this characterization coincides well with the way Kripke seems to be
thinking about the phenomenon of rule-following. As he says a propos of following the rule for addition:
I learnedand internalized instructions fora rule, which determines
how addition is to be continued . This set of directions, I may suppose,
I explicitly gave myself at some earlier time . It is this set of directions
that justifies and determines my present response (op. cit., p. 16).
I think it was a mistake on Kripkes part to use the word justify in this
passage rather than the word rationalize. In talking about rulefollowing, it is important to bear in mind that we might be following
bad rules. The problem of rule-following arises no less for Affirming
the Consequent or Gamblers Fallacy than it does for Modus Ponens.
If I am following Gamblers Fallacy, my betting the house on black
after a long string of reds at the roulette wheel would not be justified
but it would be rationalized by the rule that I am following. Given that
I am committed to the fallacious rule, it makes sense that I would bet
the house on black.
We may summarize our characterization of personal-level rulefollowing by the following four theses:
(Acceptance) If S is following rule R (If C, do A), then S has somehow
accepted R.
12
epistemic rules
13
Even if I knew very little about what mitochondria are, I would be very
confident that I should accept this proposition. What could be the reason for my confidence if not that I have accepted the general principle:
Accept any proposition of the form All F s are F s.
Therefore,
x doesnt have a Cauchy surface.
Once again, I may know very little about the ingredient concepts. But
I can be very confident that, if I were justified in believing the premises,
I would be justified in believing the conclusion. Once more, the only
plausible explanation is that I have internalized (or accepted) a general
Modus Ponens rule.
Acceptance and Intention. Let us turn now to asking why there is
supposed to be a problem about rule-following. Why, in particular,
does Kripkes Wittgenstein maintain that it is not possible for us to
follow rules?
Kripkes problem is focused on Acceptance. He is struck by the fact
that the patterns to which we are said to be able to commit ourselves
are infinitary patterns. Thus, we claim to follow the rule of inference
Modus Ponens:
(Modus Ponens): If you are rationally permitted to believe both that p
and that If p, then q, then, you are prima facie rationally permitted to
believe that q.
MP, however, is defined over an infinite number of possible propositions. How is it possible, Kripke asks, for a thinker to commit himself
to uphold this potentially infinitary pattern? Kripke despairs of answering this challenge head-on.
As we all know, Kripkes argument proceeds by elimination. There
look to be only two serious candidates for constituting the state of rule
acceptance: either it consists in some intentional state of a thinker, or it
consists in his dispositions, very broadly understood, to use that symbol
in certain ways. And he finds fault with both options.
Let us go along for now with the rejection of the dispositional suggestion. Still, what could possibly be wrong with invoking some intentional notion, as Crispin Wright has done? As Wright puts it:
so far from finding any mystery in the matter, we habitually assign just
these characteristics [the characteristics constitutive of the acceptance of
14
14
See also Philip Pettit, Rules, Reasons and Norms (New York: Oxford, 2002), p. 27:
The notion of following a rule, as it is conceived here, involves an important element
over and beyond that of conforming to a rule. The conformity must be intentional,
being something that is achieved at least in part, on the basis of belief and desire. To
follow a rule is to conform to it, but the act of conforming, or at least the act of trying to
conformif that is distinctmust be intentional. It must be explicable, in the appropriate way, by the agents beliefs and desires.
epistemic rules
15
Kripke continues:
Despite the initial plausibility of this objection, the sceptics response is
all too obvious: True, if count as I used the word in the past, referred to
the act of counting (and my other words are correctly interpreted in the
standard way) then plus must have stood for addition. But I applied
count like plus to only finitely many past cases. Thus the sceptic
can question my present interpretation of my past usage of count as
he did with plus (op. cit., p. 16).
15
For the distinction between dogmatists and conservatives about perception, see
James Pryor, The Skeptic and the Dogmatist, Nos, xxxiv (2000): 51749.
16
epistemic rules
17
18
16
Jerry Fodor may have been the first to appreciate this clearly; see his A Theory of
Content and Other Essays (Cambridge: MIT, 1990), pp. 13536. I do not believe that any
of the main arguments of my The Rule-Following Considerations, Mind, ?? (1989);
?????, are affected by paying greater heed to this distinction, although I am sure I
was not as clear about it in that paper as I should have been.
17
I have gone back and forth about the plausibility of the Meaning Assumption as
applied to public language expressions. In my New York University seminar of Spring
2006, I defended it, but in an earlier version of this paper I retreated to saying that it
was not settled. I thank Christopher Peacocke for rightly insisting to me that it met my
characterization of person-level rule-following.
epistemic rules
19
18
For all that we have said, of course, it remains possible that we need to think of
mental meaning as generated by sub-personal rule-following and that this will cause
problems of its own. I shall come back to this question towards the end of the paper.
19
For discussion and references, see my The Rule Following Considerations. More
on this below.
20
intentional contents, there would still be a problem about how rulefollowing is possible.
The passage I have in mind is at Philosophical Investigations 219. In it
Wittgenstein considers the temptation to say that when we commit
ourselves to some rule, that rule determines how we are to act in indefinitely many future cases:
All the steps are really already taken, means: I no longer have any
choice. The rule once stamped with a particular meaning, traces the
lines along which it is to be followed through the whole of space.
Even if we were to grant that we could somehow imbue the rule with a
meaning that would determine how it applies in indefinitely many
cases in the future, Wittgenstein seems to be saying, it would still
not help us understand how rule-following is possible.
How mystifying this must seem from a Kripkean point of view. How
would it help? How could it not help? We wanted an answer to the
question: By virtue of what is it true that I use the 1 sign according
to the rule for addition and not some other rule? According to the
picture currently under consideration, one of our options is to say
that it is by virtue of the fact that I use the 1 sign with the intention
that its use conform to the rule for addition, and where it is understood that the availability of such intentions is not itself a function
of our following rules in respect of them. Under the terms of the picture in place, what would be left over?
How should we understand what Wittgenstein is saying here? It is,
of course, always hard to be confident of any particular interpretation
of this philosophers cryptic remarks; but here is a suggestion that
seems of independent philosophical interest.
Let us revert to our email example. Suppose I have adopted the
rule: Answer any email (that calls for an answer) immediately upon
epistemic rules
21
At least in this case, then, rule-following, on the Intention model, requires inference: it requires the rule-follower to infer what the rule calls
for in the circumstances in which he finds himself.
In this regard, though, the email case is hardly special. Since any
rule has general content, if our acceptance of a rule is pictured as involving its representation by a mental state of ours, an inference will
always be required to determine what action the rule calls for in any
particular circumstance. On the Intention View, then, applying a rule
will always involve inference.
Inference, however, as we have already seen above, is a form of
rule-following par excellence. In the email case, in moving from
the intention, via the premise about the antecedent, to the conclusion, I am relying on a general rule that says that from any such premises I am entitled to draw such-and-so conclusion. Since, as I have
set up the example, I have construed the email rule as an imperative, this is not quite Modus Ponens, of course, but it is something
very similar:
(MP*) From If C, do A and C, conclude do A!
22
20
This, I believe, is the correct interpretation of Wittgensteins remarks about needing a rule to interpret a rule. In the Kripkean framework, this is read as supposing that a
rule can only be given to you as an inert sign whose meaning you would then have to
divine. And this sets off an infinite regress of interpretations. However, a different way
of reading Wittgenstein here is to see him as concerned not with the question: How
could an inert sign guide us, if not through the use of further rules? But rather with
the question: How could a general content guide us, if not through the use of further rules?
21
See L. Carroll, What the Tortoise Said to Achilles, Mind, ?? (1895): 27880.
There is also a similarity to Quines arguments in his Truth by Convention, in his
The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays (Cambridge: Harvard, 1976), pp. ?????.
epistemic rules
23
The claim is that the following five propositions form an inconsistent set.
(1) Rule-following is possible.
(2) Following a rule consists in acting on ones acceptance (or internalization) of a rule.
(3) Accepting a rule consists in an intentional state with general (prescriptive) content.
(4) Acting under particular circumstances on an intentional state with
general content involves some sort of deductive inference to what
the content calls for under the circumstances.
(5) Inference involves following a rule.
22
Notice that this argument is not only neutral on whether what is at issue are intentions as opposed to other sorts of intentional state, but also on whether what is at issue
are personal-level intentional states as opposed to sub-personal content-bearing states. So
long as you think that the acceptance of a rule consists in some sort of intentional state
with general content and that, as a result, inference will be required to act on that state,
there will be a problemit does not matter whether this is thought of as occurring at
the personal or the sub-personal levelmore on this below.
24
The drift of the considerations I have been presenting seems to capture the intended point behind this passage.
Even without assuming Naturalism as an a priori constraint on the
acceptability of a solution to the rule-following problem, and without
assuming that mental content itself must be engendered by rulefollowing, it would seem that we have shown that, in its most fundamental incarnation, rule acceptance cannot consist in the formation
of a propositional attitude in which the requirements of the rule are
explicitly encoded.
Such a picture would be one according to which rule-following is
always fully sighted, always fully informed by some recognition of the requirements of the rule being followed. And the point that Wittgenstein
seems to be making is that, in its most fundamental incarnation, not
all rule-following can be like thatsome rule-following must simply
be blind. The argument I have presented supports this conclusion.
Rule-following without Intentionality: Dispositions. The question is how
rule-following could be blind. How can someone commit himself to a
certain pattern in his thought or behavior without this consisting in
the formation of some appropriate kind of intentional state?
The only option that seems to be available to us is the one that
Kripke considers at length, that we should somehow succeed in understanding what it is for someone to accept a given rule just by invoking his or her dispositions to conform to the rule. If we were able to do
that, we could explain how it is possible to act on a rule without inference because the relation between a disposition and its exercise is,
of course, noninferential.
Now, Kripke, as we know, gives an extended critique of the dispositional view. However, that critique has not generally been thought to
be very effective; many writers have rejected it.23 So perhaps there is
hope for rule-following after all, in the form of a dispositional account.
My own view, by contrast with received opinion, is that Kripkes critique is extremely effective, although even I underestimated the force
of what I now take to be its most telling strand. And so I think that it
cannot offer us any refuge after all, if we abandon the Intentional View.
The core idea of a dispositional account is that what it is for someone to accept the rule Modus Ponens is, roughly, for him to be dis23
See, for example, Scott Soames, Skepticism about Meaning: Indeterminacy, Normativity and the Rule Following Paradox, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, ?? (1998):
?????; Paul Horwich, Meaning (New York: Oxford, 1998).
epistemic rules
25
24
26
epistemic rules
27
that rule, but so, too, is my being disposed to infer q. Suppose I consider
a particular MP inference, find myself disposed to draw the conclusion, but, for whatever reason, fail to do so. That disposition to draw
the conclusion would itself be explained and rationalized by my acceptance of the MP rule.
However, it is, I take it, independently plausible that something can
neither be explained by itself, nor rationalized by itself. So, following
rule R and being disposed to conform to it cannot be the same thing.
Here we see, once again, how Kripkes Meaning Assumption gets in
the way of his argument: a good point about rule-following comes out
looking false when it is extended to mental content.
Is Going Sub-Personal the Solution? I emphasized from the very beginning that the notion of rule-following that appears to underwrite
the rule-following picture of rational belief is a personal-level notion.
I reason about what to believe, not a part of my brain. As a result, it is
the personal-level notion with which I have been most concerned in
this paper.
Someone may therefore be tempted to think that perhaps the moral
of the preceding discussion is precisely that it cannot be the personallevel notion that is at work in the rule-following picture, that the solution to the difficulties we have been outlining is to go sub-personal.
This suggestion resonates with what has been a robust tendency in
the literature on rule-following. There are many discussions of the
Intentional View that accuse it of being overly intellectualized and
which recommend substituting a sub-personal notion in its place.26 It
is not very often made clear exactly what that is supposed to amount
to. The preceding discussion should help us see that this is not a very
useful suggestion.
In the present context, going sub-personal presumably means identifying rule-acceptance or -internalization not with some person-level
state, such as an intention, but with some sub-personal state. Such a
state will either be an intentional state or some nonintentional state.
Let us say that it is some intentional state in which the rules requirements are explicitly represented. Then, once again, it would appear
that some inference (now, sub-personal) will be required to figure
out what the rule calls for under the circumstances. And at this point
the regress problem will recur. (That is what I meant by saying earlier
that the structure of the regress problem seems to be indifferent as to
whether the states of rule-acceptance are personal or sub-personal.)
26
28
epistemic rules
29
28